💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-the-left-that-was.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:35:05. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Left That Was
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: 22 May 1991
Language: en
Topics: the left, social ecology
Source: http://social-ecology.org/wp/1991/04/the-left-that-was-a-personal-reflection/

Murray Bookchin

The Left That Was

I would like to recall a Left That Was–an idealistic, often

theoretically coherent Left that militantly emphasized its

internationalism, its rationality in its treatment of reality, its

democratic spirit, and its vigorous revolutionary aspirations. From a

retrospective viewpoint of a hundred years or so, it is easy to find

many failings in the Left That Was: I have spent much of my own life

criticizing the Left’s failings (as I saw them) and many of its

premises, such as its emphasis on the historical primacy of economic

factors (although this fault can be overstated by ignoring its social

idealism), its fixation on the proletariat as a “hegemonic” class, and

its failure to understand the problems raised by status hierarchy and

domination.

But the Left That Was–the Left of the nineteenth and early twentieth

century–did not have our devastating experiences with Bolshevism and

particularly Stalinism to correct its weaknesses. It developed in a time

of a rising mass movement of working people–a proletariat, in

particular–that had not gained anything from the democratic revolutions

of the past (as had the peasantry). The Left That Was, nonetheless, had

features that should be regarded as imperishable for any movement that

seeks to create a better world–a rich generosity of spirit, a commitment

to a humane world, a rare degree of political independence, a vibrant

revolutionary spirit, and an unwavering opposition to capitalism. These

attributes were characteristics of the Left That Was, by which I mean

not the Leninist “Old Left” or the Maoist “New Left” that followed, but

traditional ideas underlying the Left as such. They defined the Left and

distinguished it from liberalism, progressivism, reformism, and the

like.

My concern, here, is that these attributes are fading rapidly from the

present-day Left. The Left today has withdrawn into a strident form of

nationalism and statism, presumably in the interests of “national

liberation”; an inchoate nihilism, presumably under the aegis of

postmodernism; and an ethnic parochialism, presumably in the name of

fighting racial discrimination. New versions of nationalism, a lack of

concern for democracy, and a fragmenting sectorialism and parochialism

abound. Dogmatism and moral intimidation have turned this sectorialism

and parochialism into a whiplash, one that silences all analyses that go

beyond mere bumper-sticker slogans.

Too many careers and reputations are being made by many “leaders” in the

present-day Left through shrill voices rather than clear insights. Their

sloganeering has no content, and their verbiage offers little

understanding of the fact that we are all ultimately one community of

human beings, and that we can transcend the mere conditioned reflexes

that undermine our commitment to mutual recognition and care for each

other as well as the planet. I am not speaking of a New Age “oneness”

that ignores basic class, status, and ethnic divisions in present-day

society, divisions that must be resolved by radical social change. I am

discussing the failure of today’s Left to establish any affinity with a

humane Left That Was, one that celebrated our potential for creating a

shared humanity and civilization.

I realize only too well that these remarks will be viewed by many

contemporary leftists as unsatisfactory. But in the Left That Was, the

working class was at least seen (however erroneously) as the “non-class

class”–that is, as a particular class that was obliged by inherent

tendencies in capitalism to express the universal interests of humanity

as well as its potentiality to create a rational society. This notion at

least assumed that there were universal human interests that could be

substantiated and realized under socialism, communism, or anarchism.

Today’s Left is “deconstructing” this appeal to universality to a point

where it denies its validity and opposes reason itself on the basis that

it is purely analytical and “unfeeling.” What has been carried over to

our time from the sixties is a basically uncritical assortment of narrow

interests–and, one is obliged to add, alluring university careers–that

have reduced universalistic to particularistic concerns. The great ideal

of an emancipated humanity–hopefully one in harmony with nonhuman

nature–has been steadily eroded by particularistic claims to hegemonic

roles for gender-biased, ethnic-biased, and other like tendencies.

These tendencies threaten to turn the Left back to a more parochial,

exclusionary, and ironically, more hierarchical past insofar as one

group, whether alone or in concert with others, affirms its superior

qualifications to lead society and guide movements for social change.

What many Leftists today are destroying is a great tradition of human

solidarity and a belief in the potentiality for humanness, one that

transcends nationality, ethnicity, gender differences, and a politics of

hegemonic superiority.

I cannot hope to deal here with all the details of the social idealism,

humanism, and drive for theoretical coherence that made the Left That

Was so different from the pap leftism that exists today. Instead, I

should like to focus on the internationalist and confederalist

tendencies, the democratic spirit, the antimilitarism, and the rational

secularism that distinguished it from other political and social

movements of our period.

Internationalism, Nationalism, and Confederation

The nationalism that permeates much of the Left of the eighties and

nineties (often in the name of “national liberation”) was largely alien

to the far-seeing Leftists of the last century and the early part of the

present one. In using the word Left, I am drawing from the language of

the French Revolution of 1789–94 so that I can include various types of

anarchist as well as socialist thought. The Left That Was not only

established its pedigree in the French Revolution but defined itself in

opposition to that revolution’s shortcomings, such as the Jacobin

message of “patriotism” (although even this “nationalistic” notion had

its roots in the belief that France belonged to its people rather than

to the King of France–who was obliged to change his title to the King of

the French after 1789 as a result).

Repelled by the references of the French revolutionaries to la patrie,

the Left That Was generally came to regard nationalism as a regressive,

indeed, as a divisive force that separated human from human by creating

national boundaries. The Left That Was saw all national boundaries as

the barbed wire that compartmentalized human beings by dividing them

according to particularistic loyalties and commitments that obscured the

domination of all oppressed people by ruling strata.

To Marx and Engels, the subjugated of the world had no country. They had

only their international solidarity to sustain them, their unity as a

class that was historically destined to remove class society as such.

Hence the ringing conclusion of The Communist Manifesto: “Working Men of

All Countries, Unite!” And in the body of that work (which the anarchist

Mikhail Bakunin translated into Russian), we are told: “In the national

struggles of the proletarians of different countries, [Communists] point

out and bring to the front the common interests of the entire

proletariat, independently of all nationality.”

Further, the Manifesto declares, “The working men have no country. We

cannot take away from them what they have not got.” To the extent that

Marx and Engels did give their support to some national liberation

struggles, it was largely from their concerns about matters of

geopolitics and economics or even for sentimental reasons, as in the

case of Ireland, rather than principle. They supported the Polish

national movement, for example, primarily because they wanted to weaken

the Russian Empire, which in their day was the supreme

counterrevolutionary power on the European continent. And they wished to

see a united Germany, arguing (very wrongly, in my view) that the

nation-state was desirable in providing the best arena for the

development of capitalism, which they regarded as historically

progressive (again wrongly, in my view). But never did they impute any

virtues to nationalism as an end in itself.

Specifically, it was Frederick Engels, a popularizer and also a

vulgarizer of Marx’s thought, who regarded the nation-state as “the

normal political constitution of the European bourgeoisie” in a letter

to Karl Kautsky, barely a month before the physically debilitated Marx

died. Dealing as it did with Poland’s struggle for independence from

Russia, Engels’s letter advanced what Paul Nettl has called a “narrow

preoccupation” with the “resurrection” of the country. This letter later

created a great deal of mischief in the Marxist movement: it provided

self-proclaimed Marxist parties like the German Social-Democratic Party

with an excuse to support their own country in August 1914, which

subsequently destroyed proletarian internationalism during World War I.

But even within the Marxist movement, Engels’s “narrow preoccupation”

with nationalism did not go unchallenged in the pre-1914 era. Rosa

Luxemburg’s refusal to bow to nationalist tendencies in the Polish

Socialist Party was of outstanding importance in perpetuating the

internationalist legacy of socialism–she was no less a leading voice in

that party than she was in the German Social-Democratic Party and the

Second International generally. Her general views were consistently

revolutionary: the socialist ideal of achieving a common humanity, she

held, was incompatible with nationalist parochialism. As early as 1908,

Luxemburg wrote:

Speaking of the right of nations to self-determination we dispense with

the idea of a nation as a whole. It becomes merely a social and

political unity [for the purposes of measurement]. But it was just this

concept of nations as one of the categories of bourgeois ideology that

Marxist theory attacked most fiercely, pointing out under slogans like

“national self-determination” or “freedom of the citizen,” “equality

before the law”–there lurks all the time a twisted and limited meaning.

In a society based on classes, the nation as a uniform social-political

whole simply does not exist. Instead, there exists within each nation

classes with antagonistic interests and “rights.” There is literally no

social arena–from the strongest material relationship to the most subtle

moral one–in which the possessing classes and a self-conscious

proletariat could take one and the same position and figure as one

undifferentiated national whole. [emphasis added]

She expressed these views most sharply with reference to the Russian,

Ottoman, Austro-Hungarian, and other empires of the day, and she gained

a sizable number of supporters in the socialist movement as a whole. As

it turned out, I may note, Luxemburg was bitterly opposed on this point

by two of the most insipid vulgarizers of Marx’s theories–Karl Kautsky

of the German Social-Democratic Party and George Plekhanov of the

Russian Social-Democratic Party, not to speak of activists like Josef

Pilsudski, of the Polish Socialist Party, who was to become the

notorious “strongman” of Poland during the interwar period. It was

Lenin, in particular, who supported “national struggles” largely for

opportunistic reasons and for notions that stem from Engels’s view of

the nation-state as historically “progressive.”

Anarchists were even more hostile than many Marxist socialists in their

opposition to nationalism. Anarchist theorists and activists opposed the

formation of nation-states everywhere in the world, a view that placed

them politically far in advance of the Marxists. Any approval of the

nation-state, much less a centralized entity of any kind, ran contrary

to anarchist anti-statism and its commitment to a universalized

conception of humanity.

Bakunin’s views on the subject of nationalism were very forthright.

Without denying the right of every cultural group, indeed the “smallest

folk-unit,” to enjoy the freedom to exercise its own rights as a

community, he warned:

We should place human, universal justice above all national interests.

And we should abandon the false principle of nationality, invented of

late by the despots of France, Russia, and Prussia for the purpose of

crushing the sovereign principle of liberty.... Everyone who sincerely

wishes peace and international justice, should once and for all renounce

the glory, the might, and the greatness of the Fatherland, should

renounce all egoistic and vain interests of patriotism.

In sharp opposition to the state’s pre-emption of societal functions of

coordination, anarchist theorists advanced the fundamental notion of

confederation, in which communes or municipalities in various regions

could freely unite by means of recallable delegates. The functions of

these confederal delegates were strictly administrative. Policy-making

was to be left to the communes or municipalities themselves (although

there was no clear agreement among anarchists on how the decision-making

process was to function).

Nor was confederalism–as an alternative to nationalism and statism–a

purely theoretical construct. Historically, confederalism and statism

had been in conflict with each other for centuries. This conflict

reached back to the distant past, but it erupted very sharply throughout

the era of the democratic and proletarian revolutions, notably in the

new United States during the 1780s, in France in 1793 and 1871, in

Russia in 1921, and in the Mediterranean countries, notably Italy and

Spain, in the nineteenth century–and again in Spain during the

revolution of 1936.

In fact, Spanish anarchism, the largest of the anarchist movements in

Europe, flatly opposed Catalan nationalism despite the fact that its

largest following by the 1930s was recruited from the Catalan

proletariat. So uncompromising were anarchist attempts to foster

internationalism that clubs were formed everywhere among the Spanish

anarchists to promote the use of Esperanto as a worldwide means of

communication. Far more ethical than even Luxemburg, anarchists

generally raised so-called “abstract rights” that were anchored in

humanity’s universality and solidarity, a vision that stood opposed to

the institutional and ideological particularism that divided human from

human.

The Commitment to Democracy

The Left That Was viewed any abridgment of free expression as abhorrent

and reactionary. With few exceptions (Lenin’s views are a case in

point), the entire Left of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries

was nourished by the ideals of “popular rule” and the radicalization of

democracy, often in sharp reaction to the authoritarian rule that had

marked the Jacobin phase of the French Revolution. (The word democracy,

I should note, varied greatly in its meaning, ranging from free

expression and assembly under republican institutions—the common

socialist view–to face-to-face democracy–the common anarchist view.)

Even Marx and Engels, who were by no means democrats in the sense of

being committed to face-to-face democracy, wrote in The Communist

Manifesto that “to raise the proletariat to the position of ruling class

[is] to win the battle for democracy”–a clear avowal that “bourgeois

democracy” was flawed in its scope and ideals. Indeed, the elimination

of classes and class rule by the proletariat was expected to yield “an

association, in which the free development of each is the free

development of all”–an avowal that literally became a slogan comparable

to “Working Men of All Countries, Unite!” and that persisted well into

the Left of the 1930s.

As a Marxist, Luxemburg never strayed from this 1848 vision. In fact,

her vision of revolution was integrally bound up with a proletariat that

in her eyes was not only prepared to take power but was acutely

knowledgeable of its humanistic task through experience and the

give-and-take of free discussion. Hence her firm belief that revolution

would be the work not of a party but of the proletariat itself. The role

of the party, in effect, was to educate, not to command. In her critique

of the Bolshevik Revolution, written only six months before she was

murdered in the aftermath of the failed Spartacist uprising of January

1919, Luxemburg declared:

Freedom only for the supporters of the [Bolshevik] government, only for

the members of one party–however numerous they may be–is no freedom at

all. Freedom is always and exclusively freedom for the one who thinks

differently. Not because of any fanatical conception of “justice” but

because all that is instructive, wholesome, and purifying in political

freedom depends on this essential characteristic and its effectiveness

vanishes when “freedom” becomes a special privilege.

Despite her support of the Russian Revolution, Luxemburg lashed out at

Lenin over this issue as early as 1918 in the harshest terms:

Lenin is completely mistaken in the means he employs. Decree,

dictatorial force of the factory overseer, draconian penalties, rule by

terror, all these things are but palliatives. The only way to rebirth is

the school of public life itself, the most unlimited, the broadest

democracy and public opinion. It is rule by terror which demoralizes.

And with very rare prescience for that time in the revolutionary

movement, she warned that the proletarian dictatorship reduced to a mere

elite would result in a “brutalization of public life,” such as

ultimately did occur under Stalinist rule.

With the repression of political life in the land as a whole, life in

the Soviets must also become crippled.... life dies out in every public

institution, becomes a mere semblance of life, in which only the

bureaucracy remains as the active element.

For the anarchists, democracy had a less formal and more substantive

meaning. Bakunin, who was presumably contrasting his views with

Rousseau’s abstract conception of the citizen, declared:

No, I have in mind only liberty worthy of that name, liberty consisting

in the full development of all the material, intellectual, and moral

powers latent in every man; a liberty which does not recognize any other

restrictions but those which are traced by the laws of our own nature,

which, properly speaking, is tantamount to saying that there are no

restrictions at all, since these laws are not imposed upon us by some

outside legislator standing above us or alongside us. Those laws are

immanent, inherent in us; they constitute the very basis of our being,

material as well as intellectual and moral; and instead of finding in

them a limit to our liberty we should regard them as its real conditions

and as its effective reason.

Bakunin’s “liberty,” in effect, is the fulfillment of humanity’s

potentiality and immanent tendency to achieve realization in an

anarchist society. Accordingly, this “liberty ... far from finding

itself checked by the freedom of others, is, on the contrary confirmed

by it.” Still further: “We understand by freedom from the positive point

of view, the development, as complete as possible, of all faculties

which man has within himself, and, from the negative point of view, the

independence of the will of everyone from the will of others.”

Antimilitarism and Revolution

The Left That Was contained many pacifists, but its most radical

tendencies eschewed nonviolence and committed themselves to

antimilitarism rather than pacifism as a social as well as a combative

issue. In their view, militarism implied a regimented society, a

subordination of democratic rights in crisis situations such as war or,

for that matter, revolution. Militarism inculcated obedience in the

masses and conditioned them to the imperatives of a command society.

But what the Left That Was demanded was not the symbolic image of the

“broken rifle”–so very much in vogue these days in pacifist

boutiques–but the training and arming of the people for revolutionary

ends, solely in the form of democratic militias. A resolution

co-authored by Luxemburg and Lenin (a rare event) and adopted by the

Second International in 1906 declared that it “sees in the democratic

organization of the army, in the popular militia instead of the standing

army, an essential guarantee for the prevention of aggressive wars, and

for facilitating the removal of differences between nations.”

This was not simply an antiwar resolution, although opposition to the

war that was fast approaching was the principal focus of the statement.

The arming of the people was a basic tenet of the Left That Was, and

pious demands for gun control among today’s leftists would have been

totally alien to the thinking of the Left That Was. As recently as the

1930s, the concept of “the people in arms” remained a basic tenet of

independent socialist, not to speak of anarchist, movements throughout

the world, including those of the United States, as I myself so well

remember. The notion of schooling the masses in reliance on the police

and army for public safety, much less of turning the other cheek in the

face of violence, would have been regarded as heinous.

Not surprisingly, revolutionary anarchists were even less ambiguous than

socialists. In contrast to the state-controlled militia that the Second

International was prepared to accept in the 1906 resolution cited above,

the anarchists sought the direct arming of the masses. In Spain, weapons

were supplied to anarchist militants from the very inception of the

movement. The workers and peasants relied on themselves, not on the

largesse of statist institutions, to obtain the means for insurrection.

Just as their notion of democracy meant direct democracy, so their

notion of antimilitarism meant that they had to countervail the state’s

monopoly of violence with an armed popular movement–not merely a

state-subsidized militia.

Secularism and Rationalism

It remains to add that anarchists and to a great extent the

revolutionary socialists of the Left That Was not only tried to speak in

the general interests of humanity but abjured any body of ideas and

prejudices that denied humanity its naturalistic place in the scheme of

things. They regarded the worship of deities as a form of subjugation to

creations of human making, as the masking of reality by illusion, and as

the manipulation of human fears, alienation, and anomie by calculated

elites in behalf of an oppressive social order. Generally, the Left That

Was boldly laid claim to the rationalist heritage of the Enlightenment

and the French Revolution, however much this saddled the Marxists with

mechanistic ideas. But also, organic forms of reason, borrowed from

Hegel, competed with mechanism and conventional empiricism. Where

intuitional notions competed with materialist ones among anarchists,

they attracted a sizable body of artists to the anarchist movements of

the past, or to anarchist ideas. Additionally, rationalism did not crowd

out emotive approaches that fostered a highly moral socialism that was

often indistinguishable from libertarian outlooks. But almost every

attempt apart from certain individual exceptions was made to place

mechanistic, organic, and emotive approaches to reality in a rational

framework–notably, to achieve a coherent approach to social analysis and

change.

That this endeavor led to disparate tendencies in the Left That Was

should not surprise us. But the notion of a rational society achieved by

rational as well as moral means and idealistic sentiments formed a

unifying outlook for the Left That Was. Few leftists would have accepted

William Blake’s notion of reason as “meddlesome” or current postmodern

views of coherence as “totalitarian.”

The Left That Was was divided over the question of whether there could

be a peaceful, indeed reformistic, evolution of capitalism into

socialism or whether an insurrectionary break with the capitalist system

was unavoidable. The wariness of the Left That Was toward reforms can

perhaps best be seen in the fact that years ago, serious debates

occurred among Western leftists of all kinds on whether they should

fight for the eight-hour day, which many thought would make capitalism

more palatable to the working class. In Tsarist Russia, the Left

seriously debated whether their organizations should try to alleviate

famine conditions among the peasantry lest their charitable efforts

deflect the anger of the peasantry away from Tsarism.

But however serious those differences were, attempts at reform for its

own sake were never part of leftist ideology. The revolutionary

Left–which truly defined socialist and anarchist movements as a

Left–certainly did not want to improve the capitalist system, much less

give it a “human face.” “Capitalism with a human face” was an expression

they would have regarded as a contradiction in terms. The Left That Was

hoped to overthrow capitalism and initiate a radically new social

system, not to rationalize the existing order and make it acceptable to

the masses.

To participate in struggles for reforms was seen as a means to educate

the masses, not a way to dole out charity or improve their material lot.

Demands for reforms were always permeated by the broader message that

fundamental social reconstruction was needed. The fight for the

eight-hour day, years ago, and strikes for better living conditions, not

to speak of legislative improvements for working people, were seen as

means for mobilizing the oppressed, for engaging them in struggles, and

for disclosing the limits–and basic irrationalism–of capitalism, not

simply or even significantly as a means for bettering life under

capitalism. It was not until a later day that reforms were advocated by

so-called leftist parties, candidates, deputies, and humane devotees of

the working class, the poor, and the elderly as techniques for

“humanizing” capitalism or rendering leftist candidates more popular–and

electable for public office.

To ask for improved working and living conditions was seen as a way of

directly challenging the “wage system” and the sovereignty of capital.

Even so-called “evolutionary” or “reformist” socialists who hoped to

ease from capitalism into socialism were revolutionary in the sense that

they believed capitalism had to be replaced by a radically new social

order. Their conflicts with the revolutionary socialists and anarchists

in the Left That Was centered on whether capitalism could be replaced by

piecemeal changes, not on whether it could be given a “human face.” The

First World War and particularly the revolutions that followed it left

reformist socialism in debris—but it also produced a Left that radically

departed in many of its basic tenets from the Left That Was.

The First World War and Bolshevism

The outbreak of the First World War, the Bolshevik revolution of 1917,

and the murder of Rosa Luxemburg and Karl Liebknecht in the Spartacus

League uprising of January 1919 (a drawing of socialist blood that

occurred with the indirect assent of the official German Social

Democrats) opened a major breach in the history of the Left generally.

At the outbreak of the war, nearly all the socialist parties of warring

Europe succumbed to nationalism, and their parliamentary fractions voted

to give war credits to their respective capitalist states. Nor did the

attitudes of certain leading anarchists, including Kropotkin, prove to

be more honorable than those of the “social patriots,” to use Lenin’s

epithet for the German and French socialist leaders who supported one or

another camp in the war.

To analyze the reasons why this breach was opened in the Left That Was

would require a study in itself. But the Bolshevik seizure of power in

November 1917 did not close the breach. Quite to the contrary–it widened

it, not only because of the unavoidable polarization of Bolshevism

against Social Democracy but because of the authoritarian elements that

had always formed a part of the highly conspiratorial Russian

revolutionary movement. The Bolshevik party had little commitment to

popular democracy. Lenin had never viewed “bourgeois democracy” as

anything more than an instrument that could be used or discarded as

expediency required. Many demands were placed on the largely Bolshevik

regime that was formed in November (it initially included Left Social

Revolutionaries as well): the advancing German army on the eastern

front, the incredibly savage civil war that followed the Revolution, the

isolation of the Bolsheviks from the workers and peasants in the early

1920s, and the attempt by the Kronstadt sailors to recover a soviet

democracy that had been effaced by the bureaucratic Bolshevik party.

These demands combined to bring out the worst features of Lenin’s

centralist views and his opportunistic views of democracy. Beginning in

the early twenties, all affiliates of the Communist International were

“Bolshevized” by Zinoviev and his Stalinist successors, until the

commitment of socialism to democracy was marginalized and largely faded

in the Communist parties of the world.

No less important in undermining the Left That Was were the various

myths, popularized by Lenin, that capitalism had entered a unique,

indeed “final” stage of its development, a stage marked by “imperialism”

and worldwide “struggles for national liberation.” Here, again, Lenin’s

position is too complex to be dealt with cursorily; but what is

important is that the traditional internationalism that had marked the

Left That Was increasingly gave way to an emphasis on “national

liberation” struggles, partly for the purpose of weakening Western

imperialism, and partly to foster economic development in colonized

countries, thereby bringing the domestic class conflict within these

countries to the top of their national agendas.

The Bolsheviks did not abandon the rhetoric of internationalism, to be

sure, any more than the Social Democrats did. But “national liberation”

struggles (which the Bolsheviks largely honored in the breach at home,

after they took power in the newly formed Soviet Union) uncritically

fostered a commitment by the Left to the formation of new nation-states.

Nationalism increasingly came to the foreground of socialist theory and

practice. It is not surprising that the first “People’s Commissar of

Nationalities” in the new Soviet Union was Joseph Stalin, who later

fostered this nationalistic trend in Marxism-Leninism and who during and

after the Second World War gave it a distinctly “patriotic” quality in

the USSR. Expressions claiming that the Soviet Union was the “fatherland

of the working class” were ubiquitous among Communists of the interwar

period, and their parties were modeled on the centralized Bolshevik

Party to allow for Stalin’s blatant interference in their affairs.

By 1936, the politics of the Communist International (or what remained

of it) had veered sharply away from the ideals that had once guided the

Left That Was. Luxemburg, honored more as a martyr than as a theorist,

was discredited by the Stalinist cabal or totally ignored. The Second

International was essentially moribund. Idealism began to give way to a

crudely amoral opportunism and to an antimilitarism that was variously

emphasized, rejected, or modified to suit the foreign policy of the

Stalinist regime.

Yet opposition there was–as late as 1939–to this degeneration of the

ideas that had defined the Left That Was–opposition from left-wing

tendencies in certain socialist parties, from anarchists, and from

dissident Communist groups. The Left That Was did not disappear without

furious debates over these ideals or without attempts to retain its

historic premises. Its ideals remained at the top of the revolutionary

agenda during the entire interwar period, not only as a source of

polemics but as part of an armed confrontation in the Spanish Revolution

of 1936. Leftist parties and groups still agonized over issues like

internationalism, democracy, antimilitarism, revolution, and their

relationship to the state–agonies that led to furious intramural and

interparty conflicts. These issues were branded on the entire era before

they began to fade–and their fading altered the very definition of

leftism itself.

The Left and the “Cold War”

The “Cold War” invaded the humanistic agenda of the Left That Was by

turning most leftist organizations into partisans of the West or the

East and by introducing a dubious “anti-imperialism” into what became

Cold War politics. “National liberation” became the virtual centerpiece

of the “New Left” and of the aging “Old Left,” at least their various

Stalinist, Maoist, and Castroist versions.

It should be understood–as this Left did not–that imperialism is not

unique to capitalism. As a means of exploitation and cultural

homogenization, and as a source of tribute, it existed throughout the

ancient, medieval, and early modern eras. In ancient times the imperial

hegemony of Babylon was followed by that of Rome and the medieval Holy

Roman Empire. Indeed, throughout history there have been African,

Indian, Asian, and in modern times, expansionist and exploitative

“sub-imperialist” states that were more precapitalist than capitalist in

character. If “war is the health of the state,” war has usually meant

expansionism (read: imperialism) among the more commanding states of the

world and even among their client states.

In the early part of the twentieth century, the various writings on

imperialism by J. A. Hobson, Rudolf Hilferding, and Lenin, among others,

did not discover the concept of imperialism. They simply added new,

uniquely capitalist features to earlier characterizations of

imperialism, such as the “export of capital” and the impact of

capitalism on the economic development of colonized countries. But what

capitalism has also exported with a vengeance, in addition to capital

itself, has been nationalism (not only demands for cultural autonomy)

and nationalism in the form of centralized nation-states. Indeed, the

centralized nation-state has been exported to peoples who might more

reasonably have turned to confederal forms of struggle and social

reconstruction in asserting their cultural uniqueness and right to

self-management. Let me emphasize that my criticisms of nationalism and

statism are not meant to reject the genuine aspirations of cultural

groups for full expression and self-governance. This is particularly the

case where attempts are made to subvert their cultural uniqueness and

their rights to autonomy. The issue with which I am concerned is how

their cultural autonomy is expressed and the institutional structures

they establish to manage themselves as unique cultural entities. The

cultural integrity of a people does not have to be embodied in the form

of a nation-state. It should, in my view, be expressed in forms that

retain valuable cultural traditions and practices in confederal

institutions of self-management. It was goals such as these in

particular that were raised and prized by the great majority of

anarchists and libertarian socialists, even certain Marxists, in the

Left That Was.

What has happened instead is that the export of the nation-state has

poisoned not only the modern Left but the human condition itself. In

recent years, “Balkanization” and parochialism have become vicious

phenomena of disastrous proportions. The recent and much-described

breakup of the Russian empire has resulted in bloody national struggles

and aspirations for state-formation that are pitting culturally

disparate communities against each other in ways that threaten to

regress to barbarism. The internationalist ideals that the Left That Was

advanced, particularly in the former “socialist bloc,” have been

replaced by an ugly parochialism–directed against Jews generally and in

much of Europe against “foreign workers” from all parts of the world. In

the Near East, Africa, Asia, and Latin America, colonized or formerly

colonized peoples have developed imperial appetites of their own, so

that many of what now pass for former colonies that have been liberated

from Euro-American imperialist powers are now pursuing brutally

imperialist aspirations of their own.

For the emergence of an authentic Left what is disastrous here is that

leftists in the United States and Europe often condone appalling

behavior on the part of former colonies, in the name of “socialism,”

“anti-imperialism,” and of course “national liberation.” The present-day

Left is no less a victim of the “Cold War” than colonized peoples who

were pawns in it. Leftists have all but jettisoned the ideals of the

Left That Was, and in so doing, they have come to accept a kind of

client status of their own–first, in the 1930s, as supporters of the

“workers’ fatherland” in the East, and more recently as supporters of

former colonies bent on their own imperialist adventures.

What matters is not whether such leftists in Europe or the United States

do or do not support “liberated” nation-states that are either newly

emerging, subimperialist, or imperialist. Whether Western leftists

“support” these nation-states and their endeavors means as much to those

states as seagull-droppings on an ocean shore. Rather, what really

matters–and what is the more serious tragedy–is that these leftists

rarely ask whether peoples they support accept statist regimes or

confederal associations, whether they oppress other cultures, or whether

they oppress their own or other populations–let alone whether they

themselves should be supporting a nation-state at all.

Indeed, many leftists fell into the habit of opposing the imperialism of

the superpowers in a mere reaction to the sides that were lined up in

the “Cold War.” This “Cold War” mentality persists even after the “Cold

War” has come to an end. More than ever, leftists today are obliged to

ask if their “anti-imperialist” and “national liberation” concerns help

to foster the emergence of more nation-states and more ethnic and

“sub-imperialist” rivalries. They must ask, what character is

anti-imperialism taking today? Is it validating ethnic rivalries, the

emergence of domestic tyrannies, sub-imperialist ambitions, and a

rapacious collection of militaristic regimes?

Clearly, parochialism is one product of the new “anti-imperialist”

nationalism and statism that have been nourished by the “Cold War” and

the reduction of specious leftists to minions of old Stalinist and

Maoist-type conflicts dressed in the garb of “national liberation.”

Parochialism can also function internally, partly as an extension of the

“Cold War” into domestic spheres of life. Self-styled spokespeople for

ethnic groups who literally pit one racial group against another,

dehumanizing (for whatever reason) one to enhance the other;

spokespeople for gender groups that parallel such exclusionary ethnic

groups in opposition to their sexual counterparts; spokespeople for

religious groups that do the same with respect to other religious

groups–all reflect atavistic developments that would have had no place

in the Left That Was. That the rights of ethnic, gender, and like strata

of a given population must be cherished and that cultural distinctions

must be prized is not in question here. But apart from the justified

claims of all these groups, their aims should be sought within a

human-oriented framework, not within an exclusionary or parochial

folk-oriented one. If an authentic Left is once again to emerge, the

myth of a “hegemonic” group of oppressed people, which seeks to

rearrange human relations in a new hierarchical pyramid, must be

replaced by the goal of achieving an ethics of complementarity in which

differences enrich the whole. In ancient times, the slaves of Sicily who

revolted and forced all free men to fight as gladiators in the island’s

amphitheaters behaved no differently from their masters. They reproduced

what was still a slave culture, replacing one kind of slave by another.

Moreover, if there is to be a Left that in any sense resembles the Left

That Was, it cannot be merely “left of center.” Liberalism–with its menu

of small reforms that obscure the irrationality of the prevailing

society and make it more socially acceptable–is an arena in its own

right. Liberalism has no “left” that can be regarded as its kin or its

critical neighbor. The Left must stake out its own arena, one that

stands in revolutionary opposition to the prevailing society, not one

that participates as a “leftist” partner in its workings.

Will There Be a Left Today?

Certainly the Left That Was fought against innumerable irrationalities

in the existing social order, such as long debilitating working hours,

desperate hunger, and abject poverty. It did so because the perpetuation

of these irrationalities would have completely demoralized the forces

fighting for basic social change. It often raised seemingly “reformist”

demands, but it did so to reveal the failure of the existing social

order to meet the most elementary needs of denied people. In fighting

for these “reforms,” however, the concern of the Left That Was was

explicitly and unwaveringly focused on the need to change the whole

social order, not on making it less irrational and more palatable.

Today, the Left That Was would have also fought with desperation against

the forces that are depleting the ozone layer, destroying the forests,

and proliferating the nuclear power plants in order to preserve life

itself on this planet.

By the same token, however, the Left That Was recognized that there are

many problems that cannot be solved within the framework of capitalism.

It held, however “unrealistically” it may seem, to its revolutionary

position rather than curry public favor or surrender its identity to

opportunistic programs. At any given moment, history does not always

present the Left with clear-cut alternatives or immediately “effective”

courses of action. In August 1914, for example, no forces existed that

could have prevented the outbreak of World War I, not even the Social

Democracy that had committed itself to opposition to the war. The Left

had to live an ineffectual, often hidden, frustrating life amidst the

effluvium of popular jingoism that engulfed so much of Europe, including

most of the workers in the socialist movement itself. Similarly, in

1938, there was no longer any possibility that the Spanish Revolution

could be rescued from fascist military attacks and insidious Stalinist

counterrevolution, despite the valiant struggles that continued for the

greater part of a year thereafter.

Regrettably, there are some impossible situations in which an authentic

Left can only take a moral stance, with no hope of intervening

successfully. In such cases, the Left can only patiently try to educate

those who are willing to listen, to advance its ideas to rational

individuals, however small their numbers may be, and to act as an

ethical force in opposition to the “art of the possible,” to use a

famous liberal definition of politics. A recent case in point was an

admirable slogan that was raised at the inception of the Gulf war,

namely “Neither Side Is Right”–a slogan that obviously did not resonate

with the nationalistic attitude of the great majority of American

people, nor one that was likely to be politically effective. Indeed, to

choose sides in the Gulf war would have been to confuse American

national chauvinism with democracy, on the one hand, or to confuse an

indifference to Saddam Hussein’s totalitarianism with

“anti-imperialism,” on the other. This eminently moral position tries to

advance a humanistic viewpoint in the face of the repellent political

and economic reality that marked both camps in the conflict.

To pretend that an authentic Left can always offer a practical solution

to every problem in society is chimerical. Offering “lesser evils” as a

solution to every evil that this society generates will lead to the

worst of all possible evils–the dissolution of the Left into a liberal

morass of endless compromises and humiliations. Amid all its fights in

support of concrete issues, an authentic Left advances the message that

the present society must be demolished and replaced by one that is

rational. Such was the case with socialists like Eugene V. Debs and

anarchists like Emma Goldman and Alexander Berkman in the Left That Was.

Put bluntly: What this society usually does should not deter Leftists

from probing the logic of events from a rational standpoint or from

calling for what society should do. Any attempt to adapt the rational

“should” to the irrational “is” vacates that space on the political

spectrum that should be occupied by a Left premised on reason, freedom,

and ecological humanism. The need to steadfastly maintain the principal

commitments that minimally define a Left may not always be popular, but

the alternative to the monstrous irrationalities that permeate

present-day society must always be kept open, fostered, and developed if

we are ever to achieve a free society.

It may well be that in the foreseeable future an authentic Left has

little, if any, prospects of gaining a large following. But if it

surrenders the most basic principles that define it–internationalism,

democracy, antimilitarism, revolution, secularism, and rationalism–as

well as others, like confederalism, the word Left will no longer have

any meaning in our political vocabulary. One may call oneself a liberal,

a social democrat, a “realo” Green, or a reformist. That is a choice

that each individual is free to make, according to his or her social and

political convictions. But for those who call themselves leftists, there

should be a clear understanding that the use of the term Left involves

the acceptance of the fundamental principles that literally define and

justify the use of the word. This means that certain ideas like

nationalism, parochialism, authoritarianism–and certainly, for

anarchists of all kinds, any commitment to a nation-state–and symbols

like the broken rifle of pacifism are totally alien to the principles

that define the Left. Such ideas, introduced into politics, have no

place in any politics that can authentically be characterized as

leftist. If no such politics exists, the term Left should be permitted

to perish with honor.

But if the Left were to finally disappear because of the melding of

reformist, liberal, nationalist, and parochial views, not only would

modern society lose the “principle of hope,” to use Ernst Bloch’s

expression, an abiding principle that has guided all revolutionary

movements of the past; the Left would cease to be the conscience of

society. Nor could it advance the belief that the present society is

totally irrational and must be replaced by one that is guided by reason,

an ecological ethics, and a genuine concern for human welfare. For my

part, that is not a world in which I would want to live.