đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș daniel-guerin-for-a-libertarian-communism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:05:53. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: For a Libertarian Communism Author: Daniel Guérin Date: 2017 Language: en Topics: libertarian communism, anarcho-communism, libertarian marxism, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, PM Press Notes: Published by PM Press under the the *Revolutionary Pocketbooks* series. Edited and introduced by David Berry. Translation by Mitchell Abidor.
This volume contains a selection of texts by the French revolutionary
activist and historian Daniel GuĂ©rin (1904â1988), published here in
English translation for the first time. They were written between the
1950s and 1980s and appeared in France in a series of collections:
Jeunesse du socialisme libertaire [Youth of Libertarian Socialism]
(Paris: Riviere, 1959), Pour un Marxisme libertaire [For a Libertarian
Marxism] (Paris: Laffont, 1969), and A la recherche dâun communisme
libertaire [In Search of a Libertarian Communism] (Paris: Spartacus,
1984). A further version of the collection was published after his
death: Pour le communisme libertaire [For Libertarian Communism] (Paris:
Spartacus, 2003). All of these contain slightly different selections of
texts around a common core of recurrent pieces, and the same is true of
this English edition. We have tried to choose those texts which would be
of most interest to present-day readers, but which also give a good
understanding of GuĂ©rinâs developing analysis of the failings of the
Left and of his belief that the only way forward was through some kind
of synthesis of Marxism and anarchism.
We are grateful to the Spartacus collective, to Daniel Guerrier, and to
Anne Guérin for permission to publish these translations.
The footnotes are GuĂ©rinâs except where indicated; additional
explanatory material is followed by my initials. We have tried (where
possible and practical) to provide references to English translations of
GuĂ©rinâs sources, and I am grateful to Iain McKay for his help with
this. I would also like to thank Chris Reynolds, Martin OâShaughnessy,
and Christophe Wall-Romana for their help in tracking down the source of
GuĂ©rinâs reference to Armand Gatti; and Danny Evans and James Yeoman for
their advice regarding films about the Spanish Revolution.
Guérin was a prolific writer on an exceptionally wide range of topics,
and relatively little has been translated into English. A list of his
publications in English can be found at the end of the volume. For
further information, including a full bibliography and links to texts
available online, please visit the website of the Association des Amis
de Daniel Guérin (the Association of the Friends of Daniel Guérin) at
https://www.danielguerin.info/
.
âSynthesisâ of Marxism and Anarchism
I have a horror of sects, of compartmentalisation, of people who are
separated by virtually nothing and who nevertheless face each other as
if across an abyss.
â Daniel GuĂ©rin[1]
As he once wrote of the fate suffered by anarchism, Daniel Guérin
(1904â1988) has himself been the victim of unwarranted neglect and, in
some circles at least, of undeserved discredit. For although many people
know of Guérin, relatively few seem aware of the breadth of his
contribution. His writings cover a vast range of subjects, from fascism
and the French Revolution to the history of the European and American
labour movements; from Marxist and anarchist theory to homosexual
liberation; from French colonialism to the Black Panthers; from Paul
Gauguin to French nuclear tests in the Pacificânot to mention several
autobiographical volumes. As an activist, Guérin was involved in various
movements and campaigns: anticolonialism, antiracism, antimilitarism,
and homosexual liberation. This is a man who counted among his personal
friends Francois Mauriac, Simone Weil, C.L.R. James, and Richard Wright,
to name but a few of the famous names which litter his autobiographies.
His youthful literary efforts provoked a letter of congratulation from
Colette; he met and corresponded with Leon Trotsky; and he had dinner
âen tĂȘte-Ă -tĂȘteâ with Ho Chi Minh. Jean-Paul Sartre judged his
reinterpretation of the French Revolution to be âone of the only
contributions by contemporary Marxists to have enriched historical
studies.â[2] The gay liberation activist Pierre Hahn believed his own
generation of homosexuals owed more to Guérin than to any other person,
and the Martinican poet Aimé Césaire paid tribute to his work on
decolonization. Noam Chomsky considers GuĂ©rinâs writings on anarchism to
be of great importance to the development of contemporary socialist
thought.
Yet despite such assessments, and although there is widespread and
enduring interest in Guérin among activists, he has been badly neglected
by academic researchers in France and especially in the English-speaking
world. This is doubtless due to a combination of factors: Guérin never
held an academic post or any leadership position (except briefly at the
Liberation as director of the Commission du Livre, a government agency
that oversaw the book publishing industry); he was consistently
anti-Stalinist during a period when the influence of the French
Communist Party, both among intellectuals and within the labour
movement, was overwhelming; he never fit easily into ideological or
political pigeonholes and was often misunderstood and misrepresented;
and in France in the 1960s and 1970s, his bisexuality was shocking even
for many on the Left. GuĂ©rin was, in a word, a âtroublemaker.â [3]
Concerned that his reinterpretation of the French Revolution, La Lutte
de classes sous la Premiere Republique, 1793â1797 (1946), had been
misunderstood, in 1947, Daniel Guérin wrote to his friend, the socialist
Marceau Pivert, that the book was to be seen as âan introduction to a
synthesis of anarchism and Marxism-Leninism I would like to write one
day.â [4] What exactly did GuĂ©rin mean by this âsynthesis,â and how and
why had he come to be convinced of its necessity? For as Alex Callinicos
has commented, âgenuinely innovative syntheses are rare and difficult to
arrive at. Too often attempted syntheses amount merely to banality,
incoherence, or eclecticism.â [5]
It must however be noted from the outset that Guérin had no pretensions
to being a theorist: he saw himself first and foremost as an activist
and secondly as a historian.[6] Indeed, from the day in 1930 when he
abandoned the poetry and novels of his youth, all his research and
writings were concerned more or less directly with his political
commitments.[7] His developing critique of Marxism and his later
interest in the relationship between Marxism and anarchism were
motivated by his own direct experience of active participation in
revolutionary struggles on a number of fronts; they can thus only be
clarified when studied in relation to social and political developments.
Although Guérin, in some of his autobiographical or
semi-autobiographical writings, had a tendency to divide his life into
more or less distinct âphases,â and despite the fact that his political
or ideological trajectory may seem to some to be rather protean, I would
argue that there was in fact an underlying ideological consistencyâeven
if changing circumstances meant that his âorganisational optionsâ (as he
put it) changed in different periods of his life. A historical
materialist all his life, he remained attached to a revolutionary
socialism with a strong ethical or moral core. Although it was many
years before he found an organisation which lived up to his
expectations, he was always at heart a libertarian communist, developing
an increasingly strong belief in the need for a âtotal revolutionâ which
would attach as much importance to issues of race, gender, and sexuality
as to workplace-based conflict. Whether specifically in his commitment
to anticolonialism or to sexual liberation, or more generally in his
emphasis on what today would be called intersectionality, Guérin was
undoubtedly ahead of his time.
Despite coming from the âgrande bourgeoisieââa background which he would
come to rejectâGuĂ©rin owed much to the influence of his branch of the
family: humanist, liberal and cultured, both his parents had been
passionately pro-Dreyfus, both were influenced by Tolstoyâs ethical and
social ideas, and his fatherâs library contained The Communist Manifesto
as well as works by BenoĂźt Malan, Proudhon, and Kropotkin.[8] The young
Daniel seems to have been particularly influenced by his fatherâs
pacifism and was also deeply affected by his own reading of Tolstoyâs
Diaries and Resurrection.[9] In the context of the increasingly
polarised debates of the inter-war period between the Far Right and Far
Left (âMaurras versus Marxâ as he put it), he identified with the
âMarxist extreme Leftâ from a relatively early age.[10] His later
âdiscoveryâ of the Parisian working class and of the concrete realities
of their everyday existence (to a large extent through his homosexual
relationships with young workers) reinforced a profound âworkerismâ
which would stay with him for the rest of his life.[11]
This workerism would lead him in 1930â1931 to join the syndicalists
grouped around the veteran revolutionary Pierre Monatte: typically,
perhaps, GuĂ©rinâs first real active involvement was in the campaign for
the reunification of the two major syndicalist confederations, the CGT
(dominated at that time by the PS-SFIO, the Socialist Party) and the
CGTU (dominated by the PCF, the French Communist Party). His workerism
was also responsible for a strong attraction towards the PCF, far more
âproletarianâ than the Socialist Party, despite his âvisceral
anti-Stalinismâ and what he saw as the Partyâs âcrass ideological
excesses, its inability to win over the majority of workers, and its
mechanical submission to the Kremlinâs orders.â[12] Yet GuĂ©rin was no
more impressed with the PS, which he found petty-bourgeois,
narrow-minded, dogmatically anticommunist, and obsessed with
electioneering:
The tragedy for many militants of our generation was our repugnance at
having to opt for one or the other of the two main organisations which
claimed, wrongly, to represent the working class. Stalinism and social
democracy both repelled us, each in its own way. Yet those workers who
were active politically were in one of these two parties. The smaller,
intermediate groups and the extremist sects seemed to us to be doomed to
impotence and marginalisation. The SFIO, despite the social conformism
of its leadership, at least had the advantage over the Communist Party
of enjoying a certain degree of internal democracy, and to some extent
allowed revolutionaries to express themselves; whereas the monolithic
automatism of Stalinism forbade any critics from opening their mouths
and made it very difficult for them even to stay in the party.[13]
Hence his decision to rejoin the SFIO in 1935, shortly before the
creation by Marceau Pivert of the Gauche révolutionnaire (Revolutionary
Left) tendency within the party, of which he would become a leading
member. GuĂ©rin was attracted by Pivertâs âLuxemburgist,â libertarian and
syndicalist tendencies.[14] He was consistently on the revolutionary
wing of the Gauche révolutionnaire and of its successor, the Parti
socialiste ouvrier et paysan (PSOP, or Workersâ and Peasantsâ Socialist
Party, created when the GR was expelled from the SFIO in 1938), and, in
the Popular Front period, he drew a clear distinction between what he
called the âPopular Front no. 1ââan electoral alliance between social
democracy, Stalinism, and bourgeois liberalismâand the âPopular Front
no. 2ââthe powerful, extra-parliamentary, working-class movement, which
came into conflict with the more moderate (and more bourgeois) Popular
Front government.[15] He viewed the âentryismâ of the French Trotskyists
in these years as a welcome counterbalance to the reformism of the
majority of the Socialist Party.[16]
Indeed, in the 1930s, GuĂ©rin agreed with Trotskyâs position on many
issues: on the nature of fascism and how to stop it; on war and
revolutionary proletarian internationalism; on opposition to the
collusion between âsocial-patriotismâ (i.e., mainstream social
democracy) and ânational-communismâ (i.e., the PCF) as well as any pact
with the bourgeois Radicals; and on the need to fight actively for the
liberation of Europeâs colonies. As GuĂ©rin comments after recounting in
glowing terms his sole meeting with Trotsky in Barbizon (near
Fontainebleau) in 1933: âOn a theoretical level as well as on the level
of political practice, Trotsky would remain, for many of us, both a
stimulus to action and a teacher.â [17]
Ultimately, GuĂ©rinâs experience of the labour movement and of the Left
in the 1930sâas well as his research on the nature and origins of
fascism and Nazism[18]âled him to reject both social democracy and
Stalinism as effective strategies for defeating fascism and preventing
war. Indeed, the Leftââdivided, ossified, negative, and narrow-mindedâ
in GuĂ©rinâs wordsâbore its share of responsibility and had made tragic
errors.[19] The SFIO was criticised by Guérin for its electoralism and
for allowing its hands to be tied by the Parti radical-socialiste, âa
bourgeois party whose corruption and bankruptcy were in large part
responsible for the fascist explosionâ; for its incomprehension of the
nature of the capitalist state, which led to the impotence of Leon
Blumâs 1936 Popular Front government; for its failure to take fascism
seriously (and to aid the Spanish Republicans), despite the warnings,
until it was too late; and for its obsessive rivalry with the PCF. The
PCF was equally harshly criticised by GuĂ©rinâfor what seemed to him to
be its blind obedience to the Comintern, the criminal stupidity of the
Cominternâs âthird periodâ and for its counter-revolutionary strategy
both in Spain and in France.[20]
As for Trotsky, Guérin disagreed with him over the creation of the
Fourth International in 1938, which seemed to him premature and
divisive. More generally, Guérin was critical of what he saw as
Trotskyâs tendency continually to transpose the experiences of the
Russian Bolsheviks onto contemporary events in the West, and of his
âauthoritarian rigidness.â Trotskyism, GuĂ©rin argued, represented âthe
ideology of the infallible leader who, in an authoritarian fashion,
directs the policy of a fraction or of a party.â [21] What GuĂ©rin wanted
to see was âthe full development of the spontaneity of the working
class.â [22] Writing in 1963, GuĂ©rin would conclude with regard to such
disputes over revolutionary tactics:
The revolutionary organisation which was lacking in June 1936 was not,
in my opinion, an authoritarian leadership emanating from a small group
or sect, but an organ for the coordination of the workersâ councils,
growing directly out of the occupied workplaces. The mistake of the
Gauche révolutionnaire was not so much that it was unable, because of
its lack of preparation, to transform itself into a revolutionary party
on the Leninist or Trotskyist model, but that it was unable ... to help
the working class to find for itself its own form of power structure to
confront the fraud that was the Popular Front no. 1.[23]
So as GuĂ©rin summarised the state of the Left in the 1930s: âEverything
made the renewal of the concepts and methods of struggle employed by the
French Left both indispensable and urgent.â [24] These debates on the
Left regarding tactics (working-class autonomy or âPopular Frontismâ)
and the role of the âavant-gardeâ or, in syndicalist terms, the
âactivist minorityâ (minoritĂ© agissante) would recur in the postwar
years, and GuĂ©rinâs position would vary little.
Despite GuĂ©rinâs reservations about Trotskyism, his analysis of the
nature of the Vichy regime was very similar to that put forward by the
Fourth International, and he was also impressed with Trotskyâs manifesto
of May 1940, âLaguerre imperialiste et la revolution proletarienne
mondialeâ [Imperialist War and the World Proletarian Revolution],
including it in a collection of Trotskyâs writings on the Second World
War he would edit in 1970.[25] He worked with the Trotskyists in the
resistance, not least because they remained true to their
internationalism and to their class politics.[26] They rejected, for
instance, what GuĂ©rin saw as the PCFâs demagogic nationalism. GuĂ©rin was
thus closely involved with the Trotskyistsâ attempts to organise
extremely dangerous anti-militarist and anti-Nazi propaganda among
German soldiers. He also contributed to the activities of a group of
Trotskyist workers producing newsletters carrying reports of workplace
struggles against both French employers and the German authorities.
However, an extended study tour of the United States from 1946 to 1949,
which included visits to branches or prominent militants of the
Socialist Workersâ Party and the breakaway Workersâ Party, represented a
turning point in GuĂ©rinâs âTrotskyism.â In a 1948 letter to Marceau
Pivert, he commented on his unhappiness with the Trotskyistsâ tendency
to ârepeat mechanically old formulae without rethinking them, relying
lazily and uncritically on the (undeniably admirable) writings of
Trotsky.â[27] Looking back thirty years later, he would conclude: âIt
was thanks to the American Trotskyists, despite their undeniable
commitment, that I ceased forever believing in the virtues of
revolutionary parties built on authoritarian, Leninist lines.â[28]
Unlike many on the Left associated with postwar ideological renewal,
most of whom would focus on a revision or reinterpretation of Marxism,
often at a philosophical level (Sartre, Althusser, or Henri Lefebvre,
for example), Guérin the historian began with a return to what he saw as
the source of revolutionary theory and praxis: in 1946, he published his
study of class struggle in the First French Republic (1793â1797).[29]
The aim of the book was to âdraw lessons from the greatest, longest and
deepest revolutionary experience France has ever known, lessons which
would help regenerate the revolutionary, libertarian socialism of
today,â and to âextract some ideas which would be applicable to our time
and of direct use to the contemporary reader who has yet to fully digest
the lessons of another revolution: the Russian Revolution.â[30] Applying
the concepts of permanent revolution and combined and uneven
development, inspired by Trotskyâs History of the Russian Revolution,
Guérin argued that the beginnings of a conflict of class interest could
already be detected within the revolutionary camp between an âembryonicâ
proletariatâthe bras nus (manual workers), represented by the
EnragĂ©sâand the bourgeoisieârepresented by Robespierre and the Jacobin
leadership. For Guérin, the French Revolution thus represented not only
the birth of bourgeois parliamentary democracy, but also the emergence
of âa new type of democracy,â a form of working-class direct democracy
as seen, however imperfectly, in the âsectionsâ (local popular
assemblies), precursors of the Commune of 1871 and the Soviets of 1905
and 1917.[31] In the second edition of the work (1968) he would add âthe
Commune of May 1968â to that genealogy.
Similarly, this interpretation tended to emphasise the political
ambivalence of the bourgeois Jacobin leadership which âhesitated
continually between the solidarity uniting it with the popular classes
against the aristocracy and that uniting all the wealthy,
property-owning classes against those who owned little or nothing.â[32]
For Guérin, the essential lesson to be drawn from the French Revolution
was thus the conflict of class interest between the bourgeoisie and the
working classes. Bourgeois, social democratic, and Stalinist
interpretations of the Revolutionâlike those of Jean Jaures, Albert
Mathiez, and so many othersâwhich tended to maintain the âcult of
Robespierreâ and to reinforce the labour movementâs dependence on
bourgeois democracy, were thus to be rejected.[33]
Class Struggle in the First Republic has been described by Eric
Hobsbawm, himself a longstanding Communist Party member, as âa curious
combination of libertarian and Trotskyist ideasânot without a dash of
Rosa Luxemburg.â[34] It not only shocked many academic historians of the
Revolutionâespecially those with more or less close links to the PCF
(Georges Lefebvre, and especially Albert Soboul and George Rude)âbut
also those politicians who, in GuĂ©rinâs words, âhave been responsible
for perverting and undermining true proletarian socialism.â[35] The
fallout was intense and the ensuing debate lasted for many years;
indeed, Guérin is still today regarded with distrust by many historians
influenced by the Republican and mainstream Marxist (non-Trotskyist)
interpretations of the Revolution as a bourgeois revolution.[36] Guérin
brought that whole historiographical tradition into question. The
political significance was that the Revolutionary Terror had been used
as a parallel to justify Bolshevik repression of democratic freedoms and
repression of more leftist movements. Stalin had been compared to
Robespierre. The Jacobin tradition of patriotism and national unity in
defence of the bourgeois democratic Republic has been one of the
characteristics of the dominant tendencies within the French Left, and
therefore central to the political mythologies of the Popular Front and
the Resistance. GuĂ©rin, as Ian Birchall has put it, âwas polemicizing
against the notion of a Resistance uniting all classes against the
foreign invader.â[37]
What is more, the PCF had been campaigning since 1945 for unity at the
top with the SFIO, and in the 1956 elections called for the
re-establishment of a Popular Front government. Guérin, as we have seen,
argued that alliance with the supposedly âprogressiveâ bourgeoisie in
the struggle against fascism was a contradiction at the heart of the
Popular Front strategy. His conception of the way forward for the Left
was very different. At a time when fascism in the form of Poujadism
looked as if it might once more be a real threat, Guérin argued that
what was needed was a âgenuineâ Popular Front, that is, a grassroots
social movement rather than a governmental alliance, a truly popular
movement centred on the working classes that would bring together the
labour movement and all socialists who rejected both the pro-American
SFIO and the pro-Soviet PCF:
And if we succeed in building this new Popular Front, let us not repeat
the mistakes of the 1936 Popular Front, which because of its timidity
and impotence ended up driving the middle classes towards fascism,
rather than turning them away from it as had been its aim. Only a
combative Popular Front, which dares to attack big business, will be
able to halt our middle classes on the slope which leads to fascism and
to their destruction.[38]
GuĂ©rinâs friend and translator, C.L.R. James, wrote in 1958 of the
political significance of GuĂ©rinâ s revisiting the history of the French
Revolution:
Such a book had never yet been produced and could not have been produced
in any epoch other than our own. It is impregnated with the experience
and study of the greatest event of our time: the development and then
degeneration of the Russian Revolution, and is animated implicitly by
one central concern: how can the revolutionary masses avoid the dreadful
pitfalls of bureaucratisation and the resurgence of a new oppressive
state power, and instead establish a system of direct democracy?[39]
It was in very similar terms that Guérin expressed the central question
facing the Left in a 1959 essay, âLa Revolution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©e.â[40] This
is an important text in GuĂ©rinâs ideological itinerary, continuing the
political analysis he began in La Lutte de classes sous la PemiĂšre
République and developed in La Revolution française et nous [The French
Revolution and Us] (written in 1944 but not published until 1969) and
âQuand le fascisme nous devançaitâ [When Fascism Was Winning]
(1955).[41]
In âLa RĂ©volution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©e,â GuĂ©rin argued that the âJacobinâ
traits in Marxism and particularly in Leninism were the result of an
incomplete understanding on Marx and Engelsâ part of the class nature of
Jacobinism and the Jacobin dictatorship, to be distinguished according
to Guérin from the democratically controlled contrainte révolutionnaire
(ârevolutionary coercionâ) exercised by the popular sections. Thus by
applying a historical materialist analysis to the experiences of the
French revolutionary movement, Guérin came to argue, essentially, that
âauthenticâ socialism (contrary to what had been argued by Blanqui or
Lenin) arose spontaneously out of working-class struggle and that it was
fundamentally libertarian. Authoritarian conceptions of party
organisation and revolutionary strategy had their origins in bourgeois
or even aristocratic modes of thought.
GuĂ©rin believed that when Marx and Engels referredârather vaguelyâto a
âdictatorship of the proletariatâ they envisaged it as a dictatorship
exercised by the working class as a whole, rather than by an
avant-garde. But, he continued, Marx and Engels did not adequately
differentiate their interpretation from that of the Blanquists. This
made possible Leninâs later authoritarian conceptions: âLenin, who saw
himself as both a âJacobinâ and a âMarxist,â invented the idea of the
dictatorship of a party substituting itself for the working class and
acting by proxy in its name.â[42] This, for GuĂ©rin, was where it all
started to go badly wrong: âThe double experience of the French and
Russian Revolutions has taught us that this is where we touch upon the
central mechanism whereby direct democracy, the self-government of the
people, is transformed, gradually, by the introduction of the
revolutionary âdictatorship,â into the reconstitution of an apparatus
for the oppression of the people.â[43]
GuĂ©rinâs leftist, class-based critique of Jacobinism thus had three
related implications for contemporary debates about political tactics
and strategy. First, it implied a rejection of âclass collaborationâ and
therefore of any type of alliance with the bourgeois Left (Popular
Frontism). Second, it implied that the revolutionary movement should be
uncompromising, that it should push for more radical social change and
not stop halfway (which, as Saint-Just famously remarked, was to dig
oneâs own grave), rejecting the Stalinist emphasis on the unavoidability
of separate historical âstagesâ in the long-term revolutionary process.
Third, it implied a rejection both of the Leninist model of a
centralised, hierarchical party dominating the labour movement and of
the âsubstitutismâ (substitution of the party for the proletariat) which
had come to characterise the Bolshevik dictatorship.
This critique clearly had its sources both in GuĂ©rinâs reinterpretation
of the French Revolution and in the social and political conditions of
the time. La Revolution franrçaise et nous was informed by GuĂ©rinâs
critique of social democratic and Stalinist strategies before, during,
and after the war. âLa rĂ©volution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©eâ was written at a
significant historic moment for socialists in France: after the
artificial national unity of the immediate postwar years had given way
to profound social and political conflict; as Guy Molletâs SFIO became
increasingly identified with the defence of the bourgeois status quo and
the Western camp in the cold war; as the immensely powerful postwar PCF
reeled under the effects of the Hungarian uprising of 1956 and of the
Khrushchev revelations the same year; and as the unpopular and
politically unstable Fourth Republic collapsed in the face of a
threatened military coup. It was this situation which made renewal of
the Left so necessary. In 1959, Guérin also picked up on the results of
a survey of the attitudes of French youth towards politics, which
indicated to him two things: first, that what alienated the younger
generation from âsocialismâ was âbureaucrats and purges,â and second,
that, as one respondent put it, âFrench youth are becoming more and more
anarchist.â[44] Ever the optimist, GuĂ©rin declared:
Far from allowing ourselves to sink into doubt, inaction, and despair,
the time has come for the French Left to begin again from zero, to
rethink its problems from their very foundations .... The necessary
synthesis of the ideas of equality and liberty ... cannot and must not
be attempted, in my opinion, in the framework and to the benefit of a
bankrupt bourgeois democracy. It can and must only be done in the
framework of socialist thought, which remains, despite everything, the
only reliable value of our times. The failure of both reformism and
Stalinism imposes on us the urgent duty to find a way of reconciling
(proletarian) democracy with socialism, freedom with Revolution.[45]
What Guérin would thus do which was quite remarkable in post-Liberation
France was endeavour to separate Marxism from Bolshevismâhis continued
friendly and supportive contacts with a number of Trotskyists
notwithstandingâand it is noteworthy that he had contact in this period
with a number of prominent non-orthodox Marxists. After 1945,
especially, he was involved (centrally or more peripherally) in a number
of circles or networks, and according to the sociologist Michel Crozier
(who, since their meeting in America, saw Guérin as something of a
mentor) GuĂ©rin self-identified in the late 1940s and early 1950sââthe
golden age of the Left intelligentsiaââas an âindependent Marxist.â[46]
C.L.R. James, for instance, has already been mentioned. He and Guérin
appear to have met in the 1930s; they became good friends, Guérin
visited him while in the USA in 1949, and they corresponded over many
years. Convinced of the contemporary relevance and of the importance of
GuĂ©rinâs analysis, James even began to translate La Lutte de classes
into English, and described the book as âone of the most important
modern textbooks in ... the study of Marxismâ and âone of the great
theoretical landmarks of our movement.â[47]
Similarly, Guérin had first met Karl Korsch in Berlin in 1932, and
visited him in his exile in Cambridge, Massachusetts, in 1947, where
according to Guérin they spent many hours together.[48] The two would
collaborate a decade later in their bibliographical researches on the
relationship between Marx and Bakunin.[49] Also during his time in the
USA in 1947, Guérin became friendly with a group of refugee Germans in
Washington, D.C., dissident Marxists, âas hospitable as they were
brilliant,â connected with the so-called Frankfurt School: Franz
Neumann, Otto Kirchheimer and Herbert Marcuse.[50]
In France, Guérin already knew the leading figures in the Socialisme ou
Barbarie group from their days in the Fourth Internationalâs PCI
(Internationalist Communist Party) together: GuĂ©rinâs papers contain a
number of texts produced by the so-called Chaulieu-Montal Tendency in
the late 1940s.[51] It is interesting to note that the Socialisme ou
Barbarie groupâs theses on the Russian Revolution feature in the list of
theories and authors discovered by the Algerian nationalist and
revolutionary, Mohammed Harbi, thanks to his first meeting with Guérin
(at a meeting of the PCI discussion group, the âCercle Lenineâ) in
1953.[52] In 1965 Guérin took part, with Castoriadis, Lefort, and Edgar
Morin, in a forum on âMarxism Todayâ organised by Socialisme ou Barbarie
(whose work Morin would describe a few years later as representing âan
original synthesis of Marxism and anarchismâ[53]). GuĂ©rin also
contributed to Morinâs Arguments (1956â1962), an important journal
launched in response to the events of 1956 with a view to a
âreconsideration not only of Stalinist Marxism, but of the Marxist way
of thinking,â[54] and he had been centrally involved with the French
âTitoistsâ around Clara Malraux and the review Contemporains
(1950â1951).[55]
The present state of our knowledge of these relationships does not
enable us to be precise regarding the nature, extent or direction of any
influence which might have resulted, but the least we can say is that
Guérin was at the heart of the Left-intellectual ferment which
characterised these years, that he had an address book, as his daughter
Anne recently put it,[56] as fat as a dictionary and that he shared many
of the theoretical preoccupations of many leading Marxists in the twenty
years or so following the Second World War, be it the party-form,
bureaucracy, alienation or sexual repression.
In the mid-to-late 1950s, like other former or âcriticalâ Trotskyists,
as well as ex-members of the FCL (the Libertarian Communist Federation,
banned in 1956[57]), GuĂ©rin belongedâthough âwithout much convictionââto
a series of Left-socialist organisations: the Nouvelle Gauche [New
Left], the Union de la Gauche Socialiste [Union of the Socialist Left],
and, briefly, the Parti Socialiste Unifie [Unified Socialist Party].[58]
But it was also around 1956 that GuĂ©rin âdiscoveredâ anarchism. Looking
back on a 1930 boat trip to Vietnam and the small library he had taken
with him, GuĂ©rin commented that of all the authors he had studiedâMarx,
Proudhon, Georges Sorel, Hubert Lagardelle, Fernand Pelloutier, Lenin,
Trotsky, Gandhi, and many othersââMarx had, without a doubt, been
preponderant.â[59] But having become increasingly critical of Leninism,
GuĂ©rin discovered the collected works of Bakunin, a ârevelationâ which
rendered him forever âallergic to all versions of authoritarian
socialism, whether Jacobin, Marxist, Leninist, or Trotskyist.â[60]
Guérin would describe the following ten years or so (i.e., the mid-1950s
to the mid-1960s)âwhich saw the publication notably of the popular
anthology Ni Dieu ni MaĂźtre and of LâAnarchisme, which sold like
hotcakes at the Sorbonne in May 1968-as his âclassical anarchist
phase.â[61] He became especially interested in Proudhon, whom he admired
as the first theorist of autogestion, or worker self-management;[62]
Bakunin, representative of revolutionary, working-class anarchism, close
to Marxism, Guérin insisted, yet remarkably prescient about the dangers
of statist communism; and Max Stirner, appreciated as a precursor of
1968 because of his determination to attack bourgeois prejudice and
puritanism.
The discovery of Bakunin coincided with the appearance of the Hungarian
workersâ committees and the Soviet suppression of the Hungarian uprising
in 1956. These events provoked Guérin into studying the councilist
tradition, which had come to be seen by many as representing a form of
revolutionary socialist direct democracy in contrast to the
Bolshevik-controlled soviets.[63] It was also during the 1950s that
Guérin, moving on from his study of the French Revolution, had begun to
research the political debates and conflicts within the First
International and more generally the relationship between Marxism and
anarchism.
Guérin had had no contact with the anarchist movement before the Second
World War, other than to read E. Armandâs individualist anarchist organ
Lâen dehors. [64] According to Georges Fontenis, a leading figure in the
postwar anarchist movement, Guérin began to have direct contact with the
then Anarchist Federation (FA) in 1945, when the second edition of his
Fascism and Big Business was published. The FAâs newspaper, Le
Libertaire, reviewed GuĂ©rinâs books favourably, and in the 1950s, he was
invited to galas of the FA and (from 1953) of the FCL to do book
signings. He got to know leading anarchist militants and would drop in
at the FCLâs offices on the Quai de Valmy in Paris. Fontenis described
him as being âan active sympathiserâ at that point.[65] His new-found
sympathies certainly seem to have been sufficiently well-known for the
US embassy in Paris to refuse him a visa to visit his wife and daughter
in 1950 on the grounds that he was both a Trotskyist and an
anarchist.[66] The ideological stance of the FCL (âlibertarian Marxismâ)
and its position on the Algerian war (âcritical supportâ for the
nationalist movement in the context of the struggle against French
bourgeois imperialism) proved doubly attractive to the anticolonialist
Guérin.[67] In part for these reasons, 1954 (the beginning of the
Algerian war of independence) represented the beginning of a
relationship, notably with Fontenis (leading light of the FCL), which as
we shall see would ultimately take Guérin into the ranks of the
âlibertarian communistâ movement.
In 1959, Guérin published a collection of articles entitled jeunesse du
socialisme libertaire: literally the youthâor perhaps the rise, or
inventionâof libertarian socialism. This represented both a continuation
of the critique of Marxism and Leninism begun during the war, andâas far
as I am awareâGuĂ©rinâs first analysis of the nineteenthâcentury
anarchist tradition. Significantly, a copy of this collection has been
found with a handwritten dedication to Maximilien Rubel, âto whom this
little book owes so much.â[68] A few years later, in 1965, he would
publish both Anarchism: From Theory to Practice and the two-volume
anthology No Gods No Masters. The purpose was to ârehabilitateâ
anarchism, and the anthology represented the âdossier of evidenceâ:
Anarchism has for many years suffered from an undeserved disrepute, from
an iniustice which has manifested itself in three ways.
Firstly, its detractors claim that it is simply a thing of the past. It
did not survive the great revolutionary tests of our time: the Russian
Revolution and the Spanish Revolution. It has no place in the modern
world, a world characterised by centralisation, by large political and
economic entities, by the idea of totalitarianism. There is nothing left
for the anarchists to do but, âby force of circumstanceâ as Victor Serge
put it, to âjoin the revolutionary Marxists.â
Secondly, the better to devalue it, those who would slander anarchism
serve up a tendentious interpretation of its doctrine. Anarchism is
essentially individualistic, particularistic, hostile to any form of
organisation. It leads to fragmentation, to the egocentric withdrawal of
small local units of administration and production. It is incapable of
centralizing or of planning. It is nostalgic for the âgolden age.â It
tends to resurrect archaic social forms. It suffers from a childish
optimism; its âidealismâ takes no account of the solid realities of the
material infrastructure. It is incurably petit-bourgeois; it places
itself outside of the class movement of the modern proletariat. In a
word, it is âreactionary.â
And finally, certain of its commentators take care to rescue from
oblivion and to draw attention to only its most controversial
deviations, such as terrorism, individual assassinations, propaganda by
explosives and so on.[69]
Although, as we have seen, he referred to the two books (Anarchism and
No Gods No Masters) as representing his âclassical anarchistâ phase, and
despite his assertion that the basics of anarchist doctrine were
relatively homogeneous, elsewhere he was very clear that both books
focussed on a particular kind of anarchism. To begin with, âthe
fundamental aspect of these doctrinesâ was, for GuĂ©rin, that âanarchy,
is indeed, above all, synonymous with socialism. The anarchist is, first
and foremost, a socialist whose aim is to put an end to the exploitation
of man by man. Anarchism is no more than one of the branches of
socialist thought .... For Adolph Fischer, one of the Chicago martyrs,
âevery anarchist is a socialist, but every socialist is not necessarily
an anarchist.ââ [70]
In Pour un Marxisme libertaire (1969), Guérin described himself as
coming from the school of âanti-Stalinist Marxism,â but as having for
some time been in the habit of âdelving into the treasury of libertarian
thought.â Anarchism, he insisted, was still relevant and still very much
alive, âprovided that it is first divested of a great deal of
childishness, utopianism and romanticism,â[71] He went on to comment
that because of this openness towards the contribution of anarchism, his
book, Anarchism, had been misunderstood by some, and that it did not
mean that he had become an âecumenicalâ anarchist, to use Georges
Fontenisâ term.[72] In âAnarchisme et Marxismeâ (written in 1973),
GuĂ©rin emphasised that his book on anarchism had focussed on âsocial,
constructive, collectivist or communist anarchismâ because this was the
kind of anarchism which had most in common with Marxism.[73]
The reason Guérin gave for focussing on this kind of anarchism, as
opposed to insurrectionist, individualist or illegalist anarchism or
terrorism, was that it was entirely relevant to the problems faced by
contemporary revolutionaries: âlibertarian visions of the future ...
invite serious consideration. It is clear that they fulfil to a very
large extent the needs of our times, and that they can contribute to the
building of our future.â[74]
But is this really âclassical anarchism,â as GuĂ©rin put it, given the
insistence on âconstructive anarchism, which depends on organisation, on
self-discipline, on integration, on federalist and noncoercive
centralisationâ; the emphasis on experiments in workersâ control in
Algeria, Yugoslavia and Cuba; the openness to the idea that such states
could be seen as socialist and capable of reform in a libertarian
direction?[75] This was not the conclusion of English anarchist Nicolas
Walter, whose review of Ni dieu ni maftre commented that âthe selection
of passages shows a consistent bias towards activism, and the more
intellectual, theoretical and philosophical approach to anarchism is
almost completely ignored .... There is a similar bias towards
revolution, and the more moderate, pragmatic and reformist approach to
anarchism is almost completely omitted as well.â[76] As for GuĂ©rinâs
LâAnarchisme, Walter detected a similar bias towards Proudhon and
Bakunin, and was surprised at the emphasis on Gramsci, âwhich might be
expected in a Marxist account [of the Italian workersâ councils after
the Great War] but is refreshing in an anarchist one.â Walter was also
sceptical about the attention paid to Algeria and Yugoslavia. In
summary, however, these two books were âthe expression of an original
and exciting view of anarchism.â[77]
So GuĂ©rinâs two books arguably represented an original departure, and it
is worth quoting some remarks made by Patrice Spadoni who worked
alongside Guérin in different libertarian communist groups in the 1970s
and 1980s:
It has to be said that Daniel GuĂ©rinâs non-dogmatism never ceased to
amaze us. In the 1970s, a period in which there was so much
blinkeredness and sectarianism, in our own ranks as well as among the
Leninists, Daniel would often take us aback. The young libertarian
communists that we were ... turned pale with shock when he sang the
praises of a Proudhon, of whom he was saying âyes and noâ while we said
âno and noâ; then we would go white with horror, when he started quoting
Stirner whom we loathed-without having really read him; then we became
livid, when he began a dialogue with social-democrats; and finally, we
practically had a melt-down when he expressed respect, albeit without
agreeing with them, for the revolt of the militants associated with
Action directe.[78]
Two of these taboos are worth picking up on when considering the extent
to which GuĂ©rinâs take on anarchism was a novel one: Proudhon and
Stirner.
Proudhon had already ceased to be an ideological reference for any
section of the French anarchist movement by at least the time of the
Great War, except for a small minority of individualists opposed to any
kind of collective ownership of the means of production. Most anarchists
referred to either Kropotkin or Bakunin. This was partly because of the
ambiguities in Proudhonâs own writings regarding property, and partly
because of the increasingly reactionary positions adopted by some of his
âMutualistâ followers after his death in 1865.
The fact that Proudhon is so central to GuĂ©rinâs ârehabilitationâ of
anarchism is thus surprising and tells us something about what he was
trying to do and how it is he came to study anarchism in such depth:
whereas Proudhon had already for many years been commonly referred to as
the âpere de lâanarchie,â the âfather of anarchy,â GuĂ©rin refers to him
as the âpere de lâautogestion,â the âfather of self-management.â This is
the crux of the matter: Guérin was looking for a way to guarantee that
in any future revolution, control of the workplace, of the economy and
of society as a whole would remain at the base, that spontaneous forms
of democracyâlike the soviets, in the beginningâwould not be hijacked by
any centralised power.[79] Marx, Guérin insisted, hardly mentioned
workersâ control or self-management at all, whereas Proudhon paid it a
great deal of attention.[80] Workersâ control was, for GuĂ©rin, âwithout
any doubt the most original creation of anarchism, and goes right to the
heart of contemporary realities.â[81] Proudhon had been one of the first
to try to answer the question raised by other social reformers of the
early nineteenth century. As GuĂ©rin put it: âWho should manage the
economy? Private capitalism? The state? Workersâ organisations? In other
words, there wereâand still areâthree options: free enterprise,
nationalisation, or socialisation (i.e., self-management).â[82] From
1840 onwards, Proudhon had argued passionately for the third option,
something which set him apart from most other socialists of the time,
who, like Louis Blanc, argued for one form or another of state control
(if only on a transitional basis). Unlike Marx, Engels and others,
GuĂ©rin argued, Proudhon saw workersâ control as a concrete problem to be
raised now, rather than relegated to some distant future. As a
consequence, he thought and wrote in detail about how it might function:
âAlmost all the issues which have caused such problems for present-day
experiments in self-management were already foreseen and described in
Proudhonâs writings.â [83]
As for Stirnerâgenerally anathema to the non-individualist wing of the
anarchist movement-the answer lies in what Guérin perceived to be
Stirnerâs latent homosexuality, his concern with sexual liberation and
his determination to attack bourgeois prejudice and puritanism: âStirner
was a precursor of May â68.â[84] His âgreatest claim to originality, his
most memorable idea, was his discovery of the âuniqueâ individual....
Stirner became, as a consequence, the voice of all those who throw down
a challenge to normality.â [85]
What we can see here, underlying GuĂ©rinâs approving summary of the
meaning and importance of Stirner, is someone who had for many years
been forced to suffer in silence because of the endemic homophobia of
the labour movement, someone who had been forced by societyâs moral
prejudices to live a near-schizoid existence, totally suppressing one
half of his personality. It was GuĂ©rinâs personal experience of and
outrage at the homophobia of many Marxists and what seemed to be
classical Marxismâs exclusive concern with materialism and class that
accounts in large part for his sympathy with Stirner.
So to the extent that Guérin insists that every anarchist is an
individualistâat the same time as being a âsocialâ anarchist (anarchiste
societaire)âto the extent that he approves of Stirnerâs emphasis on the
uniqueness of each individual, it is because he admires the
determination to resist social conformism and moral prejudice. Guérin
certainly had no truck with the precious âfreedom of the individualâ
which by the 1920s had already become the stock mantra of those
anarchists who rejected any attempt to produce a more ideologically and
organisationally coherent revolutionary movement or who wished to ground
their action in a realistic (or in GuĂ©rinâs words âscientificâ) analysis
of social conditions.
So having called himself a âlibertarian socialistâ in the late 1950s
before going through an âanarchist phaseâ in the 1960s, by 1968 GuĂ©rin
was advocating âlibertarian Marxism,â a term he would later change to
âlibertarian communismâ in order not to alienate some of his new
anarchist friends (though the content remained the same). In 1969, with
Georges Fontenis and others Guérin launched the Mouvement communiste
libertaire (MCL), which attempted to bring together various groups such
as supporters of Denis Bergerâs Voie communiste, former members of the
FCL and individuals such as Gabriel Cohn-Bendit who had been associated
with Socialisme ou Barbarie.[86] Guérin was responsible for the
organisationâs paper, Guerre de classes (Class War). In 1971, the MCL
merged with another group to become the Organisation communiste
libertaire (OCL). In 1980, after complex debates notably over the
question of trade union activity, Guérin-who rejected ultra-Left forms
of âspontaneismeâ which condemned trade unionism as
counter-revolutionaryâwould ultimately join the Union des travailleurs
communistes libertaires (UTCL), created in 1978. He would remain a
member until his death in 1988.[87]
Looking back on those years, Georges Fontenis would write: âFor us [the
FCL], as for GuĂ©rin, âlibertarian Marxismâ was never to be seen as a
fusion or a marriage, but as a living synthesis very different from the
sum of its parts.â[88] How should we interpret this?
Guérin was always keen to emphasise the commonalities in Marxism and
anarchism, and underscored the fact that, in his view at least, they
shared the same roots and the same objectives. Having said that, and
despite the fact that Rubel seems to have influenced GuĂ©rin, GuĂ©rinâs
study of Marx led him to suggest that those such as Rubel who saw Marx
as a libertarian were exaggerating and/or being too selective.[89]
Reviewing the ambivalent but predominantly hostile relations between
Marx and Engels, on the one hand, and Stirner, Proudhon, and Bakunin, on
the other, Guérin concluded that the disagreements between them were
based to a great extent on misunderstanding and exaggeration on both
sides: âEach of the two movements needs the theoretical and practical
contribution of the other,â GuĂ©rin argued, and this is why he saw the
expulsion of the Bakuninists from the International Working Menâs
Association Congress at The Hague in 1872 as âa disastrous event for the
working class.â [90]
âLibertarian communismâ was for GuĂ©rin an attempt to ârevivify
everything that was constructive in anarchismâs contribution in the
past.â We have noted that his Anarchism focused on âsocial,
constructive, collectivist, or communist anarchism.â[91] GuĂ©rin was more
critical of âtraditionalâ anarchism, with what he saw as its knee-jerk
rejection of organisation, and particularly what he considered to be its
Manichean and simplistic approach to the question of the âstateâ in
modern, industrial and increasingly internationalised societies. He
became interested particularly in militants such as the Spanish
anarchist Diego Abad de Santillan, whose ideas on âintegratedâ economic
self-management contrasted with what Guérin insisted was the naive and
backward-looking âlibertarian communismâ of the Spanish CNT advocated at
its 1936 Saragossa conference by Isaac Puente and inspired, Guérin
thought, by Kropotkin.[92] Such a policy seemed to Guérin to take no
account of the nature of modern consumer societies and the need for
economic planning and coordination at national and transnational level.
In this connection, Guérin also became interested in the ideas of the
Belgian collectivist socialist Cesar de Paepeâwho argued against the
anarchists of the Jura Federation in favour of what he called an
âan-archic stateââon the national and transnational organisation of
public services within a libertarian framework.[93]
On the other hand, GuĂ©rinâs libertarian Marxism or communism did not
reject those aspects of Marxism which still seemed to Guérin valid and
useful: (i) the notion of alienation, much discussed since Erich Frommâs
1941 Fear of Freedom, and which Guérin saw as being in accordance with
the anarchist emphasis on the freedom and autonomy of the individual;
(ii) the insistence that the workers shall be emancipated by the workers
themselves; (iii) the analysis of capitalist society; and (iv) the
historical materialist dialectic, which for Guérin remained
one of the guiding threads enabling us to understand the past and the
present, on condition that the method not be applied rigidly,
mechanically, or as an excuse not to fight on the false pretext that the
material conditions for a revolution are absent, as the Stalinists
claimed was the case in France in 1936, 1945 and 1968. Historical
materialism must never be reduced to a determinism; the door must always
be open to individual will and to the revolutionary spontaneity of the
masses.[94]
Indeed, following his focus on anarchism in the 1960s, Guérin returned
in the 1970s to his earlier researches on Marxism, and in his new quest
for a synthesis of the two ideologies he found a particularly fruitful
source in Rosa Luxemburg, in whom he developed a particular interest and
he played a role in the wider resurgence of interest in her ideas. She
was for Guérin the only German social democrat who stayed true to what
he called âoriginalâ Marxism, and in 1971 he published an anthology of
her critical writings on the pre-1914 SFIO, as well as an important
study of the notion of spontaneity in her work.[95] Guérin saw no
significant difference between her conception of revolutionary
working-class spontaneity and the anarchist one, nor between her
conception of the âmass strikeâ and the syndicalist idea of the âgeneral
strike.â Her criticisms of Lenin in 1904 and of the Bolshevik Party in
the spring of 1918 (regarding the democratic freedoms of the working
class) seemed to him very anarchistic, as did her conception of a
socialism propelled from below by workersâ councils. She was, he argued,
âone of the links between anarchism and authentic Marxism,â and for this
reason she played an important role in the development of GuĂ©rinâs
thinking about convergences between certain forms of Marxism and certain
forms of anarchism. [96]
Guérin was convinced that a libertarian communism which represented such
a synthesis of the best of Marxism and the best of anarchism would be
much more attractive to progressive workers than âdegenerate,
authoritarian Marxism or old, outdated, and fossilised anarchism.â[97]
But he was adamant that he was not a theorist, that libertarian
communism was, as yet, only an âapproximation,â not a fixed dogma:
It cannot, it seems to me, be defined on paper, in absolute terms. It
cannot be an endless raking over of the past, but must rather be a
rallying point for the future. The only thing of which I am convinced is
that the future social revolution will have nothing to do with either
Muscovite despotism or anaemic social-democracy; that it will not be
authoritarian, but libertarian and rooted in self-management, or, if you
like, councilist.[98]
To what extent, then, can we say that Guérin succeeded in producing a
âsynthesisâ? Assessments by fellow revolutionaries have varied. GuĂ©rin
himself used to complain that many militants were so attached to
ideological pigeonholing and that quasi-tribal loyalties were so strong
that his purpose was frequently misunderstood, with many who identified
as anarchists criticising him for having âbecome a Marxist,â and vice
versa.[99] Yet Guérin was always very clear that there have been many
different Marxisms and many different anarchisms, and he also insisted
that his understanding of âlibertarian communismâ went beyond or
transcended (âdĂ©passeâ) both anarchism and Marxism.[100]
Nicolas Walter, in a broadly positive review of GuĂ©rinâs work, and
apparently struggling to characterise his politics, described him as âa
veteran socialist who became an anarchistâ and as âa Marxist writer of a
more or less Trotskyist varietyâ who had gone on to attempt a synthesis
between Marxism and anarchism before finally turning to âa syndicalist
form of anarchism.â[101]
George Woodcock, in a review of Noam Chomskyâs introduction to the
Monthly Review Press edition of GuĂ©rinâs Anarchism, insisted that
âneither is an anarchist by any known criterion; they are both left-wing
Marxistsâ-their failing having been to focus too narrowly on the
economic, on workersâ control, on an âobsolete,â âanarchosyndicalistâ
perspective.[102] Such a judgement is clearly based on a particular and
not uncontentious conception of anarchism.
The opposite conclusion was drawn by another anarchist, Miguel Chueca,
who has argued that if we look at all the major issues dividing
anarchists from Marxistsânamely, according to GuĂ©rinâs Pour un Marxisme
libertaire, the post-revolutionary âwithering awayâ of the state, the
role of minorities (or vanguards or avant-gardes) and the resort to
bourgeois democratic methodsâthen âthe âsynthesisâ results, in all
cases, in a choice in favour of the anarchist position.â[103] Chueca
seems to have based his conclusion on an essentialist view of anarchism
(in the singular) and of Marxism, and on an identification of Marxism
with Leninism. He appears to disregard some significant issues, such as
GuĂ©rinâs insistence on the historical materialist dialectic, and the
need for centralised (albeit ânon-coerciveâ) economic planning.
Writing from a sympathetic but not uncritical, Trotskyist perspective,
Ian Birchall suggests that ultimately GuĂ©rinâs greatest achievement was
his practice as a militant:
GuĂ©rinâs greatness lay in his role as a mediator rather than as a
synthesist. Over six decades he had a record of willingness to cooperate
with any section of the French left that shared his fundamental goals of
proletarian self-emancipation, colonial liberation and sexual freedom.
He was a vigorous polemicist, but saw no fragment of the left, however
obscure, as beneath his attention .... He was also typically generous,
never seeking to malign his opponents, however profoundly he disagreed
with them .... He was always willing to challenge orthodoxy, whether
Marxist or anarchist .... Yet behind the varying formulations one
consistent principle remained: âThe Revolution of our age will be made
from belowâor not at all.â[104]
Others have embraced GuĂ©rinâs theoretical contribution and it is clear
that his ideas on a âlibertarian Marxismâ or âlibertarian communismâ
were enormously influential from the 1960s onwards, and many today
(notably, but not only, those in France close to the organisation
Alternative libertaireâ[105]) see in him a precursor and are admiring of
his theoretical and practical contribution to the search for a
libertarian communismâalbeit as a contribution which needed further
development in the context of the social struggles of the 1980s and
beyond. Indeed Guérin was the first to accept that he had not yet seen
the âdefinitive crystalisation of such an unconventional and difficult
synthesis,â which would âemerge from social strugglesâ with âinnovative
forms which nobody today can claim to predictâ: [106]
It would be pointless today to try to paper over the cracks in the more
or less crumbling and rotting edifice of socialist doctrines, to plug
away at patching together some of those fragments of traditional Marxism
and anarchism which are still useful, to launch oneself into
demonstrations of Marxian or Bakuninian erudition, to attempt to trace,
merely on paper, ingenious syntheses or tortuous reconciliations.... To
call oneself a libertarian communist today, does not mean looking
backwards, but towards the future. The libertarian communist is not an
exegete, but a militant.[107]
---
A version of this introduction was first published in Alex Prichard,
Ruth Kinna, Saku Pinta, and David Berry (eds.), Libertarian Socialism:
Politics in Black and Red (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012; 2^(nd)
edition, Oakland: PM Press, 2017).
My education was anti-Stalinist Marxist. But for a good long while I
have been foolhardy enough to draw heavily on the treasure chest of
libertarian thought, ever relevant and alive on condition that it is
first stripped of a not insignificant number of childish, utopian, and
romantic notions as little useful as they are out of date.
Hence a misunderstanding that is all but inevitable but embittered by a
certain bad faith on the part of my opponents: the Marxists have turned
their backs on me as an anarchist, and the anarchists, because of my
Marxism, have not always wanted to view me as one of them.
A young, neophyteâand hence sectarianâMarxist even thought he saw in my
writings the assuaging of a consciousness that was âtornâ between
Marxism and anarchism and tossed desperately back and forth between the
two, when in fact it is without the least such vacillation or any
concern for my personal intellectual comfort that I believe in both the
need for and the practicability of a synthesis between Marxism and
anarchism.
Recently a working-class newspaper of Trotskyist bent and, let it be
said in passing, of high quality, assured its readers that I had gone
over from Marxism to anarchism. Taking advantage of the right to respond
that was democratically afforded me, I responded to this inaccurate
statement, the fruit of a basic need to catalogue everyone, that I was
making âa contribution to the search for a synthesis between Marxism and
anarchism.â âA synthesis,â I added, âthat since May â68 has moved from
the realm of ideas to that of action.â
But I was still seeking a denomination, since in order to communicate we
all need a label. The one I had decided on ten years ago, that of
âlibertarian socialist,â no longer seemed to me appropriate, for there
are many kinds of socialism, from social democratic reformism to
ârevisionist communismâ and an adulterated humanism. In short, the word
âsocialismâ belongs to the category of debased words.
[Italian students with whom I had debated Marxism and anarchism in
general and self-management in particular, provided me with the label:
these young people call themselves libertarian Marxists. In truth this
is not a discovery: the protesters of May in France, red and black flags
mixed together, were libertarian Marxists, without being aware of it or
calling themselves such.]
Hence the title of this book. Assembled here are a certain number of
texts, varied in their subject matter and the periods in which they were
written, but which all converge from various roads on the approach to a
libertarian communism.
The short book published under the title Anarchism might have created a
double misunderstanding: that I espoused all the ideas laid out in it
for information purposes, and also that I showed myself unable to draw
from this digest a synthesis of my own devising, which would be valid in
the present and the future.[108] This supposition was doubly inexact,
for I willingly effaced myself before the subject. In the present
collection I attempt to fly with my own wings. At my own risk.
[The materials presented here are followed by the date they were
written, though some retouching was done in order to bring the style and
content up to date.]
The revolution that is rising before us will beâalready isâlibertarian
communist.
[May 1969]
---
Note: The paragraphs in square brackets were present in the original
1969 version of this article (âPourquoi âmarxiste libertaireâ?â), but
omitted from subsequent editions.
Anarchism has long been a victim of an undeserved discredit, of an
injustice that has manifested itself in three ways.
First, its defamers insist that anarchism is dead, that it has not
resisted the great revolutionary tests of our time: the Russian
Revolution and the Spanish Revolution. That it no longer has a place in
the modern world, characterized as this is by centralization,
large-scale political and economic units, and the totalitarian concept.
All that is left to the anarchists, as Victor Serge said, is, âby the
force of events to go over to revolutionary Marxism.â[109]
Second, its detractors, in order to better discredit it, propose an
absolutely tendentious vision of its doctrine. Anarchism is said to be
essentially individualist, particularist, and resistant to any form of
organization. It aims at fracturing and atomizing, at the retreat into
themselves of local units of administration and production. It is said
to be incapable of unity, centralization, and planning. Itâs nostalgic
for âthe Golden Age.â It aims for the reviving of outmoded forms of
society. It sins by a childish optimism; its âidealismâ fails to take
into account the solid reality of the material infrastructure.
Finally, certain commentators are interested solely in wresting from
oblivion and publicizing only its most controversial deviations, like
individual assassinations and propaganda by the deed.
In revisiting the question Iâm not simply trying to retrospectively
repair a triple injustice or trying to write a work of erudition. It
seems to me, in fact, that anarchismâs constructive ideas are still
alive; that they can, on condition they be reexamined and closely
scrutinized, assist contemporary socialist thought in making a new
start.
Nineteenth-century anarchism is clearly distinguishable from
twentieth-century anarchism. Nineteenth-century anarchism was
essentially doctrinal. Though Proudhon had played a more or less central
role in the revolution of 1848, and the disciples of Bakunin were not
totally foreign to the Paris Commune, these two nineteenth-century
revolutions in their essence were not libertarian revolutions, but to a
certain extent rather âJacobinâ revolutions. On the contrary, the
twentieth century is, for the anarchists, one of revolutionary practice.
They played an active role in the two Russian Revolutions and, even
more, in the Spanish Revolution.
The study of the authentic anarchist doctrine, as it was formed in the
nineteenth century, shows that anarchy is neither disorganization,
disorder, nor atomization, but the search for true organization, true
unity, true order, and true centralization, which can only reside, not
in authority, coercion, or compulsion exercised from the top down, but
in free, spontaneous, federalist association from the bottom up. As for
the study of the Russian and Spanish revolutions and the role played in
them by the anarchists, it shows that contrary to the false legend
believed by some, these great and tragic experiences show that
libertarian socialism was largely in the right against the socialism
Iâll call âauthoritarian.â Throughout the world, socialist thought over
the course of the fifty years that followed the Russian Revolution, of
the thirty years that followed the Spanish Revolution, has remained
obsessed with a caricature of Marxism, bursting with its dogmas. In
particular, the internecine quarrel between Trotsky and Stalin, which is
the one best known to the advanced reader, if it contributed to wresting
Marxism-Leninism from a sterilizing conformism, did not truly cast
complete light on the Russian Revolution, because it did not
addressâcould not addressâthe heart of the problem.
For Voline, anarchist historian of the Russian Revolution, to speak of a
âbetrayalâ of the revolution, as Trotsky does, is insufficient as an
explanation: âHow was that betrayal possible in the aftermath of so
beautiful and total a revolutionary victory? This is the real question
.... What Trotsky calls betrayal was, in fact, the ineluctable effect of
a slow degeneration due to incorrect methods .... It was the
degeneration of the revolution ... that led to Stalin, and not Stalin
who caused the revolution to degener.â Voline asks: âCould Trotsky
really âexplainâ the drama since, along with Lenin, he himself
contributed to the disarming of the masses.â[110]
The assertion of the late, lamented Isaac Deutscher, according to which
the Trotsky-Stalin controversy would âcontinue and reverberate for the
rest of the centuryâ is debatable.[111] The debate that should be
reopened and continued is perhaps less that between Leninâs successors,
which is already outdated, but rather that between authoritarian
socialism and libertarian socialism. In recent time anarchism has come
out of the shadow to which it was relegated by its enemies.
Materials for a fresh examination of anarchism are today available to
those who are impassioned about social emancipation and in search of its
most effective forms. And also, perhaps, the materials for a synthesis,
one both possible and necessary, between the two equally fertile schools
of thought: that of Marx and Engels and that of Proudhon and Bakunin.
Ideas, it should be said, contemporary in their flowering and less
distant from each other than might be thought. Errico Malatesta, the
great Italian anarchist, observed that all the anarchist literature of
the nineteenth century âwas impregnated with Marxism.â[112] And in the
other direction, the ideas of Proudhon and Bakunin contributed in no
small degree to enriching Marxism.
[1965]
The problem is one with a certain topicality. In effect, it revolves
around the question already touched on by the social reformers of the
nineteenth century and posed with even more perplexity by the men of
today: who should manage the economy? Is it private capitalism? Is it
the state? Is it the associated workers? In other words, three options
existed and continue to exist: free enterprise, nationalization, and
socialization, i.e., self-management.
From 1848 Pierre-Joseph Proudhon was the ardent advocate of the third
solution. In this he set himself apart from the socialists of his time,
supporters of at least transitional state management. Their spokesman
was Louis Blanc in his pamphlet on The Organization of Labor
(1840).[113] It was Louis Blanc who was Proudhonâs bĂȘte noire, rather
than Marx and Engels, whose Communist Manifesto, written in German in
1847, he was not aware of. Louis Blancâs influence makes itself felt in
the Manifesto, where it was a question of âcentralizing all the
instruments of production in the hands of the state.â State
centralization crops up constantly in it, like a litany: âCentralization
of credit in the hands of the state with state capital and its exclusive
monopoly.â âCentralization in the hands of the state of all means of
transport.â âThe organization of industrial armies, particularly for
agriculture.â
Itâs true that the authors of the Manifesto, still following Louis
Blanc, envisaged a later stage, no longer statist but clearly
libertarian, from which, the proletariat having destroyed classes and
thus class antagonism, the state would disappear and production
wouldâfinallyâbe managed by the workers.
But the end of the transitional statist period was relegated to a
distant future, was more or less considered utopian and, because of
this, it was felt unnecessary to lay out the problems of workersâ
self-management before its time. When one reads Marx one is surprised at
the rarity, the brevity, and the summary nature of the passages
concerning the free association of producers. On the other hand Proudhon
who, because he was of working-class origins and upbringing, considered
self-management a concrete, immediate problem, studied its functioning
in depth and in detail. This is why those of our contemporaries who
consider the problem of self-management or who try to put it into
practice gain far more from the works of Proudhon than from those of
Marx. Before trying to lay out the Proudhonian conception of workersâ
self-management it is necessary to briefly recall, in contrast, his
rejection of âauthoritarianâ management of the economy. Since he could
not have read the Communist Manifesto and could only have had imperfect
knowledge of Marxist thought, notably through the Poverty of Philosophy,
written in French, it is principally against Louis Blanc, his compatriot
and direct adversary, that Proudhon multiplied his attacks:
The state is the patrimony, itâs the blood and the life of Louis Blanc.
Hit out at the state and Louis Blanc is a dead man.
Once the economic revolution is accomplished, must the state and the
government remain? With the economic revolution ... the state should
completely disappear.[114]
âThe instruments of production and exchange should not be entrusted to
the state. Being to the workers what the hive is to bees, their
management should be entrusted to workersâ associations.â[115] Only thus
âlarge-scale industry which, through the alienation of popular power,
lowers the wage earner to a state worse than slavery, becomes one of the
main organs of freedom and public happiness.â[116] âWe associated
producers or those on the path of association.â Proudhon proclaims in
the style of a manifesto, âhave no need of the state .... Exploitation
by the state is still monarchy, still wage labor ... We no more want
government of man by man than exploitation of man by man. Socialism is
the opposite of governmentalism .... We want these associations to be
... the first nucleus of a vast federation of companies and enterprises,
united by the common bond of the democratic and social republic.â[117]
Let us now see what the workersâ self-management which Proudhon opposed
to the transitional state management dear to both Louis Blanc and Karl
Marx consisted of.
The revolution of February 1848 saw a spontaneous blossoming of workersâ
productive associations born in Paris and Lyon. It was this nascent
self-management, rather than the political revolution, which was, for
the Proudhon of 1848, âthe revolutionary fact.â It had not been invented
by a theoretician or preached by doctrinaires. It was not given its
initial impetus by the government. It came from the people. And Proudhon
implored the workers throughout the republic to organize in the same
way; that they draw to them, first small property, small merchants, and
small industry, then large property and large enterprises, and then the
most extensive operations (mines, canals, railroads, etc.), and in so
doing âbecome the masters of everything.â[118]
Thereâs a tendency today to only recall Proudhonâs desire, naive to be
sure, and doubtless anti-economic, to ensure the survival of small-scale
artisanal and commercial enterprise. There is certainly no lack of texts
where Proudhon takes the side of small producers. Georges Gurvitch
observed in the rich little book he dedicated to Proudhon that the
writer had entitled a postscript to his Confessions of a Revolutionary
(1851): âApotheosis of the middle class,â and that heâd âdreamed of a
reconciliation of the proletariat and the middle class.â[119] In his
posthumous book, The Theory of Property, Proudhon made the following
clarification:
The object of workersâ associations is not to replace individual action
by collective action, as was madly believed in 1848, but rather that of
ensuring all the entrepreneurs of small and middle industry the benefit
of the discoveries, machines, improvements and procedures otherwise
unavailable to modest enterprises and fortunes.
But Proudhonian thought is ambivalent on this point. Proudhon was a
living contradiction. He railed against property, the source of
injustice and exploitation, and celebrated it to the extent that he saw
in it a guarantee of personal independence. What is more, we too often
have the tendency to confuse Proudhon with the tiny so-called
Proudhonian coterie that, according to Bakunin, formed around him in the
final years of his life. This fairly reactionary coterie was, he said,
âstillborn.â[120] Within the first International it vainly attempted to
oppose private ownership of the means of production to collectivism. And
if it did not live long it was mainly because most of its followers,
easily convinced by Bakuninâs arguments, did not hesitate to abandon
their supposedly Proudhonian concepts in favour of collectivism.
In any case, the last Mutualists, as they called themselves, only
partially rejected collective property. They only fought against it in
agriculture, given the individualism of the French farmer, but they
accepted it in transport, and in the case of industrial self-management
they called for the thing while rejecting the name.[121] If they were so
afraid of the name it was mainly because the temporary united front
formed against them by Bakuninâs collectivist disciples and certain
authoritarian Marxists, barely disguised supporters of state management
of the economyâlike Lucraft at the Basel Congress[122]âdid nothing to
reassure them. Marxist defamation did the rest, attributing to Proudhon
the somewhat reactionary point of view of his epigones.
In fact, Proudhon was in step with his time. As Pierre Haubtmann pointed
out in his magisterial thesis, âHe has often been incorrectly presented
as hostile to the very principle of large-scale industry. There is no
doubt that at the sight of the Moloch factoryâlike the tentacular
stateâhe reflexively recoils in fear, which leads him, in reaction, to
lean towards small businesses and decentralization. But as concerns
economic life, it would be a serious error to think that he was hostile
to the principle of mass production. On the contrary, he speaks to us at
length and enthusiastically of the need for powerful workersâ productive
associations. Of their role and their grandiose future. He thus accepts
and even desires large-scale industry .... But he wants to humanize it,
to exorcise its evil power, to socialize it by handing its fate over to
a community of workers, equal, free, and responsible.â[123] Proudhon
understands it is impossible to go backwards. He is realistic enough to
see, as he writes in his Notebooks, that âsmall-scale industry is as
foolish as small-scale culture.â[124]
As for large-scale modern industry, demanding a significant number of
workers, he is decisively collectivist: âIn the future large-scale
industry and large-scale agriculture must be born of association.â[125]
In General Idea of Revolution in the Nineteenth Century (1851) Proudhon
several times returned to this modernist and, I might say, futurist
concept: âThe workersâ companies, a protest against wage labor, are
called on to play a considerable role in the near future. This role will
above all consist in the management of the great instruments of labor
and of certain tasks, which âdemandâ both a great division of functions
and a great collective force.â[126]
In his Justice (1858) Proudhon waxes indignant that people have dared to
present him as an enemy of technical progress.[127] In his final work,
which appeared shortly after his death, On the Political Capacity of the
Working Class, he again confirms: âThe construction of railroads should
have been entrusted to workersâ companies. If itâs a matter of
large-scale manufacturing, extractive, maritime or steel industries, it
is clear that there is place for association. No one any longer contests
this.â[128]
In my book Anarchism I already listed the essential conditions for
workersâ self-management:
the company.
in the company that ensure him an encyclopedic education. Proudhon
insists absolutely on âhaving the worker go through the series of
industrial operations to which he is connected. In this way the division
of labor can no longer be a cause of degradation for the worker; on the
contrary, it is the instrument of his education and the guarantor of his
security.â[129]
Pierre Haubtmann, commenting on Proudhon, remarked that for Marx itâs
the âautomatic workshopââwe would say automationâwhich, through the
division of labor and the reduction of working hours, both pushed to the
extreme, will allow every man to achieve âtotal development.â Machinery
extending man, disalienation will enter into play, not in work, but in
leisure. Proudhon is hardly seduced by such a perspective. For him, man
is essentially a producer. He wants him to constantly be at work. Weâre
at antipodes from the exuberant Right to be Lazy by Paul Lafargue.[130]
For the ferocious Puritan, for the âSaint Paul of socialismâ that
Proudhon was, leisure is not far from being a synonym for lust.[131] He
expects âdisalienationâ from a mode of production that would give the
worker a synthetic vision of the labor process.[132]
Gurvitch, contrasting Marx and Proudhon, underlines the following
passage from Justice: âThe spirit is no longer in the worker; it has
passed over to the machine. What should be the virtue of the worker has
become his degradation.â This evil can only be corrected âif the
collective forces alienated for the profit of a few exploiters are
returned to labor as a whole.â[133]
Proudhon counts on an increase in productivity under self-management,
thanks to the joy of disalienated labor.
After this digression, according to Proudhon the essential conditions of
self-management are:
the associates.
importance of the talent, and the breadth of the responsibility. Each
associate participates in the profits in proportion to his services.
hours, and liquidate his share.
architects, and their accountants. Proudhon insists on the fact that the
proletariat is still lacking in certain abilities. It must be recognized
that âdue to the insufficiency of its insights and its lack of business
expertise the working class is still incapable of managing interests as
large as those involved in commerce and large-scale industry, and
consequently falls short of achieving its destiny. Men are lacking among
the proletariat.â[134]
Hence the need to join to workersâ self-management âindustrial and
commercial notablesâ who will initiate the workers in the disciplines of
business and who will be paid a fixed wage: âThere is room for everyone
under the sun of the revolution.â[135]
Let us note in passing that this libertarian understanding of
self-management is at antipodes from the paternalistic and statist
âself-managementâ laid out by Louis Blanc in a decree of September 15,
1849.[136] The author of The Organization of Labor wanted to create
workersâ associations under the aegis of and sponsored by the state. He
envisioned an authoritarian division of profits: 25 percent for the
amortization of capital, 25 percent for social assistance funds, 25
percent for reserve funds; 25 percent to be shared among the workers.
Proudhon wanted nothing to do with a âself-managementâ of this kind. No
compromise was possible for an intransigent individual like him. The
associated workers were not âto submit to the stateâ but âto be the
state itself.â[137] âThe association ... can do everything, reform
everything without the assistance of the authorities, conquer and force
authority itself to submit.â
Proudhon wanted âto march to government through association and not to
association through government.â[138]
He warned against the illusion that the state, as dreamed of by the
authoritarian socialists, could tolerate free self-management. How
âcould it accept, alongside a centralized power, the formation of enemy
centers?â From which this warning, whose intransigence becomes
prophetic: âNothing is doable through the initiative, spontaneity, and
independent actions of individuals and collectivities as long as they
face the colossal force with which the state is invested by
centralization.â[139]
In fact, Proudhon anticipates here the tragedy of contemporary
self-management, as experienced in both Yugoslavia and Algeria within
the framework of a dictatorial state.
In fact, it is the libertarian and not the statist concept of
self-management that prevailed at the congresses of the First
International. At the Lausanne Congress (1867) the rapporteur, the
Belgian Cesar de Paepe, having proposed making the state the owner of
the enterprises to be nationalized, Charles Longuet, at the time a
libertarian, added: âAgreed, on the condition that it be understood that
we define the state as the collective of citizens ... and also that
these services will not be administered by state functionaries but by
workersâ companies.â The debate was picked up again the following year
(1868) at the Brussels Congress and the same rapporteur was careful to
make the requested rectification: âCollective property will belong to
the entire society, but it will be conceded to workersâ associations.
The state will now be only the federation of various groups of workers.â
The proposal, thus, refined, was adopted.[140]
The optimism Proudhon demonstrated in 1848 relating to self-management
was somewhat belied by the lesson of facts. A few years later, in 1857,
he subjected the workersâ organizations still in existence to a harsh
critique. Their inspiration had been naive, illusory, and utopian. They
had paid the price for inexperience. They had fallen into particularism
and exclusivism. They had functioned like a collective managerial class
and been swept along by the ideas of hierarchy and supremacy. All the
abuses of capitalist societies âwere exaggerated in these so-called
fraternal companies.â They had been torn by discord, rivalries,
defections, and betrayals. Their managers, once they had been initiated
into the business, had withdrawn âto set themselves up as bosses and
bourgeois.â Elsewhere, it was the associates who had called for the
sharing out of products. Of the several hundred workersâ associations
created in 1848, twenty remained nine years later. And Proudhon opposed
a notion of âuniversalâ and âsyntheticâ self-management to that narrow
and particularist mentality. The task for the future was far more than
the âassembling into societies of a few hundred workers;â it was nothing
less than âthe economic reconstituting of a nation of thirty-six million
souls.â The future workersâ associations, âinstead of acting for the
profit of a few,â must work for all.[141] Self-management thus demanded
âa certain educationâ of the self-managers. âOne is not born an
associate; one becomes one.â The most difficult task of the associations
was that of âcivilizing the associates.â What they had lackedâand here
Proudhon renewed his warning of 1851âwas âmen issued from the working
masses who had learned at the school of the exploiters to do without
them,â It was less a matter of forming âa mass of capitalâ than a âfund
of men.â[142]
On the legal plane Proudhon had initially envisaged entrusting the
property of their enterprises to the workersâ associations. Now, as
Georges Gurvitch points out, he rejected his original notion âof
ownership by groups of producers.â[143] In order to do this he
distinguished, in a posthumous work, between possession and
property.[144] Property is absolutist, aristocratic, feudal, despotic;
possession is democratic, republican, egalitarian: it consists in the
usufructuary enjoyment of a non-cedable, indivisible and inalienable
concession. The producers would receive, as âallods,â like the ancient
Germans, their instruments of production. They would not be the owners.
This âhigher formulationâ of ownership would unite all the advantages of
property and association without any of the drawbacks. What would
succeed property would be, as Gurvitch says, federative co-property
attributed not to the state, but to all the producers, united in a vast
agricultural and industrial federation. The economic federation would
come to âcounterbalanceâ the state, a state this time not erased from
the Proudhonian map, but transformed from top to bottom.
And Proudhon sees a revised and corrected self-management in the future:
âItâs no longer vain rhetoric that proclaims it: itâs economic and
social necessity. The moment approaches when weâll only be able to
advance under these new conditions .... The classes ... must be resolved
into one sole association of producers.â[145]
On what bases will the exchanges between the various workersâ
associations be ensured? Proudhon initially maintained that the exchange
value of all merchandise could be measured by the amount of labor
necessary for its production. The various production associations would
sell their goods at cost. The workers, paid with âlabor bonds,â would
purchase merchandise at exchange posts or in social stores at cost.
This so-called Mutualist conception was a tad utopian, in any case
difficult to apply under capitalism. The Peopleâs Bank, founded by
Proudhon in early 1849, succeeded in obtaining some 20,000 members in
six weeks, but its existence was to be brief. To be sure, the sudden
rise to power of Prince-President Louis Bonaparte had something to do
with this. But it was illusory to think that Mutualism would spread and
to exclaim as Proudhon did that âit was truly the new world, the society
of âpromiseâ which, grafted onto the old world, gradually transformed
it!â
It appears that Pierre Haubtmann was correct in stressing in his thesis
the illusory character of the Mutualism of the years 1846â1848. But he
perhaps attacked Proudhon too vigorously in the way that he invokes the
sins of his youth, which would quickly be corrected by his concrete and
more positive visions of workersâ self-management.
Remuneration based on the evaluation of working hours was debatable for
various reasons. Around 1880 the anarchist communists (or âlibertarian
communistsâ) of the school of Kropotkin, Malatesta, ElisĂ©e Reclus, Carlo
Cafiero and others did not fail to criticize it. In the first place, in
their eyes it was unjust: âThree hours of Peterâs labor,â Cafiero
objected, âare often worth five hours of Paulâs.â Factors other than
duration intervene in the determination of the value of labor: the
intensity, the professional and intellectual education required, etc. We
must also take into account the workerâs family responsibilities. One
finds the same objections in the Critique of the Gotha Program, written
by Karl Marx in 1875, but hushed up by German social democracy until
1891. and which the libertarian communists thus were not aware of when
they argued against Proudhon.
What is more, maintains the school of Kropotkin, under a collectivist
regime the worker remains a wage earner, a slave to the community that
purchases and keeps an eye on the quantity of his labor. Remuneration
proportionate to the hours of labor furnished by each cannot be an
ideal, but at best a temporary expedient. We must have done with
morality based on accounting ledgers, with the philosophy of âmust and
have to.â
This mode of remuneration proceeds from a watered down individualism in
contradiction with collective ownership of the means of production. It
is incapable of implementing a profound and revolutionary transformation
of man. Itâs incompatible with anarchism. A new form of ownership
demands a new form of remuneration: the services rendered society cannot
be evaluated in monetary units. Needs must be placed above services. All
the products produced by the labor of all should belong to all, and each
should freely take his share. To each according to his needs; this must
be the motto of libertarian communism.[146]
But Malatesta, Kropotkin, and their friends seem to have been unaware
that Proudhon himself at least partially foresaw their objections and in
the end revised his original conception. His Theory of Property,
published posthumously, explained that it was only in his First
Memorandum on Property, that of 1840, that he supported the equality of
salaries to the equality of labor. âI had forgotten to say two things;
first that labor is measured by a composite of duration and intensity;
second, that there should not be included in the workerâs wage either
the amortization of his educational costs and the work he undertook on
his own as a non-paid apprentice, or the insurance premiums against the
risks he runs, and which are far from being the same in all
professions.â
Proudhon asserted he had ârepairedâ this âomissionâ in his subsequent
writings, where he had the unequal costs and risks paid for by the
mutual insurance cooperative societies.[147] We note here that Proudhon
in no way considered the remuneration of association members a salary,
but rather a distribution of profits, freely decided by associated
workers and those jointly responsible. If not, as Pierre Haubtmann
notes, self-management makes no sense.
The libertarian communists also reproached Proudhonâs Mutualism and the
more consistent collectivism of Bakunin for not having wanted to
prejudge the form that the remuneration of labor would take under a
socialist regime. These critics seem to lose sight of the fact that the
two founders of anarchism were careful not to prematurely imprison
society in a rigid framework. On this point they wanted to preserve the
greatest latitude for the workersâ associations. For Bakunin
collectivism had to be practiced âunder varied forms and conditions,
which will be determined in each locale, in each region, and each
commune by its degree of civilization and the will of the
population.â[148]
But the libertarian communists themselves provide the justification for
this flexibility, for this refusal of premature solutions when, contrary
to their impatient expectations, they insist that in the ideal regime of
their choice âlabor will produce much more than is needed for all.â In
fact, it is only when the era of abundance arrives that âbourgeoisâ
norms of remuneration can give way to specifically âcommunistâ norms.
And not before this, as Marx and Lenin saw with a certain lucidity,
though not without statist prejudice.[149]
In 1884, writing the program of an anarchist International still in a
state of limbo, Malatesta admitted that communism would only be
immediately realizable in extremely limited sectors and that âfor the
restâ one must âtransitionallyâ accept collectivism. âIn order to be
realizable, communism requires a great moral development of the members
of society, an elevated and profound feeling of solidarity that the
revolutionary outburst will perhaps not suffice in producing, which is
even more likely in that at the beginning the material conditions
favoring such a development will be lacking.â[150]
After Malatesta, the anarchist Fernand Pelloutier, having become a
revolutionary syndicalist, would be even more categorical: âNo one
believes ... that the imminent revolution will realize pure communism.
Since it will in all likelihood break out before anarchist education has
been completed, men will not be mature enough to absolutely rule
themselves. We must take men as they are, as the old society left them
to us.â[151]
Among the norms inherited from bourgeois economics, there is one whose
maintenance under collectivism or self-management raises thorny
problems, to wit, competition. Just as in Proudhonâs eyes private
property in the products of labor constitutes a guarantee for the
producer of their personal independence, competition is âthe expression
of social spontaneity,â the guarantor of the âfreedomâ of associations.
In addition, it constitutes, for a long time to come, an irreplaceable
stimulant without which âan immense relaxation would succeed the ardent
tension of industry.â âRemove competition ... and society, deprived of
its motive force, would stop like a pendulum whose spring is
loose.â[152] Proudhon proposed practical recipes: âVis-a-vis society,
the workersâ company commits to always providing the products and
services requested of it at a price close to cost.... To this effect the
workersâ company forbids itself any [monopolistic] coalitions, accepts
the law of competition, and places its books and archives at the
disposal of society, which, as the sanction of its right of control,
preserves the ability to dissolve it.â[153] âCompetition and association
mutually support each other .... The most deplorable error of socialism
is that of having regarded [competition] as the overturning of society.
There can be no question of destroying competition .... Itâs a question
of finding its equilibrium, I would even say its organization.â[154]
This attachment to the principle of competition earned Proudhon the
sarcasm of Louis Blanc. âWe are unable to understand those who imagined
some strange coupling of two opposing principles. Grafting association
onto competition is a poor idea. It means replacing eunuchs with
hermaphrodites.â[155]
Louis Blanc wanted to âarrive at a uniform priceâ fixed by the state and
to prevent any competition between the workshops of one industry.
Proudhon replied that prices âare only settled by competition,â that is,
by the consumerâs ability to âto do without the services of those who
overstate them.â[156]
To be sure, Proudhon did not hide the evils of competition, which he had
abundantly described in his Philosophy of Poverty. He knew it was a
source of inequality. He admitted that âin competition victory is
assured to the largest battalions.â As long as it is âanarchicâ (in the
pejorative sense of the term), as it only exists for the profit of
private interests, it necessarily engenders civil war and, in the end,
oligarchy. âCompetition kills competition.â[157]
But in Proudhonâs opinion the absence of competition would be no less
pernicious. He cited the example of the state-run tobacco office. This
monopoly, from the very fact that it is free of competition, is too dear
a service and its productivity is insufficient. If all industries were
subject to such a regime, the nation, according to him, would no longer
be able to balance its receipts and expenses.[158]
However the competition dreamed of by Proudhon is not the unfettered
competition of the capitalist economy, but a competition endowed with a
higher principle that âsocializesâ it; a competition that operates on
the basis of an honest exchange in a spirit of solidarity; a competition
which, while safeguarding individual initiative, will return the wealth
currently diverted by capitalist appropriation to the collective.[159]
It is clear that there is something utopian in this conception.
Competition and the so-called market economy inevitably produce
inequality and exploitation, even if the departure point is a situation
of perfect equality. They can only be joined to workersâ self-management
transitionally, as a necessary lesser evil while waiting for the
development within the self-managers of a mentality of âsincerity of
exchange,â as Proudhon called it[160] and above all, when society has
passed from the stage of penury to that of abundance and competition
loses its entire raison dâĂȘtre.
But in this transitional period it seems desirable that competition
should be limited, as is the case today in Yugoslavia, to the sphere of
the means of consumption, where it at least has the advantage of
defending the interests of the consumer.[161]
Nevertheless, in Yugoslavia competition too often leads to excesses and
irrationalities which the authoritarian adversaries of the market
economy take pleasure in denouncing. Useful both as a stimulant to the
spirit of enterprise and as a means of struggle against the high cost of
living, it too often sustains among the Yugoslavian self-managers a
selfish and quasi-capitalist mentality from which concern for the
general interest is absent.
It should be noted that workersâ self-management in Yugoslavia is
criticized by the Cubans and the Chinese, precisely because of its
inability to reconcile competition and socialism.
Well before the authoritarian âcommunistsâ of today denounced the
coupling of self-management and competition, the libertarian communists
of the 1880s attacked the Proudhonian collectivist economy based on the
principle of struggle, where all that would be done would be
reestablishing among the competitors equality at the starting point in
order to then cast them into a battle necessarily resulting in victors
and vanquished, where the exchange of products would end by being
carried out in accordance with supply and demand, âwhich would mean
descending into competition, into the bourgeois world.â This language
very much resembles that of certain detractors of the Yugoslav
experience in the communist world. They think it necessary to direct at
self-management the hostility inspired in them by the competitive market
economy, as if the two notions were inseparable from each other. This
wasâand I speak of him in the past tenseâthe case of Che Guevara, for
example, who mistrusted self-management because he thought it synonymous
with competition.[162]
Proudhon, to return to him, sees quite clearly that management by
workersâ associations can only be unitary. He insists on âthe need for
centralization and unity.â I do not find in him âthat provincialism
closed to the wide worldâ that some think they saw. He asks the
question: âArenât the workersâ companies for the exploitation of
large-scale industries an expression of unity? What we put in place of
government is industrial organization. What we put in place of political
centralization is economic centralization.â
For Proudhon, self-management is society finally âalive, organized;â
âthe highest degree of freedom and order which humanity can achieve.â
And in a burst of enthusiasm he exclaims, âHere we are free, emancipated
from our embryonic shell. All relations have been inverted. Yesterday we
walked upside down. We are changing our existence. This, in the
nineteenth century, is the revolution.â[163]
Nevertheless, despite his concern for unity, Proudhon dreads
authoritarian planning, which is why he instinctively prefers to it
competition of solidaristic inspiration. But, in a more consistent
fashion, anarchism has since made itself the advocate for democratic and
libertarian planning, elaborated from the bottom up by the confederation
of self-managed enterprises.
It is in this way that Bakunin glimpsed the possibilities of a planning
on a worldwide scale which open up to self-management: âThe workersâ
cooperative associations are a new fact in history. We are witnessing
their birth and we can only sense but not determine at this time the
immense development that without any doubt will ensue and the new
political and social conditions that will arise in the future. It is
possible and even quite probable that one day, going beyond the limits
of communes, provinces, and even current states, they will provide all
of human society with a new constitution, divided not into nations, but
into industrial groups.â They will thus form âan immense economic
federationâ with, at its summit, a supreme assembly. In light of âdata
as broad as it is precise and detailed, of worldwide statistics, they
will combine supply and demand in order to guide, determine, and
distribute among the different countries the production of international
industry in such a way that there will no longer be, or almost no longer
be, commercial and industrial crises, forced stagnation, and any wasted
effort or capital.â[164]
The Proudhonian conception of management by workersâ associations bore
within it an ambiguity. It was not always specified if self-managed
groups would remain in competition with capitalist enterprises, if, as
is today said in Algeria, the socialist sector would co-exist with the
private sector or if, on the contrary, production as a whole would be
socialized and placed under self-management.
Bakunin, unlike his teacher Proudhon, whose ideas are hesitant on this
point, is a consistent collectivist. He clearly sees the dangers of the
coexistence of these two sectors. The workers, even associated, cannot
assemble the capital capable of fighting against big bourgeois capital.
And what is more, the danger exists that within the workersâ association
there will arise, from the contagion of the capitalist environment, âa
new class of exploiters of the labor of the proletariat.â
Self-management contains within it all the seeds of the economic
emancipation of the working masses, but it can only develop all these
seeds when âcapital, industrial establishments, primary materials, and
tools ... will become the collective property of productive workersâ
associations, both industrial and agricultural, freely organized and
federated among themselves.â âThe social transformation can only occur
in a radical and definitive fashion by methods acting upon all of
society,â that is, by a social revolution transforming private property
into collective property. In such a social organization the workers will
collectively be their own capitalists, their own bosses. The only things
left to private property will be âthose things that are truly for
personal use.â[165]
As long as the social revolution has not been accomplished Bakunin,
while admitting that productive cooperatives have the advantage of
accustoming workers to managing their own affairs, that they create the
first seeds of collective workersâ action, thought that these islands
within capitalist society could only have limited effectiveness, and he
incited workers âto occupy themselves less with cooperation than with
strikes.â[166] As Gurvitch notes, this is the opposite position from
Proudhonâs, who nourished illusions about the rapid absorption of the
capitalist economy by workersâ self-management, underestimated the
importance of unions and made too little of the right to strike.[167]
Proudhonâs ideas on self-management do not form a body of homogeneous
doctrine, perfectly adjusted, free of any hesitation or ambiguity. Far
from it. Contradictions abound in it.
There is a Mutualist Proudhon who defends, exalts, and attempts to save
the independent small producer from the implacable wheel of progress and
there is a resolutely collectivist Proudhon who does not hesitate to
march with his time, with technical progress, with technology, with
large-scale industry.
There is an optimistic Proudhon who in 1848 covers in flowers the
spontaneously born workersâ associations, and there is a pessimistic
Proudhon who, a few years later, in 1857, will draw up a severe balance
sheet of the failure of these associations.
There is a dreamer Proudhon who imagines Mutualism susceptible of
partial application within the capitalist regime and who persuades
himself that the socialist sector, from its own dynamism, will spread,
and there is a Proudhon who is much more realistic, and as a result
reticent on this point.
There is, as concerns the legal status of property under
self-management, a disintegrationist Proudhon who, at first, envisages
entrusting it to the workersâ associations themselves in accordance with
the principle âthe factories to the workers,â and there is an
integrationist Proudhon who will later prefer placing all producers in
one vast agricultural and industrial federation.
There is a simplistic Proudhon who proposes an extremely arguable
definition of labor value, and there is a subtler Proudhon who then
admits that the duration of labor cannot be the sole basis for this
calculation and who strives to repair what he calls his âomissions.â
There is the Proudhon who puts private property on trial, and there is a
Proudhon who praises it, just as there is a Proudhon who celebrates the
virtues of competition and there is a Proudhon who insists on its evils.
Itâs only quite rarely that he succeeds in constructing a true synthesis
of contradictory notions, and this is why he hides his failures while
flattering himself only for having âbalancedâ the antinomies.
There is a decentralizing and federalist Proudhon, who mistrusts all
planning for fear of reviving authority, and there is a Proudhon who
does not hesitate to prescribe economic centralization and stresses the
unitary character of production.
There is a Proudhon who, by affirming the capacities of the working
class and its duty to radically separate itself from bourgeois
institutions, opens the way to modern working-class syndicalism, and
there is a Proudhon who underestimates struggles for specific demands,
haunted as he is by the formation of workersâ production cooperatives.
Here we touch on what is perhaps the most serious omission in the
Proudhonian conception of self-management. It fails to be articulated
and coordinated by an anarcho-syndicalism or a revolutionary syndicalism
of the type that made possible the admirable experience of the Spanish
collectivizations of 1936. When Proudhon alludes to âa vast agricultural
and industrial federation,â he fails to dig deeper in the syndicalist
manner into that notion which, under his pen, remains unarticulated and
vague.
There is a Proudhon who, in the first part of his militant life, was
strictly concerned with economic organization, who mistrusted everything
having to do with politics, and there is a second Proudhon who will
cease neglecting the problem of territorial administration, who will
base it on the autonomous commune,[168] though failing to connect in a
sufficiently precise and coherent manner communal power on one side and
workersâ production associations on the other.
Finally, there is a Proudhon who categorically refuses any form of
stateâto the point that he issued a sectarian rejection of the
sponsoring of workersâ associations by a socialist-leaning stateâand
there is also a Proudhon who no longer considers himself an anarchist
but rather a federalist, and who participates in the state.
These, briefly recalled, are some of the omissions and failings
concerning workersâ self-management in Proudhonian thought.
But alongside these weaknesses, how many lucid points of view, how many
prophetic insights! The reader of Proudhon, if he is up to date on the
concrete problems posed by the practice of self-management in Yugoslavia
[in the 1950s and the early â60s], and in Algeria [from independence
until Boumedienneâs coup dâĂ©tat, 1962â1965], constantly finds himself on
familiar ground. Almost all the difficulties that form the drama of
contemporary self-management can be found announced and described in
Proudhonâs writings. In it they are the object of heart-rending
warnings, whether itâs on the question of the incompatibility of the
tentacular state and free self-management, or of the lack of men
prepared for self-management, or of the lack of technical cadres, or of
the unavoidabilityâat least during a transitional periodâof a market
economy containing a certain degree of competition, and, finally, on the
difficulty of establishing total communism prematurely, which will only
be practicable when abundance reigns and the consumer will only have to
draw from the pile. On all these points Proudhon illuminates the future
with a powerful spotlight.
But even when he hesitates, when he contradicts himself, when he changes
his mind, he provides his reader with a precious lesson in relativism.
It is thrilling to witness the flowering of a creative mind ever in
movement, forever seeking, never fixed, never dogmatic, tumultuous to be
sure, sometimes allowing himself to be carried away by a quip, by
improvisation, by failure to reflect, but capable of correcting himself,
revising himself, of accepting lessons from the facts, of evolving in
the light of experience.
And in any case Proudhon had his excuses. First, in laying the
foundations for workersâ self-management, he entered a domain so virgin
and new that no one could serve as his guide. Second, the contradictions
were less in his ideas than in the object they reflected. Workersâ
self-management, by its very nature, is contradictory. It is condemned
to waver between two poles: on one side the autonomy of production
groups, necessary so that each member feels truly free and
âdisalienated.â On the other hand, the need for coordination in order to
have the general interest prevail over selfish ones.
This coordination, I think, can be ensured under optimal conditions by
revolutionary working-class syndicalism, which is best qualified to play
such a role, since it is the direct and authentic emanation of the
workers. But where it is lacking, where it is degenerated and
bureaucratized, where it is insufficiently structured, where it is
underestimated, tamed, regarded as a poor relation, like a fifth wheel,
the role of coordinator inevitably falls to the state, a state which, by
the force of circumstances, wants above all to perpetuate itself, to
constantly extend its remit, to infringe on any forms of autonomy, to
nibble away at freedom.
In the final analysis the most profound contradiction that rends
workersâ self-management springs from the historical backwardness of the
education of the proletariat. The capitalist regime, as well as the
unionism of immediate demands that is its corollary, did not prepare the
workers, or prepared them poorly, for their self-management functions.
For an entire period they are thus obliged to seek outside their ranks
the experts, technical cadres, accountants, etc. Where the cadres barely
exist, as in Algeria, the functioning of self-management is seriously
hindered: someone recently observed that Algerian self-management
requires two hundred thousand accountants and the countryâs government
envisages the accelerated education of twenty thousand. But where these
experts exist, at least partially, their intrusion from without
subordinates self-management. âGuardianship organizations,â when they
provide technical assistance to self-managed enterprises, tend to
substitute themselves for the self-managers and to become managers in
their stead.
These serious drawbacks can only be eliminated when the fusion âof
science and the working classâ dreamed of by Ferdinand Lassalle and,
after him, by Rosa Luxemburg will allow the abolition of guardianship.
As the masses gradually educate themselves the social base upon which
the guardians rest will fade away. They will only be âexecutive organs,â
controllable and revocable by the âconscious actionsâ of the
workers.[169]
Socialism is fated to remain a vain word, a demagogic and hollow option,
as long as the workers are not able to manage production for themselves,
as long as they are enslaved, or allow themselves to be enslaved, by a
parasitic bureaucracy imitating the bosses whose place they cannot wait
to take.
In countries like Yugoslavia and Algeria, where self-management still
suffers from many vices in its functioning, it at least has the
advantage of allowing the masses to do their apprenticeship both in
democracy and management, of stimulating their enthusiasm at work (on
the condition, of course, of ensuring them-which is not always the
case-equitable remuneration). It inculcates in them the sense of their
responsibilities, instead of maintaining, as is the case under the yoke
of the omnipotent state, millennial habits of passivity, submission, and
the inferiority complex left to them by a slavish past.
At the end of such an apprenticeship self-management is, in a way,
condemned to succeed. For if this is not the case socialism will have
failed in its historical mission. As Proudhon observed: âUpon the
response that will be given ... depends the entire future of the
workers. If that response is in the affirmative a new world opens before
humanity. If it is in the negative, the proletariat can give up all hope
... : In this world there is no hope for them.â[170]
[1965, in Pour un Marxisme libertaire]
Voline, libertarian historian of the Russian Revolution after having
been an actor and witness, wrote, âA fundamental problem was left to us
by the preceding revolutions: above all I mean those of 1789 and 1917.
Arising in large part against oppression, animated by a powerful surge
of freedom, and proclaiming freedom as their essential goal, why did
these revolutions descend into new dictatorships carried out by other
dominating and privileged strata, into a new slavery of the popular
masses? What would the conditions be that would allow a revolution to
avoid this sad end? Is this end due to passing factors, to errors or
mistakes that could be avoided in the future? And in the latter case,
what would be the means to eliminate the danger that threatens the
imminent revolutions?â[171]
With Voline, I think that the two great historical experiences of the
French and Russian Revolutions are indissolubly connected. Despite the
differences in periods, environment, and âclass content,â the problems
they raise, the pitfalls they ran up against, were fundamentally the
same. At the very most, in the first revolution they manifested
themselves in a more embryonic form than in the later one. And so the
men of today can only hope to find the path to their future definitive
emancipation if they are able to distinguish between what was progress
and what was failure in these two experiences in order to draw the
lessons for the future.
In my opinion the basic cause for the relative failure of the two
greatest revolutions in history resides not, to borrow again from
Voline, in âhistoric inevitability,â or simply in the subjective
âerrorsâ of revolutionary actors. The revolution bears within itself a
serious contradiction (a contradiction which fortunatelyâand we will
return to the subjectâis not irremediable and is attenuated with time):
it can only arise, it can only vanquish if it issues from the depths of
the popular masses, from their irresistible spontaneous uprising; but
although the class instinct drives the popular masses to break their
chains, they are yet lacking in education and consciousness. And since,
in their formidable but tumultuous and blind drive towards liberty, they
run up against privileged, conscious, educated, organized, and tested
social classes, they can only vanquish the resistance they meet if they
succeed in obtaining in the heat of the struggle, the consciousness, the
science, the organization, and the experience they lack. But the very
fact of forging the weapons I have just listed summarily, and which
alone can ensure their superiority over the enemy, bears an immense
peril within it: that of killing the spontaneity that is the very spirit
of the revolution; that of compromising freedom through organization;
that of allowing the movement to be confiscated by an elite minority of
more educated, more conscious, more experienced militants who, to begin
with, offer themselves as guides in order, in the end, to impose
themselves as chiefs and to subject the masses to new forms of the
oppression of man by man.
For as long as socialism has been capable of reflecting on this problem,
for as long as it has been aware of this contradiction, more or less
since the beginning of the nineteenth century, socialism has not ceased
to struggle with it, to waver between the two opposing poles of freedom
and order. Every one of its thinkers and actors has laboriously and
stumblingly striven, at the price of many hesitations and
contradictions, to resolve the fundamental dilemma of the revolution.
Proudhon, in his famous Memoire sur la Propriété (1840), thought he had
found the synthesis when he optimistically wrote: âthe highest
perfection of society is found in the unity of order and anarchy.â But a
quarter of a century later he melancholically noted: âThese two ideas,
freedom ... and order, stand together .... They cannot be separated, nor
can one be absorbed in the other; we must resign ourselves to living
with both, with keeping them in balance .... No political force has yet
provided the true solution to the harmony of freedom and order.â[172]
Today an immense empire, constructed under the sign of âsocialismâ (and
of âcommunismâ), seeks painfully, without design, and sometimes
convulsively to escape the iron shackles of an âorderâ founded on
coercion in order to find the road to freedom which its millions of
subjects, daily more experienced and conscious, aspire to. The problem
has been posed in an ever-more-burning fashion, and the final word has
not been spoken.
If we look at it more closely, the problem has three relatively distinct
aspects, though they are intimately connected.
and consciousness, the masses and the leaders, play?
political and administrative organization must be substituted for the
one just defeated?
administered after the abolition of private property (a problem that is
posed in all its magnitude for the proletarian revolution but which was
posed only embryonically for the French Revolution)?
On each of these three questions, the socialists of the nineteenth
century hesitated, shilly-shallied, contradicted themselves, and
confronted each other. Which socialists?
Broadly speaking, three main currents can be distinguished:
the heirs of the Jacobin and Blanquist tradition of the French
Revolution, others of the German (or more precisely, Prussian) tradition
of the military discipline of the State with a capital âSâ[173]
heirs of the direct democracy of 1793, of the communalist and federalist
idea, and others of Saint-Simonian apoliticism aspiring to substitute
âthe administration of thingsâ for political government.
laboriously striving, not always coherently or successfully, and often
for purely tactical reasons (for they had to make concessions to the two
wings of the working-class movement) to reconcile the two aforementioned
currents, to find a compromise between the authoritarian and libertarian
ideas.
Let us try to briefly summarize the attempts made by these three
currents of socialist thought to resolve the three fundamental problems
of the revolution.
The authoritarians do not have faith in the capacity of the masses to
achieve consciousness on their own and, even when they claim the
contrary, they have a panic fear of the masses. If they are to be
believed, the masses are still degraded by centuries of oppression. They
need to be guided and led. A small elite of leaders must be substituted
for them to teach them revolutionary strategy and lead them to victory.
The libertarians, on the contrary, maintain that the revolution must be
the work of the masses themselves, of their spontaneity, of their free
initiative, of their creative faculties, as unsuspected as they are
formidable. They put people on guard against the chiefs who, in the name
of greater consciousness, aspire to impose themselves on the masses in
order to then despoil them of the fruits of their victory.
As for Marx and Engels, they at times placed the accent on spontaneity
and at others on consciousness. But their synthesis remains a shaky,
uncertain, and contradictory one. It must also be said that the
libertarians do not always escape the same reproach. We find in
Proudhon, juxtaposed to the optimistic exaltation of âthe political
capacity of the working classes,â pessimistic passages in which he casts
doubt on said capacity and joins the authoritarians in their suggestion
that the masses must be led from above.[174] In the same way Mikhail
Bakunin does not always succeed in ridding himself of the â48erâ
conspiratorialism of his youth and, immediately after relying on the
irresistible primal instincts of the masses, he turns around and calls
for the invisible âinfiltrationâ of the latter by conscious leaders
organized in secret societies. From which this strange back and forth:
those he accuses, at times not without basis, of authoritarianism, catch
him in the act of authoritarian Machiavellianism.
The two antagonistic tendencies of the First International mutually
condemned each other, each with a certain amount of reason, for
backstage maneuvers to ensure control of the movement.[175] We had to
wait for Rosa Luxemburg for a more or less viable synthesis to be
proposed between spontaneity and consciousness. But Trotsky compromised
this laboriously obtained equilibrium in order to take the contradiction
to its extreme. At certain moments he is âLuxemburgist.â As can be seen
in his 1905 (1907) and his History of the Russian Revolution (1930), he
has a feeling and an instinct for revolution from below; he places the
accent on the autonomous actions of the masses, but in the end, after
having brilliantly combatted them, he rallies to Leninâs Blanquist
conception of organization[176] and, once in power, he would act in a
more authoritarian fashion than the leader of the school. Finally, in
the harsh combat of his exile, he would shelter behind a now sanctified
Lenin in order to put Stalin on trial, and this identification would
prevent him until his final day from setting free the element of
Luxemburgism within him.
The authoritarians maintain that the popular masses, led by their
chiefs, must substitute for the bourgeois state their own state adorned
with the epithet âproletarian,â and that, in order to ensure the
permanence of the latter, they must push to the extreme the means of
coercion used by the former (centralization, discipline, hierarchy,
police). This schema draws from libertariansâand this for more than a
centuryâcries of fright and horror. What is the use, they ask, of a
revolution that would be satisfied with replacing one repressive
apparatus for another? Uncompromising enemies of the state, of every
form of state, they expect from the proletarian revolution the complete
and definitive abolition of state coercion. They want to substitute the
free federation of associated communes and bottom-up direct democracy
for the old oppressive state.
Marx and Engels sought their way between the extremes of these two
tendencies. They bore the Jacobin imprint, but on one hand contact with
Proudhon around 1844 and the influence of Moses Hess,[177] and on the
other the critique of Hegelianism and the discovery of âalienationâ
rendered them somewhat libertarian. They rejected the authoritarian
statism of the Frenchman Louis Blanc as well as that of the German
Lassalle.[178] They declared themselves supporters of the abrogation of
the state. But only in the long run. The state, âthe governmental
hodgepodge,â must continue in the aftermath of the revolution, but only
for a time. As soon as the material conditions are realized that will
allow for it to be done away with it will âwither away.â And while
waiting for that day, we must strive to âimmediately attenuate as much
as possible its most harmful eff ects.â[179] This immediate perspective
justly worries the libertarians. The survival, even âprovisional,â of
the state says nothing good to them, and they prophetically announce
that once reestablished the Leviathan will obstinately refuse to
resign.[180] The libertariansâ dogged criticism placed Marx and Engels
in an embarrassing position, and there were times when they made so many
concessions to their ideological adversaries that at a certain moment
the debate over the state between socialists seemed to have no point or
to be nothing but a simple quibble over words. Alas, this beautiful
harmony lasted but a morning.
But the Bolshevism of the twentieth century reveals that this was not a
simply verbal dispute. Marx and Engelsâ transitory state becomes,
already in its embryonic form with Lenin and even more with Leninâs
successors, a tentacular monster, which in no uncertain terms proclaims
its refusal to wither away.
Finally, what form of property should replace private capitalism?
The authoritarians have no hesitation in responding. Since their main
defect is a lack of imagination, and since they fear the unknown, they
fall back on forms of administration and management plagiarized from the
past. The state will swoop up in its immense net all of production, all
of exchange, all of finance. âState capitalismâ will survive the social
revolution. The bureaucracy, already gigantic under Napoleon, under the
King of Prussia, and under the Tsar, will no longer be satisfied under a
socialist regime with levying taxes and raising armies and increasing
the police force: it will extend its tentacles over the factories, the
mines, the banks, and the means of transport. The libertarians issue a
cry of fright. This exorbitant expansion of the powers of the state
looks to them to be the grave of liberty. Max Stirner was one of the
first to rise up against the statism of the communist society.[181]
Proudhon shouted no less loudly, and Bakunin followed him: âI detest
communism,â he declared in a speech, âbecause it necessarily arrives at
the centralization of property in the hands of the state, while I ...
want the organization of society and collective and social property from
the bottom up by way of free association, and not from the top down by
means of some form of authority.â[182]
But the anti-authoritarians are not unanimous in formulating their
counter-proposal. Stirner suggests a âfree associationâ of âegoists,â
too philosophical in inspiration and also too unstable. Proudhon, more
concretely, suggests a combinationâwhich in some ways is retrograde,
petit-bourgeois, corresponding to the already outmoded state of
small-scale industryâof small-scale commerce, of artisanal production:
private property must be safe-guarded. Small producers, remaining
independent, must offer each other mutual aid. At the very most he
accepts collective property in a certain number of sectors, which he
agrees have already been conquered by large-scale industry: transport,
mines, etc. But both Stirner and Proudhon, each in his own fashion,
leave themselves open to the blistering critique administered themâa
little unjustly, it must be saidâby Marxism.
Bakunin for his part separates himself deliberately from Proudhon. For a
brief time, he constituted a united front with Marx within the First
International against his former teacher. He rejects post-Proudhonian
individualism. He learns the lessons of industrialization. He calls for
collective property. He presents himself as neither a communist nor a
Mutualist but a collectivist. Production should be managed, both on a
local basis by âthe solidarization of communesâ and on an occupational
basis by groups or associations of workers. Under the influence of the
Bakuninists the Basel Congress of the First International in 1869
decided that in the future society âthe government will be replaced by
councils of workersâ organisations.â[183] Marx and Engels waver and
hedge. In the Communist Manifesto of 1848, inspired by Louis Blanc,
theyâd adopted the easy omni-statist solution. But later, under the
influence of the Paris Commune of 1871 and the pressure of the
anarchists, they would temper this statism and speak of âthe
self-government of the producers.â[184] But these hints at anarchism
would not last long and Marx and Engels would almost immediately return,
in their fight to the death with Bakunin and his disciples, to a more
authoritarian and statist phraseology.
So it is not totally without reason (though not always with total good
faith) that Bakunin accused the Marxists of concentrating all of
industrial and agricultural production in the hands of the state. In
Lenin the statist and authoritarian tendencies, super-imposed on an
anarchism they contradict and annihilate, already exist in germ, and
under Stalin, âquantityâ being transformed into âquality,â they
degenerate into an oppressive state capitalism that Bakunin, in his
occasionally unfair criticism of Marx, seems to have anticipated.
This brief historical reminder is only of interest insofar as it can
assist us in orienting ourselves in the present. The lessons we will
draw from them allow us to understand, in a striking and dramatic way,
that despite many conceptions that seem today to be outmoded, childish,
or proved wrong by experience (for example their âapoliticismâ, on the
essential questions the libertarians were in the right against the
authoritarians. The latter let loose rivers of insults on the former,
calling their program âa jumble of ideas from beyond the grave,â
reactionary utopias, outdated and decadent.[185] But it can be seen
today, as Voline stresses, that it is the authoritarian idea that, far
from belonging to the future, is nothing but a survival from the old,
bourgeois world, worn out and moribund.[186] If there is a utopia, it is
that of so-called state communism, whose bankruptcy is so patent that
its own beneficiaries (concerned above all with safeguarding their
interests as a privileged caste) seek today, laboriously and
stumblingly, the means to amend it and evade it.
The future belongs neither to classical capitalism nor, as the late
Merleau-Ponty tried to persuade us, to a capitalism revised and
corrected by a âneoliberalismâ or by social democratic reformism.[187]
Their dual bankruptcy is no less resounding than that of state
communism. The future still belongs, more than ever belongs, to
communism, but a libertarian communism. As Kropotkin prophetically
announced in 1896, our era âwill bear the effects of the reawakening of
libertarian ideas .... The next revolution will no longer be the Jacobin
revolution.â[188]
The three fundamental problems of the Revolution that we outlined above
can and must finally find their solution. We are no longer in the era of
the stammering, stumbling socialist thinkers of the nineteenth century.
The problems are no longer posed abstractly, but rather concretely.
Today we have at our disposal an abundant harvest of practical
experiences. The technique of Revolution has been immensely enriched.
The libertarian idea is no longer inscribed in the clouds, but emerges
from the facts themselves, from the most profound and authentic
aspirations, even when they are repressed, of the popular masses.
The problem of spontaneity and consciousness is easier to resolve today
than a century ago. If the masses, as a result of the oppression they
suffer, are still a bit behindhand in understanding the bankruptcy of
the capitalist system, if they are still lacking in education and
political lucidity, they have made up a large part of the historic
delay. Everywhere, in the advanced capitalist countries, as well as in
the developing countries and those subject to so-called communism, they
have made a great leap forward. They are much harder to dupe. They know
the full extent of their rights. Their knowledge of the world and their
own destiny has been considerably enriched. If the deficiencies of the
French proletariat prior to 1840, because of its inexperience and small
numbers, gave birth to Blanquism, if that of the Russian proletariat
before 1917 gave birth to Leninism, and that of the new, exhausted
proletariat broken up following the civil war of 1918â1920 and those
newly uprooted from the countryside gave birth to Stalinism, today the
laboring masses have less need to abdicate their power into the hands of
authoritarian and supposedly infallible tutors.
What is more, thanks notably to Rosa Luxemburg, the idea has penetrated
socialist thought that even if the masses are not yet completely mature,
even if the fusion of science and the working class dreamed of by
Lassalle has not yet taken place, the only way to catch up and to remedy
this deficiency is to assist the masses in doing their apprenticeship in
direct democracy from the bottom up.[189] It is in developing,
encouraging, and stimulating their free initiatives; it is in
inculcating in them the sense of their responsibilities instead of
maintaining in them, as state âcommunismâ does (whether in power or in
opposition), the age-old habits of passivity, submission, and feeling of
inferiority passed on to them by a past of oppression. Even if this
apprenticeship is at times difficult, even if the rhythm is at times
slow, even if it cripples society with supplementary costs, even if it
can only be effected at the cost of some âdisorder,â these difficulties,
these delays, these supplementary costs, these growing pains, are
infinitely less harmful than the false order, the false brilliance, the
false âefficiencyâ of state âcommunism,â which obliterate man, kill
popular initiative, and finally dishonor the very idea of
communism.[190]
As concerns the problem of the state, the lessons of the Russian
Revolution are clearly written on the wall. Liquidating the power of the
masses, as was done in the immediate aftermath of the triumph of the
Revolution; reconstructing over the ruins of the former state machine a
new oppressive apparatus even more perfected than the previous one, one
fraudulently baptized âparty of the proletariat,â often by absorbing
into the new regime the âexpertsâ of the defunct regime (still imbued
with their former authority); allowing the construction of a new
privileged class which considers its own survival as an end in itself
and which perpetuates the state that ensures that survival, is not the
model to be followed. What is more, if we take literally the Marxist
theory of the âwithering awayâ of the state, the material conditions
that had provoked and, according to the Marxists, legitimized the
reconstruction of a state apparatus, should allow us today to do without
that cumbersome gendarme so eager to remain in place that is the state.
Industrialization, though developing unevenly in each country, is taking
giant steps throughout the world. The discovery of new sources of energy
with unlimited possibilities is enormously accelerating this evolution.
The totalitarian state engendered by poverty and which justifies itself
by this poverty, daily becomes ever more superfluous. As for the
management of the economy, all the experiments carried out, both in the
quintessential capitalist countries like the United States as well as
those in the countries subjected to state âcommunism,â demonstrate that
the future, at least for large sectors of the economy, no longer belongs
to gigantic production units. Gigantism, which dazzled the late Yankee
captains of industry as well as the communist Lenin, belongs to the
past. Too Big: this is the name of a book on the evils of this plague on
the American economy.[191] For his part Khrushchev, that wily boor,
finally grasped, though late and timidly, the need for industrial
decentralization. It was long believed that the sacrosanct imperatives
of the planned economy demanded state management of the economy. Today
it is realized that top-down planning, bureaucratic planning, is a
frightful source of disorder and waste and, as Merleau-Ponty said, âIt
does not plan.â[192] Charles Bettelheim showed us, in a book that was
too often conformist at the time it was written, that it could only
function efficiently if it was managed from the bottom up and not from
the top down, if it emanated from the lower echelons of production and
was constantly subject to their controlâwhile in the USSR this control
by the masses shines by its absence. Without any doubt, the future
belongs to the autonomous management of enterprises by associations of
workers. What remains to be worked out is the mechanism, delicate to be
sure, of their federation, of the harmonizing of varied interests in a
free order. From this point of view the attempt at a synthesis between
anarchism and statism promoted by the now undeservedly forgotten Belgian
socialist CĂ©sar de Paepe deserves exhumation.[193]
On other levels the evolution of technology and the organization of
labor open the road to a socialism from the bottom up. The most recent
research in the field of the psychology of work leads to the conclusion
that production is only âefficientâ if it does not crush man, if it
associates instead of alienating him, if it appeals to his initiative,
his full cooperation, and if it transmutes his drudgery into joyful
labor, a condition that is not fully realizable either in the industrial
barracks of private capitalism or those of state capitalism. What is
more, the acceleration of the means of transport facilitates enormously
the exercise of direct democracy. For example: thanks to airplanes, in a
few hours the delegates of local branches of American labor unionsâthe
most modern of which, such as those of the automobile workers, are
dispersed across a whole continentâcan be easily assembled.
But if we want to regenerate socialism, turned upside down by the
authoritarians, and put it back on its feet, we must act quickly. In
1896 Kropotkin forcefully said that as long as socialism has an
authoritarian and statist face it will inspire a certain mistrust in the
workers and, because of this, it will see its efforts compromised and
its later development paralyzed.[194] Private capitalism, historically
condemned, only survives today because of the arms race on the one hand
and the bankruptcy of state âcommunismâ on the other. We cannot
ideologically defeat big business and its so-called free enterprise,
under cover of which a handful of monopolies dominate, we cannot see off
nationalism and fascism, ever ready to rise from the ashes, unless we
are capable of producing in practice a concrete substitute for state
pseudo-communism. As for the so-called socialist countries, they will
only escape their current impasse if we assist them, not in liquidating,
but in completely rebuilding their socialism. Khrushchev came crashing
down for having hesitated too long between the past and the future. The
GomuĆkas, Titos, and DubÄeksâdespite their good will, their desire for
de-Stalinization, and their antistatist tendenciesârisk grinding to a
halt, wobbling on the tightrope where they stand in an unstable
equilibrium and, in the long run, will fail if they do not acquire the
audacity and clear-sightedness that will allow them to define the
essential bases for a libertarian communism.[195]
The Revolution of our time will be made from the bottom upâor it will
not be made at all.
[1958, in Jeunesse du Socialisme Libertaire]
Today, we are surrounded by nothing but ruins. The ideologies that were
drummed into us, the political regimes that we were made to submit to or
were held up as models are all falling to pieces. As Edgar Quinet said,
we have lost all our baggage.[196]
Fascism, the ultimate and barbarous form of manâs domination of man,
collapsed a quarter century ago in a bloodbath. And the very people who
clung to it like a life raft, who had called it to the rescue against
the working class, even at the point of foreign bayonets, got skinned in
the adventure and are forced, even though they still secretly prefer it,
to offer their merchandise in a camouflaged form.
The least that can be said is that bourgeois democracy was not
reinvigorated by the crushing defeat of fascism. In any event, it had
made the latterâs bed and showed itself incapable of standing in its
way. It no longer has a doctrine or any faith in itself. It has not
succeeded in restoring its image by capturing for its benefit the fervor
of the French popular masses against Hitlerism. The Resistance lost its
raison dâĂȘtre on the day its enemy disappeared. Its false unity
immediately disintegrated. Its myth was deflated. The politicians of the
postwar period were the most pitiful we have ever endured. They
themselves vaporized the overly credulous confidence of those who, for
want of anything better, turned to London against Vichy.[197] Bourgeois
democracy showed itself to be totally incapable of resolving the
problems and contradictions of the postwar period, contradictions even
more insoluble than they were before the so-called crusade undertaken to
find a solution to them. It was only able to survive at home through a
shameful and hypocritical caricature of fascist methods, and abroad
through colonial wars and even wars of aggression. It has capitulated.
Its succession is open. And the anachronistic Fifth Republic was only
able to put an ineffective band-aid on the wound, one more harmful than
the previous medicines and, what is more, ephemeral.[198]
And then Stalinism, which claimed and which many believed to be made of
sterner stuff and to be historically destined to substitute itself for
the moribund (fascist or âdemocraticïżœïżœïżœ) forms of bourgeois domination,
collapsed in its turn in the scandal of the ignominies revealed in
Khrushchevâs secret report, in the horrors of the Hungarian repression,
and the invasion of Czechoslovakia.[199]
But a world that is collapsing is also a world being reborn. Far from
allowing ourselves to fall into doubt, inaction, confusion or despair,
the time has come for the French working-class movement to start again
from zero, to rethink the very bases of its problems, to remake, as
Quinet said, all of its baggage of ideas.
It was a concern of that order that, in the days following the
Liberation, led me to go back to the French Revolution.[200] If my
intentions were not clear enough and if as a result and through my
fault, they escaped many of my readers and opponents, a British critic
nevertheless understood: âEach generation must re-write history for
itself. If the nineteenth century in Western Europe was the century of
Liberty, the present century is that of Equality. The twin ideals of the
French Revolution, so long separated by the political ascendancy of
nineteenth-century Liberalism, are coming together again. This
rapprochement, dictated by the course of events and the direction of the
historical process itself, makes new demands on all who aspire to
describe and interpret that process. If the twin ideals which Western
civilization owes so largely to the French Revolution are to be again
reconciled in action, they must surely be alsoâand perhaps
firstâreconciled in the description of their evolution by historians.â
And this anonymous critic found it ânatural that when France is passing
through a phase of political and economic reconstruction ... she should
seek guidance from a more many-sided social interpretation of her
history.â [201]
But in my opinion, the necessary synthesis of the ideas of equality and
liberty that this critic recommended in far too vague and confused a
fashion cannot and must not be attempted within the framework and for
the benefit of a bankrupt bourgeois democracy. It can and should be
within the framework of socialist (and communist) thought, which
remains, despite it all, the sole solid value of our epoch. The dual
failures of reformism and Stalinism place before us the urgent duty of
reconciling proletarian democracy and socialism, freedom and Revolution.
And it was precisely the French Revolution that first provided us with
the material for this synthesis. For the first time in history the
antagonistic notions of freedom and coercion, of state power and the
power of the masses confronted each other, clearly if not fully, in its
immense crucible. From this fertile experience, as Kropotkin saw,
emerged the two great currents of modern socialist thought on the basis
of which we can remake our ideological âbaggageâ only if we finally
succeed in finding the correct synthesis.[202]
The return to the French Revolution has, until today, been relatively
fruitless, because modern revolutionaries, all of whom have nevertheless
studied it closely and passionately, have only been concerned with
superficial analogies, with formal points of resemblance with this
situation, or that political group, or some other personality of their
time. It would be quite amusing to recapitulate all these fantasies,
sometimes brilliant, sometimes simply absurd, about which historians of
the Russian Revolution like Boris Souvarine, Erich Wollenberg, and Isaac
Deutscher were right to have reservations.[203] But we would need pages
and pages to do this, and we have better things to do. If, on the other
hand, we abandon the little game of analogies and attempt to get to the
heart of the problems of the French Revolution and analyze its internal
mechanism, we could draw lessons from it which would be extremely useful
for understanding the present.
The first thing to emphasise is that the French Revolution was the first
coherent, wide-scale, historical manifestation of a new type of
democracy. The Great Revolution was not simply, as too many republican
historians believed, the cradle of parliamentary democracy: because at
the same time that it was a bourgeois revolution it was also the embryo
of proletarian revolution, it bore within itself the seed of a new form
of revolutionary power whose features would become more distinct over
the course of the revolutions of the late nineteenth and the twentieth
centuries. The thread that runs from the Commune of 1793 to that of
1871, and from that to the soviets of 1905 and 1917, is clear.
I would here like to limit myself to briefly summarizing some of the
general features of the âdirect democracyâ of 1793. If we step into the
âsections,â the popular societies of the Year II,[204] we have the
feeling of a reinvigorating immersion in democracy. The periodic
self-purging of each âpopular society,â each candidate mounting the
podium to offer him or herself to the scrutiny of all; the concern to
ensure the most perfect possible expression of the popular will, to
prevent its stifling by the golden-tongued or by idlers; permitting the
working people to lay down their tools without any financial sacrifice
and so to fully participate in public life; ensuring permanent control
of the representatives by the represented; and the placing of the two
sexes on a level of complete equality in deliberations.[205] ... These
are some of the features of a democracy truly propelled from the bottom
up.
The General Council of the Commune of 1793, at least until the
decapitation of its magistrates by the bourgeois central power, also
offers us a remarkable example of direct democracy. The members of the
Council were the delegates of their respective sections, constantly in
contact with them and under the control of those who gave them their
mandates, always up to date on the will of the base through the
admission of popular delegations to the sittings of the Council. At the
Commune there was no such thing as the âseparation of powersâ between
the executive and the legislative. The members of the Council were both
administrators and legislators. These modest sans-culottes did not
become professional politicians; they remained the men of their
professions or trades, still exercising them to the extent that their
functions on the Commune allowed this, and ready to exercise them again
at the end of their mandates.[206]
But of all these features the most admirable one is doubtless the
maturity of a direct democracy experimented with for the first time in a
relatively backward country, barely out of the night of feudalism and
absolutism, still plunged in illiteracy and age-old habits of
submission. No âanarchy,â no confusion in this unprecedented and
improvised management by the people. To convince oneself of this it is
enough to leaf through the minutes of the popular societies, of the
sittings of the general council of the Commune. There one can see the
masses, as if aware of their natural tendency to indiscipline, animated
by an ever present concern for self-discipline. They organize their
deliberations and they impose order on those who might be tempted to
provoke disorder. Even though in 1793 their experience of public life
was relatively recent, even though most of the sans-culottes, guided it
is true by educated petit-bourgeois, did not yet know how to read or
write, they already demonstrated a capacity for self-management that
even today the bourgeoisie, anxious to preserve its monopoly over public
affairs, persists against all the evidence in denying. And certain
revolutionary theoreticians, full of a sense of intellectual
superiority, sometimes also tend to underestimate this capacity of the
masses for self-government.
But at the same time the difficulties and contradictions of
self-management made their appearance. The lack of education and the
relative backwardness of their political consciousness were obstacles to
the massesâ full participation in public life. Not all of the people
have a sense of their true interests. While some demonstrated
extraordinary lucidity for the period, others allowed themselves to be
led astray. The revolutionary bourgeoisie took advantage of the prestige
it earned in its uncompromising struggle against the remnants of the
ancien régime to inculcate in the sans-culottes a seductive but false
ideology which in fact went against their aspirations for full equality.
If we flick through the voluminous collection of reports from the secret
agents of the Ministry of the Interior, we can see that informers
reported comments made on the streets by men of the people, the contents
of which are sometimes revolutionary, sometimes
counter-revolutionary.[207] And these remarks are all lumped together
and considered to be the expressions of the vox populi without any
attempt to discriminate among them or to analyze their obvious
contradictions.
The relative confusion of the people, notably of manual workers deprived
of education, left the field open to better educated or more conscious
minorities. This was how the Maison Commune Section, made up largely of
masons, a small core group âgot it to do whatever they wanted.â[208] In
many popular societies, despite all the care taken and the concern to
ensure the most perfect functioning of democracy, factions led the dance
in one direction or the other, and they sometimes even opposed each
other.
The great lesson of 1793 is not just that direct democracy is viable, it
is also that the vanguard of a society, when it is still a minority in
relation to the mass of the country that it carries along with it,
cannot avoid, in that life-or-death battle that is a revolution,
imposing its will on the majority, first and preferentially through
persuasion, and, if persuasion fails, by force.
It was in the experience of the French Revolution that Marx and Engels
found the source for their famous notion of the âdictatorshipâ of the
proletariat. Unfortunately, it was never truly elaborated by its
authors. Without claiming, like Kautsky in the period when he was a
reformist, that in their work it is nothing but a Wörtchen, a little
word occasionally used but of no importance,[209] one is forced to say
that they only ever used it too briefly and too vaguely in their
writings. And when in particular they discover it in the French
Revolution the terms they employ are far from clear and are
debatable.[210] In fact, the revolutionaries of the Year II, convinced
though they were of the need for exceptional measures, for having
recourse to force, had a horror of using the word dictatorship. The
Commune of 1793, like its heir of 1871, wanted to guide and not âimpose
its supremacy.â Marat himself, the sole revolutionary of his time who
called for a dictatorship, was forced to resort to careful language: he
asked for a guide and not a master. But even in this veiled form he
scandalized his brothers in arms and earned their loud protests.
Let it be understood: democracy had just issued its first cry. The
tyrant had just been overthrown and the Bastille razed. The word
âdictatorshipâ had a bad ring to it. It evoked the idea of a descent
once again into tyranny, into personal power. In fact, for the men of
the eighteenth century, nourished on memories of antiquity, dictatorship
had a precise and formidable meaning. They recalledâand the Encyclopedia
was there to remind themâthat the Romans, âhaving driven out their kings
saw themselves obliged, in difficult times, to temporarily create a
dictator enjoying greater power than any enjoyed by the ancient kings.â
They recalled that later, the institution having degenerated, Sulla and
Caesar proclaimed themselves perpetual dictators and exercised absolute
sovereignty, in the latter case going as far as being suspected of
having monarchist aims. They did not want either a new monarch or a new
Caesar.
The men of 1793 had an even clearer memory of England. How could they
forget that a century earlier Oliver Cromwell had overthrown an absolute
monarch, usurped popular power, established a dictatorship, and even
attempted to have himself crowned king? They feared a new Cromwell like
the plague, and this was one of their complaints against Robespierre on
the eve of Thermidor.[211]
Finally, the rank-and-file sans-culottes, the men and women of the
popular societies, instinctively distrusted the word dictatorship, for
it would have represented only a portion of revolutionary reality: they
first of all wanted to convince, to open to everyone the doors to the
nascent democracy, and they only resorted to force when those they
wanted to convince and admit into democracy answered them with lead.
Perhaps they intuited that it is always an error to borrow words from
the enemyâs vocabulary. âThe sovereignty of the people,â as Henri de
Saint-Simon pointed out, is one of those unfortunate borrowings. From
the day they administer themselves the people are the sovereigns of no
one. âThe Despotism of libertyâ (a phrase the men of â93 sometimes used
in preference to âdictatorshipâ for it has a more collective resonance)
and âdictatorship of the proletariatâ are no less antonymic. The form of
coercion that the proletarian vanguard finds itself forced to exercise
against counter-revolutionaries is of so fundamentally different a
nature from the past forms of oppression, and it is compensated for by
so advanced a degree of democracy for the formerly oppressed, that the
word dictatorship clashes with that of proletariat.
Such was the opinion of the libertarian collectivists like Bakunin, who
were of course aware that the possessing classes would not voluntarily
renounce their privileges and that they must be forced to do so, and who
were determined to âorganize a revolutionary force capable of triumphing
over reactionâ; but at the same time they categorically rejected any
slogan of âso-called revolutionary dictatorship, even as a revolutionary
transition,â even if it is ârevolutionary in the Jacobin manner.â[212]
As for reformists, they not only reject the words âdictatorship of the
proletariat,â but also what we have just seen defined as valid, namely
the idea of revolutionary constraint or coercion. And so, for too long,
Marxist revolutionaries have not dared to express any reservations
concerning the words used, for fear of being suspected of âopportunismâ
regarding their essence.[213]
The inappropriateness of the terms appears still more clearly if we go
back to the sources. The Babouvists (followers of Babeuf) were the first
to speak of revolutionary âdictatorship.â[214] Although they had the
merit of drawing a clear lesson from the bourgeoisieâs theft of the
revolution, we know that they appeared too late, at a moment when the
masses had surrendered. A minuscule and isolated minority, they doubted
the peopleâs capacity to lead themselves, at least in the near term, and
they called for a dictatorship, either the dictatorship of one man or
that of âhands wisely and resolutely revolutionary.â[215]
The German communist Weitling and the French revolutionary Blanqui
borrowed this concept of dictatorship from the Babouvists.[216]
Incapable of joining up with a mass movement that was still embryonic,
with a proletariat still too ignorant and demoralized to govern itself,
they believed that small, bold minorities could seize power by surprise
and establish socialism from above by means of the most rigorous
dictatorial centralization, while waiting for the people to be mature
enough to share power with their leaders. While the idealist Weitling
envisaged a personal dictatorship, that of âa new messiah,â Blanqui,
more realistic, closer to the nascent working-class movement, spoke of a
âParisian dictatorship,â that is, a dictatorship of the Parisian
proletariat, though in his mind the proletariat was only capable of
exercising this âdictatorshipâ in the person of one man, through the
intermediary of its educated elite, of Blanqui and his secret
society.[217]
Marx and Engels, though opposed to the Blanquistsâ minoritarian and
voluntarist concepts, in 1850 made them the concession of adopting the
famous formula,[218] going as far as identifying communism and
Blanquism.[219] There is no doubt that in the minds of the founders of
scientific socialism, revolutionary coercion seemed to be exercised by
the working class and not, as in the case of the Blanquists, by a
vanguard detached from the class.[220] But they did not differentiate
such an interpretation of the âdictatorship of the proletariatâ clearly
enough from that of the Blanquists. Later Lenin, claiming to adhere both
to Jacobinism and Marxism, would invent the concept of the dictatorship
of one party substituting itself for the working class and acting in its
name.[221] And his disciples in the Urals, taking his logic to its
ultimate conclusion, frankly proclaimed, without being disavowed, that
the dictatorship of the proletariat would be a dictatorship over the
proletariat.[222]
From 1921 the German anarchist Rudolf Rocker, noting the âbankruptcy of
state âcommunismââ in Russia would maintain that the dictatorship of one
class in and of itself is âabsolutely unthinkable.â and that in reality
it is a matter of the dictatorship of one party claiming to speak in the
name of a class. And he would forcefully rise up against the illusion of
transforming the state, an organ of oppression, into an organ for the
liberation of the oppressed, baptized âdictatorshipâ of the proletariat.
âThe state,â he wrote, âcan only be what it is, the defender of
privilege and the exploitation of the masses, the creator of new classes
and monopolies. Whoever does not know the role of the state does not
grasp the essence of the current social order and is incapable of
showing humanity the new horizons of its evolution.â[223]
The dual experiences of the French and Russian Revolutions teach us that
we are touching upon the central point of a mechanism at the end of
which direct democracy, peopleâs self-management, gradually mutates,
through the establishing of the revolutionary âdictatorship,â into the
reconstitution of an apparatus for the oppression of the people. Of
course, the process was not exactly identical in the two revolutions.
The first was that of an essentially bourgeois revolution, though
already containing the embryo of proletarian revolution. The second was
an essentially proletarian revolution, though having at the same time to
fulfill the tasks of the bourgeois revolution. In the first case it was
not the âdictatorshipâ from below, which had however already made an
appearance, it was the dictatorship from above, that of the bourgeois
revolutionary government, which provided the starting point for a new
oppressive apparatus. In the second case it was from the âdictatorship
from below,â that of the proletariat in arms, for whom the party almost
immediately substituted itself, that the oppressive apparatus was
finally reconstituted. But in the two cases, despite this important
difference, an analogy can be seen: the concentration of power, the
âdictatorship,â is presented as the product of necessity.[224] The
revolution is in danger from both within and without. The reconstituting
of the oppressive apparatus is invoked as indispensable for the crushing
of counter-revolution.
Was the ânecessityââthe counter-revolutionary dangerâreally the only
reason for this abrupt turnabout? This is what most left-wing historians
claim. Georges Lefebvre assures us that the Revolution could only be
saved if the people were âorganized and led by bourgeois cadres,â It was
necessary to bring together all the nationâs forces for the benefit of
the army. This could only occur by means of a strong and centralized
government. Dictatorship from below could not succeed in this, since
apart from the fact that it lacked the needed abilities, it could not
forego an overall plan and a center of execution.[225] Albert Soboul
considers that the direct democracy of the sans-culottes was, due to its
âweakness,â impracticable in the crisis through which the republic was
passing.[226] Before them, Georges Guy-Grand, minimizing the political
capacity of the popular vanguard, maintained that âthe people of Paris
did not know what to do with their riots. The riots were valid means of
destroying, and destruction must sometimes be done. But demolishing
Bastilles, massacring prisoners, aiming cannons at the Convention are
not enough to make a country live. When cadres needed to be
reconstituted, when industries and the government had to be made to
function, there was no choice but to rely on the sole elements
available, which were bourgeois.â[227]
But it is not certain that the Revolution could only be saved by these
techniques and from above. A relatively effective collaboration had been
established at the base between the administration of staple goods and
the popular societies, between the government and the revolutionary
committees. The reinforcement of central power stifled and killed the
initiative from below that had been the heart of the Revolution.
Bourgeois ability was substituted for popular enthusiasm. The Revolution
lost its essential strength, its internal dynamic.
What is more, we must be wary of those who invoke the pretext of
âcompetenceâ to legitimize the exclusive and abusive use of bourgeois
expertise during a revolutionary period. First, because men of the
people are less ignorant, less incompetent than some people claim in
order to make their case. Second, because the plebeians of 1793, when
they were lacking in technical abilities, overcame that deficiency by
their sense of democracy and their higher awareness of their obligations
to the revolution. Finally, because the bourgeois technicians, reputed
to be indispensable and irreplaceable, too often profited by their
situation, which was considered impregnable, to intrigue against the
people and to even develop suspicious ties with counter-revolutionaries.
People like Carnot, Cambon, Lindet, and BarĂšre were the agents of the
great bourgeoisie and the sworn enemies of the sans-culottes. During a
revolution a man lacking in competency but devoted body and soul to the
peopleâs cause, when he assumes civil or military responsibilities is
worth more than a competent individual ready to betray.
During the six months or so of the flourishing of direct democracy the
people demonstrated their creative genius; they revealed, though in a
still embryonic form, that there exist other revolutionary techniques
than those of the bourgeoisie, than one that is topdown. Certainly it is
the latter that prevailed at the time, for the bourgeoisie had a
maturity and an experience that conferred on it an enormous advantage
over the people. But Year II of the Republic, if one knows how to
decipher its message, foretells that the fertile potential of
revolutionary techniques from below will one day win out in the
proletarian revolution over the techniques inherited from the Jacobin
bourgeoisie. Albert Mathiez, accustomed, as Georges Lefebvre admits, to
âconsidering the Revolution from above.â[228] felt that he needed to
draw an enthusiastic parallel between the âharshâ dictatorship of Public
Safety of 1793 and that of 1920 in Russia.[229]
But even during the period when Mathiez was invoking the revolutionary
bourgeois dictatorship of 1793 in an attempt to legitimize Leninâs
Jacobin dictatorship, the German anarchist Rudolf Rocker supported the
contrary thesis: âReferring to the French Revolution to justify the
tactics of the Bolsheviks in Russia,â he said, demonstrates âa total
misunderstanding of historical facts .... Historical experience
demonstrates the exact opposite: at every decisive moment of the French
Revolution the true initiative in action rose directly from the people.
The secret of the Revolution resides in this creative activity of the
masses.â On the other hand, it was when Robespierre deprived the popular
movement of its autonomy and made it submit to central power, when he
persecuted the authentically revolutionary tendencies and crushed the
Left opposition, that the âebbing of the Revolution, preface to 9
Thermidor and, later, to the Napoleonic dictatorship of the sword.â
began.[230] Rocker concluded with bitterness in 1921: âIn Russia they
are repeating today what occurred in France in March 1794.â
Because the Great Revolution was not only bourgeois but was also
accompanied by an embryonic proletarian revolution, one sees in it the
germ of a phenomenon that will only assume its full scope in the
degeneration of the Russian Revolution. Already, in 1793, democracy from
below gave birth to a caste of parvenus differentiating themselves from
the masses and aspiring to commandeer the popular revolution to their
profit. In the ambivalent mentality of these plebeians, revolutionary
faith and material appetites were closely intertwined. As JaurĂšs phrased
it, the Revolution looked to them to be âboth an ideal and a
career.â[231] They served the bourgeois revolution at the same time that
they used it. Robespierre and Saint-Just, like Lenin in his time,
denounced the appetite of this nascent and already invasive bureaucracy.
A certain number of them entered into open conflict with the Committee
of Public Safety. If their attachment to bourgeois law and property
flowed from their greed, they nevertheless had individual interests to
defend against the revolutionary bourgeoisie. The latter, in fact, only
wanted to leave them as small a piece of the pie as possible, first
because that enormous budget-devouring plebs was expensive; second,
because the bourgeoisie distrusted its origins among and its links to
the people and, above all, the support from the working-class quarters
which it had obtained demagogically with a view to occupying all posts;
and finally because the bourgeoisie intended to keep the control of the
revolutionary government in the hands of its tried and tested experts.
The struggle for power that opposed the plebeians to the experts was a
sharp one and, in the end, it was settled by the guillotine. Certain
important sectors such as the Ministry of War, the secret funds,[232]
and the war industries were the stakes in this rivalry. The battle over
the war industry was particularly revealing, for it was here that two
modes of economic management confronted each other: free enterprise and
what is today called state capitalism. If the plebeians had achieved
their goals and if the war industry had been nationalized as they
demanded, a portion of the profits coveted and finally seized by the
revolutionary bourgeoisie would have gone into their pockets.
Trotsky, incompletely informed, is not totally correct when he asserts
that Stalinism âhad no prehistory,â that the French Revolution knew
nothing that resembled the Soviet bureaucracy, derived from a single
revolutionary party and having its roots in the collective ownership of
the means of production.[233] I think, on the contrary, that the
HĂ©bertist plebeians were, in more ways than one, a foreshadowing of the
Russian bureaucrats of the Stalinist era.
In the same way, once the generals of the ancien régime, traitors to the
revolution, were eliminated, there arose alongside the devoted but
incompetent sans-culotte generals a new type of young chiefs risen from
the ranks, capable but consumed by ambition and who would later be the
instruments of reaction and military dictatorship. To a certain extent,
these future Marshals of the Empire were the prefiguration of Soviet
marshals.
The French Revolution had hardly ended before âtheoreticiansâ plunged
into the analysis of its mechanisms and the search for its lessons with
passionate ardor and an often remarkable lucidity. Their attention was
concentrated essentially on two great problems: that of permanent
revolution and that of the state. What they discovered first was that
the Great Revolution, because it had been only bourgeois, had betrayed
popular aspirations and had to be continued until the complete
liberation of man. What they all deduced from this was socialism.[234]
Some of them also discovered that within the Revolution a new type of
people power, oriented from the bottom up, had made its appearance on
the historical stage and that it had finally been supplanted by a
powerfully reconstituted top-down oppressive apparatus. And they
wondered with fright how the people could avoid seeing their revolution
commandeered in the future. From this they deduced anarchism.
The first person who saw this, in 1794, was the Enragé Varlet.[235] In a
short pamphlet written right after Thermidor he wrote this prophetic
sentence: âFor any reasoning being, government and revolution are
incompatible.â And he accused the ârevolutionary governmentâ of having,
in the name of public safety, established a dictatorship.[236] âThis is
the conclusion,â wrote two historians of anarchism, âthat the first of
the EnragĂ©s drew from 1793, and that conclusion is anarchist.â[237]
Varletâs pamphlet contained a profound idea: a revolution led by the
masses and a strong authority (against the masses) are two incompatible
things.
The Babouvists drew this conclusion in their turn. âThe rulers,â wrote
Babeuf, âonly make revolutions in order to continue governing. We want
to make one to eternally ensure the peopleâs happiness through real
democracy.â And Buonarotti, his disciple, foreseeing the commandeering
of future revolutions by new elites added, âIf there was formed within
the state a class exclusively knowledgeable about the principles of the
social art, laws, and administration, it would soon discover the secret
of creating distinctions and privileges for itself.â[238] Buonarotti
deduced from this that only the radical suppression of social
inequalities, that only communism would allow society to be rid of the
scourge of the state: âA people without property and without the vices
and crimes it engenders would not feel the need for the great number of
laws under which the civilized societies of Europe groan.â[239]
But the Babouvists were not able to draw all the consequences of this
discovery. Isolated from the masses, they contradicted themselves, as we
saw, by calling for the dictatorship of one man or of a âwiseâ elite,
which would later lead Proudhon to write that âthe negation of
government, which shone briefly through the Enragés and the Hebertists
before being snuffed out, would have issued from Babeufâs doctrines, if
Babeuf had been able to think through the logical consequences of his
own premise.â[240]
It is Proudhon who, in 1851, had the merit of having drawn from the
French Revolution a truly profound analysis of the problem of the state.
The author of The General Idea of Revolution in the Nineteenth Century
started with a critique of bourgeois and parliamentary democracy, of
democracy from above, and of democracy by decree.[241] He denounced its
fraudulent nature. He attacked Robespierre, an open enemy of direct
democracy. He stressed the failings of the democratic constitution of
1793, a departure point, to be sure, but a bastard compromise between
bourgeois democracy and direct democracy, which promised the people
everything and gave them nothing and which, in any case, was no sooner
promulgated than its implementation was indefinitely put off.
Getting to the heart of the problem, Proudhon declared, after Varlet,
that âin proclaiming freedom of opinion, equality before the law, the
sovereignty of the people, and the subordination of authority to the
country, the Revolution made two incompatible things of society and the
government.â He affirms âthe absolute incompatibility of authority with
freedom.â And he pronounced a fiery condemnation of the state: âNo
authority, no government, not even a peopleâs government: the Revolution
resides in this .... The government of the people will always be the
swindling of the people .... If the Revolution allows government [the
state] to survive somewhere, it will return everywhere.â And he attacks
the boldest of thinkers, the âauthoritarianâ socialists who, while
admitting the misdeeds of the state âstill said that while government is
doubtless a scourge ... it was still a necessary evil. âThis is why,â he
adds, âthe most emancipatory revolutions have always ended in an act of
faith and submission to authority, why all revolutions have only served
to reconstitute tyranny.â âThe people gave themselves a tyrant instead
of a protector. Everywhere and at all times the government, however
popular it was at its origin, after having shown itself to be liberal
for a certain time, gradually became exceptional and exclusive.â
He harshly condemned the centralization carried out through the decree
of December 4, 1793.[242] This centralization was understandable under
the former monarchy, but âunder the pretext of a One and Indivisible
Republic, to remove from the people the right to dispose of their
forces, to call those who speak in favor of liberty and local
sovereignty âfederalistsâ who are to be proscribed, means putting the
lie to the true spirit of the French Revolution, to its most authentic
tendencies. The system of centralization that prevailed in â93 was
nothing but a transformed feudalism. Napoleon, who put the final touches
to it, testified to this.â Later, Bakunin, a disciple of Proudhon, would
echo him: âA strange thing, that great revolution which, for the first
time in history, proclaimed the freedom, not only of the citizen, but of
man; but in making itself the heir of the monarchy it killed, it at the
same time revived the negation of all freedom: the centralization and
omnipotence of the state.â[243]
But Proudhonâs thought goes farther and deeper. He fears that the
exercise of direct democracy, that the most ingenious formulas aimed at
promoting an authentic government of the people, by the peopleâthe
fusing of the legislative and executive powers, the election and
revocability of functionaries recruited by the people from within their
number, and permanent popular controlâthat this system, which may be
âirreproachableâ in theory, âin practice encounters an insurmountable
difficulty.â In fact, even in this optimal hypothesis the risk remains
of the incompatibility between society and authority. âIf the entire
people, as sovereigns, becomes the government, one seeks in vain where
the governed would be .... If the people, organized as the authority,
has nothing above them, I ask who is below?â There is no middle way, one
must âeither work or rule.â âThe people passing en masse over to the
state, the state no longer has the least reason to exist, since there no
longer exists a people: the result of the governmental equation is
zero.â
How to escape this contradiction, this âvicious circleâ? Proudhon
answers that the government must be dissolved in the economic
organization. âThe governmental institution ... has its raison dâĂȘtre in
economic anarchy. Since the Revolution puts an end to this anarchy and
organizes the industrial forces, there is no longer a pretext for
political centralization.â
Bakunin in turn stresses that since their thought was ânourishedâ by a
certain theory, which âwas nothing but the Jacobin political system more
or less modified for the use of revolutionary socialists, the socialist
workers of France never wanted to understand [that] when, in the name of
the Revolution, you want to build a state, even if only a transitory
state, it is a reactionary step and you are working for despotism.â[244]
To a certain extent the disagreement between Marxists and anarchists
flows from the fact that the former do not always view the French
Revolution in the same way as the latter. Deutscher saw that within
Bolshevism there were two spirits, the Marxist and the Jacobin, a
conflict that would never be resolved, neither in Lenin nor in
Trotsky.[245] As we will see, there can be found within Bolshevism
holdovers from Jacobinism more accentuated than in the original Marxism.
But I think that Marxism itself never completely overcame an analogous
contradiction. There is within it a libertarian frame of mind as well as
a Jacobin and authoritarian frame of mind.
In my opinion, the origin of this duality can mainly be found in an at
times correct, but also at times erroneous appreciation of the real
content of the French Revolution. The Marxists see that the latter
betrayed popular aspirations because it was, objectively and in its
immediate results, a bourgeois revolution. But at the same time they are
blinded by an abusive application of the materialist concept of history,
which sometimes leads them to consider it only from the point of view
and within the limits of the bourgeois revolution. Of course they are
right to stress those relatively and inarguably progressive features of
the bourgeois revolution, but there are moments when they present these
features, which even anarchists like Bakunin and Kropotkin, if not
Proudhon, exalted in a unilateral fashion, overestimating and idealizing
them.
Because he was a Menshevik, Boris Nicolaevsky exaggeratedly stresses
this tendency of Marxism. But there is something true about his
analysis. And the German ultra-leftist of 1848, Gottschalk, was not
completely wrong in balking at the Marxist perspective of âescaping the
hell of the Middle Agesâ only to âvoluntarily leap into the purgatoryâ
of capitalism.[246] What Isaac Deutscher says of the Russian Marxists
prior to 1917âfor, paradoxically, there was much âMenshevismâ in these
âBolsheviksââis also, I think, valid to a certain extent for the
founders of Marxism: âSince they saw in capitalism an indispensable
halfway house on the road from feudalism to socialism, they stressed the
advantages of that halfway house, its progressive features, its
civilizing influence, its attractive atmosphere and so on.â[247]
If we examine the many passages in Marx and Engels concerning the French
Revolution it has to be said that sometimes they see and sometimes they
lose sight of its character as a âpermanent revolution.â To be sure,
they do see the revolution from below, but only occasionally. To give an
example, Marx does not hesitate to present the humble supporters in the
working-class quarters of Jacques Roux and Varlet as the âmain
representativesâ of the revolutionary movement, but Engels nevertheless
writes that to the âproletariatâ of 1793 âin its incapacity to help
itself, help could, at best, be brought in from without or down from
above.â[248]
And so we can already understand better what Deutscher means by Jacobin
spirit, namely the tradition of bourgeois revolution and dictatorship
from above of 1793, somewhat idealized and insufficiently differentiated
from compulsion from below. And by extension, we can understand the
tradition of Babouvist and Blanquist conspiratorialism which borrows the
dictatorial and minoritarian techniques of the bourgeois revolution in
order to put them at the service of a new revolution.
One can see why the anarchists discern in the socialism and communism of
the nineteenth century a certain âJacobin,â âauthoritarian,â
âgovernmentalistâ tendency; a propensity towards the âcult of state
disciplineâ inherited from Robespierre and the Jacobins; that they
define a âbourgeois frame of mind,â âa political legacy of bourgeois
revolutionismâ to which they oppose the affirmation that the âsocial
revolutions of our day have nothing or almost nothing to imitate in the
revolutionary methods of the Jacobins of 1793.â[249]
Marx and Engels deserve this reproach far less than other authoritarian
and statist socialist currents of the nineteenth century. But they had
some difficulty in freeing themselves of the Jacobin tradition. For
example, they were slow in ridding themselves of the Jacobin myth of the
ârigorous centralization offered as a model by the France of 1793.â They
finally rejected it, under the pressure of the anarchists, but not
before having stumbled, hesitated, and modified their analysis and, even
after all these corrective measures, they still went down the wrong
road.[250] This wavering would allow Lenin to forget the anti-centralist
passages in their writingsânotably a clarification by Engels in
1885[251]âand to retain only âthe facts cited by Engels concerning the
centralized French Republic from 1792 to 1799,â and to baptize Marx a
âcentralist.â[252]
Indeed, the Jacobin hold was much stronger on the Russian Bolsheviks
than it was on the founders of Marxism. And in large part this deviation
has its origin in an occasionally incorrect and one-sided interpretation
of the French Revolution. Lenin, it is true, clearly saw its permanent
revolution aspects. He demonstrated that the popular movement, which he
incorrectly called a âbourgeois democratic revolution,â was far from
reaching its objectives in 1794, and that it would only succeed in doing
so in 1871.[253] If total victory was not won at the end of the
eighteenth century, it was because âthe material bases for socialismâ
were still lacking.[254] The bourgeois regime is only progressive in
relation to the autocracy that precedes it, as the final form of
domination and âthe most fitting arena for the struggle of the
proletariat against the bourgeoisie.â[255] Only the proletariat is
capable of pushing the revolution to its final end, âfor it goes much
further than the democratic revolution.â[256]
But Lenin long rejected the concept of permanent revolution and
maintained that the Russian proletariat, after the conquest of power,
had to voluntarily limit itself to the bourgeois democratic regime. This
is why he often tends to overestimate the heritage of the French
Revolution, affirming that it will remain âperhaps for all time the
model for certain revolutionary methods,â and that the historians of the
proletariat should see in Jacobinism âone of the culminating points that
the oppressed class reached in the struggle for its emancipation, [one
of the] best examples of democratic revolution.â[257] This is why he
idealized Danton[258] and did not hesitate to proclaim himself
âJacobin.â[259] This is why, with much exaggeration, he attributes to
bourgeois revolutionaries radical measures against the capitalists and
claimed to act, like them, with âJacobin inflexibility.â[260]
Leninâs Jacobin attitudes brought him a sharp reply from Trotsky in
1904. For the latter, who had not yet become a Bolshevik, Jacobinism âis
the maximum degree of radicalism that bourgeois society can provide.â
Modern revolutionaries must protect themselves from Jacobinism as much
as from reformism. Jacobinism and proletarian socialism are âtwo molds,
two doctrines, two tactics, two psychologies separated by an abyss.â If
both are intransigent, their intransigence is qualitatively different.
The attempt to introduce Jacobin methods into the proletarian
revolutions of the twentieth century is nothing but opportunism. Just
like reformism, it is the expression of âa tendency to tie the
proletariat to an ideology, a tactic, and finally a psychology foreign
and hostile to its class interests.â[261]
In conclusion, the French Revolution was the source of two great
currents of socialist thought which, across the twentieth century, have
lasted until today: an authoritarian Jacobin current and a libertarian
current. One, of a âbourgeois disposition,â oriented from the top down,
is above all concerned with revolutionary effectiveness and claims to be
taking account of ânecessities.â The other, of an essentially
proletarian spirit, is oriented from the bottom up, and places the
safeguarding of freedom to the fore. Between these two currents numerous
more or less shaky compromises have already been elaborated.
Bakuninâs anarchist collectivism attempted to reconcile Proudhon and
Marx. Within the First International, Marxism sought a middle way
between Blanqui and Bakunin. The Commune of 1871 was an empirical
synthesis of Jacobinism and federalism. Lenin himself, in State and
Revolution, was tom between anarchism and state âcommunism,â between
mass spontaneity and Jacobin iron discipline. Yet the real synthesis of
these two currents is still to be effected. As H.E. Kaminski wrote, it
is not only necessary, it is inevitable: âHistory itself constructs its
compromises.â[262] The degeneration of the Russian Revolution and the
collapse and historical bankruptcy of Stalinism places it more than ever
on the agenda. It alone will allow us to remake our âbaggage of ideasâ
and to forever prevent our revolutions being commandeered by new
Jacobins utilizing tanks, in comparison with which the guillotine of
1793 will look like a toy.
[1956, in Jeunesse du Socialisme Libertaire]
Two books that appeared simultaneously, those of Titoâs prisoner Milovan
Djilas and Michel Collinet,[263] have led us to rethink the ideological
foundations of Bolshevism. Even though produced by two men of different
temperaments and origins and using quite divergent methods, they reach
more or less the same conclusions and present more or less the same
qualities, as well as the same defects.
One of their merits is to demonstrate that the Blanquist concept of the
party formulated by Lenin from 1901 contained at least in germ the
totalitarian communism of the Stalinist era. Djilas and Collinet stress
that the ideological monopoly of the leadership of the party, in this
case Lenin himself, claiming to embody the objective aspirations of
society,[264] was in fact an idealist conception of history that would
later result in the total monopolization of the bureaucratic apparatus
over that society.[265]
Where the two writers diverge is on the historical excuse of
ânecessity.â Djilas, still incompletely freed of the authoritarian
concepts he was brought up on, believes that the success of the
revolution, which had to defend its very existence and the indispensable
industrialization of the USSR, required the establishment of a tyranny.
Collinet, on the contrary, condemns Lenin for having made a virtue of
necessity, and does not think totalitarian dictatorship necessarily
flowed from the tragic circumstances of the Civil War.[266]
While establishing a direct connection between Leninism and Stalinism,
the two authors stress, correctly, that under no circumstances can the
two regimes be confused and that differences of an important nature
distinguish them, and not simple ânuances,â as Collinet once lets slip.
Forms that were still revolutionary during Leninâs time were transformed
into reactionary ones under Stalin.
Collinet and Djilas, in the most solid part of their work, provide both
brilliant and implacable descriptions of the privileged ânew class,â of
the feudal bureaucracy that seized power in the USSR. For Collinet
todayâs Russian society realizes âthe most perfect absorption of society
by the state that history has ever seen,â and for Djilas modern history
has never recorded a regime oppressing the masses in so brutal,
inhumane, and illegal a fashion. The methods it employed constitute âone
of the most shameful pages of human history.â And in a flight of
inspiration, he opposes the idealism, devotion, and spirit of sacrifice
of communism of its early days to the intolerance, corruption,
stagnation, and intellectual decadence of contemporary communism. The
analysis of the ânew class,â of the way it exploits the working class
and its poor economic management, is more acute in Djilas than it is in
Collinet: Djilasâand this is the main interest of his bookâis a witness
who lived the evil from within.
The two authors are in agreement in denouncing the thirst for and
obsession with power of the communist oligarchs, as well as in
stigmatizing the transformation of Marxism into a dogmatism, into an
essentially sterile and conservative scholasticism.
Both Collinet and Djilas reproach Trotsky, not without reason and almost
in the same terms, for having shown himself incapable, despite the great
merit of his indictment of Stalinism, of defining sociologically and
fully exposing the meaning of contemporary communism. Why? Because he
lacked perspective, according to Djilas; because he persisted until his
death in not questioning Leninist ideas of organization according to
Collinet. There is probably something of the truth in both of these
explanations.
But to my mind both books are marred by a certain number of errors I
would like to point out. In the first place, they both show a total lack
of understanding of the concept of âpermanent revolution.â Collinet
makes the mistake of considering Marxâs famous text of March 1850 an
unimportant accident in the history of Marxist thought, an ephemeral
âBlanquistâ crisis from which the author quickly recovered.[267] He and
Djilas draw erroneous conclusions from a correct observation, which is
that the âpermanent revolutionâ is more acutely manifested in backward
countries where it is easier to directly leap over the capitalist stage
from feudalism to socialism. But they are wrong in concluding that
revolutionary Marxism is only applicable to underdeveloped countries and
that it has no chance in highly industrialized nations. Maintaining, for
example, as Djilas does, that in a country like Germany only reformism
can carry the day means forgetting that from 1918 to 1933 the German
proletariat was on the brink of victory on several occasions and that
without the errors caused by its being a satellite of Moscow, it would
probably have abolished the most advanced capitalism of Europe. In May
â68 did we not see the working-class revolt in France a hairâs breadth
from overthrowing an advanced capitalism?
What is more, the two books insist insufficiently upon the relatively
progressive aspects of communism in power, although both mention some of
them. Collinet accepts that the national bourgeoisies have been
eliminated, the poor peasants liberated from the yoke of big landowners
and usurers, and that industrialization has been carried out; Djilas
that the collective ownership of the means of production has allowed for
the realization of rapid progress in certain sectors of the economy. But
the Yugoslav contradicts himself by claiming against all evidence that
no great scientific discoveries have been made under the Soviet regime
and that in this domain the USSR probably trails tsarist Russia. And in
the final conclusions of these two books the progressive aspect is
forgotten and the balance sheet presented is too negative.
In the same way, concerning the possibilities for the evolution of the
post-Stalinist regime the two authors demonstrate a pessimism that in my
eyes is excessive. To be sure, they are right in maintaining that the
Khrushchev regime was that of a conservative pragmatism lacking in
ideas. They are also right in stressing the relatively narrow limits of
de-Stalinization and in being skeptical about the democratization and
the decentralization of the regime, be it in Russia itself, Yugoslavia,
or Poland. But at times when reading them it seems that âdialecticalâ
evolution is blocked, that it forbids all hope. And yet, in other
passages the two authors admit that the break with the Stalinist past is
profound, that something has truly changed, that the domination of the
ânew classâ has been shaken, that liberation is on the march, and that
the release of popular discontent is irreversible. But they conclude
that the outcome will be irremediable ruin and the collapse of
âcommunismâ without indicating with what the âmonsterâ will be replaced.
An ambiguity all the more worrisome in that one senses in their analysis
a singular indulgence towards Western bourgeois democracy, considered
the sole alternative to âcommunist tyranny.â
It seems that for both Collinet and Djilas the Russian regime alone is
responsible for the Cold War and the division of the world into two
blocs. The capitalist and imperialist character of the Western
democracies is blurred. For Collinet financial capitalism is a âmythical
monster,â and even Djilas who has spent time in the U.S., contests the
idea that the Western governments are controlled by a handful of
monopolists. Collinet claims with a straight face that there exist
Western democracies âuntainted by any vestiges of imperialism,â and
Djilas that the United States tend towards an increasingly statist
regime. The dangers that American big business and its claim to world
leadership present are conjured away. Collinet goes even further when he
attacks the Bandung Accords which, according to him, are ânothing but a
weapon against the Western democracies,â and when he presents Mossadegh
and Nasser as instruments in the service of Russian expansionism.[268]
The impact of the indictment of Stalinist totalitarianism and the
executioners of the Hungarian people is considerably weakened by the
blank check issued the aggressors of Suez and Western colonialism.
Why do Collinet and Djilas both go off the rails at the end of their
analysis? In my opinion the real reason for their error is their
inability to find a third way outside of those of Stalinism and
bourgeois democracy. And the source of this inability is the refusal to
rally to libertarian Marxist ideas.
They make only vague and insufficient allusions to the great conflict
between authoritarian socialism and anarchist socialism that so deeply
divided the working-class movement of the nineteenth century. They seem
to be ignorant of the fact that the totalitarian communism they denounce
was condemned a century before them in prophetic terms by Proudhon and
Bakunin. For Collinet and even more for Djilas authority directly
exercised by the proletariat in the absence of any state coercion is an
âillusionâ and a âutopia.â And yet the two authors occasionally
contradict themselves and express unconscious libertarian aspirations.
Collinet lets slip that âthe logic of democracy was not the Jacobin
state, even animated by good intentions, but the state, withering away
and transferring its functions to the entire social body.â And Djilas,
after having denounced the Jacobin-style intolerance of contemporary
communists, exalts âmanâs imperishable aspiration for freedom,â and
announces as imminent the moment when industrialization will render
communism âsuperfluous.â Analyzing the demands of the underground
opposition currently maturing in the USSR, Collinetâwho is more precise
than Djilas on this matter although, alas, he does not go as far as he
shouldâsays that âthey do not appear to be demanding Western
parliamentarism; rather their essence is the independence of the people
and their economic and cultural organizations in relation to the party
and state apparatuses.â
If Collinet and Djilas had more clearly deduced these libertarian
conclusions from their analyses they would have avoided getting bogged
down, due to their failure to clearly glimpse a third way, in a
pro-Western Menshevism that deprives their argument of much of its force
and persuasive power. None of this, of course, justifies the prison
sentence inflicted on the Yugoslav, which does no honor to Titoâs
regime.
The lesson: a revolutionary socialist who frees himself of
Marxist-Leninist Jacobinism is in great danger of falling into
petitbourgeois and counter-revolutionary ideologies. There is only one
healthy and certain way to âde-Jacobinize,â to distance oneself from
authoritarian socialism, and that is to go over to libertarian Marxism,
the only reliable value of our time, the only socialism that has
remained young, the only authentic socialism.
[1957, in Jeunesse du socialisme libertaire]
With the exception of that by Cohn-Bendit, what is striking about some
of the countless books written a tad too hastily about May â68 is the
relative absence of references or insufficient references to the
revolutionary past.[269] The books in which this omission can be found
were written in general by young people. The young were the initiators
of May and feel a legitimate pride in it. Through May, many discovered
the Revolution, a Revolution that not all of them knew beforehand from
books, or only knew it poorly due to the falsified versions that had
been presented to them. From which a strange point of view develops
which leads them to believe that in France everything began with May
â68, that May was an absolutely original creation without any direct
ties to French working-class and revolutionary traditions.
Claude Lefort displayed an illusion of this kind when in an article in
Le Monde,[270] he boldly asserted that âwith the May movement ...
something new is being announced ... an opposition that does not yet
know what to call itself, but which challenges the power structure in
such a way that it cannot be confused with the movements of the past.â
It is true that Lefort in this case was carried away by the ardor of a
polemic against the various Trotskyist groups he reproaches, not without
reason, with seeking to recuperate and monopolize the May movement at
the risk of fossilizing it. But in making his case he exaggeratedly tips
the balance in a direction opposite to that of the Trotskyist tradition,
and I do not share his opinion that May is so radically different from
the movements of the past.
To be sure, what is new, what is absolutely novel in May is that we
witnessed the first act of an extended social revolution whose detonator
was constituted not by workers, as in the past, but for the first time
by students. Nevertheless, this peculiarity of May only concerns the
first two weeks of the famous month, when it was the students who built
the barricades and held the streets. The second phase of the âMay
revolution,â the far more important one, that which more profoundly
shook the political power and the bosses, which gave rise to the alarm
of the property-owning class and the flight of their capital, was a
revolution of the working class in the style and at the level of the
great social crises of the past.
One wonders whether the reason certain people tend to overestimate the
originality of the May revolution is that it arose during a historical
stage when the Revolution had been emptied of all content in France;
when it had been betrayed, perverted, erased from the map by two
powerful political steam-rollers, two sterilizers of critical thinking:
Stalinism and Gaullism. If May looked boldly anti-establishment, if it
seemed to bring into question all established values and authorities as
Claude Lefort seems to think, is it not because Stalinism for the last
forty years and Gaullism for the past ten had caused the French to lose
the habit of radical contestation, of libertarian protest? A habit, a
taste, a tradition that had been theirs for almost 150 years.
Let us take the time to travel into our past and rediscover the
countless May â68s of our national and social history.
For my part, scratching and digging behind the misleading façade
constructed by bourgeois historians, I attempted to revive the mass
movement of the revolution of 1793, extraordinary and unbelievable
because it occurred in a France still more or less plunged in the
darkness of absolutism, aristocracy, and clericalism. I followed step by
step the bold incursions in the direction of the revolutions of the
future dared by the sans-culotte vanguard, so far in advance of its
time: the practice of direct democracy, the omnipotence of the power of
the street. I compared, and how could one not, the Enragés of 1793 and
those of 1968 by stressing this phrase of Jacque Roux, precursor of
Daniel Cohn-Bendit: âOnly the young are capable of the degree of ardor
necessary to make a revolution.â
When I had to describe the burst of vitality, of good sense, of good
humor, more good-natured than cruel, that cast the people into the great
adventure of de-Christianization in 1793 and led to the overturning of
idols, I gave the chapter dedicated to this subject an expression
borrowed from May â68: âAll power to the imagination.â For what we have
here is the same creative genius.
All the social revolutions in France that followed that of 1793 and were
born of its traditions were, like their predecessor, an exuberant
festival of recovered freedom and an enormous collective release.
To a certain extent that was the case with the general strike in Paris
in 1840, at the very moment when the idea of socialism was born in
peopleâs minds. This general strike is too little known, for here, too,
the bourgeois historians, with the exception of Octave Festy, were no
doubt superficial and negligent by design.
And what should we say about the tumultuous, fertile revolution of 1848,
which bred so many ideas that emerged over several months from a popular
crucible in turmoil, when so many public meetings and vast assemblies of
the people where held, when so many newspapers, pamphlets, and tracts
were born.
The libertarian explosion that was the Commune of 1871, the direct heir
of that of 1793, was of the same kind. It is often hidden from us, or
relegated to second place, by authors who have their eyes almost
exclusively fixed on its civil war aspects. But during the short span of
time when revolutionary Paris was able to blossom during a relative
respite before it was subjected to the fatal aggression of the
Versaillais, what a flowering, what an overflowing of joy and liberty!
Armand Gatti, in the beautiful text he wrote in May â68 to comment on
the projection of slides on the walls, perfectly grasped the parallels
between âMay â68â and the Commune.[271] Likewise, it would be giving a
one-sided vision of the May revolution to reduce it to a series of
street battles and to minimize the general contestation and the direct
democracy. The confrontation with the CRS was the price that had to be
paid to open the festival of freedom at the Sorbonne.[272]
The same libertarian impulse can be found in the great strike that
followed the end of World War I in France just fifty years ago, combined
with the mutinies of French sailors refusing to go to war with the
Russian soviets. Do people know that on June 8, 1919, Toulon was the
theater of a genuine insurrection, where sailors, soldiers, and workers
fought shoulder to shoulder in the streets, stones in hand, against the
gendarmes?[273]
For my part, I was fortunate enough, along with millions of other
militants, to live through June â36, the immediate precursor to the
workersâ May â68. And along with all of them I can testify that France,
paralyzed by the general strike and the factory occupations, and with
the power of the masses master of the country, was on a par with the
workersâ uprising we lived through a year ago. Like the preceding
explosions, the ârevolutionâ of 1936 was an impressive festival of
popular joy. Parades of millions of demonstrators filled the streets,
just as on May 13, 1968. And in the factories, of which the workers had
become masters, we participated in an immense popular festival, an
enormous Bastille Day, one far more spontaneous than the one celebrated
every year by the bourgeois republican tradition.[274]
Having participated in many debates in the lecture halls of the occupied
university buildings in May, I can attest to the fact that the
passionate and vibrant crowds that squeezed into them, far from turning
their backs on the revolutionary past, were eager to find a continuity
in it, to quench their thirst at that eternal spring of libertarian
energy, which many of them had just discovered.
The rebirth of anarchism during May â68 might have seemed surprising.
But looked at more closely, the French working class, and by extension
the French people, has always retained an anarchistâor rather
anarcho-syndicalistâsubstratum. Contrary to appearances, the CGTâs
tradition of class struggle and direct action which flourished from 1895
to 1914 never died. Many militants, and even leaders, who have since
become Stalinist âCommunists,â have not completely succeeded in killing
within themselves a repressed nostalgia for anarcho-syndicalism. The
union split of 1921, the creation of the CGTU and then its
Bolshevization did not cause the old syndicalist ferment to vanish from
the consciousness of the workers.[275]
The general strikes of 1936 and 1968, both of which were accompanied by
a wave of occupations, were spontaneous mass mobilizations of the rank
and file, and were authentically anarcho-syndicalist.
Despite the maneuvers of counter-revolutionary bureaucrats like Georges
SĂ©guy,[276] the CGT of today in large measure remains, deep in its
heart, anarcho-syndicalist, and that is what infuriates the
aforementioned individual.
Finally, if anarchism was rediscovered in May, or rather entered into
symbiosis with Marxism, there is no need to go far to find the cause: it
is quite simply because at the moment that it blooms every social
revolution can only be libertarian.
Only afterwards do the recuperators, the leaders who lay their paws on
the Revolution, disfigure it and stifle it.
The revolution of May was aware of this danger. Up till now it has not
succumbed. But beware!
[1969, in Pour un Marxisme libertaire]
Self-management in revolutionary Spain is relatively little known. Even
within the Republican camp it was more or less passed over in silence or
disparaged. The horrible civil war submerged it, and still submerges it
today in peopleâs memories. It is not mentioned at all in the film To
Die in Madrid.[277] And yet, it was perhaps the most positive legacy of
the Spanish Revolution: the attempt at an original form of socialist
economy.
In the wake of the revolution of July 19, 1936, the swift popular
response to the Francoist coup dâĂ©tat, many agricultural estates and
factories had been abandoned by their owners. Agricultural day laborers
were the first to decide to continue cultivating the land. Their social
consciousness seems to have been even higher than that of the urban
workers. They spontaneously organized themselves into collectives. In
August a union conference was held in Barcelona representing several
hundred thousand agricultural workers and small farmers. The legal
blessing only occurred shortly afterwards: on October 7, 1936, the
central Republican government nationalized the lands of âpersons
involved in the fascist rebellion.â
The agricultural collectives gave themselves dual management, both union
and communal, with the communalist spirit predominating. At general
assemblies peasants elected a management committee of eleven members in
each village. Aside from the secretary, all of the members continued to
work with their hands. Labor was mandatory for all healthy men between
eighteen and sixty. The peasants were divided into groups of ten or
more, with a delegate at their head. Each group was assigned a zone of
cultivation or a function in accordance with the age of its members and
the nature of the task. Every evening the management committee received
the delegates of the groups. They frequently invited the residents to a
general assembly of the neighborhood for an account of their activity.
Everything was held in common, except personal savings, and livestock
and fowl destined for family consumption. The artisans, hairdressers,
and cobblers were grouped in collectives. The sheep of the community,
for example, were distributed in groups of three to four hundred,
entrusted to two shepherds and methodically distributed across the
mountain.
Wage labor and, partially at least, money were abolished. Each worker or
family received in remuneration for his labor a bond denominated in
pesetas that could only be exchanged for consumer goods in communal
stores, often located in churches or their out-buildings. The unused sum
was credited to the individualâs reserve account. It was possible to
withdraw pocket money from this sum in limited amounts. Rent,
electricity, medical care, pharmaceutical products, and old age
assistance were free, as was school, which was often located in a former
convent and mandatory for all children below fourteen, for whom manual
labor was prohibited.
Membership in the collective was voluntary. No pressure was exercised on
small landowners. They could, if they wished, participate in common
tasks and place their products in the communal stores. They were
admitted to general assemblies, benefiting from most of the advantages
of the community. They were only prevented from owning more land than
they could cultivate and one condition was posed: that their person or
property not disturb the collective order. In most socialized villages
the number of individuals who stood on their own, peasants or merchants,
grew ever smaller.
The communal collectives were united in cantonal federations, above
which were provincial federations. The land of a cantonal federation
formed one holding, without boundary markings. Solidarity between
villages was pushed to the extreme. Compensation funds allowed for the
assisting of the least favored collectives.
Rural socialization varied in importance from one province to another.
In Catalonia, a land of small and mid-sized property, where farmers had
strong individualist traditions, it was reduced to a few tiny islands,
the peasant union confederation wisely preferring to first convince
landowners by the exemplary success of a few pilot collectives.
On the other hand, in Aragon more than three quarters of the lands were
socialized. The passage of a Catalan militia, the famous Durruti Column,
en route for the north to fight the Francoists, and the subsequent
creation of a revolutionary power issued from the rank and file, the
only one of its kind in Republican Spain, stimulated the creative
initiative of the agricultural workers. Around 450 collectives were
formed, bringing together 600,000 members. In the province of Levante
(its capital Valencia), the richest in Spain, some 600 collectives
arose. They took in 43 percent of all localities, 50 percent of citrus
production and 70 percent of its distribution. In Castile 300
collectives were formed with 100,000 members on the initiative of 1,000
volunteers sent as experts in self-management by Levante. Socialization
also touched Extremadura and a portion of AndalucĂa. There were a few
attempts at it in Asturias, but they were quickly repressed.
It should be noted that this socialism from the base was not, as some
believe, the work of the anarchists alone. According to Gustave Levalâs
testimony, those engaged in self-management were often âanarchists
without knowing it.â[278] Among the latter provinces enumerated above,
it was the socialist, Catholic, and in Asturias even Communist peasants
who took the initiative in self-management.
When it was not sabotaged by its enemies or hindered by the war,
agricultural self-management was an unquestionable success. The land was
united into one holding and cultivated over great expanses according to
a general plan and the directives of agronomists. Small landowners
integrated their plots with those of the community. Socialization
demonstrated its superiority both over large absentee landholdings,
which left a part of the land unplanted, and over smallholdings,
cultivated with the use of rudimentary techniques, inadequate seeding,
and without fertilizer. Production increased by 30â50 percent. The
amount of cultivated land increased, working methods were improved, and
human, animal, and mechanical energy used more rationally. Farming was
diversified, irrigation developed, the countryside partially reforested,
nurseries opened, pigsties constructed, rural technical schools created,
pilot farms set up, livestock selected and increased, and auxiliary
industries set in motion, etc.
In Levante, the initiatives taken for the marketing of agricultural
goods deserve mention. The war having caused a temporary closing of
foreign markets and of the part of the internal market controlled by
Franco, the oranges were dried; and wherever a greater quantity than
previously was obtained, essence was extracted from the peel and orange
honey, orange wine, medical alcohol, and pulp for the saving of blood
from slaughterhouses for use to feed fowl was produced. Factories
concentrated orange juice. When the peasant federation succeeded in
reestablishing relations with French ports it ensured the marketing of
agricultural goods through its warehouses, its trucks, its cargos, and
its sales outlets in France.
These successes were due, for the most part, to the peopleâs initiative
and intelligence. Though a majority were illiterate, the peasants
demonstrated a socialist consciousness, practical common sense, and a
spirit of solidarity and sacrifice that inspired admiration in foreign
visitors. Fenner Brockway of the Independent Labour Party, after a visit
to the collective of Segorbe, testified to this: âThe mood of the
peasants, their enthusiasm, the way in which they made their
contributions to the common effort, their pride in it, all of this is
admirable.â
However, there was no lack of difficulties. Credit and foreign commerce,
by the will of the bourgeois Republican government, remained in the
hands of the private sector. To be sure, the state controlled the banks,
but it avoided putting them at the service of self-management. Lacking
circulating funds, many collectives lived on what they had seized at the
time of the July 1936 revolution. Afterwards they had to resort to
makeshift methods, like seizing jewelry and precious objects belonging
to the churches, convents, Francoists, etc. Self-management also
suffered from a lack of agricultural machinery and, to a lesser degree,
a lack of technical cadres.
But the most serious obstacle was the hostility, at first hidden and
then open, of the various political general staffs of Republican Spain.
Even a party of the Far Left such as the Workersâ Party of Marxist
Unification (POUM) was not always well disposed towards the
collectives.[279] This authentically popular movement, the herald of a
new order, spontaneous and improvised, and jealous of its autonomy,
offended the machine of the Republican state as much as it did private
capitalism. It united against it both the property-owning class and the
apparatuses of the parties of the Left in power. Self-management was
accused of breaking the âunity of the frontâ between the working class
and the petit bourgeoisie and thus of playing into the hands of the
Francoist enemy. Which did not prevent the detractors from refusing
weapons to the revolutionary vanguard, reduced, in Aragon, to
confronting the fascist machineguns barehanded, and then to be attacked
for âinertia.â
On the radio the new Catalonian minister of the economy, Comorera, a
Stalinist, incited peasants not to join the collectives, suggested to
the small landowners that they combat them, and at the same time took
resupplying from the hands of the workersâ unions and favored private
commerce. Thus encouraged from above, the dark forces of reaction
increasingly sabotaged the experiment in self-management.
In the end, the government coalition, after the crushing of the
âBarcelona Communeâ in May 1937 and the outlawing of the POUM, did not
hesitate to liquidate agricultural self-management by any means
necessary. A decree dated August 10, 1937, pronounced the dissolution of
the revolutionary authority in Aragon on the pretext that it âremained
outside the centralizing current.â One of its main inspirations, Joaquin
Ascaso, was indicted for âsale of jewelryâ destined, in reality, for
procuring funds for the collectives. Immediately afterwards, the nth
Division of Commandant Lister (a Stalinist), supported by tanks, went
into action against the collectives. The leaders were arrested, their
offices occupied and then shut down, the management committees
dissolved, the communal stores robbed, the furniture smashed, and the
flocks dispersed. Around 30 percent of the collectives of Aragon were
completely destroyed.
In Levante, in Castile, in the provinces of Huesca and Teruel, armed
attacks of the same kind were perpetratedâby Republicansâagainst
agricultural self-management. It survivedâbarelyâin certain regions that
had not yet fallen into the hands of the Francoists, notably in Levante.
In Catalonia, the most industrialized region of Spain, self-management
also demonstrated its worth in industry. Workers whose employers had
fled spontaneously set to keeping their factories working. In October
1936 a union congress was held in Barcelona representing 600,000 workers
with the object of socializing industry. The workersâ initiative was
ratified by a decree of the Generalitat, the Catalan government, on
October 24, 1936. Two sectors were created, one socialist, the other
private. The socialized factories were those with more than a hundred
workers (those with between fifty and a hundred could be socialized at
the request of three quarters of the workers), those whose owners had
been declared âseditiousâ by a popular tribunal or who had abandoned its
running, and finally those whose importance to the national economy
justified their being removed from the private sector (in fact, a number
of enterprises in debt were socialized).
The socialized factories were led by a management committee with between
five and thirteen members, representing the various services, elected by
the workers in a general assembly, with a two-year term, half of them to
be renewed every year. The committee selected a director to whom it
delegated all or part of its powers. In the key factories the selection
of the director had to be approved by the regulatory body. In addition,
a government inspector was placed on every management committee.
The management committee could be revoked either by the general assembly
or by a general council of the branch of industry (composed of four
representatives of the management committees, eight from the workersâ
unions, and four technicians named by the regulatory body). This general
council planned the work and determined the distribution of profits. Its
decisions were legally binding.
In those enterprises that remained in private hands, an elected workersâ
committee controlled the working conditions âin close collaboration with
the employer.â
The decree of October 24, 1936, was a compromise between the aspiration
for autonomous management and the tendency towards state oversight and
planning, as well as a transition between capitalism and socialism. It
was written by an anarchist minister and accepted by the CNT (National
Confederation of Labor), the anarchist union, because the
anarcho-syndicalists participated in the Catalan government.
In practice, despite the considerable powers granted the general
councils of the branches of industry, worker self-management risked
leading to a selfish particularism, each production unit concerned only
about its own interests. This was remedied by the creation of a central
equalization fund, allowing for the equitable distribution of resources.
In this way the surplus of the Barcelona bus company was transferred to
the less profitable tram company.
Exchanges occurred between industrial and peasant collectives, the
former exchanging underwear or clothing for the olive oil of the latter.
In the suburbs of Barcelona, in the commune of Hospitalitet, on whose
borders farmers were involved in the planting of crops, the agricultural
and industrial (metals, textile, etc.) self-managed organizations joined
together in one communal authority elected by the people, which ensured
the provisioning of the city.
Outside of Catalonia, notably in Levante, industrial self-management was
experimented with in a few locations. This was the case in Alcoy, near
Alicante, where 20,000 textile workers and steel workers managed the
socialized factories and created consumer cooperatives, as well as in
ClastellĂłn de la Plana, where the steel factories were integrated into
larger units under the impetus of a technical commission in daily
contact with each of its management committees.
But like agricultural self-management, industrial self-management faced
the hostility of the administrative bureaucracy, the authoritarian
socialists, and the Communists. The central Republican government
refused it any credits, even when the Catalan minister of the economy,
the anarchist Fabregas, offered the billions on deposit in the savings
banks as a guarantee for the advances to self-management. When he was
replaced in 1937 by Comorera the latter deprived the self-managed
factories of the primary material they lavished on the private sector.
It also neglected to ensure the deliveries ordered by the Catalan
administration to the socialized enterprises.
Later, the central government used the pretext of the needs of national
defense to seize control of the war industries. By a decree of August
23, 1937, it suspended the application of the Catalan socialization
decree of October 1936 in the steel and mining industries, said to be
âcontrary to the spirit of the constitution.â The former supervisors and
the directors removed under self-management or, more precisely, who had
not wanted to accept posts as technicians in self-managed enterprises,
resumed their posts, with revenge in their hearts.
Catalan industrial self-management nevertheless survived in other
branches until the crushing of Republican Spain in 1939. But industry
having lost its main outlets and lacking in primary materials the
factories that did not work for national defense were only able to
operate with severely reduced staff and hours.
In short, Spanish self-management, hardly born, was restrained within
the strict framework of a war fought with classic military methods in
the name (or under cover) of which the republic clipped the wings of its
vanguard and compromised with internal reaction. Despite the unfavorable
conditions under which it took place and the brevity of its existence,
which prohibits an evaluation and accounting of its results, the
experiment opened new perspectives for socialism, for an authentic
socialism, animated from the bottom up, the direct emanation of the
workers of the country and the cities.[280]
[1984, in Ă la recherche dâun communisme libertaire]
It is time to outline a synthesis of all my work and attempt to sketch a
program, at the risk of seeing myself accused of engaging in
âmetapolitics.â
It would be futile to engage in a sort of replastering of an edifice of
cracked and worm-eaten socialist doctrines, to struggle to patch
together some of the surviving solid fragments of traditional Marxism
and anarchism, to indulge in Marxist or Bakuninist scholarship, to seek
to trace, merely on paper, tortuous connections.
If in this book we have often turned to the past it was of course not,
as the reader will have understood, to dwell on it self-indulgently. To
learn from it, to draw from it, yes, for previous experience is rich in
teachings, but with an eye to the future.
The libertarian communism of our time, which blossomed in the French May
â68, goes far beyond communism and anarchism.
Calling oneself a libertarian communist today does not mean looking
backwards, but rather drafting a sketch of the future. Libertarian
communists are not exegetes, they are militants. They understand that it
is incumbent upon them to change the future, no more, no less. History
has backed them against the wall. The hour of the socialist revolution
has rung everywhere. Like the moon landing, it has entered the realm of
the immediate and the possible. The precise definition of the forms of a
socialist society no longer belong to the realm of utopia. The only
people lacking in realism are those who close their eyes to these
truths.
What will be the guiding lines that we are going to follow to accomplish
the Revolution which, as Gracchus Babeuf said, will be the final one?
To start with, before going into action, libertarian communists assess
the exact nature of objective conditions; they attempt to evaluate
accurately the balance of power in every situation. Here the method
elaborated by Karl Marx and which has not aged, namely historical and
dialectical materialism, remains the surest of compasses, an
inexhaustible mine of models and guideposts. On condition, however, that
it be treated as Marx did himself, that is, without doctrinal rigidity,
and that it avoid mechanistic inflexibility; on condition that,
sheltering beneath its wing, one does not eternally invent poor pretexts
and pseudo-objective reasons to excuse oneself from pushing things to
the limit, to sow confusion, to miss the revolutionary opportunity every
time it presents itself.
Libertarian communism is a communism that rejects determinism and
fatalism, which gives space to individual will, intuition, imagination,
the rapidity of reflexes, the profound instinct of the large masses, who
are wiser at moments of crisis than the reasonings of the âelite,â who
believe in the element of surprise and provocation, in the value of
audacity, who do not allow themselves to be encumbered and paralyzed by
a weighty, supposedly âscientificâ ideological apparatus, who do not
prevaricate or bluff, who avoid both adventurism and fear of the
unknown.
Libertarian communists have learned from experience how to set about
things: they hold in contempt the impotent shambles of disorganization
as much as the bureaucratic ball and chain of over-organization.
Libertarian communists, faithful on this point to both Marx and Bakunin,
reject the fetishism of the single, monolithic, and totalitarian party,
just as they avoid the traps of a fraudulent and demobilizing
electoralism.
Libertarian communists are, in their essence, internationalists. They
consider the global struggles of the exploited as a whole. But they
nonetheless take into account the specificity and the original forms of
socialism in each country. They only conceive internationalism to be
proletarian if it is inspired from the bottom up, on a level of complete
equality, without any form of subordination to a âbig brotherâ who
thinks himself stronger and cleverer.
Libertarian communists never sacrifice the revolutionary struggle to the
diplomatic imperatives of the so-called socialist empires and, like Che
Guevara, do not hesitate to send them both packing if their aberrant
fratricidal quarrels cause mortal harm to the cause of universal
socialism.
When the moment of the revolutionary test of strength arrives,
libertarian communists will attack at both the center and the periphery,
in the political and administrative fields as well as the economic. On
the one hand, they will deal mercilessly, with all their might, and if
necessary by means of armed struggle, with the bourgeois state and the
entire complex machinery of power, be it at the level of the capital,
the regions, the departments, or the municipalities; they will never
make the mistake, on the pretext of âapoliticism,â of neglecting,
underestimating, or abstaining from dismantling the citadels, the
political centers, from which the enemyâs resistance is directed. But at
the same time, combining the economic and political struggles, they will
at their workplaces take control of all posts held by the bosses and
wrest the means of production from those who monopolize them, in order
to hand them over to their real, rightful owners: the self-managing
workers and technicians.
Once that revolution is victoriously and completely accomplished,
libertarian communists do not smash the state in order to reestablish it
in another even more oppressive form through the colossal expansion of
its capacities. Rather, they want the transmission of all power to a
confederation of federations, that is, to a confederation of communes,
themselves federated in regions, a confederation of revolutionary
workersâ unions preexisting the revolution or, failing that, the
confederation of workersâ councils born of the revolution, which does
not exclude the eventuality of a merger of the latter two. Elected for a
short mandate and not eligible for reelection, the delegates to these
various bodies are controllable and revocable at all times.
Libertarian communists shun any particularist atomization into small
units, communes, and workersâ councils, and aspire to a federalist
coordination, one which is both close-knit and freely consented to.
Rejecting bureaucratic and authoritarian planning, they believe in the
need for coherent and democratic planning, inspired from the bottom up.
Because they are of their time, libertarian communists want to wrest the
media, automation, and computers from the maleficent monopolists and
place them at the service of liberation.
Hardened authoritarians and sceptics maintain that the imperatives of
contemporary technology are incompatible with a libertarian communist
society. On the contrary, the libertarian communists intend to unleash a
new technological revolution, this time oriented towards both higher
productivity and a shorter work day, towards decentralization,
decongestion, de-bureaucratization, dis-alienation, and a return to
nature. They condemn the degrading mentality of the so-called consumer
society while preparing to raise consumption to its highest level ever.
Libertarian communists carry out this gigantic overturning at the price
of the least possible disorder, neither too slowly nor too soon. They
know that a wave of the magic wand cannot instantly effect the most
profound social transformation of all time. They do not lose sight of
the fact that with the hominid distorted by millennia of oppression,
obscurantism, and egoism, time will be needed to form a socialist man or
socialist woman. They agree to transitions while refusing to see them
perpetuated. And so it is that while assigning as the ultimate goal, to
be reached by stages, the withering away of competition, the free
provision of public and social services, the disappearance of money, and
the distribution of abundance according to the needs of each; that while
aiming at association within self-management of agriculturalists and
artisans, at the cooperative reorganization of commerce, it is not their
plan to abolish overnight competition and the laws of the marketplace,
remuneration according to labor accomplished, small farming, and
artisanal and commercial property.
They do not think superfluous the temporary assistance of active
minorities who are more educated and conscious, whatever name they might
give themselves, minorities whose contribution is unavoidable in
bringing the rearguard to full socialist maturity, but who will not stay
on stage one day longer than necessary and will merge as quickly as
possible into the egalitarian association of producers.
The libertarian communists do not offer us yet another âgroupuscule.â
For them the guiding lines that we have just laid out coincide with the
basic class instinct of the working class.
In my opinionâand long, arduous, and painful experience has demonstrated
thisâapart from libertarian communism there is no real communism.
[1969, in Pour un Marxisme libertaire]
had helped launch the Mouvement Communiste Libertaire (Libertarian
Communist Movement), and two years later the MCL merged with a number of
other groups to create the Organisation Communiste Libertaire
(Libertarian Communist Organization). This was the OCLâs manifesto. [DB]
IâIndividual and collective revolts punctuate the history of humanity,
which is a succession of exploitative societies. In every era thinkers
have arrived at an idea that calls their society into question. But it
was with the advent of modern capitalist society that the division of
society into two fundamental, antagonistic classes clearly appeared, and
it is through class struggle, the motor of the evolution of capitalist
society, that the road was constructed that leads from revolt to the
achieving of revolutionary consciousness.
Today, because it has changed form, class struggle is sometimes denied
by those who insist on either the bourgeoisification and integration of
the working class, or the birth of a new working class that will
supposedly insert itself naturally, as it were, into the decision-making
centers of capitalist society. In fact, the old social strata are
disappearing, the polarization into two fundamental classes is growing
more acute, and there is always some spot in the world where the class
war is being reignited.
Whatever the ideological forms it assumes, the capitalist mode of
production is, globally, a unity. Whether it be in the form which, based
originally on âliberalism,â is headed towards state monopoly capitalism,
or that of state bureaucratic capitalism, capitalism cannot but increase
the exploitation of labor in order to attempt to escape the mortal
crisis threatening it. Massacres, the general collapse of living
conditions, as well as the exploitation and alienation peculiar to this
or that human group (women, the young, racial or sexual minorities,
etc.) are manifestations that cannot be separated from the division of
society into two classes: that which disposes of wealth and the lives of
workers, and creates and perpetuates the superstructures (customs, moral
values, law, culture in general), and that which produces wealth.
The proletariat can today be defined broadly as follows: those who, at
one level or another, create surplus value or contribute to its
realization. Added to the proletariat are those who, belonging to
non-proletarian strata, rally to proletarian objectives (such as
intellectuals and students).
IIâClass struggle and revolution are not purely objective processes, are
not the results of mechanical necessities independent of the activities
of the exploited. The class struggle is not simply a phenomenon to be
observed: it is the driver that constantly modifies the situation and
the facts of capitalist society. Revolution is its conclusion. It is the
exploited taking into its hands the instruments of production and
exchange, of weapons, and the destruction of the centers and means of
state power.
To be sure, the class struggle is punctuated with difficulties,
failures, and bloody defeats, but proletarian action periodically
reemerges, more powerful and more extensive.
confrontation in the workplace. It also manifests itself at the level of
problems of daily life, in struggles against the oppression of women,
the young, and minorities; in the questioning of education, culture,
art, and values. But these struggles must never be separated from the
class struggle. Attacking the state and the superstructures also means
attacking capitalist domination. Fighting for better working conditions
or wage increases means carrying on the same struggle. But it is clear
that posing the problem of lifestyle, rather than just that of wage
levels, gives the struggle a more radical aspect when this means the
development of a mass movement demanding a whole new conception of life
rather than merely quantitative improvements.
workers through their direct struggles against capital and the state,
towards self-organization, and the structures of classless society
appear embryonically in the forms assumed by revolutionary action. The
tendency towards autonomous action can be seen in the course of the most
everyday struggles: wildcat strikes, expropriations, various forms of
direct action opposed to bureaucratic leadership, action committees,
rank-and-file committees, etc. With the demand for power at workersâ
general assemblies and the insistence on the revocability of delegates,
it is true self-management that is on the agenda.
For us there is no historic and formal break between the proletariat
rising to power and its struggles to achieve this, rather a continuous
and dialectical development of self-management techniques, starting from
the class struggle and ending with the victory of the proletariat and
the establishment of a classless society.
A specifically proletarian mode of organization, âcouncil power,â arose
during revolutionary periods like the Paris Commune (1871), Makhnovist
Ukraine (1918â1921), the Italian workersâ councils (1918â1922), the
Bavarian council republic (1918â1919), the Budapest Commune (1919), the
Kronstadt Commune (1921), the Spanish Revolution (1936â1937), the
Hungarian revolt (1956), the Czech revolt (1968), and May â68.
The power of the councils, achieving generalized self-management in all
realms of human activity, can only be defined through historical
practice itself, and any attempt at a definition of the new world can
only be an approximation, a proposal, an investigation.
The appearance and generalization of direct forms of workersâ power
implies that the revolutionary process is already quite advanced.
Nevertheless, it should be presumed that at this stage bourgeois power
is still far from being totally liquidated. And so a provisional dual
power is established between the revolutionary and socialist structures
put in place by the working classes and, on the other hand, the
counter-revolutionary forces.
During this period the class struggle, far from being attenuated,
reaches its climax, and it is here that the words class war take on all
their sharpness: the future of the revolution depends on the outcome of
this war. Nevertheless, it would be dangerous to view the process in
accordance with well-defined norms. Indeed, the nature of state power
(i.e., counter-revolutionary power) in its fight against the councils
can take on different forms. What is fundamental is that council power
is antagonistic to all state power, since it expresses itself within
society itself through general assemblies, whose delegates in the
various organizations that have been established are nothing but its
expression and can be recalled at any time.
At this point authority and society are no longer separate, the maximal
conditions having been realized for the satisfaction of the needs,
tendencies, and aspirations of individuals and social groups, humanity
escaping from its condition as object to become the creative subject of
its own life.
And so it is obvious that the revolution cannot be made through
intermediaries: it is the product of the spontaneous movement of the
masses and not of a general staff of specialists or a so-called vanguard
that is alone conscious and charged with the leadership and direction of
struggles. When the word âspontaneousâ is used here its use should not
at all be interpreted as adherence to a so-called spontaneist idea
privileging mass spontaneity at the expense of revolutionary
consciousness, which is its indispensable complement and which surpasses
it. In other words, an incorrect use of the notion of spontaneity would
consist in likening it to a âdisordered,â âinstinctiveâ activity that
would be incapable of engendering revolutionary consciousness, as was
claimed by Kautsky and later by Lenin in his What Is to Be Done?
It is no less obvious that the revolution cannot be a simple political
and economic restructuring of the old society. Instead, by all at once
overturning all realms through the smashing of capitalist production
relations and the state, it is not only political and economic, but also
at every moment cultural, and it is in this sense that we can utilize
the idea of total revolution.
IIIâThe real vanguard is not this or that group that proclaims itself
the historic consciousness of the proletariat. It is, in fact, those
militant workers who are at the forefront of offensive combat, and those
who maintain a certain degree of consciousness even in periods of
retreat.
The revolutionary organization is a place for meetings, exchanges,
information, and reflection which enable the development of
revolutionary theory and practice, which are nothing but two aspects of
one movement. It brings together militants who recognize each other at
the same level of reflection, activity, and cohesion. It can on no
account substitute itself for the proletarian movement itself or impose
a leadership on it or claim to be its fully achieved consciousness.
On the other hand, it must strive to synthesize the experiences of
struggle, helping to acquire the greatest possible degree of
revolutionary consciousness and the greatest possible coherence in that
consciousness, which is to be seen not as a goal or as existing in the
abstract, but as a process.
In summary, the revolutionary organizationâs role is to support the
proletarian vanguard and to assist in the self-organization of the
proletariat by playingâeither collectively or through the intervention
of militantsâthe role of propagator, catalyst, and revealer, and by
allowing the revolutionaries that compose it coordinated and convergent
interventions in the areas of information, propaganda, and support for
exemplary actions.
A consequence of this conception of the revolutionary organization is
its mission to disappear not through a mechanical decision, but when it
no longer corresponds to the functions that justify it. It will then
dissolve in the classless society.
Revolutionary praxis is carried out within the masses, and theoretical
elaboration only has meaning if it is always connected to the struggles
of the proletariat. In this way revolutionary theory is the opposite of
ideological verbiage papering over the absence of any truly proletarian
praxis.
What this means is that the purpose of the revolutionary organization is
to bring together militants in agreement with the above and
independently of any Marxist, anarchist, councilist, or libertarian
communist label, the label serving to cover in fact the top-down and
elitist understanding of the vanguard that is of course found among
Leninists, but also among so-called anarchists.
The revolutionary organization does not exclusively invoke any
particular theoretician or any preexisting organization, though
recognizing the positive contributions of those who systematized,
refined, and spread the ideas drawn from the mass movement. Rather it
positions itself as heir of the various manifestations of the
anti-authoritarian workers current of the First International, a current
which is historically known under the name of communist anarchism or
libertarian communism, a current which the so-called anarchist currents
have, unfortunately, often grossly caricatured.
The revolutionary organization is self-managed. In its structures and
functioning it must prefigure the non-bureaucratic society that will see
the distinction between order-givers and order-followers disappear and
that will establish delegation solely for technical tasks and with the
corrective of permanent recall.
Technical knowledge and competencies of all kinds must be as widespread
as possible to ensure an effective rotation of tasks. Discussion and the
elaboration of ideas must thus be the task of all militants and, even
more than the indispensable organizational norms, which can always be
revised, it is the level of coherence and the consciousness of
responsibilities reached by all concerned that is the best antidote to
any bureaucratic deviation.
---
(This platform was discussed and adopted during a meeting held in
Marseille on July 11, 1971. It had been called by the Mouvement
Communiste Libertaire [MCL, Libertarian Communist Movement], founded by
groups and individuals most of whom had come out of the former
Federation Communiste Libertaire [FCL, Libertarian Communist
Federation], the Jeunesse Anarchiste Communiste [JAC, Communist
Anarchist Youth], and the Union des Groupes Anarchistes-Communistes
[UGAC, Union of Communist-Anarchist Groups] in the wake of May 1968 and
within the framework of the fusion of several local groups of the
Organisation révolutionnaire Anarchiste [ORA, Anarchist Revolutionary
Organization]. I actively participated in the discussion concerning its
final version on the basis of a draft proposed by Georges Fontenis.[281]
It was published in November 1971 in Guerre de Classes [Class War],
newspaper of the Organisation Communiste Libertaire [OCL, Libertarian
Communist Organization].)
[In Ă la recherche dâun communisme libertaire, 1984]
Since the winter of 1986â1987, struggles have followed one after the
other. They demand to be given a combative and innovative expression.
The signatories of this appeal address all those women and men who think
that under current social and political circumstances a new
revolutionary alternative must be established. In our eyes, the creation
of a revolutionary movement capable of building on and taking forward
the newly revived struggles requires us to take two complementary paths:
is what this appeal is proposing;
self-management movement, to which organized libertarians will
immediately contribute and where they will be active alongside other
political tendencies.
We have entered a period of agitation and struggle that lays bare the
inability of the Left and the union leaderships to respond to the
aspirations of the population.
The âSocialistâ Party (PS) manages capitalism, espouses its logic, and
abandons any wish to transform society, even social democratic
reformism. It opposes the interests of all popular strata. Under cover
of âentering modernityâ it wants to implement a political and social
consensus with the Right and between the different classes. An electoral
machine above all, the PS is a party of notables and technocrats where
everything is decided at the summit, without any real democracy.
The French âCommunistâ Party (PCF) has not had a revolutionary
perspective for some time. Its leadership makes use of social
discontent, but the only model for society it has to offer is a still
terribly bureaucratic USSR. It has a completely undemocratic
organizational framework and imposes an unbearable grip on huge swaths
of the union and social movements.
The union movement is confronted with the reemergence of struggles, but
also with aspirations for self-organization that are being vigorously
expressed. The chasm has never been so wide between unionized and
non-unionized workers, between on the one hand union organizations that
choose and self-manage their own battles, and on the other hand the
fossilized union apparatuses which are often tied to the PS or the PCF.
The revolutionary, alternative, and ecological Left, with all its
variants, does not propose a credible and attractive alternative. The
top-down and centralized errors and myths inherited from Leninism
continue to weigh heavily on some. On others, it is the strong
temptation to integrate into institutional electoral politics and to
constitute a âradical reformist axisâ due to the repeated abandonment by
social democracy of its project once it reaches power.
The balance sheet of the libertarian movement, such as it exists today,
is no more positive and a debate over this point is necessary. For
various reasons, we have not succeeded in putting forward a contemporary
alternative. And many errors continue, here and there, to tarnish our
image: divisions, disorganization, a certain sectarianism, sometimes an
unreasoning cult of spontaneity, as well as the retreat into initiatives
that have the merit of testifying to an ethical refusal of an alienating
society, but which are nevertheless far too ideological and fail to
provide the means of acting on social reality.
The signatories of this appeal affirm that there is room for a new
libertarian struggle, one which is non-dogmatic, non-sectarian, and
attentive to what is happening and what is changing in society. A
struggle which is open and at the same time organized to be effective. A
coherent, well-defined message, but one that is nevertheless not carved
in stone, that is forever the object of reflection and renewal.
It is the aspirations expressed in the struggles for equality,
self-organization, and the rejection of the neoliberal logic that lead
us to this conclusion. It is also the road left open by the collapse of
yesterdayâs dominant models: social democracy, Leninism, and Stalinism.
Many militants would be open to the ideas of a resolutely
anti-capitalist and libertarian current if it were able to engage with
contemporary problems.
Finally, many anarchists and other anti-authoritarians have
distinguished themselves, some very actively, in the recent battles in
the union movement, in the student movement, in the fight against racism
and for equality, and in support of the struggles of the Kanak
people.[282] Many among them feel the movement is in need of
modernization in order to pursue and strengthen their struggles, going
beyond the structures and divisions within libertarianism that have most
often been inherited from the past.
We propose to base ourselves on these practices in order to organize
together a libertarian alternative that responds to the challenges of
our time.
This perspective rests on a statement of fact: none of the current
libertarian groups is capable of sufficiently representing this
alternative. This objective statement in no way questions the value of
the work of the various existing organizations. We do not reject them.
On the contrary, we invite all organizations, local groups, reviews, and
individuals to follow the process, to express themselves and participate
in it. Their various experiences must not be rejected and forgotten. A
new organization will be all the more rich if it were to succeed in
bringing together and capitalizing on the many contributions that
preceded it. But we have to do things differently if we are to respond
to a new situation. The best way forward seems to us to be one that
would take social and militant practice as its starting point as an
element of a process under the control of rank-and-file individuals and
collectives speaking from their experience, beyond the traditional
divisions.
The initiative we are putting forward is therefore the work of a
collective of individual signatories and we invite everyone to join in
this process.
A contemporary affirmation of a libertarian communism is possible,
elaborated on the basis of our social practice and an analysis of
society that takes into account its profound economic, sociological, and
cultural transformations:
in the conditions of todayâs society.
unemployed organize themselves and impose profound transformations
through their autonomous struggles. This is a strategy that we oppose to
that of change through institutional methods, the actions of parties and
office-holders, and the illusion of political reformism. Basing
ourselves on these struggles we can today defend a resolutely extra- and
anti-parliamentary struggle without imprisoning ourselves in purely
ideological campaigns.
as its goal is practicable now: this libertarian struggle will base
itself in social movements and the practice of its militants, practices
that are broad-based, inclusive, and carried out without sectarianism.
Practices that imply not only the self-management of struggles but also
involvement in trade union activity in all of todayâs organizations
(i.e., as much in the CFDT, the CGT, the FEN, and even FO as in the CNT
and the independent unions).[283] But also a class-based approach
outside as well as inside the workplace, in all aspects of life and
society. Struggles against the patriarchal order. Against racism and for
equality. Against imperialism, dictatorships, and apartheid. Against
militarism. Against nuclear energy and for the defense of the
environment. Struggles both of young people in education and those who
are either unemployed or in casualized employment.
This libertarian affirmation anchored in present-day realities is very
much within the lineage of one of the major currents in the history of
the workersâ movement.
We are referringâwithout dogmatism, without wishing to produce a naive
apologia, and thus not without a critical spirit, but with a total
independence of mindâto the anti-authoritarians of the First
International, to the revolutionary syndicalists, to the
anarcho-syndicalists, to the libertarian communists or
anarchistcommunists, without neglecting the contribution of council
communism, trade unionism, self-management currents, feminism, and
ecology. Without losing sight of the fact that it is the struggles of
the workers themselves, the social movements of yesterday and today that
sustain our reflections.
Bringing all of this heritage to bear on contemporary issues implies
syntheses and much modernization on the way to a new political current
facing towards the future.
We do not fetishize organization, but in order to elaborate and defend
this struggle, organization is a necessity.
An organization means: the pooling of resources, experiences, different
focuses, and political education; a place for debate for the elaboration
of collective analyses; a means of quickly circulating information and
of coordination; the search for a strategy which engages with
present-day realities; a platform that expresses our identity.
We must seek a form of self-management of organization that is both
democratic and federalist; that does not lead to confusion; that
organizes convergences without denying differences; that offers a
collective framework without hindering the free speech and activity of
all. A self-managed organization, where the main orientations are
decided democratically by all, by consensus or, if not, by vote. An
effective organization with the necessary structures and means. An
organization aimed at international practices and an international
dimension at a time when Europe is in preparation.[284] It has always
been the case that the anti-capitalist struggle cannot be contained
within the narrow framework of each state.
We must also stress that we are not proposing a sect that will have no
other end than its own growth. We must create a form of activism where
commitment will not be all-consuming and alienating.
One of the assets of a new organization could be the publishing of a new
type of press capable of reaching a broader public, which would be the
expression of a current and an organization, certainly, but also an open
tribune: a press self-managed by the militants; a a portion of its
columns as a permanent forum, open and pluralistic, where the militants
of social movements and of revolutionary, libertarian, and
self-management currents could express themselves.
---
(This Appeal was signed in May 1989 by around a hundred libertarians,
political, trade union and social movement activists, members of various
organizations and of none.)
[In Pour le communisme libertaire, 2003]
English translations of works by Daniel Guérin
(in chronological order of first publication)
Fascism and Big Business (New York: Pioneer Press, 1939; Monad Press &
Pathfinder Press for Anchor Foundation, 1973; Pathfinder Press, 1994);
1939 edition translated by Frances and Mason Merrill, introduced by
Dwight Macdonald.
Negroes on the March: A Frenchmanâs Report on the American Negro
Struggle (New York: George L. Weissman, 1956); translated and edited by
Duncan Ferguson.
The West Indies and Their Future (London: Dennis Dobson, 1961);
translated by Austryn Whainhouse.
âThe Czechoslovak Working Class in the Resistance Movementâ in Ken
Coates (ed.), London Bulletin no. 9 (April 1969), pp. 15â18.
âThe Czechoslovak Working Class in the Resistance Movementâ in Ken
Coates (ed.), Czechoslovakia and Socialism (Nottingham: Bertrand Russell
Peace Foundation, 1969), pp. 79â89.
Anarchism: From Theory to Practice (New York: Monthly Review Press,
1970); translated by Mary Klopper, introduced by Noam Chomsky.
Class Struggle in the First French Republic: Bourgeois and Bras Nus,
i793- 1795 (London: Pluto, 1977); translated by Ian Paterson.
The Writings of a Savage: Paul Gauguin, ed. Daniel Guérin (New York:
Viking Press, 1978); translated by Eleanor Levieyx, introduced by Wayne
Andersen.
100 Years of Labor in the USA (London: Ink Links, 1979); translated by
Alan Adler.
Anarchism and Marxism (Sanday, Orkney: Cienfuegos Press, 1981); from a
talk given in New York on 6 November 1973, with an introduction by
Guérin.
âLutte Ouvriere/Daniel GuĂ©rin: Trotsky and the Second World Warâ in
Revolutionary History vol. 1, no. 3 (1988), available online at
http://www.revolutionaryhistory.co.uk/rho103fdglt.html
.
âMarxism and Anarchismâ in David Goodway (ed.), For Anarchism: History,
Theory and Practice (London: Routledge [History Workshop Series], 1989),
pp. 109â26; translated by David Goodway. The Brown Plague: Travels in
Late Weimar and Early Nazi Germany (Durham, NC: Duke University Press,
1994); translated and introduced by Robert Schwartzwald.
âA Libertarian Marx?â in Discussion Bulletin [Industrial Union Caucus in
Education, USA] no. 86(November-December1997), pp. 3â5.
No Gods No Masters: An Anthology of Anarchism (Edinburgh: AK Press,
1998, 2^(nd) edition 2005), 2 vols., translated by Paul Sharkey.
Daniel GuĂ©rin (1904â1988) was a prominent member of the French left for
half a century, and arguably one of the most original and most
interesting. One of the first on the left to attach central importance
to the struggle against colonialism, he became one of the best-known
figures in anticolonial campaigns throughout the 1950s and â6os. He was
also one of the first in France to warn of the rising dangers of
fascism, publishing The Brown Plague in 1933 and Fascism and Big
Business in 1936. He met Leon Trotsky in 1933 and would work with the
Trotskyist resistance during the war; a respected member of the Fourth
International during the 1940s, he was a close, personal friend of
Michel Raptis (alias Pablo) until his death. His controversial,
libertarian Marxist interpretation of the French Revolution, Class
Struggle in the First Republic, 1793â1797 (1945, 2^(nd) ed. 1968) was
judged by his friend C.L.R. James to be âone of the great theoretical
landmarks of our movementâ and by Sartre to be âone of the only
contributions by contemporary Marxists to have enriched historical
studies.â Increasingly critical of what he saw as the authoritarianism
inherent in Leninism, he influenced a generation of activists with his
ârehabilitationâ of anarchism through his Anarchism and the anthology No
Gods No Masters, before playing a role in the resurgence of interest in
Rosa Luxemburg and becoming better known for his attempts to promote a
âsynthesisâ of Marxism and anarchism. He was also regarded by 1968 as
the grandfather of the gay liberation movement in France and in the
1970s as a leading light in antimilitarist campaigns. His writings have
been repeatedly republished both in French and in translation.
David Berry has a BA in French and German from Oxford University, an MA
in French Studies from the University of Sussex, and a DPhil in history,
also from Sussex. He is currently a senior lecturer in politics and
history at Loughborough University, UK. His publications include A
History of the French Anarchist Movement, 1917â1945 (AK Press, 2009);
New Perspectives on Anarchism, Labour and Syndicalism: The Individual,
the National and the Transnational (Cambridge Scholars Publishing,
2010), coedited with Constance Bantman; Libertarian Socialism: Politics
in Black and Red (PM Press, 2011), coedited with Alex Prichard, Ruth
Kinna, and Saku Pinta; and several journal articles and book chapters on
Daniel Guérin. He is currently preparing a biography of Guérin to be
published by PM Press.
Mitchell Abidor is the principal French translator for the Marxists
Internet Archive. PM Pressâs collections of his translations include
Anarchists Never Surrender: Essays, Polemics, and Correspondence on
Anarchism, 1908â1938 by Victor Serge; Voices of the Paris Commune; and
Death to Bourgeois Society: The Propagandists of the Deed. His other
published translations include The Great Anger: Ultra-Revolutionary
Writing in France from the Atheist Priest to the Bonnot Gang;
Communards: The Paris Commune of 1871 as Told by Those Who Fought for
It; and A Socialist History of the French Revolution by Jean Jaures.
[1] Daniel Guérin, Front populaire, Révolution manquée. Témoignage
militant (Aries: Editions Actes Sud, 1977), p. 29. All translations in
this introduction are the present authorâs, unless stated otherwise.
[2] In Questions de mĂ©thode, quoted in Ian Birchall, âSartreâs Encounter
with Daniel GuĂ©rinâ, Sartre Studies International vol. 2, no. 1 (1996),
p. 46.
[3] See Louis Janover, âDaniel GuĂ©rin, le trouble-fetĂȘâ in LâHomme et la
sociĂ©tĂ© no. 94 (1989), thematic issue on âDissonances dans la
Revolutionâ, pp. 83â93.
[4] Letter to Marceau Pivert, 18 November 1947, Bibliotheque de
Documentation Internationale Contemporaine (hereafter BDIC), Fonds
GuĂ©rin, Fâ e. Res 688/10/2. La Lutte de classes sous la Premiere
Republique, 1793â1797 [Class Struggle under the First Republic] (Paris:
Gallimard, 1946; new edition 1968), 2 vols.
[5] Alex Callinicos (ed.), Marxist Theory (Oxford University Press,
1989), p. 108.
[6] Daniel GuĂ©rin, A la recherche dâun communisme libertaire (Paris:
Spartacus, 1984), pp. 10â1.
[7] See D. Berry, âMetamorphosis: The Making of Daniel GuĂ©rin,
1904â1930â in Modern & Contemporary France vol. 22, no. 3 (2014), pp.
32I-42, and âFrom Son of the Bourgeoisie to Servant of the Revolution:
The Roots of Daniel GuĂ©rinâs Revolutionary Socialismâ in Moving the
Social-journal of Social History and the History of Social Movements no.
51 (2014), pp. 283â311.
[8] On Malon, see K. Steven Vincent, Between Marxism and Anarchism:
Benoit Malon and French Reformist Socialism (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1992). On Proudhon and Kropotkin, see Iain McKayâs
edited anthologies, both of which have useful introductions: Property Is
Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Reader (Oakland: AK Press, 2011) and
Direct Struggle Against Capital: A Peter Kropotkin Anthology (Oakland:
AK Press, 2014).
[9] Cf. Alexandre Christoyannopoulos, âLeo Tolstoy on the State: A
Detailed Picture of Tolstoyâs Denunciation of State Violence and
Deceptionâ, in Anarchist Studies vol. 16, no. 1 (Spring 2008), pp.
20â47.
[10] Daniel GuĂ©rin, Autobiographie de jeunesse, dâune dissidence
sexuelle au socialisme (Paris: Belfond, 1972), pp. 126â7. Charles
Maurras was the leader of the right-wing, nationalist and royalist
movement, Action française.
[11] For more detail, see D. Berry, ââWorkers of the World, Embrace!â
Daniel GuĂ©rin, the Labour Movement and Homosexualityâ in Left History
vol. 9, no. 2 (Spring/Summer 2004), pp. 11â43. See also Peter Sedgwick,
âOut of Hiding: The Comradeships of Daniel GuĂ©rinâ, Salmagundi vol. 58,
no. 9 (June 1982), pp. 197â220.
[12] Guérin, A la recherche, p. 9; Guérin, Front populaire, p. 23.
[13] Guérin, Front populaire, p. 147.
[14] See Thierry Hohl, âDaniel GuĂ©rin, âpivertisteâ. Un parcours dans la
Gauche rĂ©volutionnaire de la STIO (1935â1938)â in Dissidences 2 (2007),
pp. 133â49, and Jacques Kergoat, Marceau Pivert, âsocialiste de gaucheâ
(Paris: Les Editions de lâAtelier/Editions Ouvrieres, 1994).
âLuxembourgismeâ was an identifiable current on the French left opposed
to both Bolshevism and social democracy from around 1928â31. See Alain
Guillermâs preface to the third edition of Rosa Luxembourg, Marxisme et
Dictature: La democratie selon Unine et Luxembourg (Paris: Spartacus,
1974).
[15] GuĂ©rinâs Front populaire is a classic ârevolutionistâ
interpretation of the Popular Front experience.
[16] What has since become known as âentryismâ (âentrismeâ in French)
was originally referred to as âthe French turnâ (âle tournant
frarn;aisâ). This was the new tactic proposed by Trotsky in 1934 in
response to the growing fascist threat across Europe, and the first
instance of it was the suggestion in June of that year that the French
Trotskyists enter the PS in order to contribute to the development of a
more radical current within the party. See Daniel Bensald, Les
trotskysmes (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2002), pp. 31â2
and Alex Callinicos, Trotskyism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1990), pp. 18â9.
[17] GuĂ©rin, Front populaire, p. 104. GuĂ©rinâs Fascisme et grand capital
(Paris: Gallimard, 1936) was inspired by Trotsky.
[18] Guérin, La Peste brune a passe par Iii (Paris: Librairie du
Travail, 1933), translated as The Brown Plague: Travels in Late Weimar
and Early Nazi Germany (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1994);
Fascisme et grand capital (Paris: Gallimard, 1936), trans. Fascism and
Big Business (New York: Monad Press, 1973). Fascism has been criticised
by some for tending towards reductionism: see Claude Lefort, âLâanalyse
Marxiste et le fascismeâ, Les Temps modernes 2 (November 1945), pp.
357â62. GuĂ©rin defended himself vigorously against such criticisms, and
many regard his analysis as fundamentally correct: see for example Alain
Bihrâs introduction to the 1999 edition of Fascisme et grand capital
(Paris: Editions Syllepse and Phenix Editions), pp. 7â14.
[19] GuĂ©rin, âQuand le fascisme nous devançaitâ, in La Peste brune
(Paris: Spartacus, 1996), pp. 21â2.
[20] Ibid., p. 25.
[21] GuĂ©rin, Front populaire, pp. 150, 156â7, 365.
[22] Ibid., p. 157.
[23] Ibid., p. 213.
[24] Ibid., p. 23.
[25] See Jean van Heijenoort, âManifeste: La France sous Hitler et
PĂ©tainâ, in Rodolphe Prager (ed.), Les congres de la quatriĂšme
internationale (manifestes, theses, resolutions) (Paris: La Breche,
1981) vol. II, pp. 35â44; L. Trotsky, âLa guerre imperialiste et la
revolution proletarienne mondialeâ in D. GuĂ©rin (ed.), Sur la deuxieme
guerre mondiale (Brussels: Editions la Taupe, 1970), pp. 187â245. An
English-language version of the manifesto is available on the Marxists
Internet Archive at
.
[26] Interview with Pierre Andre Boutang in Guérin, television
documentary by Jean-Jose Marchand (1985; broadcast on FR3, 4 & 11
September 1989). For more details, see D. Berry, ââLike a Wisp of Straw
Amidst the Raging Elementsâ: Daniel GuĂ©rin in the Second World Warâ, in
Hanna Diamond and Simon Kitson (eds.), Vichy, Resistance, Liberation:
New Perspectives on Wartime France (Festschrift in Honour of H.R.
Kedward) (Oxford: Berg, 2005), pp.143â54.
[27] Letter to Marceau Pivert, 2 Januaury 1948, BDIC, Fonds GuĂ©rin, F°Î
RĂ©s 688/9/1.
[28] Daniel Guérin, Le Feu du Sang. Autobiographie politique et chamelle
(Paris: Editions Grasset & Fasquelle, 1977), p. 149. On GuĂ©rinâs tour of
the U.S., see ibid., pp. 143â219. GuĂ©rinâs researches led to the
publication of the two-volume Ou va le peuple americain? (Paris:
Julliard, 1950â51). Sections of this would be published separately as
Decolonisation du Noir americain (Paris: Minuit, 1963), Le Mouvement
ouvrier aux Etats-Unis (Paris: Maspero, 1968), La concentration
economique aux Etats-Unis (Paris: Anthropos, 1971)âwhich included a
33pp. preface by the Trotskyist economist Ernest Mandelâand De lâOncle
Tom aux Pantheres: Le drame des Noirs americains (Paris: UGE, 1973).
Translations: Negroes on the March: A Frenchmanâs Report on the American
Negro Struggle, trans. Duncan Ferguson (New York: George L. Weissman,
1956), and 100 Years of Labour in the USA, trans. Alan Adler (London:
Ink Links, 1979). For a discussion of GuĂ©rinâs analysis, see also Larry
Portis, âDaniel GuĂ©rin et les Etats-Unis: lâoptimisme et lâintelligenceâ
in Agone 29â30 (2003), pp. 277â89.
[29] GuĂ©rin, La Lutte de classes sous la Pemiere Republique, 1793â1797,
2 vols. (Paris: Gallimard, 1946; 2^(nd) edition 1968). See also Denis
Berger, âLa revolution plurielle (pour Daniel GuĂ©rin)â in E. Balibar,
J.-S. Beek, D. Bensald et al., Permanences de la Revolution. Pour un
autre bicentenaire (Paris: La Breche, 1989), pp. 195â208; David Berry,
âDaniel GuĂ©rin a la Liberation. De lâhistorien de la Revolution au
militant rĂ©volutionnaire: un toumant ideologiqueâ, Agone 29â30 (2003),
pp. 257â73; Michel Lequenne, âDaniel GuĂ©rin, lâhomme de 93 et le
probleme de Robespierreâ, Critique communiste 130â1 (May 1993), pp.
31â4; Julia Guseva, âLa Terreur pendant la Revolution et
lâinterpretation de D. GuĂ©rinâ, Dissidences 2 (2007), pp. 77â88;
Jean-Numa Ducange, âComment Daniel GuĂ©rin utilise-t-il lâreuvre de Karl
Kautsky sur la Revolution française dans La Lutte de classes sous la
premiere Republique, et pourquoi?â, ibid., pp. 89-m. Norah Carlin,
âDaniel GuĂ©rin and the working class in the French Revolutionâ,
International Socialism 47 (1990), pp. 197â223, discusses changes made
by Guérin to La Lutte de classes for the 1968 edition.
[30] Guérin, La Revolution française et nous (Paris: Maspero, 1976), pp.
7â8. Note that the reference to âlibertarian socialismâ is in the
preface to La Revolution française et nous, written thirty years after
the main text and after Guérin had moved closer to anarchism.
[31] Cf. Murray Bookchinâs comments on the sections in âThe Forms of
Freedomâ (1968) in Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Montreal: Black Rose Books,
1971), p.165.
[32] Guérin, La Lutte de classes (1968), vol. I, p. 31.
[33] Ibid., p. 58.
[34] E.J. Hobsbawm, Echoes of the Marseillaise: Two Centuries Look Back
on the French Revolution (London: Verso, 1990), p. 53.
[35] Guérin, La Revolutionfrançaise et nous, p. 7.
[36] For an overview, see Olivier Betoume and Aglaia I. Hartig, Penser
lâhistoire de la Revolution. Deux siecles de passionfrançaise (Paris: La
Decouverte, 1989), esp. pp. 110â4. For a recent reassessment of the
long-running dispute between Guérin and G. Lefebvre, see Antonio de
Francesco, âDaniel GuĂ©rin et Georges Lefebvre, une rencontre
improbableâ, La Revolutionfrançaise,
http://lrf.revues.org/index162.html
, date accessed 28 March 2011.
[37] Ian Birchall, âSartreâs Encounter with Daniel GuĂ©rinâ, Sartre
Studies International vol. 2, no. 1 (1996), p. 46.
[38] GuĂ©rin, âFaisons le pointâ, Le Liberateur politique et social pour
la nouvelle gauche (12 February 1956). A populist, reactionary and
xenophobic anti-taxation movement of small shopkeepers, founded by
Pierre Poujade in 1953, âPoujadismeâ had âmore than a hint of fascismâ
as Rod Kedward has put itâsee La Vie en Bleu. France and the French
since 1900 (London: Penguin, 2006), p. 376. It was as a representative
of Poujadeâs party that Jean-Marie Le Pen was elected to the National
Assembly in 1956.
[39] C.L.R. James, âLâactualite de la Revolution françaiseâ,
Perspectives socialistes: Revue bimensuelle de âUnion de la Gauche
Socialiste 4 (15 February 1958), pp. 20â1.
[40] GuĂ©rin, âLa Revolution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©eâ, in ]eunesse du socialisme
libertaire (Paris: Riviere, 1959), pp. 27â63. See âThe French Revolution
De-Jacobinizedâ in the present collection.
[41] La Revolution française et nous was originally intended as the
preface to La Lutte de classes. âQuand le fascisme nous devançaitâ was
originally commissioned for a special issue of Les Temps Modernes on the
state of the left, but was then rejected by Sartre for being too
critical of the PCF, according to a letter from Guérin to C.L.R. James,
10 August 1955. BDIC, Fonds Guérin, F°Π721/60/5.
[42] GuĂ©rin, âLa Revolution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©eâ, p. 43.
[43] Ibid., pp. 43â4.
[44] GuĂ©rin, âPrefaceâ, in Jeunesse du socialisme libertaire, pp. 7â8.
[45] GuĂ©rin, âLa Revolution dĂ©jacobinisĂ©eâ, 30â1.
[46] Michel Crozier, Ma Belle Epoque. Memoires.1947â1969 (Paris: Fayard,
2002), pp. 79 er 86.
[47] Guérin, Le Feu du sang, p. 218; Kent Worcester, C.LR. James. A
Political Biography (Albany: SUNY, 1996), p. 201; James, letter to
Guérin, 24 May 1956, BDIC, Fonds Guérin, F°Π721/57/2.
[48] Guérin, Le Feu du sang, p. 189. In his account of these meetings,
Guérin refers positively to the collection La Contre-revolution
bureaucratique (Paris: UGE, 1973), which contained texts by Korsch,
Pannekoek, Ruhle and others taken from International Council
Correspondence, Living Marxism and International Socialism. The
councilists had previously republished in translation an article of
GuĂ©rinâs from the French syndicalist journal Revolution proletarienne:
âFascist Corporatismâ, in International Council Correspondence vol. 3,
no. 2 (February 1937), pp. 14â26. (I am grateful to Saku Pinta for
bringing this to my attention.) On Korsch, see Douglas Kellner (ed.),
Karl Korsch: Revolutionary Theory (Austin: University of Texas Press,
1977), which includes a lengthy biographical study.
[49] Guérin/Korsch correspondence, April-June 1954. Karl Korsch Papers,
Intemationaal Instituut voor Sociale Geschiedenis (hereafter USG), Boxes
1â24.
[50] Guérin, Le Feu du sang, p. 156.
[51] Guérin Papers, USG, Box 1, Folder 14. Pierre Chaulieu and Claude
Montal were the pseudonyms of Cornelius Castoriadis and Claude Lefort
respectively.
[52] The list also included James Guillaumeâs history of the IWMA,
Victor Sergeâs Memoirs of a Revolutionary, Volineâs The Unknown
Revolution, Makhno, and the many publications of the Spartacus group
created by Rene Lefeuvre. Mohammed Harbi, Une Vie debout. Memoires
politiques, Tome I: 1945â1962 (Paris: La Decouverte, 2001), pp. 109â12.
Harbi incorrectly describes the Cercle Lenine as being connected to the
PCF; see La Verite, 1 January 1954. On the different analyses of the
nature of the USSR, see Marcel van der Linden, Western Marxism and the
Soviet Union. A Survey of Critical Theories and Debates Since 1917
(Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2007); on Castoriadis and Lefort, see pp.
116â8.
[53] Edgar Morin, âLâAnarchisme en 1968, Magazine litteraire 19 (1968),
available at
https://www.theyliewedie.org/ressources/biblio/fr/Morin_Edgar_-_L'anarchisme_en_1968.html
, accessed 13 April 2021.
[54] See Edgar Morin, âLa refome de penseeâ, in Arguments, 1956â1962
(Toulouse: Privat, 1983), vol. I, p. ix.
[55] For an explanation of why Yugoslaviaâs break with the Soviet bloc
in 1948 was so important to the extreme left in the west, see the
semi-autobiographical account in chapter 5, âLes âannees yougoslavesââ,
of Le Trotskisme. Une histoire sansfard (Paris: Editions Syllepse, 2005)
by Guennâs friend and comrade Michel Lequenne.
[56] Anne GuĂ©rin, âLes ruptures de Daniel GuĂ©rin. Notice biographiqueâ,
in Daniel GuĂ©rin, De lâOncle Tom aux Pantheres noires (Pantin: Les bons
caracteres, 2010), p. 9.
[57] On the FCL, see Georges Fontenis, Changer le monde: Histoire du
mouvement communiste libertaire, 1945â1997 (Paris: Alternative
libertaire, 2000) and, for a more critical view, Philippe Dubacq,
Anarchisme et Marxisme au travers de la Federation communiste libertaire
(1945â1956), Noir et Rouge 23 (1991).
[58] Guérin, Le Feu du sang, p. 233.
[59] Guérin, A la recherche, p. 9.
[60] Ibid., p. 9.
[61] Ibid., p. 10. LâAnarchisme, de la doctrine a la pratique (Paris:
Gallimard, 1965); Ni Dieu ni Maftre, anthologie de lâanarchisme
(Lausanne: La Cite-Lausanne, 1965). Both have been republished several
times since, and LâAnarchisme has been translated into more than 20
languages. They have been published in English as Anarchism: From Theory
to Practice (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970), with an introduction
by Noam Chomsky, and No Gods No Masters: An Anthology of Anarchism
(Edinburgh: AK Press, 1998).
[62] This is not uncontentious-indeed Ernest Mandel takes issue with
Guérin over this question in his anthology Controle ouvrier, conseils
ouvriers, autogestion (Paris: Maspero, 1970), p. 7.
[63] See GuĂ©rinâs 1969 article, âConseils ouvriers et syndicalisme rev
olutionnaire. Lâexemple hongrois, 1956â in A la recherche, pp. 111â5;
the same piece was republished as âSyndicalisme rĂ©volutionnaire et
conseillismeâ in Pour le communisme libertaire, pp. 155â62.
[64] Letters to the author, 12 and 26 February 1986. L'en dehors
appeared weekly, 1922â39, and used to campaign for complete sexual
freedom, regarding homosexuality as an entirely valid form of âfree
loveâ. See Richard D. Sonn, Sex, Violence, and the Avant-Garde:
Anarchism in Interwar France (University Park: Pennsylvania State
University Press, 2010).
[65] Georges Fontenis, âLe long parcours de Daniel GuĂ©rin vers le
communisme libertaireâ, special number of Alternative Libertaire on
Guérin (1998), p. 37.
[66] Guérin, Le Feu du sang, p. 228.
[67] It is also noteworthy that Guérin would include a section on
decolonisation in his Anarchism and found material from Proudhon and
Bakunin which supported the FCLâs position. See Sylvain Pattieu, Les
camarades des freres: Trotskistes et libertaires dans la guerre dâAlgene
(Paris: Syllepse, 2002); Sidi Mohammed Barkat (ed.), Des Franfais contre
la terreur dâĂ©tat (Algerie 1954â1962) (Paris: Editions Reflex, 2002);
Sylvain Boulouque, Les anarchistes franfais face aux guerres coloniales
(1945â1962) (Lyon: Atelier de creation libertaire, 2003).
[68] According to a note by the editors in Guérin, Pour le communisme
libertaire (Paris: Spartacus, 2003), p. 5. Rubel (1905â96) had had links
with the councilist movement and would publish the short text, âMarx
theoricien de lâanarchismeâ [Marx, theoretician of anarchism] in his
Marx, critique du Marxisme [Marx, critic of Marxism] (Paris: Editions
Payot, 1974; new edition 2000), a collection of articles previously
published between 1957 and 1973· The text has since been published as a
booklet, Marx theoricien de lâanarchisme (Saint-Denis: Vent du châmin,
1983; Geneva: Editions Entremonde, 2010). His argument in brief was that
âunder the name communism, Marx developed a theory of anarchism; and
further, that in fact it was he who was the first to provide a rational
basis for the anarchist utopia and to put forward a project for
achieving it: Marxists Internet Archive,
https://www.marxists.org/archive/rubel/1973/marx-anarchism.htm
, accessed 29 March 2011.
[69] Preface of 1970 to Guérin (ed.), Ni Vieu ni Maftre. Antholoqie de
lâanarchisme (Paris: La Decouverte, 1999), vol. I, pp. 6â7. See pp. 41â3
in this volume.
[70] LâAnarchisme, p. 21.
[71] Daniel Guérin, Pour un Marxisme libertaire (Paris: Robert Laffont,
1969), p. 7.
[72] Georges Fontenis, âLe long parcoursâ, p. 38.
[73] âAnarchisme et Marxismeâ, p. 237, in LâAnarchisme (1981 edition),
pp. 229â52. For an English-language version, see the booklet Anarchism &
Marxism (Sanday, Orkney: Cienfuegos Press, 1981), or âMarxism and
Anarchismâ, in David Goodway (ed.), For Anarchism: History, Theory and
Practice (London: Routledge, 1989), pp. 109â26.
[74] LâAnarchisme, pp. 13â4.
[75] Anarchism, p. 153.
[76] Nicolas Walter, âDaniel GuĂ©rinâs Anarchismâ, Anarchy vol. 8, no. 94
(1968), p. 378.
[77] Ibid., p. 381.
[78] Patrice Spadoni, âLa synthese entre lâanarchisme et le Marxisme:
âUn point de ralliement vers lâavenirââ, Alternative Libertaire special
number (2000), p. 43. Guérin, Proudhon oui et non (Paris: Gallimard,
1978),
[79] See his â1917â1921, de lâautogestion a la bureaucratie sovietiqueâ,
in De la Revolution dâoctobre a lâempire eclate: 70 ans de reflexions
sur la nature de lâURSS (Paris: Alternative libertaire/UTCL, n.d.);
âProudhon et lâautogestion ouvriereâ in L'ActualitĂ© de Proudhon
(Bruxelles: Universite libre de Bruxelles, 1967), pp. 67â87; âLâEspagne
libertaireâ, editorial introduction to part of Autogestion et
socialisme, special issue on âLes anarchistes et lâautogestionâ nos.
18/19 (janvier-avril 1972), pp. 81â2; âLâautogestion contemporaineâ,
Nair et rouge nos. 31/32 (octobre 1965-fevrier 1966), pp. 16â24.
[80] See similarly critical remarks about Marxismâs neglect of this
issue by Castoriadis in an interview for a special issue of the UTCLâs
magazine on the usefulness (or otherwise) of Marxism for libertarian
communists: âMarx aujourdâhui. Entretien avec Cornelius Castoriadisâ
Lutter! no. 5 (May 1983), pp. 15â8. GuĂ©rinâs article on âMarx et Engels
militantsâ appeared in the same issue, pp. 19â20.
[81] LâAnarchisme, p. 16.
[82] âProudhon pere de lâautogestionâ (1965) in Proudhon oui et non
(Paris: Gallimard, 1978), p. 165.
[83] Ibid., p. 191.
[84] Guérin, Ni Dieu ni Maltre, vol. I, p. 12. Guérin began his
anthology of anarchist texts with the âprecursorâ Stirner; he also added
an appendix on Stirner to the 1981 edition of LâAnarchisme. See also D.
GuĂ©rin, Homosexualite et Revolution (Saint-Denis: Le Vent du châmin,
1983), p. 12, and âStirner, âPere de lâanarchismeâ?â, La Rue 26 (ler et
2eme trimestre 1979), pp. 76â89. GuĂ©rin also believed Proudhon to have
been a repressed homosexual: see âProudhon et lâamour âunisexualââ in
Arcadie nos. 133/134 (janvier/ fevner 1965).
[85] âStirner, âPere de lâanarchismeâ?â, p. 83.
[86] See Fontenis, Changer le monde, pp. r61-2 and 255â6.
[87] The UTCLâs manifesto, adopted at its Fourth Congress in 1986, was
republished (with a dedication to GuĂ©rin) by the UTCLâs successor
organisation, Alternative Libertaire: Un projet de societe communiste
libertaire (Paris: Alternative libertaire, 2002). See also Theo Rival,
Syndicalistes et libertaires: Une histoire de /âUnion des travailleurs
communistes libertaires (1974â1991) (Paris: Editions dâAltemative
libertaire, 2013).
[88] Fontenis, Changer le monde, p. Bo, note i. See also David Berry,
âChange the world without taking power? The libertarian communist
tradition in France todayâ, journal of Contemporary European Studies
vol. 16, no. 1 (Spring 2008), pp. 111â30.
[89] GuĂ©rin, âAnarchisme et Marxismeâ, in LâAnarchisme (1981), p. 250.
[90] Ibid., p. 248.
[91] Ibid., p. 237.
[92] On Abad de Santillan, see the section on âLâEspagne libertaireâ, in
Les anarchistes et lâautogestion, special issue on âAutogestion et
socialismeâ nos. 18â19 (1972), pp. 81â117, including an introduction by
Guérin.
[93] See GuĂ©rin, Ni Dieu ni Maltre, vol. I, pp. 268â91.
[94] GuĂ©rin, âAnarchisme et Marxismeâ, in LâAnarchisme (1981), p. 252.
[95] Rosa Luxemburg, Le socialisme en France, 1898â1912 (Paris: Belfond,
1971), with an introduction by GuĂ©rin, pp. 7â48; Rosa Luxemburg et la
spontaniite révolutionnaire (Paris: Flammarion, 1971). Typically for
Guérin, the second half of the latter volume brings together a number of
texts representing different opinions on the subject. The following year
he took part in a debate with Gilbert Badia, Michael Lowy, Madeleine
Reberioux, Denis Vidal-Naquet and others on the contemporary relevance
of Luxemburgâs ideas. Gilbert Badia et al., âRosa Luxemburg et nous:
Debatâ, Politique aujourdâhui: Recherches et pratiques socialistes dans
le monde (1972), pp. 77â106. Looking back at the revival of interest in
Luxemburg in the 1960s and 70s, Lowy recently commented: âThere seems to
be a hidden connection between the rediscovery of Rosa Luxemburg and
eras of heightened contestation.â Lowy, âRosa Luxemburg, un Marxisme
pour le XXIe siecleâ, p. 59, Contretemps 8 (2010), pp. 59â63. This is a
special issue devoted to Luxemburgâs continuing relevance to
revolutionary politics.
[96] GuĂ©rin, âAnarchisme et Marxismeâ, p. 233. As the co-editor (with
Jean-Jacques Lebel) of a collection entitled âChanger la Vieâ for the
publisher Pierre Belfond, Guérin took the opportunity to republish
Trotskyâs Our Political Tasks (1904), in which the young Trotsky was
very critical of Leninâs âJacobinismâ and of what he called the
âdictatorship over the proletariatâ: Leon Trotsky, Nos tiiches
politiques (Paris: Belfond, 1970). Luxemburgâs âOrganizational Questions
of Russian Social Democracyâ is also included in the volume as an
appendix. It is noteworthy that the English-language version of Our
Political Tasks, produced in the 1970s by the Trotskyist New Park
Publications, omits the sections in which Trotsky was most critical of
Lenin. (Unfortunately, the Marxists Internet Archive have used the same
partial translation.)
[97] GuĂ©rin, âAnarchisme et Marxismeâ, p. 252.
[98] GuĂ©rin, A la recherche, pp. 10â1.
[99] GuĂ©rin, âPourquoi communiste libertaire?â, in A la recherche, p.
17.
[100] GuĂ©rin, âUn communisme libertaire, pour quoi?â, A la recherche,
pp. 123â5. Cf. Bookchinâs remark that âthe problem is not to âabandonâ
Marxism, or to âannulâ it, but to transcend it dialecticallyâ: Murray
Bookchin, âListen, Marxist.â in Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Montreal: Black
Rose Books, 1971), p. 177.
[101] Nicolas Walter, âDaniel GuĂ©rinâs Anarchismâ, Anarchy vol. 8, no.
94 (1968), pp. 376â82. GuĂ©rin was not entirely unknown to English
readers at the time. Freedom had published a translation of a 1966
interview on 30 September 1967.
[102] George Woodcock, âChomskyâs Anarchismâ in Freedom, 16 November
1974. pp. 4â5.
[103] Miguel Chueca, âAnarchisme et Marxisme. La tentative de Daniel
GuĂ©rin dâunir les deux philosophies et âlâanarchismeâ de Marx vu par
Maximilien Rubelâ in Refractions no. 7, available at
refractions7/chueca1.htm http://www.plusloin.org/refractions/ refractions7/chueca1.htm
(accessed 29 August 2006).
[104] Ian Birchall, âDaniel GuĂ©rinâs Dialogue with Leninismâ in
Revolutionary History vol. 9, no. 2 (2006), pp. 194â5.
[105] See Irene Pereira, Un nouvel esprit contestataire. La grammaire
pragmatiste du syndicalisme dâaction directe libertaire (Unpublished
PhD, Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales, Paris, 2009;
supervised by Luc Boltanski); Patrice Spadoni, âDaniel GuĂ©rin ou le
projet dâune synthese entre lâanarchisme et le Marxismeâ in Philippe
Corcuff and Michael Lowy (eds.), Changer le monde sans prendre le
pouvoir? Nouveaux libertaires, nouveaux communistes, special issue of
Contretemps, no. 6 (February 2003), pp. 118â26; Olivier Besancenot and
Michael Lowy, Affinites rillolutionnaires: Nos etoiles rouges et
noires-Pour une solidarite entre marxistes et libertaires (Paris:
Editions Mille et Une Nuits, 2014). GuĂ©rinâs daughter Anne has claimed
recently that GuĂ©rin was the âMaitre a penserâ of both Daniel
Cohn-Bendit and the Trotskyist Alain Krivine-Biographical preface to
Daniel GuĂ©rin, De lâOncle Tom aux Pantheres noires (Pantin: Les Bons
caracteres, 2010), p. 8. See also Christophe Bourseillerâs comment that
âthe politics of the Mouvement communiste libertaire derived largely
from the theoretical reflexion of Daniel GuĂ©rin.â Histoire generale de
âlâultra-gaucheâ (Paris: Editions Denoel, 2003), p. 484. In 1986 GuĂ©rin
also contributed to the UTCLâs âProjet communiste libertaireâ, which was
republished by Alternative Libertaire in 1993 and again in 2002: Un
projet de societe communiste libertaire (Paris: Alternative Libertaire,
2002). The âAppel pour une alternative libertaireâ of 1989 (which
ultimately led to the creation of AL) was also co-written by Guérin: see
Guérin, Pour le communisme libertaire (Paris: Spartacus, 2003), pp.
181â6.
[106] Guérin, A la recherche, p. 10.
[107] GuĂ©rin, âUn communisme libertaire, pour quoi?â, in A la recherche,
p. 123.
[108] GuĂ©rin is referring to LâAnarchisme, de la doctrine Ă la pratique
first published in 1965 by Gallimard. It was published in English as
Anarchism: From Theory to Practice (Monthly Review Press, 1970), with an
Introduction by Noam Chomsky. [DB]
[109] Sergeâs preface to Joaquin Maurin, RĂ©volution et Contre-Revolution
en Espagne (Rieder, 1937).
[110] See Volineâs The Unknown Revolution, 1917â1921 (Book 2, Part V,
Ch. 7), first published in French in 1947. Voline was the pseudonym of
Vsevolod Mikhailovich Eikhenbaum (1882â1945), a prominent Russian
anarchist who took part in both the Russian and Ukrainian revolutions
before being forced into exile by the Bolsheviks. [DB]
[111] See Deutscherâs biography of Trotsky, The Prophet Armed, The
Prophet Unarmed and The Prophet Outcast (first published 1954â63).
[112] Malatesta, polemic of 1897 quoted by Luigi Fabbri, Dittoturae
Rivoluzione (1921).
[113] Louis Blanc (1811â1882) was a leading socialist reformer who
popularised the demand, âFrom each according to their abilities, to each
according to their needs.â A member of the republican provisional
government installed after the revolution of February 1848, he would
later be a member of parliament under the Third Republic, sitting with
the extreme left. In 1848, he famously pushed for the creation of
cooperative workshops, to be financed at least initially by the state,
in order to provide employment and promote cooperativism within a
framework of economic regulation. [DB]
[114] Idee generale de la Revolution au XiXeme siecle (1851; 1926
edition), pp. 363â4. [These quotes are from the first article in a
polemic between Proudhon and Blanc entitled âResistance to the
Revolutionâ, extracts in Property Is Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon
Anthology (Oakland: AK Press, 2011). âDB]
[115] Idee generale de la Revolution au XiXeme siecle (1851; 1926
edition), pp. 277â8, 329. [âGeneral Idea of the Revolution in the
Nineteenth Centuryâ, Property Is Theft!, pp. 583â4, 595 âDB]
[116] Idee generale de la Revolution au XiXeme siecle (1851; 1926
edition), pp. 280. [Ibid., Property Is Theft!, p. 585 âDB]
[117] âElection Manifestoâ, Le Peuple, 8 November 1848. [âElection
Manifesto of Le Peupleâ, Property Is Theft!, pp. 376â8.]
[118] Ibid., p. 375.
[119] Georges Gurvitch, Proudhon (PUF, 1965).
[120] Theorie de la propriete (A.Lacroix, Verboeckhoven & Cie, 1866), p.
183.
[121] Archives Bakounine (Champ Libre, 1973â83), ed. Arthur Lehning,
vol. I, p. 241.
[122] James Guillaume, Le Collectivisme de /âInternationale (Neuchatel,
1904), p. 12.
[123] Benjamin Lucraft, 1809â1897, was a craftsman from London, a
leading Chartist and a member of the committee of the International
Working Menâs Association. As a delegate to the Basel congress (1869),
he argued not only for land nationalisation, but for the large-scale
cultivation of the land by the state on behalf of the people. [DB]
[124] Pierre Haubtmann, P J. Proudhon, genese dâun antitheiste
(unpublished doc toral thesis), pp. 994â5. [Haubtmann also published
several books on Proudhonâs life and work. âDB]
[125] Carnets, vol. III, p. 114.
[126] Ibid. [See K. Steven Vincent, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and the Rise
of French Republican Socialism (New York/Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1984), p. 156âDB]
[127] Idee generale de la Revolution au XiXeme siecle (1851; 1926
edition), p. 175 ; âGeneral Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth
Centuryâ, Property Is Theft!, p. 558. [DB]
[128] De la justice dans la Revolution et dans lâEglise (Marcel Riviere,
1858), vol. III, pp. 459â93, quoted in Georges Gurvitch, Proudhon et
Mane une confrontation (Centre de documentation universitaire, 1964), p.
93.
[129] De la capacite politique, pp. 171 & 190. [Quotation from âThe
Political Capacity of the Working Classes.â Property Is Theft!, p. 748;
also seep. 759 âDB]
[130] Idee generale, pp. 277â83 & 329. [âGeneral Idea of the
Revolutionâ, Property Is Theft!, pp. 583â6 âDB]
[131] Paul Lafargue, Le Droit a la Paresse (first published 1880).
[132] See my study, âProudhon et lâamour unisexuelâ in Essai sur la
revolution sexuel/e apres Reich et Kinsey (Belfond, 1963).
[133] See K. Marx, Poverty of Philosophy and Haubtmann, P J. Proudhon,
genese dâun antitheiste, pp. 998â9.
[134] De la justice, vol. III, p. 91; Gurvitch, Proudhon et Marx.
[135] De la justice, vol. III, p. 115.
[136] Idee generate, p. 283. [General Idea of the Revolution (London:
Pluto Press, 1989), p. 224 â DB]
[137] Proudhon, Les Confessions dâun rĂ©volutionnaire pour servir a
lâhistoire de la revo â lution de Fevrier (1848) (Marcel Riviere, 1929
edition), pp. 257â60.
[138] âManifeste de la democratie anarchisteâ [Manifesto of anarchist
democ racy] in Le Peup/e, 22, 26 & 31 March 1848.
[139] Carnets, vol. III, pp. 211 & 312.
[140] De la capacite politique (Marcel Riviere, 1924 edition), pp. 329 &
403.
[141] Jacques Freymond (ed.), La Premiere Internationale (Droz, 1962),
vol. I, pp. 151 & 365â465.
[142] âConclusionâ in Manuel du speculateur a la Bourse (Garnier, 1857).
[143] Extracts from the conclusion of the Stock Exchange Speculatorâs
Manual (1857) can be found in Property Is Theft!, pp. 610â7. [DB]
[144] Gurvitch, Proudhon et Marx, pp. 46 & 108.
[145] Theorie de la propriete.
[146] Ibid.
[147] Malatesta, Programme et organisation de LâAssociation
internationale des travailleurs (Florence, 1884); Kropotkine, La
Conquete du pain (Stock, 1890); Kropotkine, Ulnarchie, sa philosophie,
son ideal (Stock, 1896), pp. 27â8 & 31; Kropotkine, La Science moderne
et l!Zlnarchie (Stock, 1913), pp. 82â3 & 103. [âProgram and Organisation
of the International Working Menâs Associationâ, The Method of Freedom:
An Errico Malatesta Reader (Oakland: AK Press, 2014); Kropotkin, The
Conquest of Bread (Oakland: AK Press, 2006), âAnarchy: Its Philosophy
and Idealâ and âmodern Science and Anarchismâ are contained in edited
form in the Kropotkin anthology, Anarchism: A Collection of
Revolutionary Writings (New York: Dover Press, 2002)].
[148] Theorie de la propriete, p. 22.
[149] Bakounine, Ćuvres (Stock, 1895â1913), vol. VI, p. 401.
[150] Marx, Lettre sur le programme de Gotha; Lenine, LâEtat et la
Revolution (1917).
[151] Malatesta, Programme et organisation de l'Association
internationale des travailleurs. [Method of Freedom, pp. 47â8 âDB]
[152] Femand Pelloutier, âLâanarchisme et les syndicats ouvriersâ, in
Les Temps nouveaux, 2 November 1895. [âAnarchism and the Workersâ Unionâ
in No Gods No Masters (Oakland: AK Press, 2005), pp. 409â15 âDB]
[153] Philosophie de la misere, in Ćuvres completes (A. Lacroix,
Verboeckhoven & Cie, 1867), vol. I, p. 225.
[154] Idee generate de la Revolution au Xixeme siecle, p. 281. [Property
Is Theft!, p. 585âDB]
[155] Philosophie de la misere, in Ćuvres completes (A. Lacroix,
Verboeckhoven & Cie, 1867), vol. I, p. 208.
[156] Ibid., p. 210.
[157] Ibid.
[158] Ibid., pp. 209, 211 & 234.
[159] Philosophie de la misere, vol. I, pp. 186 & 215.
[160] Ibid., pp. 209 & 217.
[161] Ibid., vol. II, p. 414.
[162] Albert Meister, Socialisme et Autogestion, lâexperience yougoslave
(Seuil, 1964), p.334.
[163] Cf. Ernest Germain, âLa loi de la valeur, lâautogestion et les
investissements dans lâeconomie des Etats ouvriersâ, in Quatrieme
Internationale, February-March 1964.
[164] Idee generale, pp. 202â3, 301â2, 342, 420, 428.
[165] âProgramme et statuts de la Fratemite rĂ©volutionnaireâ (1865) in
Max Nettlau, Michel Bakounine (London: 1896), vol. I, p. 224.
[166] Bakounine, Ćuvres, vol. V. pp. 216â8; Archives Bakounine, vol. i,
2^(nd) Part, article from Al Rubicone, 3 January 1872.
[167] In Archives, vol. I, 2^(nd) Part, p. 73.
[168] Gurvitch, Proudhon et Marx, p. 113. 57. De la justice, vol. I, p.
320; Contradictions politiques (1862), p. 237 & 245â6.
[169] Rosa Luxemburg, âMasse et chefsâ [âGeknickte Hoffnungenâ, 1903],
in Marxisme contre dictature (Spartacus, 1974), pp. 36â7.
[170] Proudhon, Manuel du speculateur, âConclusionâ.
[171] La Revolution Inconnue, 1917â1921 (1969 edn.), p. 19. In The Ego
and Its Own (1845), Max Stirner had already announced as the âprinciple
of Revolutionâ this pessimistic axiom: âAlways there is only a new
master set in the old oneâs place, and the overturning is a-building up
.... Since the master rises again as state, the servant appears again as
subject.â [English translation by Steven T. Byington (1907) âDB].
[172] In De la capacite politique des classes ouvrieres (MarcelRiviere
edn., 1924), p. 200.
[173] Louis-Auguste Blanqui (1805â1881), although from a bourgeois
background, was a hugely influential revolutionary socialist republican
and was involved in various attempted insurrections from an early age.
âBlanquismâ is characterised by a lack of faith in working-class
movements and by the belief that bourgeois society could only be
destroyed by a violent coup effected by a small group of revolutionaries
who would then introduce a new and more just social order. [DB]
[174] Proudhon in De la capacite, pp. 88 & 119.
[175] Cf. Karl Marx, Lâalliance de la democratie socialiste et Iâ
association internationale des travailleurs. Rapport et documents
publies par ordre du congres international de La Haye (London: A.
Darson; Hamburg: 0. Meissner, 1873).
[176] See his Terrorism and Communism (1920).
[177] An early socialist who met Marx and Engels in the 1840s, Hess
(1812â1875) envisaged the realisation of the ideals of freedom and
equality through the achievement of communism. [DB]
[178] A contradictory figure in early German socialism, Ferdinand
Lassalle (1825â1864) was a republican and democrat, and insisted on the
necessary role of the state in socialism. [DB]
[179] In Engelsâ 1891 preface to the first French edition of Marx, La
Guerre civile en France (Bibliotheque dâetudes socialistes, 1901).
[180] Thomas Hobbesâ Leviathan (1651) is, among other things, an
apologia for despotism.
[181] See The Ego and Its Own.
[182] Speech to the 1868 Bern congress of the Ligue de la paix et de la
liberte, in Memoire de la Federationjurassienne (Sonvillier, 1873), p.
28.
[183] Oscar Testut, LâInternationale (1871), p. 154.
[184] Marx in The Civil War in France.
[185] See the end of ch. 6 in Plekhanov, Anarchisme et Socialisme, force
et violence (Librairie de lâHumanite, 1923), as well as the preface by
Eleanor Marx-Aveling.
[186] Voline, op. cit., pp. 218 and 229.
[187] The philosopher Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908â1961) was a prominent
member of the left intelligentsia in the postwar years. Influenced by
Marx, he was a member of the editorial committee of Sartreâs review Les
Temps modernes (until the two fell out in 1952); he also played a
leading role in the Union des Forces Democratiques created in 1958 by
various elements of the non-communist left to oppose General Charles de
Gaulleâs attempt to become president of a reformed Republic. [DB]
[188] Kropotkin, LâAnarchie, sa philosophie, son ideal (Stock, 1896), p.
51.
[189] Cf. the 1904 text by Rosa Luxemburg reproduced as an appendix to
the French translation of Trotsky, Nos taches politiques (Belfond, 1970
[1904]). [This is a reference to Luxemburgâs âOrganizational Questions
of the Russian Social Democracyâ, available on the Marxists Internet
Archive at
https://www.Marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1904/questions-rscl/index.
htm https://www.Marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1904/questions-rscl/index.
htm
; Guérin, with the anarchist artist Jean-Jacques Lebel, was the editor
of the series in which Trotskyâs Our Political Tasks, a critique of
Lenin and Leninism, was published. âDB]
[190] âSocialismâ in the 1969 version published in D. GuĂ©rin, Pour un
Marxisme libertaire (Laffont, 1969). [MA & DB]
[191] Morris Ernst, Too Big (New York, 1940).
[192] âReforme ou maladie senile du communismeâ, LâExpress, 23 November
1956.
[193] Cesar de Paepe, âDe lâorganisation des services publics dans la
societe futureâ, 1874, in Ni dieu ni maftre, anthologie de lâanarchisme,
1969 edition, p. 317. [Now available in a slightly abridged translation
in No Gods No Masters: An Anthology of Anarchism (Oakland: AK Press,
2005) âDB] Cf. G.D.H. Cole, A History of Socialist Thought (London:
Macmillan, 1958), vol. II, pp. 204â7.
[194] Kropotkin, op. cit., pp. 31â3.
[195] The so-called GomuĆkaâs thaw was a short period in 1956 when,
encouraged by Khrushchevâs famous speech to the Twentieth Congress of
the Soviet Communist Party denouncing Stalin, the Polish Communist
leader initiated a certain liberalization under the banner of a âPolish
road to socialism.â Titoâs split with Stalin in 1948 and the adoption of
the principle of self-management as the basis of a democratic socialist
economy in 1950 meant that Yugoslavia was seen by many anti-Stalinist
socialists in the west as a beacon of hope (which is why Yugoslavian
self-management was discussed, albeit critically, in GuĂ©rinâs 1965 book,
Anarchism: From Theory to Practice). Alexander DubÄek was the figurehead
of the âPrague Springâ of 1968 whose aim was âsocialism with a human
face.â All these attempts were crushed. [DB]
[196] âNous avons perdu nos bagages.â Edgar Quinet, La Revolution
(Editions Lacroix, Vanoeckhoven & Cie, 1869 [1865]), vol. I, p. 8.
[Quinet was a prominent republican writer and historian. âDB]
[197] âVichyâ is shorthand for the quasi-fascist, collaborationist
âFrench Stateâ created in 1940 under Marshal Petain with its capital in
the southern spa town of Vichy (the northern half of the country,
including Paris, having been occupied by German forces). [DB]
[198] Franceâs postwar Fourth Republic (1946â1958) was notorious for its
political instability and inability to resolve the Algerian war of
independence; it finally collapsed in 1958 under pressure from a
generalsâ putsch in Algiers, and General Charles de Gaulle was made head
of the government (and later president). The Fifth Republic, which he
created, saw a reduction in the powers of parliament, a reinforced
executive and the creation of a semi-presidential regime, widely
perceived at the time on the left (including by Guérin) as being
Bonapartist or quasi-fascist. Today there are still widespread calls for
its democratization or even for the creation of a Sixth Republic. [DB]
[199] The Hungarian Revolution of 1956 and the Prague Spring of 1968
were both crushed by Soviet bloc tanks. Both events led to a haemorrhage
of members from Western Communist Parties. [DB]
[200] La lutte de classes sous la Premiere Republique, 1793â1797 (Paris:
Gallimard, 1946; revised edition 1968), 2 vols.
[201] Times Literary Supplement, 15 November 1947. [GuĂ©rinâs text
incorrectly gave the year of publication as 1946. He also failed to
notice that the authorâs name was given in the contents page: Professor
David Thomson. âDB]
[202] See Kropotkinâs The Great French Revolution, 1789â1793, first
published as La Grande Revolution, 1789â1793 (Paris: Stock, 1909). Most
historians of socialist thought have failed to emphasise adequately the
fact that these currents of thought were not simply born in the minds of
the nineteenth-century ideologists (themselves the heirs of the
philosophes of the eighteenth century), but from the lived experience of
class struggles, in particular that of 1793. This gap is particularly
evident in the chapter on the French Revolution with which the late
lamented G.D.H. Cole opened his monumental history of socialist thought
(A History of Socialist Thought, vol. I, 1953, pp. 11â2).
[203] Boris Souvarine, Staline (Editions Champs Libre, 1977 [1935]), p.
265; Erich Wollenberg, The Red Army (London, 1970), pp. 78â80; Isaac
Deutscher, Staline (Gallimard, 1953), p. 7.
[204] As part of a broader move to do away with everything related to
the prerevolutionary regime and the reactionary influence of the
Catholic Church, a new Republican calendar, with months named after
seasonal aspects of the natural world, was instituted. âYear Iâ began
after the declaration of the Republic in 1792. The calendar was later
abolished by Napoleon, but taken up again very briefly during the Paris
Commune of 1871. [DB]
[205] See, amongst others, Marc-Antoine Jullien in the âSociete
populaireâ of La Rochelle, 5 March 1793, in Edouard Lockroy, Une mission
en Vendee, 1793 (Paris: Paul Ollendorf editeur, 1893), pp. 245â8, quoted
in Daniel GuĂ©rin, La lutte de classes, vol. I, pp. 177â8.
[206] See Paul Sainte-Claire Deville, La Commune de lâan II (Paris:
Pion, 1946).
[207] Pierre Caron, Paris pendant la Terreur (Paris: Alphonse Picard,
1910â1964), 6 vols.
[208] In Pierre Caron, Paris pendant la Terreur, vol. 6 (âobserverâ
Boucheseiche, 29 March 1794).
[209] Karl Kautsky, Die Diktatur des Proletariats (Vienna 1918);
published as The Dictatorship of the Proletariat in 1919 (National
Labour Press) [DB]. See also his Materialistische Geschichtsauffassung
(1927), vol. II, p. 469. Cf. Leninâs The Proletarian Revolution and the
Renegade Kautsky (1918).
[210] Thus in his critique of the Erfurt Programme, Engels wrote that
the democratic republic was âthe specific form for the dictatorship of
the proletariat, as the Great French Revolution has already shown.â âA
Critique of the Draft Social-Democratic Program of 1891â, Marx-Engels
Complete Works, vol. 27. p. 217.
[211] When Saint-Just proposed the concentration of power in the hands
of Robespierre, the idea of a personal dictatorship caused a furore
among his colleagues, and Robert Lindet exclaimed: âWe did not make the
Revolution in order to benefit one individual.â In Armand Montier,
Robert Lindet (1899), p. 249. [Thermidor was a month in the
revolutionary calendar, and 9 Thermidor Year II was the date of the
overthrow of Robespierre and the Jacobins; âThermidorâ has thus come to
be shorthand for counterrevolution. âDB]
[212] Bakunin, article in L'Egalite (26 June 1869) reproduced as an
appendix in Memoire de la Federationjurassienne (Sonvillier, 1873);
Ćuvres (Stock), vol. IV, p. 344; âProgramme de lâOrganisation
rĂ©volutionnaire des Freres intemationauxâ, in Ul.lliance internationale
de la democratie socialiste et lâAssociation internationale des
travailleurs (London & Hamburg, 1873). It is true that Bakunin, when
under the influence of the Blanquists, would occasionally use the word
âdictatorshipâ, but he would always pull himself back immediately:
âdictatorship, but not one sanctioned by the officerâs sash,
governmental title or legal institution, and all the more powerful for
having none of the accoutrements of powerâ (Letter to Albert Richard,
1870, in Richard, Bakounine et lâInternationale a Lyon. Cf. also Fritz
Brupbacher, âSoixante ans dâheresieâ in Socialisme et Liberte (Editions
de la Baconniere Boudry, 1955), p. 259.
[213] They shook with fear at the thought of contradicting Lenin, for
whom anyone who did not understand the necessity of dictatorship had
understood nothing about the Revolution and could therefore not be a
true revolutionary. See his âContribution a lâhistoire de la dictatureâ
(1920), in V.I. Lenin, De lâEtat (Paris: Bureau dâeditions, 1935).
[214] Gracchus Babeuf (1760â1797), guillotined for his part in the
Conspiracy of the Equals, was widely influential in the nineteenth
century and is regarded as a precursor of revolutionary socialism. See
Ian Birchall, The Spectre of Babeuf (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2016).
[DB]
[215] Philippe Buonarotti, Conspiration pour /âegaliti, dite de Babeuf
(Librairie romantique, 1828), vol. I, pp. 93, 134, 139, 140. [History of
Babeujâs âConspiracy of Equalsâ âDB]
[216] Wilhelm Weitling (1808â1871), a Prussian tailor, lived in Paris
from 1837 to 1841 and was influenced by Charles Fourier, Robert Owen,
Etienne Cabet and early millenarian Christian movements. A member of the
communist League of the Just, he was admired by many leading
revolutionaries of the time, including Marx and Bakunin. [DB]
[217] Kautsky, The Dictatorship of the Proletariat; Preface by V.P.
Volguine in Albert Soboul, Pierre Angrand and Jean Dauty (eds.), Textes
choisis de Blanqui (Paris: Editions sociales, 1955), pp. 20 and 41;
Maurice Dommanget, Les idees politiques et sociales dâAuguste Blanqui
(Paris: Librairie Marcel Riviere, 1957), pp. 170â3.
[218] Cf. Les Cahiers du bolchevisme, 14 March 1933, p. 451.
[219] Marx, La Lutte de classes en France [1850] (Ed. Schleicher, 1900),
p.147. [âThe proletariat rallies more and more around revolutionary
socialism, around communism, for which the bourgeoisie has itself
invented the name of Blanqui. This socialism is the declaration of the
permanence of the revolution, the class dictatorship of the proletariat
as the necessary transit point to the abolition of class distinctions
generallyâ âMarxists Internet Archive. DB]
[220] Maximilien Rubel, Karl Marx, pages choisies pour une ethique
socialiste (Paris: Marcel Riviere, 1948), pp. 224â5.
[221] A reference to Leninâs comment: âA Jacobin who wholly identifies
himself with the organisation of the proletariatâa proletariat conscious
of its class interestsâis a revolutionary Social Democrat.â (Collected
Works 7: p. 383) Rosa Luxemburg challenges this claim in her
âOrganizational Questions of the Russian Social Democracyâ, while
Kropotkin stressed the fundamentally bourgeois nature and role of the
Jacobins in La Science Moderne et lâAnarchie (Paris, 1913) and The Great
French Revolution, 2789â1793 (1909). [DB]
[222] Cf. Leon Trotski, Nos taches politiques [1904], notably the final
chapter entitled âDictature sur le proletariatâ.
[223] Der Bankrott des russischen Staatskommunismus (Berlin, 1921), pp.
28â31; published in French as Les soviets trahis par les bolcheviks
(Spartacus, 1973, new edition 1998). [This text, whose title means âThe
Bankruptcy of Russian State-Communismâ, does not seem to have been
translated into English. DB]
[224] Cf. Proudhon, Idee generate de la Revolution (1851) in Ćuvres
completes (Paris: Riviere, 1926), pp. 121â6; Deutscher, Staline, pp.
8â9.
[225] Georges Lefebvre, Annales historiques ... April-June 1947, p.175.
[226] Albert Soboul, âRobespierre and the Popular Movement of 1793â1794â
in Past and Present (May 1954), p. 60.
[227] Georges Guy-Grand, La Democratie et lâapres-guerre (Paris: Gamier,
1920), p.230.
[228] Georges Lefebvre, Etudes sur la Revolutionjranfaise (Paris: PUF,
1954), p. 21.
[229] Albert Mathiez, LâHumanite, 19 August 1920; quoted in Guy-Grand,
op. cit., p. 225.
[230] Der Bankrott, op. cit.
[231] Jean Jaures (1859â1914), a schoolteacher and university lecturer
turned politician, was one of the principal figures in the history of
French socialism. Initially a left-wing republican, he was instrumental
in creating and became the leader of the French Socialist Party (opposed
to the Socialist Party of France led by the self-proclaimed Marxist
Jules Guesde), and in 1904 he founded the newspaper LâHumanite (which
from 1920 would be the paper of the French Communist Party). In 1905,
the two socialist parties merged to create the Unified Socialist Party,
French Section of the Workersâ International (PSU-SFIO). Because of his
outspoken pacifism, Jaures was assassinated by a nationalist in 1914
shortly before the outbreak of war. [DB]
[232] The Ministry of War used the fonds secrets (secret funds) to fund
intelligence activities. [DB]
[233] Trotsky, Staline (Paris: UGE, 1979 [1948]), pp. 485, 556â60.
[234] The expression âpermanent revolutionâ can be found in the writings
of Bakunin as well as in those of Blanqui and Marx. [See also Proudhonâs
âToast to the Revolutionâ, 17 October 1848: âFrom this it follows that
revolution is always in history and that, strictly speaking, there are
not several revolutions, but only one permanent revolution.â In Property
Is Theft!, p. 359âDB]
[235] Jean-François Varlet (1764â1837) was a supporter of the
sans-culotte Hebert and was imprisoned more than once for his
insurrectionism. [DB]
[236] Varlet, LâExplosion, 15 Vendemiaire, Year III.
[237] Alain Sergent and Claude Harmel, Histoire de lâAnarchie (Le
Portulan, 1949), p. 82. (Republished by Editions Champ Libre in 1984.)
[238] Born into the Italian nobility, Philippe Buonarroti (1761â1837)
went to France in 1793 and was granted French citizenship for his
services to the Revolution. He met Babeuf in prison after Thermidor and
became a follower. Buonarottiâs History of Babeufâs âConspiracy of
Equalsâ (1828) was very influential. [DB]
[239] Babeuf, Tribun du peuple, II, 294, 13 April 1796; Buonarroti, op.
cit., pp. 264â6.
[240] Proudhon, Idee genirale, p. 195·
[241] Ibid., pp. 177â236.
[242] The decree of 14 Frimaire, Year II (by the revolutionary calendar)
strengthened the power of the central authorities in Paris (especially
the Committee of Public Safety and the Committee of General Security)
and reduced those of local authorities. [MA & DB]
[243] Bakunin, Ćuvres, vol. I, p. 11.
[244] Bakunin, Ćuvres, vol. II, pp. 108 and 232. It was the same for the
German socialists: Rudolf Rocker emphasised (in his Johann Most, Berlin,
1924, p. 53) how Wilhelm Liebknecht, the co-founder with August Bebel of
the Social Democratic Workersâ Party of Germany, was âinfluenced by the
ideas of the old communist Jacobins.â
[245] Trotski, op. cit., p. 95
[246] Boris Nicolaevsky, Karl Marx (Paris: Gallimard, 1937), pp. 146 and
158. [Nicolaevsky (1887â1966) was a Marxist revolutionary and member of
the Russian Social Democratic Labor Party. A prominent Menshevik
intellectual, he was deported from the USSR in 1922 and settled for a
time in Amsterdam where he became director of the International
Institute for Social History. His Karl Marx: Man and Fighter was first
published in German in 1933 and translated into English in 1936. âDB]
[247] Deutscher, Stalin: A Political Biography (Oxford University Press,
1967), p. 30. Cf. also John Maynard, Russia in Flux: Before October (New
York: Macmillan, 1955), p. 118.
[248] Marx in ch. 6 of The Holy Family (1845), available on the Marxists
Internet Archive at
https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1845/holyfamily/
; Engels, Anti-Duhring, translation from Marxists Internet Archive:
https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1877/anti-duhring/ch23.htm
.
[249] Proudhon, Idee generale, pp. 254â323; Bakunin, Ćuvres, vol. II,
pp. 108, 228, 296, 361â2; vol. VI, p. 257.
[250] Engels, Karl Marx devant lesjures de Cologne (Ed. Costes, 1939),
p. 247 and note; Marx, Le Dix-Huit Brumaire de Louis-Bonaparte (Ed.
Scleicher freres, 1900), pp. 342â4; Marx, La Guerre civile, pp. 16, 46,
49; Engels, Critique du programme dâErjurt, op. cit.
[251] See the note by Engels in the 1885 edition of Marxâs address of
the Central Committee to the Communist Leagueâ where Marx proclaimed
that workers âmust not only strive for a single and indivisible German
republic, but also within this republic for the most determined
centralisation of power in the hands of the state authority.â Engels
noted that âthis passage is based on a misunderstandingâ and that it was
now âa well-known fact that throughout the whole [Great French]
revolution ... the whole administration of the departments,
arrondissements and communes consisted of authorities elected by the
respective constituents themselves, and that these authorities acted
with complete freedom within general state laws [and] that precisely
this provincial and local self-government ... became the most powerful
lever of the revolution.â (The Marx-Engels Reader [New York: WW. Norton
0-â Co, 1978), pp. 509â10) [DB]
[252] Lenin, State and Revolution (1917).
[253] Lenine, Pages choisies (Bureau dâedition, 1926â7), vol. II, pp.
372â3.
[254] Lenine, Ćuvres, (First edition), vol. XX, p. 640.
[255] Lenin, Pages choisies, vol. II, p. 93.
[256] Lenin, Pages choisies, vol. II, pp. 115â6.
[257] Lenin, Pages choisies, vol. II, p. 296; Ćuvres, vol. XX, p. 640.
[258] Lenin, Pages choisies, vol. III, p. 339.
[259] Lenin, Ćuvres, vol. XX, p. 640; Pages choisies, vol. I, p. 192.
[260] Lenin, Ćuvres, vol. XXI, pp. 213, 227, 232.
[261] Trotsky, Nos taches politiques, p. 66.
[262] H.-E. Kaminski, Bakounine, La vie dâun rĂ©volutionnaire (Paris:
Aubier, 1938), p. 17. [Republished by Editions La Table Ronde, 2003.
Hanns-Erich Kaminski (1899â1963) was a socialist journalist originally
from Eastern Prussia. He published a book about Italian fascism and
campaigned for an alliance of the German Socialist and Communist Parties
in the face of the Nazi threat. Having immigrated to Paris in 1933, he
moved closer to anarchosyndicalist circles and visited Barcelona in
1936. It was this experience which led to a book about the Spanish
Revolution (Ceux de Barcelone, 1937) and the biography ofBakunin. In
1940 he immigrated to Argentina. âDB]
[263] Milovan Djilas, The New Class: An Analysis of the Communist System
(Thames & Hudson, 1957); Michel Collinet, Du Bolchevisme: evolution et
variations du Mandsmeteninisme (Le Livre Contemporain, 1957). [Djilas, a
former Yugoslav Partisan and Communist leader and at one point touted to
succeed Tito as president, became increasingly critical of the
Yugoslavian system and was imprisoned in 1956. The New Class had been
finished before his arrest and was published in the USA in 1957, which
led to his being sentenced to a further seven yearsâ imprisonment.
Eventually released in 1966, he remained a dissident in Belgrade until
his death in 1995. Collinet (1904â1977) was also a former Communist
turned dissident, and then became a member of the Socialist Partyâs
Revolutionary Left faction and, later, the Workersâ and Peasantsâ
Socialist Party alongside Guérin. He was active in the Resistance during
the Second World War, and remained a member of the Socialist Party after
the Liberation. âDB]
[264] It is regrettable that neither Collinet nor Djilas quote the
remarkable pages (pp. 157, 205) that, well before them, Valine, in his
Revolution inconnue, dedicated to the Bolsheviksâ claim to
infallibility.
[265] Nevertheless, Collinet and Djilas both exaggerate Leninâs dogmatic
rigidity and underestimate his surprising intellectual flexibility and
his ability to revise his positions in light of facts, aptitudes that on
every occasion disconcerted his dull lieutenants and in a large measure
compensated for the failing for which he is criticized.
[266] Collinet here joins Valine without stating so (op. cit., pp.
180â2).
[267] Address of the Central Committee to the Communist League, London,
March 1850. [DB]
[268] The Bandung Conference of 1955 brought together twenty-nine Asian
and African countries, mostly former colonies, with the aim of promoting
economic and cultural cooperation and opposing colonialism and
neo-colonialism. Mohammad Mosaddegh was the democratically elected prime
minister of Iran who was removed from power in a coup organised by
British and US intelligence agencies in 1953. Gamal Abdel Nasser led the
overthrow of the Egyptian monarchy in 1952 and nationalized the Suez
Canal in 1956, which led to invasion by Britain, France, and Israel.
[DB]
[269] Le Gauchisme, remede a la maladie senile du communisme (Paris:
Seuil, 1969). [In fact, the book-published in English as Obsolete
Communism: The Left-Wing Alternative (Oakland: AK Press, 2001)-was
coauthored by Daniel and his elder brother Gabriel. Daniel was
associated with the anarchist group Noir et Rouge and was extremely
critical of the Anarchist Federation; he became the figurehead of the
revolutionary studentsâ movement of May 1968. Gabriel was a member of
the French Communist Party, but left it in 1956 and was associated with
the Socialisme ou Barbarie group around Cornelius Castoriadis, as well
as with other libertarian Marxist networks. DB]
[270] Le Monde, April 5, 1969.
[271] This seems to refer to Gattiâs experimental play Les 13 soleils de
la rue St. Blaise, produced by the Theatre de lâEst Parisien. The
award-winning poet, dramatist, and filmmaker Annand Gatti was born in
1924, the son of an Italian anarchist, and would take part in the armed
resistance to Nazism. After the war he worked as a journalist for many
years before he produced his first literary work and directed his first
film. [DB]
[272] The CRS (Compagnies Republicaine de Securite) are the French riot
police, created in 1944. [DB]
[273] Cf. âLes Mutineries de la mer Noireâ, Les Cahiers de Mai (July
1969).
[274] Commonly known in the English-speaking world as Bastille Day, 14
July has been the official French national celebration day since 1880,
and marks not only the popular storming of the Bastille fortress, a
symbol of absolutist monarchism, on 14 July 1789, but also the âFestival
of Federationâ of 14 July 1790, which was organized by the supporters of
constitutional monarchy and was intended to promote national unity in
order to prevent any rolling back of constitutional changes and any
further social conflict leading to more radical reforms. [DB]
[275] The Confederation Generale du Travail (General Labour
Confederation) was the first national trade union organisation in
France, and before the First World War was strongly influenced by
anarchism, leading to the militant practice dubbed ârevolutionary
syndicalismâ. Increasingly moderate during and after the Great War, the
movement split in the 1920s, with a Communist-dominated minority
creating the CGTU (Unitary CGT). [DB]
[276] Georges Seguy had been a Communist Party (PCF) member since the
1940s and was general secretary of the CGT (which since the Liberation
of 1945 had been dominated by the PCF) from 1967 to 1982. [DB]
[277] A 1962 documentary by Frédéric Rossif. English-language films in
which the collectivizations do feature include Ken Loachâs Land and
Freedom (1995); see also Mark Littlewood, Ethel MacDonald: An
Anarchistâs Story (2007),
http://www.spanishcivilwarfilm.com
. [DB]
[278] Gaston Leval, Espagne libertaire 36â39 (Editions du
Cercle/Editions de la Tete de feuilles, 1971). [Published in English as
Collectives in the Spanish Revolution (London: Freedom Press, 1975) âDB]
[279] The POUM was formed by Andreu Nin and Joaquin Maurin in 1935 and
was affiliated internationally to the so-called London Bureau alongside
the ILP (Independent Labour Party) in Britain and the PSOP (Workersâ and
Peasantsâ Socialist Party) in France (of which GuĂ©rin was a prominent
member at the time). [DB]
[280] See Sam Dolgoff, Anarchist Collectives: Workersâ Self-management
in the Spanish Revolution, 1936â39 (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1975);
Frank Mintz, Anarchism and Workersâ Self-management in Revolutionary
Spain (Oakland: AK Press, 2012). [DB]
[281] Georges Fontenis (1920â2010) was one of the leading figures in the
postwar revolutionary movement in France. He played an important role in
the reconstruction and reform of the French anarchist movement (notably
through the creation of the FCL), and in supporting those fighting for
Algerian independence in the 1950s and 1960s. A prominent activist in
May â68, he would go on to help (re)create a libertarian communist
movement in the 1970s. He was also in later life one of the pillars of
the Free Thought (La Libre Pensee) movement. Having joined the Union of
Libertarian Communist Workers (UTCL) in 1980, he would subsequently
become a member of Alternative Libertaire, and would remain a member
until his death at the age of ninety. [DB]
[282] The Kanak are the indigenous people of New Caledonia (a French
colonial possession in the Pacific). [DB]
[283] As the editors of Pour le communisme libertaire (the 2003
Spartacus edition of the collection of articles on which the present
volume is based) point out, the reference to the various trade union
federations and confederations should be updated: âAs much in the CGT
and the FSU, even in FO, and perhaps the CFDT, as in the CNT and the SUD
unions.â The CNT (Confederation Nationale du Travail, or National Labour
Confederation) was founded in 1946 and modelled on the Spanish CNT. The
manifestoâs general point is clear: the important thing is to fight for
revolutionary practices in all the union organizations. [DB]
[284] This text was written a few years after the Single European Act of
1986, which paved the way for the creation of a single market and single
currency, but before their actual creation and the emergence of the
European Union. [DB]