đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș maximilien-rubel-marx-theoretician-of-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:48:57. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Marx, Theoretician of Anarchism Author: Maximilien Rubel Date: 1973 Language: en Topics: council communism, Libertarian Marxism, Karl Marx Source: *LâEurope en formation*, no 163â164, octobre-novembre 1973; Retrieved on 2020-10-25 from https://www.marxists.org/archive/rubel/1973/marx-anarchism.htm Notes: Transcribed for marxists.org by Adam Buick; Translated by Adam Buick; CopyLeft: Creative Commons (Attribute & ShareAlike) marxists.org 2005.
Marx has been badly served by disciples who have succeeded neither in
assessing the limits of his theory nor in determining its standards and
field of application and has ended up by taking on the role of some
mythical giant, a symbol of the omniscience and omnipotence of homo
faber, maker of his own destiny.
The history of the School remains to be written, but at least we know
how it came into being: Marxism, as the codification of a misunderstood
and misinterpreted body of thought, was born and developed at a time
when Marxâs work was not yet available in its entirely and when
important parts of it remained unpublished. Thus, the triumph of Marxism
as a State doctrine and Party ideology preceded by several decades the
publication of the writings where Marx set out most clearly and
completely the scientific basis and ethical purpose of his social
theory. That great upheavals took place which invoked a body of thought
whose major principles were unknown to the protagonists in the drama of
history should have been enough to show that Marxism was the greatest,
if not the most tragic, misunderstanding of the century. But at the same
time this allows us to appreciate the significance of the theory held by
Marx that it is not revolutionary ideas or moral principles which bring
about changes in society, but rather human and material forces; that
ideas and ideologies very often serve only to disguise the interest of
the class in whose interests the upheavals take place. Political Marxism
cannot appeal to Marxâs science and at the same time escape the critical
analysis which that science uses to unmask the ideologies of power and
exploitation.
Marxism as the ideology of a master class has succeeded in emptying the
concepts of socialism and communism, as Marx and his forerunners
understood them, of their original meaning and has replaced it with the
picture of a reality which is its complete negation. Although closely
linked to the other two, a third concept â anarchism â seems however to
have escaped this fate of becoming a mystification. But while people
know that Marx had very little sympathy for certain anarchists, it is
not so generally known that despite this he still shared the anarchist
ideal and objectives: the disappearance of the State. It is therefore
pertinent to recall that in embracing the cause of working class
emancipation, Marx started off in the anarchist tradition rather than in
that of socialism or communism; and that, when finally he chose to call
himself a âcommunist,â for him this term did not refer to one of the
communist currents which then existed, but rather to a movement of
thought and mode of action which had yet to be founded by gathering
together all the revolutionary elements which had been inherited from
existing doctrines and from the experience of past struggles.
In the reflections which follow we will try to show that, under the name
communism, Marx developed a theory of anarchism; and further, that in
fact it was he who was the first to provide a rational basis for the
anarchist utopia and to put forward a project for achieving it. In view
of the limited scope of the present essay we will only put this forward
as an item for discussion. Proof by means of quotations will be reduced
to a minimum so as to better bring out the central argument: Marx
theoretician of anarchism.
When in Paris in February 1845, on the eve of his departure for exile in
Brussels, Marx signed a contract with a German publisher he committed
himself to supplying in a few months a work in two volumes entitled âA
Critique of Politics and Political Economyâ without suspecting that he
had imposed on himself a task which would take up his while life and of
which he would be able to carry out only a largish fragment.
The choice of subject was no accident. Having given up all hope of a
university career, Marx had carried over into his political journalism
the results of his philosophical studies. His articles in the Rheinische
Zeitung of Cologne led the fight for freedom of the press in Prussia in
the name of a liberty which he conceived of as the essence of Man and as
the attire of human nature; but also in the name of a State understood
as the realisation of rational freedom, as âthe great organism, in which
legal, moral, and political freedom must be realised, and in which the
individual citizen in obeying the laws of the state only obeys the
natural laws of his own reason, of human reason.â[1] But the Prussian
censorship soon silenced the philosopher-journalist. Marx, in the
solicitude of a study retreat, did not take long to ask himself about
the real nature of the State and about the rational and ethical validity
of Hegelâs political philosophy. We know what was the fruit of this
meditation enriched by the study of the history of the bourgeois
revolutions in France, Great Britain and the United States: apart from
an incomplete and unpublished work, The Critique of Hegelâs Philosophy
of the State (1843), two polemical essays, Introduction to the Critique
of Hegelâs Philosophy of Right and On the Jewish Question (Paris, 1844).
These two writings in fact form a single manifesto in which Marx
identifies once and for all and condemns unreservedly the social
institutions â the State and Money â which he saw as at the origin of
the evils and defects from which modern society suffered and would go on
suffering until a new social revolution came to abolish them. At the
same time Marx praised the force â the modern proletariat â which, after
having been the main victim of these two institutions, was going to put
an end to their reign as well as to every other form of class
domination, political and economic. The self-emancipation of the
proletariat would be the complete emancipation of humanity; after the
total loss of humanity the total victory of the human.
In the intellectual development of Marx the rejection of the State and
Money and the affirmation that the proletariat was a liberating class
came before his studies of political economy; they preceded also his
discovery of the materialist conception of history, the âguiding lineâ
which directed his later historical researches. His break with Hegelâs
philosophy of law and politics on the one hand and his critical study of
bourgeois revolutions on the other allowed him to establish clearly the
ethical postulates of his future social theory for which the scientific
basis was to be provided by the critique of political economy. Having
understood the revolutionary role of democracy and legislative power in
the genesis of the bourgeois State and governmental power, Marx made use
of the illuminating analysis of two shrewd observers of the
revolutionary possibilities of American democracy, Alexis de Tocqueville
and Thomas Hamilton, to lay down a rational basis for an anarchist
utopia as the conscious aim of the revolutionary movement of the class
which his master Saint Simon had called âthe most numerous and most
poor.â Since the critique of the State led him to envisage the
possibility of a society free from all political authority, he had to go
on to make a critique of the economic system which ensured the material
basis of the State. The ethical rejection of money also implied an
analysis of political economy, the science of the enrichment of some and
of the impoverishment of others. Later he was to describe the research
he was about to begin on the âanatomy of bourgeois societyâ and it was
by engaging in this work of social anatomy that he was to work out his
methodology. Later the rediscovery of the Hegelian dialectic would help
him to establish the plan of the âEconomyâ under six âheadingsâ or
âbooksâ: Capital, Landed Property, Wage Labour; The State, Foreign
Trade, World Market (see Preface to the Critique of Political Economy,
1859). In fact, this double âtriadâ of items for research corresponds to
the two problems which he had proposed to deal with fourteen years
previously in the work which was to contain a critique of both political
economy and politics. Marx began his work with the critical analysis of
the capitalist mode of production, but he hoped to live and work long
enough not only to complete this but also, once he had completed the
first triad of headings, to begin on the second triad which would thus
have found the Book on the State.[2] The theory of anarchism would thus
have found in Marx its first recognised exponent without there being any
need to prove this indirectly. The misunderstanding of the century of
Marxism as an ideology of the State was the result of the fact that Marx
never wrote this book. It was this which has allowed the masters of a
State apparatus labelled socialist to include Marx among the proponents
of State socialism or communism, indeed even of âauthoritarianâ
socialism.
Certainly, like every revolutionary teaching, that of Marx is not free
from ambiguities. It is by cleverly exploiting these ambiguities and by
referring to certain personal attitudes of the master that some of his
unscrupulous disciples have succeeded in putting his work at the service
of doctrines and actions which represent, in relation to both its basic
truth and its declared objective, its complete negation. At a time when
many decades of regression in human relations have called into question
all theories, values, systems and projects, it is important to gather
together the intellectual heritage of an author who, aware of the limits
of his research, made the call for critical self-education and
revolutionary self-emancipation the permanent principle of the workersâ
movement. It is not up to posterity burdened with overwhelming
responsibilities to judge a man who can no longer plead his cause; but
on the other hand it is our duty to take up a teaching which was
completely oriented towards the future, a future which certainly became
our catastrophic present but which mostly still remains to be created.
We repeat: the âBookâ on the State, foreshadowed in the plan of the
Economy but which remained unwritten, could only have contained the
theory of society freed from the State, anarchist society. Although not
directly intended for this work, the materials and works prepared or
published by Marx in the course of his literary activity allow us both
to put forward this hypothesis about the content of the planned work and
to work out what its general structure would have been. While the first
triad of headings was part of the critique of political economy, the
second would have put forward essentially a critique of politics.
Following on from the critique of capital, the critique of the State
would have established what determined the political evolution of modern
society, just as the purpose of Capital (followed by the Books on
âLanded Propertyâ and âWage Labourâ) was to âlay bare the economic law
of motion of modern societyâ (cf. Preface to Capital, 1867). In the same
way that the principles and postulates which motivated Marx when making
his critique of capital are to be found in his published and unpublished
writings prior to the Critique of Political Economy (1859), so we can
extract from these writings those which would have guided him in
developing his criticism of the State. It would however be a mistake to
suppose that at this time Marxâs thought on the nature of politics was
established in its final form, with no possibility of modifying details
and closed to all theoretical enrichment. Quite the contrary. The
problem of the State never ceased to concern Marx not only because he
failed to keep the moral engagement to finish his master work, but above
all because it was constantly kept in his mind by his participation and
polemical confrontations after September 1864 within the International
Workingmenâs Association and by political events, particularly the
rivalry for leadership between France and Prussia on the one hand and
Russia and Austria on the other. The Europe of the Treaty of Vienna had
then become no more than a fiction, while two important social phenomena
had made their appearance on the scene of history: movements for
national liberation and the workersâ movement. The struggle between
nations and the class struggle, which were difficult to reconcile from a
purely conceptual point of view, were to raise problems of theory
requiring decisions by Marx and Engels which could not but bring them
into contradiction with their own revolutionary principles. Engels made
a speciality of differentiating between peoples and nations according to
how, in his eyes, they could or could not claim the historical right to
national existence. Their sense of historical realities prevented the
two friends from following Proudhon in the way of a federalism which, in
the situation of the time, must have seemed both a pure abstraction and
an impure utopia; but they risked falling into a nationalism which was
incompatible with the universalism of the modern proletariat they had
posited.
If Proudhon, by his federalist aspirations, seems to be nearer than Marx
to the anarchist position, the picture changes when we consider
Proudhonâs overall conception of the reforms which should lead to the
abolition of capital and the State. The almost excessive praise of which
Proudhon is the object in the Holy Family (1845) should not mislead us.
From this time on there were deep theoretical differences between the
two men; the praise had only been conceded to the French socialist with
a very important reservation: Proudhonâs critique of property was
implicit in the bourgeois economic system, but however valid it might be
it did not call into question the social relations of the system which
it criticised. Quite the contrary. In Proudhonâs doctrine, the economic
categories, which were theoretical expressions of the institutions of
capital, were all systematically preserved. Proudhonâs merit was to have
revealed the inherent contradictions of economic science and to have
shown the immorality of bourgeois morality and law; his weakness was to
have accepted the categories and institutions of the capitalist economy
and to have respected, in his programme of reforms and solutions, all
the instruments of the bourgeois class and its political power: wages,
credit, banks, exchange, price, value, profit, interest, taxes,
competition, monopoly. After applying the dialectic of the negation in
his analysis of the evolution of law and legal systems, he stopped
half-way by not extending his critical method of the negation to the
capitalist economy. Proudhon opened the way for such a criticism, but it
was Marx who was to create this new method of criticism and to try to
use it as a weapon in the struggle of labour against capital and the
State.
Proudhon had made his critique of bourgeois economics and law in the
name of bourgeois morality; Marx was to make his criticism in the name
of proletarian ethics, whose standards of judgement were taken from
quite a different vision of human society. To do this he only had to
follow to its logical conclusion Proudhonâs â or rather Hegelâs â
principle of negation: the Justice of which Proudhon dreamed could only
be established by the negation of justice just as philosophy could only
be put into practice by the negation of philosophy, i.e., by a social
revolution which would at last allow humanity to become social and
society to be become human. This would be the end of the pre-history of
humanity and the beginning of individual life, the appearance of
fully-developed Man, with all-round faculties, the coming of complete
Man. Marx opposed the realist morality of Proudhon, which sought to save
the âgood sideâ of bourgeois institutions, with the ethic of a utopia
whose demands would be measured by the possibilities offered by a
science and technology sufficiently developed to provide for the needs
of the race. Marx opposed an anarchism which respected the plurality of
classes and social categories, which favoured the division of labour and
which was hostile to the associationists proposed by the utopians, with
an anarchism which rejected social classes and the division of labour, a
communism which took over all in utopian socialism that could be
achieved by a proletariat which was conscious of its emancipating role
and which had become master of the forces of production. However, in
spite of these divergent means â in particular, as we shall see, a
different attitude towards political action â the two types of anarchism
aimed at a common end which the Communist Manifesto defined in these
terms:
âIn place of the old bourgeois society, with its classes and class
antagonisms, we shall have an association, in which the free development
of each is the condition for the free development of all.â
Marx refused to invent recipes for the cooking pots of the future, but
he did better â or worse â than this: he wanted to show that historical
necessity â like some blind fate â was leading humanity to a situation
of crisis where it would face a decisive dilemma: to be destroyed by its
own technical inventions or to survive thanks to a leap in consciousness
which would allow it to break with all the forms of alienation and
servitude which had marked the stages of its history. Only this dilemma
was fated, the actual choice would be left to the social class which had
every reason to reject the existing order and to establish a
fundamentally different mode of existence. The modern proletariat was
potentially the material and moral force that was capable of taking up
this universally significant task of salvation. However this potential
force could not become real until the bourgeois period had been
completed. For the bourgeoisie too had a historical role to play. If it
had not always been conscious of this, then its apologists had had the
task of reminding it of its civilising role. In creating the world in
its image, the bourgeoisie of the industrially developed countries
embourgeoisified and proletarianised the societies which progressively
fell under its political and economic control. Seen from the viewpoint
of proletarian interests, these instruments of conquest, capital and the
State, were just means of servitude and suppression, but when the
relations of capitalist production and therefore of capitalist States
had been firmly established on a world scale, then the internal
contradictions of the world market would reveal the limits of capital
accumulation and provoke a state of permanent crisis which would
endanger the foundations of the enslaved societies and threaten the very
survival of the human race. The hour of the proletarian revolution would
sound the world over.
By extrapolating reasonably we have been able to see the logical
conclusions of the dialectical method employed by Marx in laying bare
the economic law of movement of modern society. We could back up this
view with textual references beginning with the remarks on methodology
which can be gleaned from many of Marxâs writings dating from different
periods. It is no less true that the hypothesis which Marx most
frequently offers us in his political works is that of the proletarian
revolution in the countries which have known a long period of bourgeois
civilization and capitalist economy; such a revolution would mark the
beginning of a process of development which would gradually involve the
rest of the world, historical progress being hastened through the
revolution being contagious. But whatever the hypothesis Marx had in
mind, one thing is clear: his social theory had no place for a third
revolutionary way where countries which lacked the historical experience
of developed capitalism and bourgeois democracy would show the way to
proletarian revolution to countries which had had a long capitalist and
bourgeois past.
We recall with particular insistence these elementary truths of the
conception of history called materialist because the Marxist mythology
born with the 1917 Russian revolution has succeeded in imposing on the
uniformed â and they were legion â another view of the process of this
revolution: humanity divided into two economic and political systems,
the capitalist world dominated by the industrially developed countries
and the socialist world the model for which, the USSR, had reached the
rank of second world power following a âproletarianâ revolution. In
fact, the industrialisation of Russia has been due to the creation and
exploitation of an immense proletariat and not to its triumph and
abolition. The fiction of the âdictatorship of the proletariatâ forms
part of the arsenal of ideas which the new masters have imposed in the
interests of their own power: six decades of nationalist and military
barbarism on a world scale explain the mental confusion of an
intelligentsia which has been completely misled by the myth of
âsocialist October.â[3]
Since we cannot deepen the discussion here we will restrict ourselves to
expressing our point of view in the form of an alternative: either the
materialist theory of social development has some scientific validity â
Marx himself was naturally persuaded of this â and in this case the
âsocialistâ world is a myth or the socialist world really exists and the
materialist theory of social development is completely and totally
invalidated. On the first hypothesis the myth of the socialist world is
perfectly explained: it would be the fruit of a well-organised
ideological campaign by the âfirst workersâ Stateâ aimed at disguising
its real nature. On the second hypothesis the materialist theory of how
the world would become socialist would certainly be disproved, but the
ethical and utopian demands of Marxâs teaching would have been achieved;
in other words, refuted by history as a man of science, Marx would have
triumphed as a revolutionary.
The myth of âreally existing socialismâ has been constructed in order to
morally justify one of the most powerful forms of dominating and
exploitative society that history had known. The problem of the nature
of this society has completely confused those most informed about the
theories, doctrines and ideas which together form the intellectual
heritage of socialism, communism and anarchism. Of these three schools â
or currents â of the movement of ideas which seeks a fundamental change
in human society, anarchism has suffered the least from this perversion.
Not having created a real theory of revolutionary practice, it has been
able to preserve itself from the political and ideological corruption
which has struck the two other schools of thought. Originating from
dreams and longings for the past as well as from rejection and revolt,
anarchism was formed as a radical criticism of the principle of
authority in all its forms, and it is above all as such that it was
incorporated into the materialist conception of history. This latter is
essentially the view that the historical evolution of humanity passes by
progressive stages from a permanent state of social antagonism to a mode
of existence based on social harmony and individual development. The
common aim of pre-Marxian radical and revolutionary doctrines became an
integral part of Marxâs anarchist communism just as the social criticism
transmitted by the anarchist utopia had. With Marx, utopian anarchism
was enriched by a new dimension, that of the dialectical understanding
of the workersâ movement as an ethical self-liberation embracing the
whole of humanity. The dialectical element in a theory claiming to be
scientific, indeed naturalistic, caused an intellectual strain which was
inevitably the source of the fundamental ambiguity with which Marxâs
teaching and activity is indelibly marked. Marx, who was a militant as
well as a theorist, did not always seek to harmonise in his political
activity the ends and means of anarchist communism. But the fact that he
failed as a militant does not mean that he therefore ceased to be the
theoretician of anarchism . It is thus right to apply to his own theory
the ethical thesis which he formulated with regard to Feuerbachâs
materialism (1845):
âThe question whether human thinking can pretend to objective truth is
not a theoretical but a practical question. Man must prove the truth,
i.e. the reality and power, the âthis-sidenessâ of his thinking in
practice.â[4]
The negation of the State and capitalism by the most numerous and most
poor class appears in Marx as an ethical imperative before he
demonstrated dialectically that it was a historical necessity. In its
first form, in Marxâs critical assessment of the French Revolution, it
represented a decisive choice to be made: the objective which according
to Marx humanity should strive to achieve. This objective was precisely
human emancipation by going beyond political emancipation. The freest
political State â of which the Unites States of America provided the
only example â made Man a slave because it intervened as mediator
between Man and his freedom, just like the Christ in whom the religious
person vests his own divinity. Man when politically emancipated still
only had an imaginary sovereignty. As a sovereign being enjoying the
Rights of Man he led a double existence: that of a citizen of the
political community and that of an individual member of society; that of
a heavenly and that of an earthly being. As a citizen he was free and
sovereign in the skies of politics, that universal kingdom of equality.
As an individual he was degraded in his real life, bourgeois life, and
reduced to the level of a means for his neighbour; he was the plaything
of alien forces, material and moral, such as the institutions of private
property, culture, religion, etc. Bourgeois society separated from the
political State was the realm of egoism, of the war of each against all,
of the separation of man from man. Political democracy had not freed Man
from religion by ensuring his religious liberty, any more than it freed
him from property in guaranteeing him the right to property. Similarly
when it granted everyone the freedom to choose his occupation political
democracy maintained occupational slavery and egoism. Bourgeois society
was the world of trafficking and profiting, the reign of money, the
universal power which had subjected politics and hence the State.
Such, in summary, was Marxâs initial thesis. It was a critique of the
State and capital and it belonged to anarchist thought rather than to
any socialism or communism. There was not yet anything scientific about
it, but it implicitly appealed to and based itself on an ethical
conception of the destiny of humanity in that it insisted on the need of
doing something within the framework of historical time. This is why he
did not just make a critique of political emancipation â that it reduced
man to being an egoistic monad and an abstract citizen â but put forward
both the end to be achieved and the means of achieving it:
âOnly when the real, individual man re-absorbs in himself the abstract
citizen, and as an individual human being has become a species-being in
his everyday life, in his particular work, and in his particular
situation, only when man has recognized and organized his âown powersâ
as social powers, and, consequently, no longer separates social power
from himself in the shape of political power, only then will human
emancipation have been accomplished.â[5]
Marx developed his own theory by starting from the Social Contract of
Rousseau, the theoretician of the abstract citizen and precursor of
Hegel. Rejecting only partially the political alienation which these two
thinkers proposed, he arrived at the vision of a human and social
emancipation that would re-establish the individual as a complete being
with fully developed faculties. This rejection was only partial because
this state of political alienation, as a fact of history, could not be
abolished by an act of will. Political emancipation was âa great
progress,â it was even the last form of human emancipation within the
established order, and it is as such that it could serve as a means to
overthrow this order and inaugurate the stage of real human
emancipation. The means and the end were dialectical opposites but were
reconciled ethically in the consciousness of the modern proletariat
which thus became the bearer and historical subject of the revolution.
The proletariat, as a class in which were concentrated all the evils and
which embodied the well-known crimes of all society, possessed a
universal character as a result of its universal poverty. It could not
emancipate itself without emancipating all spheres of society, and it
was by putting into practice the demands of this ethic of emancipation
that it would abolish itself as a proletariat.
Where Marx speaks of philosophy as the âheadâ and intellectual arm of
the human emancipation of which the proletariat would be the âheart,â we
prefer to speak of an ethic in order to show that it is not a question
of metaphysical speculation but a problem of existence: people should
not interpret a caricature of the world but should change it by giving
it a human face. No speculative philosophy had any solution to offer Man
for his problems of existence. This was why Marx, when he made the
revolution a categorical imperative, reasoned from a normative ethic and
not from a philosophy of history or a sociological theory. Because he
could not and did not want to limit himself to a purely ethical demand
for the regeneration of humanity and society Marxâs interest was then
aroused by one particular science: the science of the production of the
means of existence according to the law of capital.
Marx thus undertook the study of political economy as a means of
struggling for the cause to which from that time on he was to devote his
whole declassĂ© âbourgeoisâ existence. What till then had only been a
visionary institution and an ethical choice was to become a theory of
economic development and a study of what determined societies. But it
was also to be active participation in the social movement whose task
was to put into practice the ethical demands which derived from the
conditions of existence of the modern proletariat. Both the vision of a
society without State, without classes, without monetary exchange,
without religious and intellectual fears and the analysis which revealed
the process of evolution that would lead by successive steps to forms of
anarchist and communist society implied a theoretical critique of the
capitalist mode of production. Marx was to write later:
âEven when a society has got upon the right track for the discovery of
the natural laws of its movement ... it can neither clear by bold leaps,
nor remove by legal enactments, the obstacles offered by the successive
phases of its normal development. But it can shorten and lessen the
birth-pangs.â ( Preface to Capital, Volume I)
In short, Marx set out to demonstrate scientifically what he was already
persuaded of intuitively and what appeared to him to be ethically
necessary. It was in his first attempt at a critique of political
economy that he came to analyse capital from a sociological point of
view as the power to command labour and its products, a power which the
capitalist possessed not by virtue of his personal or human qualities
but as the owner of property. The wages system was a form of slavery;
any authoritarian raising of wages would only mean better rations for
the slaves:
âEven the equality of wages, which Proudhon demands, would merely
transform the relation of the present-day worker to his work into the
relation of all men to work. Society would then be conceived as an
abstract capitalist.â[6]
Economic slavery and political servitude went together. Political
emancipation, i.e., the recognition of the Rights of Man by the modern
State, had the same significance as the recognition of slavery by the
State of antiquity (The Holy Family, 1845). The worker was a slave to
his paid occupation and also to his own egoistic needs experienced as
alien needs. People were just as much subject to political servitude in
the democratic representative State as in a constitutional monarchy. âIn
the modern world, everybody is at the same time a slave and a member of
the community,â although the servitude of bourgeois society takes the
form of the maximum of freedom (ibid.). Property, industry and religion,
which are generally regarded as guarantees of individual liberty, were
in fact institutions which sanctified this state of servitude.
Robespierre, Saint-Just and their partisans failed because they did not
distinguish antiquity based on real slavery from the modern
representative State based on emancipated slavery, i.e., bourgeois
society with its universal competition, its unbridled private interests
and its alienated individualism. Napoleon, who understood perfectly the
nature of the modern State and modern society, considered the State as
an end in itself and bourgeois society as the instrument of his
political ambitions. To satisfy the egoism of the French nation, he
instituted permanent war in place of permanent revolution. His defeat
confirmed the victory of the liberal bourgeoisie which in 1830 was
finally able to make its dreams of 1789 become true: to make the
constitutional representative State the social expression of its
monopoly of power and sectional interests.
Marx, as a permanent observer of both the political evolution and
economic development of French society, was constantly concerned with
the problem of Bonapartism.[7] He considered that the French Revolution
was the classic period of the political idea and that the Bonapartist
tradition was a constant of the internal and external politics of
France. He also outlined a theory of modern Caesarism which, even if it
seemed to contradict in part the methodological principles of his theory
of the State, did not modify his initial anarchist vision. For at the
very time he was getting ready to set out the basic principles of his
materialist conception of history he had formulated the following
conception of the State which places him amongst the most radical
anarchism:
âThe existence of the state is inseparable from the existence of slavery
... The more powerful a state and hence the more political a nation, the
less inclined it is to explain the general principle governing social
ills and to seek out their causes by looking at the principle of the
state â i.e., at the actual organization of society of which the state
is the active, self-conscious and official expression.â[8]
The example of the French Revolution seemed to him at that time to be
sufficiently convincing to make him put forward a view which only
corresponded in part to the political sociology which he was soon to set
out in the German Ideology, but which can be found much later in his
reflections on the Second Empire and the 1871 Commune.
âFar from identifying the principle of the state as the source of social
ills, the heroes of the French Revolution held social ills to be the
source of political problems. Thus Robespierre regarded great wealth and
great poverty as an obstacle to pure democracy. He therefore wished to
establish a universal system of Spartan frugality. The principle of
politics is the will.â[9]
When twenty-seven years later in connexion with the Paris Commune Marx
was to return to the historical origins of the political absolutism
which the Bonapartist State represented, he was to see in the
centralisation carried out by the French Revolution the continuation of
the traditions of the monarchy:
âThe centralized State machinery which, with its ubiquitous and
complicated military, bureaucratic, clerical and judiciary organs,
entoils (enmeshes) the living civil society like a boa constrictor, was
first forged in the days of absolute monarchy as a weapon of nascent
modern society in its struggle of emancipation from feudalism ... The
first French Revolution with its task to found national unity (to create
a nation) ... was, therefore, forced to develop, what absolute monarchy
had commenced, the centralization and organization of State power, and
to expand the circumference and the attributes of the State power, the
number of its tools, its independence, and its supernaturalist sway of
real society ... Every minor solitary interest engendered by the
relations of social groups was separated from society itself, fixed and
made independent of it and opposed to it in the form of State interest,
administered by State priests with exactly determined hierarchical
functions.â[10]
This passionate denunciation of the power of the State in some way sums
up all the work of study and critical reflection which Marx carried out
in this field: his confrontation with the moral and political philosophy
of Hegel; the period during which he worked out the materialist
conception of history; his fifteen years of political and professional
journalism; and, not to be forgotten, his intense activity within the
International Workingmenâs Association. The Commune seems to have given
Marx the opportunity to put the finishing touches to his thoughts on the
problem for which he had reserved one of the six books of his Economy
and to give a picture, if only in outline, of that free association of
free men whose coming had been announced by the Communist Manifesto.
âThis was, therefore, a revolution not against this or that, legitimate,
constitutional, republican or imperialist form of State power. It was a
revolution against the State itself, of this supernaturalist abortion of
society, a resumption by the people for the people of its own social
life.â[11]
Comparing how the serfs had been emancipated from the feudal regime with
the emancipation of the modern working class, Marx noted that, unlike
the proletarians, the serfs had to struggle to allow existing social
conditions to develop freely and as a result could only arrive at âfree
labour.â The proletarians, on the other hand, had, in order to affirm
themselves as individuals, to abolish their own social condition; since
this was the same as that of the whole of society, they had to abolish
wage labour. And he added this sentence which from then on was to serve
as the theme of both his literary work and his activity as a communist
militant:
âThus they [the proletarians] find themselves directly opposed to the
form in which, hitherto, the individuals, of which society consists,
have given themselves collective expression, that is, the State. In
order, therefore, to assert themselves as individuals, they must
overthrow the State.â[12]
This view, which was nearer to the anarchism of Bakunin than to that of
Proudhon, was not uttered in the heat of the moment nor was it the
rhetoric of a politician haranguing a workersâ meeting. It was the
logical conclusion, expressed as a revolutionary demand, of the whole
development of a theory whose purpose was to demonstrate the âhistorical
necessityâ of the anarchist commune. In other words, in Marxâs theory,
the coming of âhuman societyâ was seen as the outcome of a long
historical process. Eventually, a social class would arise which would
comprise the immense majority of the population of industrial society
and which as such would be capable of carrying out a creative
revolutionary task. It was to show the logic of this development that
Marx sought to establish a causal link between scientific progress â
above all that of the natural sciences â and, on the one hand, political
and legal institutions and, on the other, the behaviour of antagonistic
social classes. Unlike Engels, Marx did not consider that the future
revolutionary transformation would take place in the same way as past
revolutions, like a cataclysm of Nature crushing men, things and
consciousness. With the coming of the modern working class, the human
race began the cycle of its real history; it entered on the way of
reason and became capable of making its dreams come true and of giving
itself a destiny in accordance with its creative faculties. The
conquests of science and technology made such an outcome possible, but
the proletariat had to intervene in order to prevent the bourgeoisie and
capital from changing this evolution into a march into the abyss:
âThe victories of art seem bought by the loss of character. At the same
pace that mankind masters nature, man seems to become enslaved to other
men or to his own infamy.â[13]
So the proletarian revolution would not be a political adventure; it
would be a universal act, carried out consciously by the immense
majority of the members of society after they had become conscious of
the necessity and the possibility of the total regeneration of humanity.
As history had become world history the threat of enslavement by capital
and its market extended all over the Earth. As a consequence there had
to arise a mass consciousness and will fully oriented towards a
fundamental and complete change of human relationships and social
institutions. So long as peopleâs survival is threatened by the danger
of a barbarism of planetary dimensions, the communist and anarchist
dreams and utopias represent the intellectual source of rational
projects and practical reforms which can give the human race the taste
of a life according to the standards of a reason and an imagination both
oriented towards renewing the destiny of humanity.
There is no leap from the realm of necessity to the realm of freedom, as
Engels thought, and there cannot be a direct transition from capitalism
to anarchism. The economic and social barbarism brought about by the
capitalist mode of production cannot be abolished by a political
revolution prepared, organised and led by an elite of professional
revolutionaries claiming to act and think in the name and for the
benefit of the exploited and alienated majority. The proletariat, formed
into a class and a party under the conditions of bourgeois democracy,
liberates itself by struggling to conquer this democracy: it turns
universal suffrage, which up till then had been âan instrument of
deception,â into a means of emancipation. A class which comprises the
immense majority of modern society only takes alienating political
action in order to triumph over politics and only conquers State power
to use it against the formerly dominant minority. The conquest of
political power is by nature a âbourgeoisâ act; it only becomes a
proletarian action by the revolutionary aim which the authors of this
overthrow give to it. This is the meaning of the historical period which
Marx was not afraid to call the âdictatorship of the proletariat,â
precisely to differentiate it from a dictatorship exercised by an elite,
dictatorship in the Jacobin and Blanquist sense of the term. Certainly,
Marx, in claiming the merit of having discovered the secret of the
historical development of modes of production and domination, could not
have foreseen that his teaching would be usurped by professional
revolutionaries and other politicians claiming the right to personify
the dictatorship of the proletariat. In fact, he only envisaged this
form of social transition for countries whose proletariat had been able
to make use of the period of bourgeois democracy to create its own
institutions and made itself the dominant class in society. Compared
with the many centuries of violence and corruption that capitalism had
needed to come to dominate the world, the length of the process of
transition to anarchist society would be shorter and less violent to the
extent that the concentration of political power would bring a mass
proletariat face to face with a numerically weak bourgeoisie:
âThe transformation of scattered private property, arising from
individual labour, into capitalist private property is, naturally, a
process, incomparably more protracted, violent, and difficult, than the
transformation of capitalistic private property, already practically
resting on socialized production, into socialized property. In the
former case, we had the expropriation of the mass of the people by a few
usurpers; in the latter, we have the expropriation of a few usurpers by
the mass of the people.â[14]
Marx did not work out all the details of a theory of the transition; in
fact noticeably different views can be found in the various theoretical
and practical outlines which are scattered throughout his works.
Nevertheless, throughout these differences, indeed contradictory
statements, a basic principle remains intact and constant to the extent
of allowing a coherent reconstruction of such a theory. It is perhaps on
this point that the myth of the founding of âMarxismâ by Marx and Engels
is seen at its most harmful. While the former made the postulate of a
proletarian self-activity the criterion of all genuine class action and
all genuine conquest of political power, the latter ended up,
particularly after the death of his friend, by separating the two
elements in the creation of the workersâ movement: the class action â
the SelbsttĂ€tigkeit â of the proletariat on the one hand and the policy
of the party on the other. Marx thought that communist and anarchist
self-education was, more than any isolated political act, an integral
part of the revolutionary activity of the workers: it was the workersâ
task to make themselves fit for the conquest and exercise of political
power as a means of resisting attempts by the bourgeoisie to reconquer
and recover its power. The proletariat had to temporarily and
consciously form itself into a material force in order to defend its
right and project to transform society by progressively establishing the
Human Community. It was in struggling to affirm itself as a force of
abolition and creation that the working class â which âof all the
instruments of production is the most productiveâ â took up the
dialectical project of creative negation; it took the risk of political
alienation in order to make politics superfluous. Such a project had
nothing in common with the destructive passion of a Bakunin or the
anarchist apocalypse of a Coeurderoy. Revolutionary purism had no place
in this political project whose aim was to make real the potential
supremacy of the oppressed and exploited masses. Marx thought that the
International Workingmenâs Association, which combined the power of
numbers with a revolutionary spirit conceived of in a quite different
way from Proudhonian anarchism, could become such a fighting
organisation. In joining the IWMA, Marx did not abandon the position he
had taken against Proudhon in 1847, when he put forward an
anti-political anarchism to be achieved by a political movement:
âDoes this mean that after the fall of the old society there will be a
new class domination culminating in a new political power? No ... The
working class, in the course of its development, will substitute for the
old civil society an association which will exclude classes and their
antagonism, and there will be no more political power properly
so-called, since political power is precisely the official expression of
antagonism in civil society. Meanwhile the antagonism between the
proletariat and the bourgeoisie is a struggle of class against class, a
struggle which carried to its highest expression is a total revolution.
Indeed, is it at all surprising that a society founded on the opposition
of classes should culminate in brutal contradiction, the shock of body
against body, as its final denouement? Do not say that social movement
excludes political movement. There is never a political movement which
is not at the same time social. It is only in an order of things in
which there are no more classes and class antagonisms that social
evolutions will cease to be political revolutions.â[15]
Marxâs point here is quite realistic and free from all idealism. This
address to the future must be clearly understood to be the expression of
a normative project committing the workers to behave as revolutionaries
while struggling politically. âThe working class is revolutionary or it
is nothingâ (letter to J.B. Schweitzer, 1865). This is the language of a
thinker whose rigorous dialectic, in contrast to a Proudhon or a
Stirner, rejects impressing people by the systematic use of gratuitous
paradox and verbal violence. And while everything is not and cannot be
settled by this demonstration of means and ends, its merit is at least
to urge the victims of alienated labour to understand and educate
themselves through undertaking together a great work of collective
creation. In this sense, Marxâs appeal remains relevant, despite the
triumph of Marxism and even because of it.
The limits of this essay do not allow us to go further in proving this.
So we will limit ourselves to citing three texts which demolish in
advance the legend â Bakuninist and Leninist â of a Marx âworshipper of
the Stateâ and âapostle of State communismâ or of the dictatorship of
the proletariat as the dictatorship of a party, indeed of a single man:
Russian).â Main themes: dictatorship of the proletariat and the
maintenance of small peasant property; economic conditions and social
revolution; disappearance of the State and the transformation of
political functions into administrative functions of self-managed
co-operative communes.
Programme) (1875). Main themes: the two phases of communist society
based on the co-operative mode of production; the bourgeoisie as a
revolutionary class; the international action of the working class;
criticism of the âiron law of wagesâ; revolutionary role of workersâ
productive co-operatives; primary education freed from the influence of
religion and the State; revolutionary dictatorship of the proletariat as
a political transition to the transformation of State functions into
social functions.
Vera Zasulitch)(1881). Main themes: the rural commune as an element of
regeneration of Russian society; ambivalence of the commune and
influence of historical background; development of the commune and the
crisis of capitalism; peasant emancipation and taxation; negative
influences and risks of disappearance of the commune; the Russian
commune, threatened by the State and capital, will only be saved by the
Russian revolution.
These three documents to some extent make up the essence of the book
which Marx considered writing on the State.
It can be seen from these remarks that Marx expressly presented his
social theory as an attempt at an objective analysis of a historical
movement and not as a moral or political code of revolutionary practice
aimed at establishing an ideal society; as the laying bare of a process
of development involving things and individuals and not as a collection
of rules for use by parties and elites seeking power. This, however, is
only the external and declared aspect of a theory which has two
conceptual tracks, one rigorously determined, the other freely making
its way towards the visionary aim of an anarchist society:
âThe social revolution of the nineteenth century cannot take its poetry
from the past but only from the future. It cannot begin with itself
before it has stripped away all superstition about the past.â[16]
The past is an unchangeable necessity; and the observer, equipped with
all the instruments of analysis, is in a position to explain the series
of phenomena which have been perceived. But while it is a vain hope that
all the dreams which humanity, through its prophets and visionaries, has
entertained will come true, the future could at least bring an end to
the institutions which have reduced peopleâs lives to a permanent state
of servitude in all social fields. This is, briefly, the link between
theory and utopia in the teaching of Marx who expressly proclaimed
himself an âanarchistâ when he wrote:
âAll socialists see anarchy as the following program: Once the aim of
the proletarian movement â i.e., abolition of classes â is attained, the
power of the state, which serves to keep the great majority of producers
in bondage to a very small exploiter minority, disappears, and the
functions of government become simple administrative functions.â[17]
The essay above does not take into account the ideas of Frederick Engels
on the State and anarchism. Without entering into the details of his
view, we can say that it does not completely coincide with that of Marx,
although it too proposes the final disappearance of the State. The most
important passages in this connection are to be found in Anti-DĂŒhring
(1877â8) which to some extent had Marxâs imprimatur. Engels here sees
the conquest of State power and the transformation of the means of
production into State property as the self-abolition of the proletariat
and the abolition of class antagonisms, indeed of âthe suppression of
the State as State.â Further on he describes this âabolitionâ of the
State as âa dying outâ of the State: âDer Staat wird nicht
âabgeschafftâ, er stirbt ab.â After Marxâs death, drawing his
inspiration from the notes left by his friend on Lewis Henry Morganâs
Ancient Society, Engels again dealt with the subject but in a wider
socio-historical context. The highest form of the State, the democratic
republic, is considered by Engels as the final phase of politics during
which the decisive struggle between the bourgeoisie and proletariat will
take place; the exploited class becomes ready for self-emancipation and
forms itself into an independent party: âuniversal suffrage is the gauge
of the maturity of the working classâ â and that suffices to do away
with capitalism and the State, and hence with class society. âAlong with
them [i.e., classes] the State will inevitably fall. The society ...
will put the whole of the machinery of State where it will then belong:
into the Museum of Antiquities, by the side of the spinning wheel and
the bronze axe.â[18] See also Engelsâs letters to Philip Van Patten of
18 April 1883 and to Edward Bernstein of 28 January 1884. In the latter
Engels quotes some passages from the Poverty of Philosophy (1847) and
the Communist Manifesto (1848) to prove âthat we proclaimed the end
[âAufhörenâ] of the State before there were really any anarchists.â
Engels undoubtedly exaggerated â a mention only of William Godwin would
invalidate this view, without referring to the others who were won over
to anarchism through reading Political Justice (1793).
[1] âThe Leading Article in No. 179 of the Kölnische Zeitung.â
Rheinische Zeitung, 10â14 July 1842.
[2] See âplan et mĂ©thode de lâEconomieâ in M. Rubel, Marx, Critique du
Marxisme, Payot, Paris, 1974, pp. 369â401.
[3] See Marx, Critique du Marxisme, pp. 63â168, for a further
development of the themes of the myth of âproletarian Octoberâ and of
Russian society as a form of capitalism.
[4] Second Thesis on Feuerbach, as translated in Karl Marx, Selected
Writings in Sociology and Social Philosophy, edited T.B. Bottomore and
M. Rubel, Pelican, 1963, p. 82.
[5] âOn the Jewish Question,â Deutsch-französische JarbĂŒcher, February
1844.
[6] Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, section on âEstranged
Labour,â 1844.
[7] See M. Rubel, Karl Marx devant le bonapartisme, Mouton & Co.,
Paris-The Hague, 1960.
[8] âCritical Remarks on the Article: The King of Prussia and Social
Reform. By a Prussian,â VorwĂ€rts, 7 and 10 August 1844.
[9] Ibid.
[10] The Civil War in France, First Draft, section on âThe Character of
the Communeâ, 1871.
[11] Ibid.
[12] The German Ideology, 1845, edited by C.J. Arthur, Lawrence &
Wishart, London, 1970, p. 85.
[13] Speech at anniversary of the Peopleâs Paper, 14 April 1856.
[14] Capital, Vol. I, end of chapter XXXII.
[15] Poverty of Philosophy, 1847, chapter II, part 5.
[16] The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon, 1851.
[17] Fictitious Splits in the International, 1872.
[18] The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State, chapter
IX.