đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș george-orwell-politics-vs-literature.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:38:04. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Politics vs. Literature Author: George Orwell Date: 1946 Language: en Topics: book review, literature Source: Retrieved on 18th December 2021 from https://orwell.ru/library/reviews/swift/english/e_swift
In Gulliverâs Travels humanity is attacked, or criticized, from at least
three different angles, and the implied character of Gulliver himself
necessarily changes somewhat in the process. In Part I he is the typical
eighteenth-century voyager, bold, practical and unromantic, his homely
outlook skilfully impressed on the reader by the biographical details at
the beginning, by his age (he is a man of forty, with two children, when
his adventures start), and by the inventory of the things in his
pockets, especially his spectacles, which make several appearances. In
Part II he has in general the same character, but at moments when the
story demands it he has a tendency to develop into an imbecile who is
capable of boasting of âour noble Country, the Mistress of Arts and
Arms, the Scourge of Franceâ, etc., etc., and at the same time of
betraying every available scandalous fact about the country which he
professes to love. In Part III he is much as he was in Part I, though,
as he is consorting chiefly with courtiers and men of learning, one has
the impression that he has risen in the social scale. In Part IV he
conceives a horror of the human race which is not apparent, or only
intermittently apparent, in the earlier books, and changes into a sort
of unreligious anchorite whose one desire is to live in some desolate
spot where he can devote himself to meditating on the goodness
oftheHouyhnhnms. However, these inconsistencies are forced upon Swift by
the fact that Gulliver is there chiefly to provide a contrast. It is
necessary, for instance, that he should appear sensible in Part I and at
least intermittently silly in Part II because in both books the
essential manoeuvre is the same, i.e. to make the human being look
ridiculous by imagining him as a creature six inches high. Whenever
Gulliver is not acting as a stooge there is a sort of continuity in his
character, which comes out especially in his resourcefulness and his
observation of physical detail. He is much the same kind of person, with
the same prose style, when he bears off the warships of Blefuscu, when
he rips open the belly of the monstrous rat, and when he sails away upon
the ocean in his frail coracle made from. the skins of Yahoos. Moreover,
it is difficult not to feel that in his shrewder moments Gulliver is
simply Swift himself, and there is at least one incident in which Swift
seems to be venting his private grievance against contemporary Society.
It will be remembered that when the Emperor of Lilliputâs palace catches
fire, Gulliver puts it out by urinating on it. Instead of being
congratulated on his presence of mind, he finds that he has committed a
capital offence by making water in the precincts of the palace, and
I was privately assured, that the Empress, conceiving the greatest
Abhorrence of what I had done, removed to the most distant Side of the
Court, firmly resolved that those buildings should never be repaired for
her Use; and, in the Presence of her chief Confidents, could not forbear
vowing Revenge.
According to Professor G. M. Trevelyan (England under Queen Anne), part
of the reason for Swiftâs failure to get preferment was that the Queen
was scandalized by the Tale of a Tub â a pamphlet in which Swift
probably felt that he had done a great service to the English Crown,
since it scarifies the Dissenters and still more the Catholics while
leaving the Established Church alone. In any case no one would deny that
Gulliverâs Travels is a rancorous as well as a pessimistic book, and
that especially in Parts I and III it often descends into political
partisanship of a narrow kind. Pettiness and magnanimity, republicanism
and authori-tarianism, love of reason and lack of curiosity, are all
mixed up in it. The hatred of the human body with which Swift is
especially associated is only dominant in Part IV, but somehow this new
preoccupation does not come as a surprise. One feels that all these
adventures, and all these changes of mood, could have happened to the
same person, and the inter-connexion between Swiftâs political loyalties
and his ultimate despair is one of the most interesting features of the
book.
Politically, Swift was one of those people who are driven into a sort of
perverse Toryism by the follies of the progressive party of the moment.
Part I of Gulliverâs Travels, ostensibly a satire on human greatness,
can be seen, if one looks a little deeper, to be simply an attack on
England, on the dominant Whig Party, and on the war with France, which â
however bad the motives of the Allies may have been â did save Europe
from being tyrannized over by a single reactionary power. Swift was not
a Jacobite nor strictly speaking a Tory, and his declared aim in the war
was merely a moderate peace treaty and not the outright defeat of
England. Nevertheless there is a tinge of quis-lingism in his attitude,
which comes out in the ending of Part I and slightly interferes with the
allegory. When Gulliver flees from Lilliput (England) to Blefuscu
(France) the assumption that a human being six inches high is inherently
contemptible seems to be dropped. Whereas the people of Lilliput have
behaved towards Gulliver with the utmost treachery and meanness, those
of Blefuscu behave generously and straightforwardly, and indeed this
section of the book ends on a different note from the all-round
disillusionment of the earlier chapters. Evidently Swiftâs animus is, in
the first place, against England. It is âyour Nativesâ (i.e. Gulliverâs
fellow-countrymen) whom the King of Brob-dingnag considers to be âthe
most pernicious Race of little odious vermin that Nature ever suffered
to crawl upon the surface of the Earthâ, and the long passage at the
end, denouncing colonization and foreign conquest, is plainly aimed at
England, although the contrary is elaborately stated. The Dutch,
Englandâs allies and target of one of Swiftâs most famous pamphlets, are
also more or less wantonly attacked in Part III. There is even what
sounds like a personal note in the passage in which Gulliver records his
satisfaction that the various countries he has discovered cannot be made
colonies of the British Crown:
The Houyhnhnms, indeed, appear not to be so well prepared for War, a
Science to which they are perfect Strangers, and especially against
missive Weapons. However, supposing myself to be a Minister of State, I
could never give my advice for invading them.... Imagine twenty thousand
of them breaking into the midst of an European army, confounding the
Ranks, overturning the Carriages, battering the Warriorsâ Faces into
Mummy, by terrible Yerks from their hinder hoofs...
Considering that Swift does not waste words, that phrase, âbattering the
warriorsâ faces into mummyâ, probably indicates a secret wish to see the
invincible armies of the Duke of Marlborough treated in a like manner.
There are similar touches elsewhere. Even the country mentioned in Part
III, where âthe Bulk of the People consist, in a Manner, wholly of
Discoverers, Witnesses, Informers, Accusers, Prosecutors, Evidences,
Swearers, together with their several subservient and subaltern
Instruments, all under the Colours, the Conduct, and Pay of Ministers of
Stateâ, is called Langdon, which is within one letter of being an
anagram of England. (As the early editions of the book contain
misprints, it may perhaps have been intended as a complete anagram.)
Swiftâs physical repulsion from humanity is certainly real enough, but
one has the feeling that his debunking of human grandeur, his diatribes
against lords, politicians, court favourites, etc., has mainly a local
application and springs from the fact that he belonged to the
unsuccessful party. He denounces injustice and oppression, but he gives
no evidence of liking democracy. In spite of his enormously greater
powers, his implied position is very similar to that of the innumerable
silly-clever Conservatives of our own day â people like Sir Alan
Herbert, Professor G. M. Young, Lord Eiton, the Tory Reform Committee or
the long line of Catholic apologists from W. H. Mallock onwards: people
who specialize in cracking neat jokes at the expense of whatever is
âmodernâ and âprogressiveâ, and whose opinions are often all the more
extreme because they know that they cannot influence the actual drift of
events. After all, such a pamphlet as An Argument to prove that the
Abolishing of Christianity, etc., is very like âTimothy Shyâ having a
bit of clean fun with the Brains Trust, or Father Ronald Knox exposing
the errors ofBertrand Russell. And the ease with which Swift has been
forgiven â and forgiven, sometimes, by devout believers â for the
blasphemies of A Tale of a Tub demonstrates clearly enough the
feebleness of religious sentiments as compared with political ones.
However, the reactionary cast of Swiftâs mind does not show itself
chiefly in his political affiliations. The important thing is his
attitude towards Science, and, more broadly, towards intellectual
curiosity. The famous Academy of Lagado, described in Part III of
Gulliverâs Travels, is no doubt a justified satire on most of the
so-called scientists of Swiftâs own day. Significantly, the people at
work in it are described as âProjectorsâ, that is, people not engaged in
disinterested research but merely on the look-out for gadgets which will
save labour and bring in money. But there is no sign â indeed, all
through the book there are many signs to the contrary â that âpureâ
science would have struck Swift as a worth-while activity. The more
serious kind of scientist has already had a kick in the pants in Part
II, when the âScholarsâ patronized by the King of Brobdingnag try to
account for Gulliverâs small stature:
After much Debate, they concluded unanimously that I was only Relplum
Scalcath, which is interpreted literally, Lusus Naturae, a Determination
exactly agreeable to the modern philosophy of Europe, whose Professors,
disdaining the old Evasion of Occult Causes, whereby the followers of
Aristotle endeavoured in vain to disguise their Ignorance, have invented
this wonderful solution of All Difficulties, to the unspeakable
Advancement of human Knowledge.
If this stood by itself one might assume that Swift is merely the enemy
of sham science. In a number of places, however, he goes out of his way
to proclaim the uselessness of all learning or speculation not directed
towards some practical end:
The learning of (the Brobdingnaglans) is very defective, consisting only
in Morality, History, Poetry, and Mathematics, wherein they must be
allowed to excel. But, the last of these is wholly applied to what may
be useful in Life, to the improvement of Agriculture, and all mechanical
Arts so that among us it would be little esteemed. And as to Ideas,
Entities, Abstractions, and Transcen-dentals, I could never drive the
least Conception into their Heads.
The Houyhnhnms, Swiftâs ideal beings, are backward even in a mechanical
sense. They are unacquainted with metals, have never heard of boats, do
not, properly speaking, practise agriculture (we are told that the oats
which they live upon âgrow naturallyâ), and appear not to have invented
wheels[1]. They have no alphabet, and evidently have not much curiosity
about the physical world. They do not believe that any inhabited country
exists beside their own, and though they understand the motions of the
sun and moon, and the nature of eclipses, âthis is the utmost progress
of their Astronomyâ. By contrast, the philosophers of the flying island
of Laputa are so continuously absorbed in mathematical speculations that
before speaking to them one has to attract their attention by napping
them on the ear with a bladder. They have catalogued ten thousand fixed
stars, have settled the periods of ninety-three comets, and have
discovered, in advance of the astronomers of Europe, that Mars has two
moons â all of which information Swift evidently regards as ridiculous,
useless and uninteresting. As one might expect, he believes that the
scientistâs place, if he has a place, is in the laboratory, and that
scientific knowledge has no bearing on political matters:
What I... thought altogether unaccountable, was the strong Disposition I
observed in them towards News and Politics, perpetually enquiring into
Public Affairs, giving their judgements in Matters of State, and
passionately disputing every inch of a Party Opinion. I have, indeed,
observed the same Disposition among most of the Mathematicians I have
known in Europe, though I could never discover the least Analogy between
the two Sciences; unless those people suppose, that, because the
smallest Circle hath as many Degrees as the largest, therefore the
Regulation and Management of the World require no more Abilities, than
the Handling and Turning of a Globe.
Is there not something familiar in that phrase âI could never discover
the least analogy between the two sciencesâ? It has precisely the note
of the popular Catholic apologists who profess to be astonished when a
scientist utters an opinion on such questions as the existence of God or
the immortality of the soul. The scientist, we are told, is an expert
only in one restricted field: why should his opinions be of value in any
other? The implication is that theology is just as much an exact science
as, for instance, chemistry, and that the priest is also an expert whose
conclusions on certain subjects must be accepted. Swift in effect makes
the same claim for the politician, but he goes one better in that he
will not allow the scientist â either the âpureâ scientist or the ad hoc
investigator â to be a useful person in his own line. Even if he had not
written Part III of Gulliverâs Travels, one could infer from the rest of
the book that, like Tolstoy and like Blake, he hates the very idea of
studying the processes of Nature. The âReasonâ which he so admires in
the Houyhnhnms does not primarily mean the power of drawing logical
inferences from observed facts. Although he never defines it, it appears
in most contexts to mean either common sense â i.e. acceptance of the
obvious and contempt for quibbles and abstractions â or absence of
passion and superstition. In general he assumes that we know all that we
need to know already, and merely use our knowledge incorrectly.
Medicine, for instance, is a useless science, because if we lived in a
more natural way, there would be no diseases. Swift, however, is not a
simple-lifer or an admirer of the Noble Savage. He is in favour of
civilization and the arts of civilization. Not only does he see the
value of good manners, good conversation, and even learning of a
literary and historical kind, he also sees that agriculture, navigation
and architecture need to be studied and could with advantages be
improved. But his implied aim is a static, incurious civilization â the
world of his own day, a little cleaner, a little saner, with no radical
change and no poking into the unknowable. More than one would expect in
anyone so free from accepted fallacies, he reveres the past, especially
classical antiquity, and believes that modern man has degenerated
sharply during the past hundred years[2]. In the island of sorcerers,
where the spirits of the dead can be called up at will:
I desired that the Senate of Rome might appear before me in one large
chamber, and a modern Representative in Counterview, in another. The
first seemed to be an Assembly of Heroes and Demy-Gods, the other a Knot
of Pedlars, Pick-pockets, Highwaymen and Bullies.
Although Swift uses this section of Part III to attack the truthfulness
of recorded history, his critical spirit deserts him as soon as he is
dealing with Greeks and Romans. He remarks, of course, upon the
corruption of imperial Rome, but he has an almost unreasoning admiration
for some of the leading figures of the ancient world:
I was struck with profound Veneration at the sight of Brutus, and could
easily discover the most consummate Virtue, the greatest Intrepidity and
Firmness of Mind, the truest Love of his Country, and general
Benevolence for Mankind, in every Lineament of his Countenance.... I had
the honour to have much Conversation with Brutus, and was told, that his
Ancestors Junws, Socrates, Epaminondas, Cato the younger, Sir Thomas
More, and himself, were perpetually together: a Sextumvirate, to which
all the Ages of the World cannot add a seventh.
It will be noticed that of these six people, only one is a Christian.
This is an important point. If one adds together Swiftâs pessimism, his
reverence for the past, his incuriosity and his horror of the human
body, one arrives at an attitude common among religious reactionaries â
that is, people who defend an unjust order of Society by claiming that
this world cannot be substantially improved and only the ânext worldâ
matters. However, Swift shows no sign of having any religious beliefs,
at least in any ordinary sense of the words. He does not appear to
believe seriously in life after death, and his idea of goodness is bound
up with republicanism, love of liberty, courage, âbenevolenceâ (meaning
in effect public spirit), âreasonâ and other pagan qualities. This
reminds one that there is another strain in Swift, not quite congruous
with his disbelief in progress and his general hatred of humanity.
To begin with, he has moments when he is âconstructiveâ and even
âadvancedâ. To be occasionally inconsistent is almost a mark of vitality
in Utopia books, and Swift sometimes inserts a word of praise into a
passage that ought to be purely satirical. Thus, his ideas about the
education of the young are fathered on to the Lilliputians, who have
much the same views on this subject as the Houyhnhnms. The Lilliputians
also have various social and legal institutions (for instance, there are
old age pensions, and people are rewarded for keeping the law as well as
punished for breaking it) which Swift would have liked to see prevailing
in his own country. In the middle of this passage Swift remembers his
satirical intention and adds, âIn relating these and the following Laws,
I would only be understood to mean the original Institutions, and not
the most scandalous Corruptions into which these people are fallen by
the degenerate Nature of Manâ: but as Lilliput is supposed to represent
England, and the laws he is speaking of have never had their parallel in
England, it is clear that the impulse to make constructive suggestions
has been too much for him. But Swiftâs greatest contribution to
political thought in the narrower sense of the words, is his attack,
especially in Part III, on what would now be called totalitarianism. He
has an extraordinarily clear prevision of the spy-haunted âpolice
Stateâ, with its endless heresy-hunts and treason trials, all really
designed to neutralize popular discontent by changing it into war
hysteria. And one must remember that Swift is here inferring the whole
from a quite small part, for the feeble governments of his own day did
not give him illustrations ready-made. For example, there is the
professor at the School of Political Projectors who âshewed me a large
Paper of Instructions for discovering Plots and Conspiraciesâ, and who
claimed that one can find peopleâs secret thoughts by examining their
excrement:
Because Men are never so serious, thoughtful, and intent, as when they
are at Stool, which he found by frequent Experiment: for in such
Conjunctures, when he used meerly as a trial to consider what was the
best Way of murdering the King, his Ordure would have a tincture of
Green; but quite different when he thought only of raising an
Insurrection, or burning the Metropolis.
The professor and his theory are said to have been suggested to Swift by
the â from our point of view â not particularly astonishing or
disgusting fact that in a recent State trial some letters found in
somebodyâs privy had been put in evidence. Later in the same chapter we
seem to be positively in the middle of the Russian purges:
In the Kingdom of Tribnia, by the Natives called Langdon... the Bulk of
the People consist, in a Manner, wholly of Discoverers, Witnesses,
Informers, Accusers, Prosecutors, Evidences, Swearers.
... It is first agreed, and settled among them, what suspected Persons
shall be accused of a Plot: Then, effectual Care is taken to secure all
their Letters and Papers, and put the Owners in Chains. These papers are
delivered to a Sett of Artists, very dexterous in finding out the
mysterious Meanings of Words, Syllables, and Letters.... Where this
method fails, they have two others more effectual, which the Learned
among them call Acrostics and Anagrams. First, they can decypher all
initial Letters into political Meanings: Thus: N shall signify a Plot, B
a Regiment of Horse, L a Fleet at Sea: Or, Secondly, by transposing the
Letters of the Alphabet in any suspected Paper, they can lay open the
deepest Designs of a discontented Party. So, for Example if I should say
in a Letter to a Friend, Our Brother Tom has just got the Piles, a
skilful Decypherer would discover that the same Letters, which compose
that Sentence, may be analysed in the following Words: Resist â a Plot
is brought Home â The Tour[3] And this is the anagrammatic method.
Other professors at the same school invent simplified languages, write
books by machinery, educate their pupils by inscribing the lesson on a
wafer and causing them to swallow it, or propose to abolish
individuality altogether by cutting off part of the brain of one man and
grafting it on to the head of another. There is something queerly
familiar in the atmosphere of these chapters, because, mixed up with
much fooling, there is a perception that one of the aims of
totalitarianism is not merely to make sure that people will think the
right thoughts, but actually to make them less conscious. Then, again,
Swiftâs account of the Leader who is usually to be found ruling over a
tribe of Yahoos, and of the âfavouriteâ who acts first as a dirty-worker
and later as a scapegoat, fits remarkably well into the pattern of our
own times. But are we to infer from all this that Swift was first and
foremost an enemy of tyranny and a champion of the free intelligence?
No: his own views, so far as one can discern them, are not markedly
liberal. No doubt he hates lords, kings, bishops, generals, ladies of
fashion, orders, titles and flummery generally, but he does not seem to
o think better of the common people than of their rulers, or to be in
favour of increased social equality, or to be enthusiastic about
representative institutions. The Houyhnhnms are organized upon a sort of
caste system which is racial in character, the horses which do the
menial work being of different colours from their masters and not
interbreeding with them. The educational system which Swift admires in
the Lilliputians takes hereditary class distinctions for granted, and
the children of the poorest classes do not go to school, because âtheir
Business being only to till and cultivate the Earth... therefore their
Education is of little Consequence to the Publicâ. Nor does he seem to
have been strongly in favour of freedom of speech and the Press, in
spite of the toleration which his own writings enjoyed. The King of
Brobdingnag is astonished at the multiplicity of religious and political
sects in England, and considers that those who hold âopinions
prejudicial to the publicâ (in the context this seems to mean simply
heretical opinions), though they need not be obliged to change them,
ought to be obliged to conceal them: for âas it was Tyranny in any
Government to require the first, so it was weakness not to enforce the
secondâ. There is a subtler indication of Swiftâs own attitude in the
manner in which Gulliver leaves the land of the Houyhnhnms.
Intermittently, at least. Swift was a kind of anarchist, and Part IV of
Gulliverâs Travels is a picture of an anarchistic Society, not governed
by law in the ordinary sense, but by the dictates of âReasonâ, which arc
voluntarily accepted by everyone. The General Assembly of the Houyhnhnms
âexhortsâ Gulliverâs master to get rid of him, and his neighbours put
pressure on him to make him comply. Two reasons are given. One is that
the presence of this unusual Yahoo may unsettle the rest of the tribe,
and the other is that a friendly relationship between a Houyhnhnm and a
Yahoo is ânot agreeable to Reason or Nature, or a Thing ever heard of
before among themâ. Gulliverâs master is somewhat unwilling to obey, but
the âexhortationâ (a Houyhnhnm, we are told, is never compelled to do
anything, he is merely âexhortedâ or âadvisedâ) cannot be disregarded.
This illustrates very well the totalitarian tendency which is explicit
in the anarchist or pacifist vision of Society. In a Society in which
there is no law, and in theory no compulsion, the only arbiter of
behaviour is public opinion. But public opinion, because of the
tremendous urge to conformity in gregarious animals, is less tolerant
than any system of law. When human beings are governed by âthou shalt
notâ, the individual can practise a certain amount of eccentricity: when
they are supposedly governed by âloveâ or âreasonâ, he is under
continuous pressure to make him behave and think in exactly the same way
as everyone else. The Houyhnhnms, we are told, were unanimous on almost
all subjects. The only question they ever discussed was how to deal with
the Yahoos. Otherwise there was no room for disagreement among them,
because the truth is always either self-evident, or else it is
undis-coverable and unimportant. They had apparently no word for
âopinionâ in their language, and in their conversations there was no
âdifference of sentimentsâ. They had reached, in fact, the highest stage
of totalitarian organization, the stage when conformity has become so
general that there is no need for a police force. Swift approves of this
kind of thing because among his many gifts neither curiosity nor
good-nature was included. Disagreement would always seem to him sheer
perversity. âReason,â among the Houyhn-hnms, he says, âis not a Point
Problematical, as with us, where men can argue with Plausibility on both
Sides of a Question; but strikes you with immediate Conviction; as it
must needs do, where it is not mingled, obscured, or discoloured by
Passion and Interest.â In other words, we know everything already, so
why should dissident opinions be tolerated? The totalitarian Society of
the Houyhnhnms, where there can be no freedom and no development,
follows naturally from this.
We are right to think of Swift as a rebel and iconoclast, but except in
certain secondary matters, such as his insistence that women should
receive the same education as men, he cannot be labelled âLeftâ. He is a
Tory anarchist, despising authority while disbelieving in liberty, and
preserving the aristocratic outlook while seeing clearly that the
existing aristocracy is degenerate and contemptible. When Swift utters
one of his characteristic diatribes against the rich and powerful, one
must probably, as I said earlier, write off something for the fact that
he himself belonged to the less successful party, and was personally
disappointed. The âoutsâ, for obvious reasons, are always more radical
than the âinsâ[4]. But the most essential thing in Swift is his
inability to believe that life â ordinary life on the solid earth, and
not some rationalized, deodorized version of it â could be made worth
living. Of course, no honest person claims that happiness is now a
normal condition among adult human beings; but perhaps it could be made
normal, and it is upon this question that all serious political
controversy really turns. Swift has much in common â more, I believe,
than has been noticed â with Tolstoy, another disbeliever in the
possibility of happiness. In both men you have the same anarchistic
outlook covering an authoritarian cast of mind; in both a similar
hostility to Science, the same impatience with opponents, the same
inability to see the importance of any question not interesting to
themselves ; and in both cases a sort of horror of the actual process of
life, though in Tolstoyâs case it was arrived at later and in a
different way. The sexual unhappiness of the two men was not of the same
kind, but there was this in common, that in both of them a sincere
loathing was mixed up with a morbid fascination. Tolstoy was a reformed
rake who ended by preaching complete celibacy, while continuing to
practise the opposite into extreme old age. Swift was presumably
impotent, and had an exaggerated horror of human dung: he also thought
about it incessantly, as is evident throughout his works. Such people
are not likely to enjoy even the small amount of happiness that falls to
most human beings, and, from obvious motives, are not likely to admit
that earthly life is capable of much improvement. Their incuriosity, and
hence their intolerance, spring from the same root.
Swiftâs disgust, rancour and pessimism would make sense against the
background of a ânext worldâ to which this one is the prelude. As he
does not appear to believe seriously in any such thing, it becomes
necessary to construct a paradise supposedly existing on the surface of
the earth, but something quite different from anything we know, with all
that he disapproves of â lies, folly, change, enthusiasm, pleasure, love
and dirt â eliminated from it. As his ideal being he chooses the horse,
an animal whose excrement is not offensive. The Houyhnhnms are dreary
beasts â this is so generally admitted that the point is not worth
labouring. Swiftâs genius can make them credible, but there can have
been very few readers in whom they have excited any feeling beyond
dislike. And this is not from wounded vanity at seeing animals preferred
to men; for, of the two, the Houyhnhnms are much liker to human beings
than are the Yahoos, and Gulliverâs horror of the Yahoos, together with
his recognition that they are the same kind of creature as himself,
contains a logical absurdity. This horror comes upon him at his very
first sight of them. âI never beheld,â he says, âin all my Travels, so
disagreeable an Animal, nor one against which I naturally conceived so
strong an Antipathy.â But in comparison with what are the Yahoos
disgusting? Not with the Houyhnhnms, because at this time Gulliver has
not seen a Houyhnhnm. It can only be in comparison with himself, i.e.
with a human being. Later, however, we are to be told that the Yahoos
are human beings, and human society becomes insupportable to Gulliver
because all men are Yahoos. In that case why did he not conceive his
disgust of humanity earlier? In effect we are told that the Yahoos are
fantastically different from men, and yet are the same. Swift has
over-reached himself in his fury, and is shouting at his
fellow-creatures, âYou are filthier than you are!â However, it is
impossible to feel much sympathy with the Yahoos, and it is not because
they oppress the Yahoos that the Houyhnhnms are unattractive. They are
unattractive because the âReasonâ by which they are governed is really a
desire for death. They are exempt from love, friendship, curiosity,
fear, sorrow and â except in their feelings towards the Yahoos, who
occupy rather the same place in their community as the Jews in Nazi
Germany â anger and hatred. âThey have no Fondness for their Colts or
Foles, but the Care they take, in educating them, proceeds entirely from
the Dictates of Reason.â They lay store by âFriendshipâ and
âBenevolenceâ, but âthese are not confined to particular Objects, but
universal to the whole Raceâ. They also value conversation, but in their
conversations there are no differences of opinion, and ânothing passed
but what was useful, expressed in the fewest and most significant
Wordsâ. They practise strict birth control, each couple producing two
offspring and thereafter abstaining from sexual intercourse. Their
marriages are arranged for them by their elders, on eugenic principles,
and their language contains no word for âloveâ, in the sexual sense.
When somebody dies they carry on exactly as before, without feeling any
grief. It will be seen that their aim is to be as like a corpse as is
possible while retaining physical life. One or two of their
characteristics, it is true, do not seem to be strictly âreasonableâ in
their own usage of the word. Thus, they place a great value not only on
physical hardihood but on athleticism, and they are devoted to poetry.
But these exceptions may be less arbitrary than they seem. Swift
probably emphasizes the physical strength of the Houyhnhnms in order to
make clear that they could never be conquered by the hated human race,
while a taste for poetry may figure among their qualities because poetry
appeared to Swift as the antithesis of Science, from his point of view
the most useless of all pursuits. In Part III he names âImagination,
Fancy, and Inventionâ as desirable faculties in which the Laputan
mathematicians (in spite of their love of music) were wholly lacking.
One must remember that although Swift was an admirable writer of comic
verse, the kind of poetry he thought valuable would probably be didactic
poetry. The poetry of the Houyhnhnms, he says â
must be allowed to excel (that of) all other Mortals; wherein the
Justness of their Similes, and the Minuteness, as well as exactness, of
their Descriptions, are, indeed, inimitable. Their Verses abound very
much in both of these; and usually contain either some exalted Notions
of Friendship and Benevolence, or the Praises of those who were Victors
in Races, and other bodily Exercises.
Alas, not even the genius of Swift was equal to producing a specimen by
which we could judge the poetry of the Houyhnhnms. But it sounds as
though it were chilly stuff (in heroic couplets, presumably), and not
seriously in conflict with the principles of âReasonâ.
Happiness is notoriously difficult to describe, and pictures of a just
and well-ordered Society are seldom either attractive or convincing.
Most creators of âfavourableâ Utopias, however, are concerned to show
what life could be like if it were lived more fully. Swift advocates a
simple refusal of life, justifying this by the claim that âReasonâ
consists in thwarting your instincts. The Houyhnhnms, creatures without
a history, continue for generation after generation to live prudently,
maintaining their population at exactly the same level, avoiding all
passion, suffering from no diseases, meeting death indifferently,
training up their young in the same principles â and all for what? In
order that the same process may continue indefinitely. The notions that
life here and now is worth living, or that it could be made worth
living, or that it must be sacrificed for some future good, are all
absent. The dreary world of the Houyhnhnms was about as good a Utopia as
Swift could construct, granting that he neither believed in a ânext
worldâ nor could get any pleasure out of certain normal activities. But
it is not really set up as something desirable in itself, but as the
justification for another attack on humanity. The aim, as usual, is to
humiliate Man by reminding him that he is weak and ridiculous, and above
all that he stinks; and the ultimate motive, probably, is a kind of
envy, the envy of the ghost for the living, of the man who knows he
cannot be happy for the others who â so he fears -may be a little
happier than himself. The political expression of such an outlook must
be either reactionary or nihilistic, because the person who holds it
will want to prevent Society from developing in some direction in which
his pessimism may be cheated. One can do this either by blowing
everything to pieces, or by averting social change. Swift ultimately
blew everything to pieces in the only way that was feasible before the
atomic bomb â that is, he went mad â but, as I have tried to show, his
political aims were on the whole reactionary ones.
From what I have written it may have seemed that I am against Swift, and
that my object is to refute him and even to belittle him. In a political
and moral sense I am against him, so far as I understand him. Yet
curiously enough he is one of the writers I admire with least reserve,
and Gulliverâs Travels, in particular, is a book which it seems
impossible for me to grow tired of. I read it first when I was, eight â
one day short of eight, to be exact, for I stole and furtively read the
copy which was to be given me next day on my eighth birthday â and I
have certainly not read it less than half a dozen times since. Its
fascination seems inexhaustible. If I had to make a list of six books
which were to be preserved when all others were destroyed, I would
certainly put Gulliverâs Travels among them. This raises the question:
what is the relationship between agreement with a writerâs opinions, and
enjoyment of his work?
If one is capable of intellectual detachment, one can perceive merit in
a writer whom one deeply disagrees with, but enjoyment is a different
matter. Supposing that there is such a thing as good or bad art, then
the goodness or badness must reside in the work of art itself- not
independently of the observer, indeed, but independently of the mood of
the observer. In one sense, therefore, it cannot be true that a poem is
good on Monday and bad on Tuesday. But if one judges the poem by the
appreciation it arouses, then it can certainly be true, because
appreciation, or enjoyment, is a subjective condition which cannot be
commanded. For a great deal of his waking life, even the most cultivated
person has no aesthetic feelings whatever, and the power to have
aesthetic feelings is very easily destroyed. When you are frightened, or
hungry, or are suffering from toothache or sea-sickness, King Lear is no
better from your point of view than Peter Pan. You may know in an
intellectual sense that it is better, but that is simply a fact which
you remember: you will not feel the merit of King Lear until you are
normal again. And aesthetic judgement can be upset just as disastrously
â more disastrously, because the cause is less readily recognized â by
political or moral disagreement. If a book angers, wounds or alarms you,
then you will not enjoy it, whatever its merits may be. If it seems to
you a really pernicious book, likely to influence other people in some
undesirable way, then you will probably construct an aesthetic theory to
show that it has no merits. Current literary criticism consists quite
largely of this kind of dodging to and fro between two sets of
standards. And yet the opposite process can also happen: enjoyment can
overwhelm disapproval, even though one clearly recognizes that one is
enjoying something inimical. Swift, whose world-view is so peculiarly
unacceptable, but who is nevertheless an extremely popular writer, is a
good instance of this. Why is it that we donât mind being called Yahoos,
although firmly convinced that we are not Yahoos?
It is not enough to make the usual answer that of course Swift was
wrong, in fact he was insane, but he was âa good writerâ. It is true
that the literary quality of a book is to some small extent separable
from its subject-matter. Some people have a native gift for using words,
as some people have a naturally âgood eyeâ at games. It is largely a
question of timing and of instinctively knowing how much emphasis to
use. As an example near at hand, look back at the passage I quoted
earlier, starting âIn the Kingdom of Tribnia, by the Natives called
Langdonâ. It derives much of its force from the final sentence: âAnd
this is the anagram-made Method.â Strictly speaking this sentence is
unnecessary, for we have already seen the anagram decyphered, but the
mock-solemn repetition, in which one seems to hear Swiftâs own voice
uttering the words, drives home the idiocy of the activities described,
like the final tap to a nail. But not all the power and simplicity of
Swiftâs prose, nor the imaginative effort that has been able to make not
one but a whole series of impossible worlds more credible than the
majority of history books â none of this would enable us to enjoy Swift
if his world-view were truly wounding or shocking. Millions of people,
in many countries, must have enjoyed Gulliverâs Travels while more or
less seeing its anti-human implications: and even the child who accepts
Parts i and n as a simple story gets a sense of absurdity from thinking
of human beings six inches high. The explanation must be that Swiftâs
world-view is felt to be not altogether false â or it would probably be
more accurate to say, not false all the time. Swift is a diseased
writer. He remains permanently in a depressed mood which in most people
is only intermittent, rather as though someone suffering from jaundice
or the after-effects of influenza should have the energy to write books.
But we all know that mood, and something in us responds to the
expression of it. Take, for instance, one of his most characteristic
works, The Ladyâs Dressing Room: one might add the kindred poem, Upon a
Beautiful Young Nymph Going to Bed. Which is truer, the viewpoint
expressed in these poems, or the viewpoint implied in Blakeâs phrase,
âThe naked female human form divineâ? No doubt Blake is nearer the
truth, and yet who can fail to feel a sort of pleasure in seeing that
fraud, feminine delicacy, exploded for once? Swift falsifies his picture
of the world by refusing to see anything in human life except dirt,
folly and wickedness, but the part which he abstracts from the whole
does exist, and it is something which we all know about while shrinking
from mentioning it. Part of our minds â in any normal person it is the
dominant part â believes that man is a noble animal and life is worth
living: but there is also a sort of inner self which at least
intermittently stands aghast at the horror of existence. In the queerest
way, pleasure and disgust are linked together. The human body is
beautiful: it is also repulsive and ridiculous, a fact which can be
verified at any swimming pool. The sexual organs are objects of desire
and also of loathing, so much so that in many languages, if not in all
languages, their names are used as words of abuse. Meat is delicious,
but a butcherâs shop makes one feel sick: and indeed all our food
springs ultimately from dung and dead bodies, the two things which of
all others seem to us the most horrible. A child, when it is past the
infantile stage but still looking at the world with fresh eyes, is moved
by horror almost as often as by wonder â horror of snot and spittle, of
the dogsâ excrement on the pavement, the dying toad full of maggots, the
sweaty smell of grown-ups, the hideousness of old men, with their bald
heads and bulbous noses. In his endless harping on disease, dirt and
deformity, Swift is not actually inventing anything, he is merely
leaving something out. Human behaviour, too, especially in politics, is
as he describes it, although it contains other more important factors
which he refuses to admit. So far as we can see, both horror and pain
are necessary to the continuance of life on this planet, and it is
therefore open to pessimists like Swift to say : âIf horror and pain
must always be with us, how can life be significantly improved?â His
attitude is in effect the Christian attitude, minus the bribe of a ânext
worldâ â which, however, probably has less hold upon the minds of
believers than the conviction that this world is a vale of tears and the
grave is a place of rest. It is, I am certain, a wrong attitude, and one
which could have harmful effects upon behaviour; but something in us
responds to it, as it responds to the gloomy words of the burial service
and the sweetish smell of corpses in a country church.
It is often argued, at least by people who admit the importance of
subject-matter, that a book cannot be âgoodâ if it expresses a palpably
false view of life. We are told that in our own age, for instance, any
book that has genuine literary merit will also be more or less
âprogressiveâ in tendency. This ignores the fact that throughout history
a similar struggle between progress and reaction has been raging, and
that the best books of any one age have always been written from several
different viewpoints, some of them palpably more false than others. In
so far as a writer is a propagandist, the most one can ask of him is
that he shall genuinely believe in what he is saying, and that it shall
not be something blazingly silly. To-day, for example, one can imagine a
good book being written by a Catholic, a Communist, a Fascist, pacifist,
an anarchist, perhaps by an old-style Liberal or an ordinary
Conservative: one cannot imagine a good book being written by a
spiritualist, a Buchmanite or a member of the Ku-Klux-KIan. The views
that a writer holds must be compatible with sanity, in the medical
sense, and with the power of continuous thought: beyond that what we ask
of him is talent, which is probably another name for conviction. Swift
did not possess ordinary wisdom, but he did possess a terrible intensity
of vision, capable of picking out a single hidden truth and then
magnifying it and distorting it. The durability of Gulliverâs Travels
goes to show that, if the force of belief is behind it, a world-view
which only just passes the test of sanity is sufficient to produce a
great work of art.
[1] Houyhnhnms too old to walk are described as being carried in
âsledgesâ or in âa kind of vehicle, drawn like a sledgeâ. Presumably
these had no wheels.
[2] The physical decadence which Swift claims to have observed may have
been a reality at that date. He attributes it to syphilis, which was a
new disease in Europe and may have been more virulent than it is now.
Distilled liquors, also, were a novelty in the seventeenth century and
must have led at first to a great increase in drunkenness.
[3] Tower.
[4] At the end of the book, as typical specimens of human folly and
viciousness, Swift names âa Lawyer, a Pickpocket, a Colonel, a Fool, a
Lord, a Gamester, a Politician, a Whore-master, a Physician, an
Evidence, a Suborner, an Attorney, a Traitor, or the likeâ. One sees
here the irresponsible violence of the powerless. The list lumps
together those who break the conventional code, and those who keep it.
For instance, if you automatically condemn a colonel, as such, on what
grounds do you condemn a traitor? Or again, if you want to suppress
pickpockets, you must have laws, which means that you must have lawyers.
But the whole closing passage, in which the hatred is so authentic, and
the reason given for it so inadequate, is somehow unconvincing. One has
the feeling that personal animosity is at work.