💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › daniel-guerin-two-indictments-of-communism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:09:53. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Two Indictments of Communism
Author: Daniel Guérin
Date: 1957
Language: en
Topics: Communism, libertarian communism
Source: Chapter from *For a Libertarian Communism*
Notes: Originally from Jeunesse du socialisme libertaire.

Daniel Guérin

Two Indictments of Communism

Two books that appeared simultaneously, those of Tito’s prisoner Milovan

Djilas and Michel Collinet,[1] have led us to rethink the ideological

foundations of Bolshevism. Even though produced by two men of different

temperaments and origins and using quite divergent methods, they reach

more or less the same conclusions and present more or less the same

qualities, as well as the same defects.

One of their merits is to demonstrate that the Blanquist concept of the

party formulated by Lenin from 1901 contained at least in germ the

totalitarian communism of the Stalinist era. Djilas and Collinet stress

that the ideological monopoly of the leadership of the party, in this

case Lenin himself, claiming to embody the objective aspirations of

society,[2] was in fact an idealist conception of history that would

later result in the total monopolization of the bureaucratic apparatus

over that society.[3]

Where the two writers diverge is on the historical excuse of

“necessity.” Djilas, still incompletely freed of the authoritarian

concepts he was brought up on, believes that the success of the

revolution, which had to defend its very existence and the indispensable

industrialization of the USSR, required the establishment of a tyranny.

Collinet, on the contrary, condemns Lenin for having made a virtue of

necessity, and does not think totalitarian dictatorship necessarily

flowed from the tragic circumstances of the Civil War.[4]

While establishing a direct connection between Leninism and Stalinism,

the two authors stress, correctly, that under no circumstances can the

two regimes be confused and that differences of an important nature

distinguish them, and not simple “nuances.” as Collinet once lets slip.

Forms that were still revolutionary during Lenin’s time were transformed

into reactionary ones under Stalin.

Collinet and Djilas, in the most solid part of their work, provide both

brilliant and implacable descriptions of the privileged “new class.” of

the feudal bureaucracy that seized power in the USSR. For Collinet

today’s Russian society realizes “the most perfect absorption of society

by the state that history has ever seen.” and for Djilas modern history

has never recorded a regime oppressing the masses in so brutal,

inhumane, and illegal a fashion. The methods it employed constitute “one

of the most shameful pages of human history.” And in a flight of

inspiration, he opposes the idealism, devotion, and spirit of sacrifice

of communism of its early days to the intolerance, corruption,

stagnation, and intellectual decadence of contemporary communism. The

analysis of the “new class,” of the way it exploits the working class

and its poor economic management, is more acute in Djilas than it is in

Collinet: Djilas—and this is the main interest of his book—is a witness

who lived the evil from within.

The two authors are in agreement in denouncing the thirst for and

obsession with power of the communist oligarchs, as well as in

stigmatizing the transformation of Marxism into a dogmatism, into an

essentially sterile and conservative scholasticism.

Both Collinet and Djilas reproach Trotsky, not without reason and almost

in the same terms, for having shown himself incapable, despite the great

merit of his indictment of Stalinism, of defining sociologically and

fully exposing the meaning of contemporary communism. Why? Because he

lacked perspective, according to Djilas; because he persisted until his

death in not questioning Leninist ideas of organization according to

Collinet. There is probably something of the truth in both of these

explanations.

But to my mind both books are marred by a certain number of errors I

would like to point out. In the first place, they both show a total lack

of understanding of the concept of “permanent revolution.” Collinet

makes the mistake of considering Marx’s famous text of March 1850 an

unimportant accident in the history of Marxist thought, an ephemeral

“Blanquist” crisis from which the author quickly recovered.[5] He and

Djilas draw erroneous conclusions from a correct observation, which is

that the “permanent revolution” is more acutely manifested in backward

countries where it is easier to directly leap over the capitalist stage

from feudalism to socialism. But they are wrong in concluding that

revolutionary Marxism is only applicable to underdeveloped countries and

that it has no chance in highly industrialized nations. Maintaining, for

example, as Djilas does, that in a country like Germany only reformism

can carry the day means forgetting that from 1918 to 1933 the German

proletariat was on the brink of victory on several occasions and that

without the errors caused by its being a satellite of Moscow, it would

probably have abolished the most advanced capitalism of Europe. In May

’68 did we not see the working-class revolt in France a hair’s breadth

from overthrowing an advanced capitalism?

What is more, the two books insist insufficiently upon the relatively

progressive aspects of communism in power, although both mention some of

them. Collinet accepts that the national bourgeoisies have been

eliminated, the poor peasants liberated from the yoke of big landowners

and usurers, and that industrialization has been carried out; Djilas

that the collective ownership of the means of production has allowed for

the realization of rapid progress in certain sectors of the economy. But

the Yugoslav contradicts himself by claiming against all evidence that

no great scientific discoveries have been made under the Soviet regime

and that in this domain the USSR probably trails tsarist Russia. And in

the final conclusions of these two books the progressive aspect is

forgotten and the balance sheet presented is too negative.

In the same way, concerning the possibilities for the evolution of the

post-Stalinist regime the two authors demonstrate a pessimism that in my

eyes is excessive. To be sure, they are right in maintaining that the

Khrushchev regime was that of a conservative pragmatism lacking in

ideas. They are also right in stressing the relatively narrow limits of

de-Stalinization and in being skeptical about the democratization and

the decentralization of the regime, be it in Russia itself, Yugoslavia,

or Poland. But at times when reading them it seems that “dialectical”

evolution is blocked, that it forbids all hope. And yet, in other

passages the two authors admit that the break with the Stalinist past is

profound, that something has truly changed, that the domination of the

“new class” has been shaken, that liberation is on the march, and that

the release of popular discontent is irreversible. But they conclude

that the outcome will be irremediable ruin and the collapse

of”communism” without indicating with what the “monster” will be

replaced.

An ambiguity all the more worrisome in that one senses in their analysis

a singular indulgence towards Western bourgeois democracy, considered

the sole alternative to “communist tyranny.”

It seems that for both Collinet and Djilas the Russian regime alone is

responsible for the Cold War and the division of the world into two

blocs. The capitalist and imperialist character of the Western

democracies is blurred. For Collinet financial capitalism is a “mythical

monster.” and even Djilas who has spent time in the U.S., contests the

idea that the Western governments are controlled by a handful of

monopolists. Collinet claims with a straight face that there exist

Western democracies “untainted by any vestiges of imperialism.” and

Djilas that the United States tend towards an increasingly statist

regime. The dangers that American big business and its claim to world

leadership present are conjured away. Collinet goes even further when he

attacks the Bandung Accords which, according to him, are “nothing but a

weapon against the Western democracies.” and when he presents Mossadegh

and Nasser as instruments in the service of Russian expansionism.[6] The

impact of the indictment of Stalinist totalitarianism and the

executioners of the Hungarian people is considerably weakened by the

blank check issued the aggressors of Suez and Western colonialism.

Why do Collinet and Djilas both go off the rails at the end of their

analysis? In my opinion the real reason for their error is their

inability to find a third way outside of those of Stalinism and

bourgeois democracy. And the source of this inability is the refusal to

rally to libertarian Marxist ideas.

They make only vague and insufficient allusions to the great conflict

between authoritarian socialism and anarchist socialism that so deeply

divided the working-class movement of the nineteenth century. They seem

to be ignorant of the fact that the totalitarian communism they denounce

was condemned a century before them in prophetic terms by Proudhon and

Bakunin. For Collinet and even more for Djilas authority directly

exercised by the proletariat in the absence of any state coercion is an

“illusion” and a “utopia.” And yet the two authors occasionally

contradict themselves and express unconscious libertarian aspirations.

Collinet lets slip that “the logic of democracy was not the Jacobin

state, even animated by good intentions, but the state, withering away

and transferring its functions to the entire social body.” And Djilas,

after having denounced the Jacobin-style intolerance of contemporary

communists, exalts “man’s imperishable aspiration for freedom.” and

announces as imminent the moment when industrialization will render

communism “superfluous.” Analyzing the demands of the underground

opposition currently maturing in the USSR, Collinet—who is more precise

than Djilas on this matter although, alas, he does not go as far as he

should—says that “they do not appear to be demanding Western

parliamentarism; rather their essence is the independence of the people

and their economic and cultural organizations in relation to the party

and state apparatuses.”

If Collinet and Djilas had more clearly deduced these libertarian

conclusions from their analyses they would have avoided getting bogged

down, due to their failure to clearly glimpse a third way, in a

pro-Western Menshevism that deprives their argument of much of its force

and persuasive power. None of this, of course, justifies the prison

sentence inflicted on the Yugoslav, which does no honor to Tito’s

regime.

The lesson: a revolutionary socialist who frees himself of

Marxist-Leninist Jacobinism is in great danger of falling into

petitbourgeois and counter-revolutionary ideologies. There is only one

healthy and certain way to “de-Jacobinize,” to distance oneself from

authoritarian socialism, and that is to go over to libertarian Marxism,

the only reliable value of our time, the only socialism that has

remained young, the only authentic socialism.

[1] Milovan Djilas, The New Class: An Analysis of the Communist System

(Thames & Hudson, 1957); Michel Collinet, Du Bolchevisme: evolution et

variations du Mandsmeteninisme (Le Livre Contemporain, 1957). [Djilas, a

former Yugoslav Partisan and Communist leader and at one point touted to

succeed Tito as president, became increasingly critical of the

Yugoslavian system and was imprisoned in 1956. The New Class had been

finished before his arrest and was published in the USA in 1957, which

led to his being sentenced to a further seven years’ imprisonment.

Eventually released in 1966, he remained a dissident in Belgrade until

his death in 1995. Collinet (1904–1977) was also a former Communist

turned dissident, and then became a member of the Socialist Party’s

Revolutionary Left faction and, later, the Workers’ and Peasants’

Socialist Party alongside Guérin. He was active in the Resistance during

the Second World War, and remained a member of the Socialist Party after

the Liberation. —DB]

[2] It is regrettable that neither Collinet nor Djilas quote the

remarkable pages (pp. 157, 205) that, well before them, Valine, in his

Revolution inconnue, dedicated to the Bolsheviks’ claim to

infallibility.

[3] Nevertheless, Collinet and Djilas both exaggerate Lenin’s dogmatic

rigidity and underestimate his surprising intellectual flexibility and

his ability to revise his positions in light of facts, aptitudes that on

every occasion disconcerted his dull lieutenants and in a large measure

compensated for the failing for which he is criticized.

[4] Collinet here joins Valine without stating so (op. cit., pp. 180–2).

[5] Address of the Central Committee to the Communist League, London,

March 1850. [DB]

[6] The Bandung Conference of 1955 brought together twenty-nine Asian

and African countries, mostly former colonies, with the aim of promoting

economic and cultural cooperation and opposing colonialism and

neo-colonialism. Mohammad Mosaddegh was the democratically elected prime

minister of Iran who was removed from power in a coup organised by

British and US intelligence agencies in 1953. Gamal Abdel Nasser led the

overthrow of the Egyptian monarchy in 1952 and nationalized the Suez

Canal in 1956, which led to invasion by Britain, France, and Israel.

[DB]