đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș anarcho-on-saving-marxism-from-itself.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:24:26. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: On Saving Marxism From Itself Author: Anarcho Date: June 24, 2021 Language: en Topics: marxism, a response Source: Retrieved on 26th June 2021 from https://anarchism.pageabode.com/?p=2833
Anarchists, I hope, would read Mustapha Mondâs âA Brief Question of
Syndicalismâ with mixed feelings. On the one hand, it is always nice to
see other socialists apparently searching for common ground with their
libertarian âfrienemiesâ and implicitly admit that we were right. On the
other, there is a substantial element of wishful thinking about it which
limits its usefulness.
If syndicalism and its advocation of âworkersâ self-management,
organisation, direct action and unionisation in order to abolish the
capitalist orderâ has been âforgotten and stamped into tragic
irrelevanceâ then this, in part, was the product of the hostility of
Marxists â such as Lenin or Trotsky â who spent a great deal of time
attacking both it and workersâ self-management as âpetty bourgeoisâ.
Combined with the apparent âsuccessâ of the Russian Revolution which
drew many militants away from it (and the overt hostility of the new
Communist Parties) and the rise of fascism in many of its strongholds
(Italy, Portugal, Spain, etc.), syndicalism no longer had the influence
in after the Second World War as it had before the First.
The question arises as to why workersâ control was viewed as âpetty
bourgeoisâ and this takes us to the heart of the contradiction in Mondâs
suggestion that syndicalism is a cure for the ails of Marxist socialism.
This, in turn, breaks down into three sub-questions: what is
syndicalism? What is Marxist socialism? And, are both consistent with
each other?
Syndicalism is, I would suggest, a tactic to achieve socialism rather
than a vision of socialism. This explains why we find a range of people
â anarchists (mutualists, collectivists, communists and even a few
individualists) and Marxists (James Connolly and Daniel De Leon spring
to mind) â advocating it while having differing visions of a future
society. Yet almost all were agreed that âproletarian ownership of the
workplaceâ was not desired â ownership would be social but control of
production would rest in the producersâ hands. Ownership has to be
social so that anyone joining a workplace automatically becomes a member
of the association running it, otherwise a class of workers who happened
to be there when the workplace was first collectivised would employ
another class of workers as their wage-workers.[1]
Social ownership can take many forms. Marx and Engels, however,
continually stressed State ownership and rarely, if ever, mention
workersâ control of production. Rather, nationalisation â
âcentralisation ⊠in the hands of the Stateâ, to quote The Communist
Manifesto â is stressed, along with establishing âindustrial armiesâ
(quoting the Manifesto again). As Marxist Bertell Ollman admits:
Marxâs picture of life and organisation in the first stage of communism
is very incomplete. There is no discussion of such obviously important
developments as workersâ control. We can only guess how much power
workers enjoy in their enterprises.[2]
Compare this with Proudhonâs 1848 election manifesto and its call for a
federation of democratically-run workersâ associations. This explains
why, when it comes to showing that Marx favoured workersâ control, his
few positive comments on co-operatives are utilised.[3] Yet such
comments on co-operatives could fill, perhaps, a page, while Proudhonâs
include often extensive discussions over many books and articles from
1840 to 1865. In this, Bakunin and Kropotkin followed Proudhonâs lead
while Lenin paid only lip-service to (a very limited form of) workersâ
control in 1917 before quickly dropping it in favour of State control
and âdictatorialâ one-man management.[4]
This perspective drove the Bolshevikâs systematic undermining of the
factory committees after October within the centralised, statist
economic regime they created reflecting their vision of socialism. A key
part of this process was denunciation of the particularistic, parochial
interests which they claimed factory committees expressed, as reflected
in the âpetty-bourgeoisâ perspectives in the âanarchist utopiaâ of
socialism in one workplace. The economy, they claimed, was interlinked
and this required a central body to control it, reflecting the orthodox
interpretation of Marx and Engels then and now.
The idea that âsyndicalismâ â worker-owned and run workplaces â is
Marxist has been explored by Marxists for many years in their debates
over âmarket socialismâ.[5] Mond refers to âcontemporary theorist
Richard Wolffâ who advocates a market socialism based on co-operatives
which would, to use Mondâs words, âdirectly democratise the places in
which they work, and would grant them the ownership of the means of
production which has historically evaded them so heinously. It could be
the very essence of socialismâ.[6] Suffice to say, those who argue
against market socialism in favour of planning have little difficulty
proving their orthodoxy by means of numerous quotes from Marx and Engels
(that the market socialists have little difficulty showing that these
quotes are irrelevant for any real economy is equally true). With this
in mind, I turn to this comment by Mond:
Perhaps a syndicalist society is the one which most truly conforms to
the original conceptualisation of socialism by Marx, as it would
necessarily entail the means of production being directly in the hands
of the working classes, the proletarians, through worker co-operatives,
unions, boards and committees rather than in the hands of the state
through bureaucrats, autocrats, politicians and dictators. Historyâs
âsocialistâ experiments have too often resulted in the exaltation of
authoritarianism and a lack of direct democracy, handing the means of
production to the state as so-called âpublic ownershipâ rather than
directly to the people.
Yet handing the means of production to the State was precisely what Marx
and Engels (repeatedly) advocated. Only later, once classes had
disappeared, would society become one of âassociated producersâ. It is
in this context that we need to evaluate any positive comments by Marx
and Engels on co-operatives and how these contradict their wider views
of a socialist economy. This can be seen in The Civil War in France,
rightly considered Marxâs most appealing and libertarian work (for it is
mostly reporting on a libertarian influenced revolt which owed next to
nothing to Marxism). He praises the attempts at co-operative production
made during the Commune:
Yes, gentlemen, the Commune intended to abolish that class property
which makes the labour of the many the wealth of the few. It aimed at
the expropriation of the expropriators. It wanted to make individual
property a truth by transforming the means of production, land, and
capital, now chiefly the means of enslaving and exploiting labour, into
mere instruments of free and associated labour. But this is communism,
âimpossibleâ communism! (The Civil War in France)
So far this describes mutualism and collectivism rather than communism
(âimpossibleâ or not) given that Marx had not previously stressed
associations to run the means of production but rather concentrating
these âinto the hands of the Stateâ. After this somewhat disingenuous
assertion, he continues:
If co-operative production is not to remain a sham and a snare; if it is
to supersede the capitalist system; if united co-operative societies are
to regulate national production upon a common plan, thus taking it under
their own control, and putting an end to the constant anarchy and
periodical convulsions which are the fatality of capitalist production â
what else, gentlemen, would it be but communism, âpossibleâ communism?
Now we get to the uniquely Marxist vision, the need for âa common planâ
for ânational productionâ as the means of the workers âtaking it under
their own controlâ. There are numerous issues associated with national â
never mind international â planning which neither Marx nor Engels seemed
aware of. In their writing, the task of identifying, gathering,
processing and presenting the millions of inputs and outputs of any such
plan are either ignored or assumed to be a simple matter.[7] Marx, to
use a pertinent example, considered a few sentences on two workers
producing two goods as sufficient in his deeply dishonest polemic
against Proudhon, The Poverty of Philosophy.[8] While a âcommon planâ is
easy to envision with two inputs and two outputs, one involving millions
of products and producers is less so.
This, while important, should not distract us from the key contradiction
here â namely that such planning ends meaningful workersâ control at the
point of production.
Let us assume that all the informational, knowledge and processing
issues of planning the economic (and social) activities of millions of
people have been solved. A common plan has been somehow drawn up and
agreed by the people by referendum.[9] The task is now to implement it.
A plan â to qualify as such â has to have decided upon outputs and
inputs. To be coherent, this has to apply at every level otherwise the
agreed outputs cannot be delivered (we will ignore the question of
whether the implicit assumption of perfect foresight is feasible).Thus,
once a plan has been decided, each workplace has to be given its
allocated outputs to produce (and when to produce them) and informed of
which inputs they can expect (and when to expect them). If this is not
done, then there is no plan and no regulation of national production: a
âcommon planâ has to be a central plan.
This means that any âworkersâ controlâ or âeconomic democracyâ within a
given workplace would be within these tight constraints. Indeed, unless
the plan allows it, workers cannot even paint their cafeteria a
different colour (the volume of green paint would be determined by the
plan and so any such request would have to be pre-approved in order for
the correct inputs to be specified for the expected demand). Being one
vote in millions (billions!) would make the workplace a site of
alienation, albeit a different form than under capitalism. It would
mimic the same âdemocracyâ expressed in bourgeois elections to
parliament (albeit perhaps more often). As with centralised political
democracy, centralised economic democracy would not secure for people
meaningful control over their own lives, quite the reverse as the
conscious allocation of resources is also the conscious allocation of
work (consider the impact on âthe common planâ if people decide to
change jobs).
The orthodox Marxist argument against economic federalism and workplace
autonomy is, firstly, that workers would gain a narrow, proprietorial
interest and use whatever advantage they had against society as a whole.
Second, that there is a pressing need to coordinate economic activity to
ensure efficiency in identifying and achieving social goals. Third, that
within a market-socialist economy, there would be pressures from the
market which would force the workforce to cut conditions, increase the
hours and intensity of labour, etc. in order to survive (this is often
described by the somewhat self-contradictory terms âself-exploitationâ
and âself-managed capitalismâ).
The first issue is a potential danger but it ignores that the officials
at the top of the economy can also gain a narrow, proprietorial
interest, but over the whole economy. While the anti-social activities
of a few workplaces can easily be challenged by others, those of
bureaucrats are far harder to challenge.
The second is valid and explains why anarchists have never denied that a
complex economy is interlinked and needs appropriate federal bodies to
manage appropriate social needs. However, we are also aware that it is
precisely this complexity and interwovenness that means that no central
body â no matter how big or powerful â could manage it.[10] Autonomy is
needed precisely because of the numerous unexpected problems any real
economy would face, and to generate the essential information and
knowledge only free agreement exposes (and which is inevitably lost in
the aggregation needed for the plan).
The third is valid, but applies to mutualism rather than libertarian
communism and likewise ignores the threat implied by placing economic
decision making â and so power â into the hands of central bodies. The
challenge for libertarian communism is to secure meaningful workplace
autonomy and to coordinate diverse plans without the positive and
negative influences of markets.[11] This rejection of the centralisation
inherent to a âcommon planâ does not mean rejecting coordination, just
that this must be achieved by means of federalism for appropriate
activities and at appropriate levels.
Mond is right in a sense, for there is an overlap between market
socialists and their orthodox opponents. Market socialism becomes
acceptable for the latter during the âtransition periodâ immediately
after a revolution. Thus the market socialists are denounced as
advocating a utopian project due to the inherent incompatibility of
markets and socialism, and markets are recognised as an essential aspect
of the transitional economy: how being unworkable and a necessity is
left to the magic of dialectics to explain.
It is the mirror image of the Marxist position of the State. âYes, we
agree with you anarchists that the State is a horrible institution, and
we, too, want to get rid of itâ, Marxists say, âbut we need it for a
little while (with us in control of it, naturally) until it withers
awayâ. In this case, it is âYes, we agree with you anarchists that
workersâ control of workplaces is a vital institution which we support,
but only for a little while until capitalism withers awayâ. Yet the
withering away of workplace management occurs at the same time as the
State (allegedly) withers away, but the former requires a strengthening
of the very central power the latter suggests is disappearing.
Thus we have the paradoxical situation of the central authority both
withering away and expanding its control over the economy (and so
society). This is resolved by suggesting that, as classes disappear, so
does the State, but this is simply due to the way the latter is defined.
Indeed, no class exists which âownsâ the means of production, but as
economic decision making becomes increasingly centralised as part of the
process of creating âthe common planâ, a new class which controls the
means of production, the labour process and the output develops. We are
assured this is not a State because it is merely administering things,
but this is not so:
Engels ⊠was merely playing with words. Whoever has power over things
has power over men; whoever governs production also governs the
producers; who determines consumption is master over the consumer.
This is the question; either things are administered on the basis of
free agreement among the interested parties, and this is anarchy; or
they are administered according to laws made by administrators and this
is government, it is the State, and inevitably it turns out to be
tyrannical.[12]
Thus it was not, as Mond suggests, an âunwillingness to lend more direct
control to the workersâ that âled to paradoxically renewed class
antagonisms: an irreconcilable friction between workers and
bureaucratsâ. Rather, it was the contradiction between the
decentralising and decentring of power required for meaningful workersâ
management of production and the centralising and centring of power
required for âa common planâ. As the State gathers to itself and
centralises more and more economic functions, it does not become less
and less a State, because while existing classes may steadily disappear
as a result of this process, the empowering of a centralised structure
with more and more functions creates a new ruling class (the working
class returns to its place as order-takers after a brief moment of
economic freedom). This can only be viewed as the withering away of the
State if we assume, as Marxism does, that ownership alone creates
classes.
From an anarchist perspective, while the former class division between
capitalist and proletarian may, indeed, disappear, a new one between
bureaucrat and proletariat grows. There is nothing paradoxical about it
at all, which Mond seems to recognise:
These failures of history were due to the fact that state-monopolised
property is simply Bourgeoisie property in new clothing ⊠Private
property has never truly been abolished and entrusted to the
proletarians directly, yet this is what syndicalism would achieve.
Yet here he merely echoes Proudhonâs critique of what he termed
âCommunityâ (usually somewhat inaccurately translated as âcommunismâ) in
What is Property? that the âmembers of a community, it is true, have no
private property; but the community is proprietor, and proprietor not
only of the goods, but of the persons and willsâ. While capitalism
divided ownership and use, Community (State socialism) saw ownership and
use undivided and both resulted in exploitation and oppression. The
USSR, Cuba. China, etc. prove the validity of this analysis.
So these arguments are hardly original. Bakunin sketched them in his
conflict with Marx in the International. Yet Mond still suggests that
âMarx once wrote that the dictatorship of the proletariat âbegins with
the self-government of the communeâ. That is to say such a dictatorship
would be a bottom-up system of direct democracy, rather than top-down
controlâ. The irony here is that Mond is quoting Marx from his marginal
notes to Bakuninâs Statism and Anarchy which dismissed, to quote Mond,
Bakuninâs âprediction that Marxism would lead to a new despotic âred
bureaucracyâ, more dictatorial than a capitalist system, played out
through history as if prophecyâ.
As such, it is bizarre to see Marxâs marginal notes on Bakunin quoted as
if it were an irrelevance that every Marxist revolution (indeed, every
Marxist movement) has seen the rise of a new class of rulers within it.
Yes, indeed, Marx did proclaim that the so-called dictatorship of the
proletariat âbegins with the self-government of the communeâ yet this
has never come to pass â for precisely the reason Bakunin sketches but
which Marx clearly does not understand. Surely, the experience of over
one hundred and fifty years of an ideologyâs practice should count more
than mere words? Mond does mention this sorry history when he admits:
It has been evident in the USSR, Cuba, China and other nations, that
once a new elite had established power, there was a lack of motivation
to move beyond the dictatorship of the proletariat. This eventually
resulted in the creation of, as Trotsky termed it, âdegenerated workersâ
statesâ.
Yet the new elite âestablished powerâ in the USSR when Trotsky was in
charge â as experienced by Emma Goldman in 1920 â and while he viewed it
as a âworkersâ stateâ in spite of party dictatorship and one-man
management in production. The formation of this new class, as Goldman
also explained, was a direct product of the Bolshevik vision of
socialism based on nationalisation and centralisation â and the millions
of bureaucrats this generated.[13] Of course, many Marxists â like
Ollman â suggest that Russia cannot be used to draw any conclusions
about Marxism due to its economic backwardness but that seems to forget
that Marx was without telephones â never mind computers! â when he put
pen to paper. Given this, I would suggest that âthe concept of
syndicalismâ is âdependent on the absence of a stateâ, if by syndicalism
it is meant meaningful workersâ control: any centralised economic body
would systematically undermine it by its very nature.
Yet we must never forget that powerful role the term âtransitionâ plays
in Marxist ideology. This allows Marxists to claim that Marxism is
âanti-Stateâ while, simultaneously, arguing for the necessity to build a
new State. Thus âsyndicalistâ self-management of production can be
simultaneously opposed and supported depending upon whether we are
talking about the transitional period or not. Yet the direction is clear
â the aim is to move away from such workersâ management and towards
central regulation and control.
All too often, anarchist criticism of Marxism is dismissed as sectarian
(although that does not stop other Marxists, usually of the same group,
writing disgracefully inaccurate attacks on anarchism). No matter, for
we should be proud of the fact we correctly predicted the fate of
Marxism. Yes, social democracy became as reformist as Bakunin predicted.
Yes, State Socialism simply replaced the boss by the bureaucrat as
Proudhon predicted. Whether economically or politically, the
âdictatorship of the proletariatâ became the âdictatorship over the
proletariatâ.
Still, it is hard not to agree with Mond that the socialist and labour
movement would be in a better position âhad we listened to Bakunin
during the First International and followed a path of syndicalismâ. So
why bother to seek in âsyndicalismâ an antidote to bureaucratic dangers
within Marxism? Why not simply embrace syndicalism? After all,
syndicalism became popular in part because Marxism â in its
Social-Democratic incarnation â proved to be the rule of party and union
officials within socialist and labour groupings.
Yes, by tracking down the pitifully few positive comments by Marx and
Engels on co-operatives and ignoring the lack of commitment to workersâ
management in their most famous programmes, it could be possible to
present an image of them as advocates of âsyndicalismâ. However, this is
not convincing nor would it account for the systematic opposition of
most Marxist movements to such a vision. Given the Marxist prejudices in
favour of centralisation, the few scattered remarks of its founding
fathers will be of little use and, worse, counterproductive. As Mond
shows, they would blind those who invoke them to the dynamics produced
by their other, more representative, perspectives on State ownership and
central control.
This can be seen today when orthodox Marxists, rightly, label the market
socialists Proudhonists (which appears to be amongst the worst insults
any Marxist could call somebody). Perhaps, then, rather than seek to
cobble together a few scattered sentences into a quasi-coherent notion
which hides more than it exposes, can we not just admit that the
anarchists were right? That Marx, while he may have enriched socialism
by his (incomplete) analysis of capitalism, did not have a coherent
vision of a socialism that could work in practice?
Which, I think, explains this unconvincing attempt to link Marx and
syndicalism. Goldman long ago indicated how syndicalism was the only
alternative to the Bolshevik industrial State but she rightly saw the
latter as expressing Marxist ideology rather than the former.[14] Mond
suggests that âMarx was profoundly prophetic and correct in his analysis
of capitalism, its exploitation, and class struggle, with the
dialectically inevitable remedy of socialism as strikingly obvious
todayâ. Ignoring the âdialectically inevitable remedyâ comment for
obvious reasons, the question is, do we need Marx to provide an
âanalysis of capitalism, its exploitation, and class struggleâ? In terms
of the last, the answer is surely ânoâ as Marx argued that the class
struggle must move from the economic terrain onto the political, the net
effect of which was for the socialists who followed this advice to
become reformists. What of his âanalysis of capitalism, its
exploitationâ? This is less clear cut as he definitely made
contributions to this, but we must never forget that in 1867 he built
upon the foundations laid by Proudhon after mocking his analysis and
methodology in 1847.[15]
We must view Marx as we view others who enriched our understanding of
capitalism, whether socialists like Proudhon or those seeking to save
capitalism from itself like Keynes and Minsky. Once we do that, then
perhaps the socialist movement can escape the deadweight of the past
which seems to force some to link everything to Marx â even when trying
to save socialism from his legacy.
So, should we use syndicalism to save Marxism from itself? Why, when we
have anarchism?
[1] Iain McKay (2016), âProudhon, Property and Possessionâ,
Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 66 (Winter). Available at:
[2] Bertell Ollman (1978), Social and Sexual Revolution: Essays on Marx
and Reich (Montreal: Black Rose Books), pp. 65â66.
[3] Bruno Jossa (2005), âMarx, Marxism and the cooperative movementâ,
Cambridge Journal of Economics 29: 1, pp. 3â18.
[4] Maurice Brinton (2020), âThe Bolsheviks and Workersâ Controlâ, in
David Goodway (ed.) For Workersâ Power: The Selected Writings of Maurice
Brinton (Edinburgh: AK Press).
[5] Ollman Bertell (ed.) (1998), Market Socialism: The Debate Among
Socialists (London: Routledge).
[6] On Wolff, see Iain McKay (2015), âDemocracy At Work Review essayâ,
Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 64/5 (Summer). Available at:
[7] See, see example, Karl Marx and Frederick Engels (1987), Marx &
Engels Collected Works Vol 25: Engels: Dialectics of Nature (London:
Lawrence & Wishart) pp. 294â295. For commentary, see Iain McKay (2018),
âDavid Harvey on Proudhonâ, Anarchist Writers, 26^(th) November.
Available at:
[8] See Iain McKay (2017), âProudhonâs Constituted Value and the Myth of
Labour Notesâ, Anarchist Studies 25:1. Available at:
[9] Market socialist David Schweickart (1993) explores the difficulties
in any such referendum in his discussion of an early form of Parecon in
Against Capitalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 329â334.
[10] Peter Kropotkin (2014), âMessage to the Workers of the Western
Worldâ, in Iain McKay (ed.) Direct Struggle Against Capital: A Peter
Kropotkin Anthology (Edinburgh: AK Press), pp. 489â490.
[11] George Barrett (2019) sketches aspects of such a system in âThe
Anarchist Revolutionâ, in Iain McKay (ed.) Our Masters are Helpless: The
Essays of George Barrett (London: Freedom Press), pp. 25â26.
[12] Errico Malatesta (1993) in Vernon Richards (ed.) Errico Malatesta:
His Life and Ideas (London: Freedom Press), p. 145.
[13] Emma Goldman (2017), My Disillusionment in Russia (London: Active
Distribution), pp. 62, 66, 67, 107. Also see her pamphlet âThe Crushing
of the Russian Revolutionâ (2013) in Andrew Zonneveld (ed.) To Remain
Silent is Impossible: Emma Goldman and Alexander Berkman in Russia,
(Atlanta: On Our Own Authority!).
[14] Emma Goldman (2017), My Disillusionment in Russia (London: Active
Distribution), pp. 249â250.
[15] Iain McKay (2017), âThe Poverty of (Marxâs) Philosophyâ,
Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 70 (Summer). Available at: