đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș anarcho-on-saving-marxism-from-itself.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:24:26. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: On Saving Marxism From Itself
Author: Anarcho
Date: June 24, 2021
Language: en
Topics: marxism, a response
Source: Retrieved on 26th June 2021 from https://anarchism.pageabode.com/?p=2833

Anarcho

On Saving Marxism From Itself

Anarchists, I hope, would read Mustapha Mond’s “A Brief Question of

Syndicalism” with mixed feelings. On the one hand, it is always nice to

see other socialists apparently searching for common ground with their

libertarian “frienemies” and implicitly admit that we were right. On the

other, there is a substantial element of wishful thinking about it which

limits its usefulness.

If syndicalism and its advocation of “workers’ self-management,

organisation, direct action and unionisation in order to abolish the

capitalist order” has been “forgotten and stamped into tragic

irrelevance” then this, in part, was the product of the hostility of

Marxists – such as Lenin or Trotsky – who spent a great deal of time

attacking both it and workers’ self-management as “petty bourgeois”.

Combined with the apparent “success” of the Russian Revolution which

drew many militants away from it (and the overt hostility of the new

Communist Parties) and the rise of fascism in many of its strongholds

(Italy, Portugal, Spain, etc.), syndicalism no longer had the influence

in after the Second World War as it had before the First.

The question arises as to why workers’ control was viewed as “petty

bourgeois” and this takes us to the heart of the contradiction in Mond’s

suggestion that syndicalism is a cure for the ails of Marxist socialism.

This, in turn, breaks down into three sub-questions: what is

syndicalism? What is Marxist socialism? And, are both consistent with

each other?

Syndicalism is, I would suggest, a tactic to achieve socialism rather

than a vision of socialism. This explains why we find a range of people

– anarchists (mutualists, collectivists, communists and even a few

individualists) and Marxists (James Connolly and Daniel De Leon spring

to mind) – advocating it while having differing visions of a future

society. Yet almost all were agreed that “proletarian ownership of the

workplace” was not desired – ownership would be social but control of

production would rest in the producers’ hands. Ownership has to be

social so that anyone joining a workplace automatically becomes a member

of the association running it, otherwise a class of workers who happened

to be there when the workplace was first collectivised would employ

another class of workers as their wage-workers.[1]

Social ownership can take many forms. Marx and Engels, however,

continually stressed State ownership and rarely, if ever, mention

workers’ control of production. Rather, nationalisation –

“centralisation 
 in the hands of the State”, to quote The Communist

Manifesto – is stressed, along with establishing “industrial armies”

(quoting the Manifesto again). As Marxist Bertell Ollman admits:

Marx’s picture of life and organisation in the first stage of communism

is very incomplete. There is no discussion of such obviously important

developments as workers’ control. We can only guess how much power

workers enjoy in their enterprises.[2]

Compare this with Proudhon’s 1848 election manifesto and its call for a

federation of democratically-run workers’ associations. This explains

why, when it comes to showing that Marx favoured workers’ control, his

few positive comments on co-operatives are utilised.[3] Yet such

comments on co-operatives could fill, perhaps, a page, while Proudhon’s

include often extensive discussions over many books and articles from

1840 to 1865. In this, Bakunin and Kropotkin followed Proudhon’s lead

while Lenin paid only lip-service to (a very limited form of) workers’

control in 1917 before quickly dropping it in favour of State control

and “dictatorial” one-man management.[4]

This perspective drove the Bolshevik’s systematic undermining of the

factory committees after October within the centralised, statist

economic regime they created reflecting their vision of socialism. A key

part of this process was denunciation of the particularistic, parochial

interests which they claimed factory committees expressed, as reflected

in the “petty-bourgeois” perspectives in the “anarchist utopia” of

socialism in one workplace. The economy, they claimed, was interlinked

and this required a central body to control it, reflecting the orthodox

interpretation of Marx and Engels then and now.

The idea that “syndicalism” – worker-owned and run workplaces – is

Marxist has been explored by Marxists for many years in their debates

over “market socialism”.[5] Mond refers to “contemporary theorist

Richard Wolff” who advocates a market socialism based on co-operatives

which would, to use Mond’s words, “directly democratise the places in

which they work, and would grant them the ownership of the means of

production which has historically evaded them so heinously. It could be

the very essence of socialism”.[6] Suffice to say, those who argue

against market socialism in favour of planning have little difficulty

proving their orthodoxy by means of numerous quotes from Marx and Engels

(that the market socialists have little difficulty showing that these

quotes are irrelevant for any real economy is equally true). With this

in mind, I turn to this comment by Mond:

Perhaps a syndicalist society is the one which most truly conforms to

the original conceptualisation of socialism by Marx, as it would

necessarily entail the means of production being directly in the hands

of the working classes, the proletarians, through worker co-operatives,

unions, boards and committees rather than in the hands of the state

through bureaucrats, autocrats, politicians and dictators. History’s

“socialist” experiments have too often resulted in the exaltation of

authoritarianism and a lack of direct democracy, handing the means of

production to the state as so-called “public ownership” rather than

directly to the people.

Yet handing the means of production to the State was precisely what Marx

and Engels (repeatedly) advocated. Only later, once classes had

disappeared, would society become one of “associated producers”. It is

in this context that we need to evaluate any positive comments by Marx

and Engels on co-operatives and how these contradict their wider views

of a socialist economy. This can be seen in The Civil War in France,

rightly considered Marx’s most appealing and libertarian work (for it is

mostly reporting on a libertarian influenced revolt which owed next to

nothing to Marxism). He praises the attempts at co-operative production

made during the Commune:

Yes, gentlemen, the Commune intended to abolish that class property

which makes the labour of the many the wealth of the few. It aimed at

the expropriation of the expropriators. It wanted to make individual

property a truth by transforming the means of production, land, and

capital, now chiefly the means of enslaving and exploiting labour, into

mere instruments of free and associated labour. But this is communism,

“impossible” communism! (The Civil War in France)

So far this describes mutualism and collectivism rather than communism

(“impossible” or not) given that Marx had not previously stressed

associations to run the means of production but rather concentrating

these “into the hands of the State”. After this somewhat disingenuous

assertion, he continues:

If co-operative production is not to remain a sham and a snare; if it is

to supersede the capitalist system; if united co-operative societies are

to regulate national production upon a common plan, thus taking it under

their own control, and putting an end to the constant anarchy and

periodical convulsions which are the fatality of capitalist production –

what else, gentlemen, would it be but communism, “possible” communism?

Now we get to the uniquely Marxist vision, the need for “a common plan”

for “national production” as the means of the workers “taking it under

their own control”. There are numerous issues associated with national –

never mind international – planning which neither Marx nor Engels seemed

aware of. In their writing, the task of identifying, gathering,

processing and presenting the millions of inputs and outputs of any such

plan are either ignored or assumed to be a simple matter.[7] Marx, to

use a pertinent example, considered a few sentences on two workers

producing two goods as sufficient in his deeply dishonest polemic

against Proudhon, The Poverty of Philosophy.[8] While a “common plan” is

easy to envision with two inputs and two outputs, one involving millions

of products and producers is less so.

This, while important, should not distract us from the key contradiction

here – namely that such planning ends meaningful workers’ control at the

point of production.

Let us assume that all the informational, knowledge and processing

issues of planning the economic (and social) activities of millions of

people have been solved. A common plan has been somehow drawn up and

agreed by the people by referendum.[9] The task is now to implement it.

A plan – to qualify as such – has to have decided upon outputs and

inputs. To be coherent, this has to apply at every level otherwise the

agreed outputs cannot be delivered (we will ignore the question of

whether the implicit assumption of perfect foresight is feasible).Thus,

once a plan has been decided, each workplace has to be given its

allocated outputs to produce (and when to produce them) and informed of

which inputs they can expect (and when to expect them). If this is not

done, then there is no plan and no regulation of national production: a

“common plan” has to be a central plan.

This means that any “workers’ control” or “economic democracy” within a

given workplace would be within these tight constraints. Indeed, unless

the plan allows it, workers cannot even paint their cafeteria a

different colour (the volume of green paint would be determined by the

plan and so any such request would have to be pre-approved in order for

the correct inputs to be specified for the expected demand). Being one

vote in millions (billions!) would make the workplace a site of

alienation, albeit a different form than under capitalism. It would

mimic the same “democracy” expressed in bourgeois elections to

parliament (albeit perhaps more often). As with centralised political

democracy, centralised economic democracy would not secure for people

meaningful control over their own lives, quite the reverse as the

conscious allocation of resources is also the conscious allocation of

work (consider the impact on “the common plan” if people decide to

change jobs).

The orthodox Marxist argument against economic federalism and workplace

autonomy is, firstly, that workers would gain a narrow, proprietorial

interest and use whatever advantage they had against society as a whole.

Second, that there is a pressing need to coordinate economic activity to

ensure efficiency in identifying and achieving social goals. Third, that

within a market-socialist economy, there would be pressures from the

market which would force the workforce to cut conditions, increase the

hours and intensity of labour, etc. in order to survive (this is often

described by the somewhat self-contradictory terms “self-exploitation”

and “self-managed capitalism”).

The first issue is a potential danger but it ignores that the officials

at the top of the economy can also gain a narrow, proprietorial

interest, but over the whole economy. While the anti-social activities

of a few workplaces can easily be challenged by others, those of

bureaucrats are far harder to challenge.

The second is valid and explains why anarchists have never denied that a

complex economy is interlinked and needs appropriate federal bodies to

manage appropriate social needs. However, we are also aware that it is

precisely this complexity and interwovenness that means that no central

body – no matter how big or powerful – could manage it.[10] Autonomy is

needed precisely because of the numerous unexpected problems any real

economy would face, and to generate the essential information and

knowledge only free agreement exposes (and which is inevitably lost in

the aggregation needed for the plan).

The third is valid, but applies to mutualism rather than libertarian

communism and likewise ignores the threat implied by placing economic

decision making – and so power – into the hands of central bodies. The

challenge for libertarian communism is to secure meaningful workplace

autonomy and to coordinate diverse plans without the positive and

negative influences of markets.[11] This rejection of the centralisation

inherent to a “common plan” does not mean rejecting coordination, just

that this must be achieved by means of federalism for appropriate

activities and at appropriate levels.

Mond is right in a sense, for there is an overlap between market

socialists and their orthodox opponents. Market socialism becomes

acceptable for the latter during the “transition period” immediately

after a revolution. Thus the market socialists are denounced as

advocating a utopian project due to the inherent incompatibility of

markets and socialism, and markets are recognised as an essential aspect

of the transitional economy: how being unworkable and a necessity is

left to the magic of dialectics to explain.

It is the mirror image of the Marxist position of the State. “Yes, we

agree with you anarchists that the State is a horrible institution, and

we, too, want to get rid of it”, Marxists say, “but we need it for a

little while (with us in control of it, naturally) until it withers

away”. In this case, it is “Yes, we agree with you anarchists that

workers’ control of workplaces is a vital institution which we support,

but only for a little while until capitalism withers away”. Yet the

withering away of workplace management occurs at the same time as the

State (allegedly) withers away, but the former requires a strengthening

of the very central power the latter suggests is disappearing.

Thus we have the paradoxical situation of the central authority both

withering away and expanding its control over the economy (and so

society). This is resolved by suggesting that, as classes disappear, so

does the State, but this is simply due to the way the latter is defined.

Indeed, no class exists which “owns” the means of production, but as

economic decision making becomes increasingly centralised as part of the

process of creating “the common plan”, a new class which controls the

means of production, the labour process and the output develops. We are

assured this is not a State because it is merely administering things,

but this is not so:

Engels 
 was merely playing with words. Whoever has power over things

has power over men; whoever governs production also governs the

producers; who determines consumption is master over the consumer.

This is the question; either things are administered on the basis of

free agreement among the interested parties, and this is anarchy; or

they are administered according to laws made by administrators and this

is government, it is the State, and inevitably it turns out to be

tyrannical.[12]

Thus it was not, as Mond suggests, an “unwillingness to lend more direct

control to the workers” that “led to paradoxically renewed class

antagonisms: an irreconcilable friction between workers and

bureaucrats”. Rather, it was the contradiction between the

decentralising and decentring of power required for meaningful workers’

management of production and the centralising and centring of power

required for “a common plan”. As the State gathers to itself and

centralises more and more economic functions, it does not become less

and less a State, because while existing classes may steadily disappear

as a result of this process, the empowering of a centralised structure

with more and more functions creates a new ruling class (the working

class returns to its place as order-takers after a brief moment of

economic freedom). This can only be viewed as the withering away of the

State if we assume, as Marxism does, that ownership alone creates

classes.

From an anarchist perspective, while the former class division between

capitalist and proletarian may, indeed, disappear, a new one between

bureaucrat and proletariat grows. There is nothing paradoxical about it

at all, which Mond seems to recognise:

These failures of history were due to the fact that state-monopolised

property is simply Bourgeoisie property in new clothing 
 Private

property has never truly been abolished and entrusted to the

proletarians directly, yet this is what syndicalism would achieve.

Yet here he merely echoes Proudhon’s critique of what he termed

“Community” (usually somewhat inaccurately translated as “communism”) in

What is Property? that the “members of a community, it is true, have no

private property; but the community is proprietor, and proprietor not

only of the goods, but of the persons and wills”. While capitalism

divided ownership and use, Community (State socialism) saw ownership and

use undivided and both resulted in exploitation and oppression. The

USSR, Cuba. China, etc. prove the validity of this analysis.

So these arguments are hardly original. Bakunin sketched them in his

conflict with Marx in the International. Yet Mond still suggests that

“Marx once wrote that the dictatorship of the proletariat ‘begins with

the self-government of the commune’. That is to say such a dictatorship

would be a bottom-up system of direct democracy, rather than top-down

control”. The irony here is that Mond is quoting Marx from his marginal

notes to Bakunin’s Statism and Anarchy which dismissed, to quote Mond,

Bakunin’s “prediction that Marxism would lead to a new despotic ‘red

bureaucracy’, more dictatorial than a capitalist system, played out

through history as if prophecy”.

As such, it is bizarre to see Marx’s marginal notes on Bakunin quoted as

if it were an irrelevance that every Marxist revolution (indeed, every

Marxist movement) has seen the rise of a new class of rulers within it.

Yes, indeed, Marx did proclaim that the so-called dictatorship of the

proletariat “begins with the self-government of the commune” yet this

has never come to pass – for precisely the reason Bakunin sketches but

which Marx clearly does not understand. Surely, the experience of over

one hundred and fifty years of an ideology’s practice should count more

than mere words? Mond does mention this sorry history when he admits:

It has been evident in the USSR, Cuba, China and other nations, that

once a new elite had established power, there was a lack of motivation

to move beyond the dictatorship of the proletariat. This eventually

resulted in the creation of, as Trotsky termed it, “degenerated workers’

states”.

Yet the new elite “established power” in the USSR when Trotsky was in

charge – as experienced by Emma Goldman in 1920 – and while he viewed it

as a “workers’ state” in spite of party dictatorship and one-man

management in production. The formation of this new class, as Goldman

also explained, was a direct product of the Bolshevik vision of

socialism based on nationalisation and centralisation – and the millions

of bureaucrats this generated.[13] Of course, many Marxists – like

Ollman – suggest that Russia cannot be used to draw any conclusions

about Marxism due to its economic backwardness but that seems to forget

that Marx was without telephones – never mind computers! – when he put

pen to paper. Given this, I would suggest that “the concept of

syndicalism” is “dependent on the absence of a state”, if by syndicalism

it is meant meaningful workers’ control: any centralised economic body

would systematically undermine it by its very nature.

Yet we must never forget that powerful role the term “transition” plays

in Marxist ideology. This allows Marxists to claim that Marxism is

“anti-State” while, simultaneously, arguing for the necessity to build a

new State. Thus “syndicalist” self-management of production can be

simultaneously opposed and supported depending upon whether we are

talking about the transitional period or not. Yet the direction is clear

– the aim is to move away from such workers’ management and towards

central regulation and control.

All too often, anarchist criticism of Marxism is dismissed as sectarian

(although that does not stop other Marxists, usually of the same group,

writing disgracefully inaccurate attacks on anarchism). No matter, for

we should be proud of the fact we correctly predicted the fate of

Marxism. Yes, social democracy became as reformist as Bakunin predicted.

Yes, State Socialism simply replaced the boss by the bureaucrat as

Proudhon predicted. Whether economically or politically, the

“dictatorship of the proletariat” became the “dictatorship over the

proletariat”.

Still, it is hard not to agree with Mond that the socialist and labour

movement would be in a better position “had we listened to Bakunin

during the First International and followed a path of syndicalism”. So

why bother to seek in “syndicalism” an antidote to bureaucratic dangers

within Marxism? Why not simply embrace syndicalism? After all,

syndicalism became popular in part because Marxism – in its

Social-Democratic incarnation – proved to be the rule of party and union

officials within socialist and labour groupings.

Yes, by tracking down the pitifully few positive comments by Marx and

Engels on co-operatives and ignoring the lack of commitment to workers’

management in their most famous programmes, it could be possible to

present an image of them as advocates of “syndicalism”. However, this is

not convincing nor would it account for the systematic opposition of

most Marxist movements to such a vision. Given the Marxist prejudices in

favour of centralisation, the few scattered remarks of its founding

fathers will be of little use and, worse, counterproductive. As Mond

shows, they would blind those who invoke them to the dynamics produced

by their other, more representative, perspectives on State ownership and

central control.

This can be seen today when orthodox Marxists, rightly, label the market

socialists Proudhonists (which appears to be amongst the worst insults

any Marxist could call somebody). Perhaps, then, rather than seek to

cobble together a few scattered sentences into a quasi-coherent notion

which hides more than it exposes, can we not just admit that the

anarchists were right? That Marx, while he may have enriched socialism

by his (incomplete) analysis of capitalism, did not have a coherent

vision of a socialism that could work in practice?

Which, I think, explains this unconvincing attempt to link Marx and

syndicalism. Goldman long ago indicated how syndicalism was the only

alternative to the Bolshevik industrial State but she rightly saw the

latter as expressing Marxist ideology rather than the former.[14] Mond

suggests that “Marx was profoundly prophetic and correct in his analysis

of capitalism, its exploitation, and class struggle, with the

dialectically inevitable remedy of socialism as strikingly obvious

today”. Ignoring the ”dialectically inevitable remedy” comment for

obvious reasons, the question is, do we need Marx to provide an

“analysis of capitalism, its exploitation, and class struggle”? In terms

of the last, the answer is surely “no” as Marx argued that the class

struggle must move from the economic terrain onto the political, the net

effect of which was for the socialists who followed this advice to

become reformists. What of his “analysis of capitalism, its

exploitation”? This is less clear cut as he definitely made

contributions to this, but we must never forget that in 1867 he built

upon the foundations laid by Proudhon after mocking his analysis and

methodology in 1847.[15]

We must view Marx as we view others who enriched our understanding of

capitalism, whether socialists like Proudhon or those seeking to save

capitalism from itself like Keynes and Minsky. Once we do that, then

perhaps the socialist movement can escape the deadweight of the past

which seems to force some to link everything to Marx – even when trying

to save socialism from his legacy.

So, should we use syndicalism to save Marxism from itself? Why, when we

have anarchism?

[1] Iain McKay (2016), “Proudhon, Property and Possession”,

Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 66 (Winter). Available at:

anarchism.pageabode.com

[2] Bertell Ollman (1978), Social and Sexual Revolution: Essays on Marx

and Reich (Montreal: Black Rose Books), pp. 65–66.

[3] Bruno Jossa (2005), “Marx, Marxism and the cooperative movement”,

Cambridge Journal of Economics 29: 1, pp. 3–18.

[4] Maurice Brinton (2020), “The Bolsheviks and Workers’ Control”, in

David Goodway (ed.) For Workers’ Power: The Selected Writings of Maurice

Brinton (Edinburgh: AK Press).

[5] Ollman Bertell (ed.) (1998), Market Socialism: The Debate Among

Socialists (London: Routledge).

[6] On Wolff, see Iain McKay (2015), “Democracy At Work Review essay”,

Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 64/5 (Summer). Available at:

anarchism.pageabode.com

[7] See, see example, Karl Marx and Frederick Engels (1987), Marx &

Engels Collected Works Vol 25: Engels: Dialectics of Nature (London:

Lawrence & Wishart) pp. 294–295. For commentary, see Iain McKay (2018),

“David Harvey on Proudhon”, Anarchist Writers, 26^(th) November.

Available at:

anarchism.pageabode.com

[8] See Iain McKay (2017), “Proudhon’s Constituted Value and the Myth of

Labour Notes”, Anarchist Studies 25:1. Available at:

anarchism.pageabode.com

[9] Market socialist David Schweickart (1993) explores the difficulties

in any such referendum in his discussion of an early form of Parecon in

Against Capitalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 329–334.

[10] Peter Kropotkin (2014), “Message to the Workers of the Western

World”, in Iain McKay (ed.) Direct Struggle Against Capital: A Peter

Kropotkin Anthology (Edinburgh: AK Press), pp. 489–490.

[11] George Barrett (2019) sketches aspects of such a system in “The

Anarchist Revolution”, in Iain McKay (ed.) Our Masters are Helpless: The

Essays of George Barrett (London: Freedom Press), pp. 25–26.

[12] Errico Malatesta (1993) in Vernon Richards (ed.) Errico Malatesta:

His Life and Ideas (London: Freedom Press), p. 145.

[13] Emma Goldman (2017), My Disillusionment in Russia (London: Active

Distribution), pp. 62, 66, 67, 107. Also see her pamphlet “The Crushing

of the Russian Revolution” (2013) in Andrew Zonneveld (ed.) To Remain

Silent is Impossible: Emma Goldman and Alexander Berkman in Russia,

(Atlanta: On Our Own Authority!).

[14] Emma Goldman (2017), My Disillusionment in Russia (London: Active

Distribution), pp. 249–250.

[15] Iain McKay (2017), “The Poverty of (Marx’s) Philosophy”,

Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 70 (Summer). Available at:

anarchism.pageabode.com