đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș aufheben-what-was-the-ussr.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 21:55:13. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: What was the USSR?
Author: Aufheben
Date: 1997, 1998, 1999, 2000
Language: en
Topics: USSR, state capitalism, critique, statism, Libertarian Communism, Left Communism, Council Communism, Trotskyism, Trotsky, Lenin, Stalin, Ticktin, Bordiga, the state
Source: Part I in *Aufheben* #06 (Autumn 1997). Part II in *Aufheben* #07 (Autumn 1998). Part III in *Aufheben* #08 (Autumn 1999). Part IV in *Aufheben* #09 (Autumn 2000). All parts retrieved from http://libcom.org/library/what-was-ussr-aufheben

Aufheben

What was the USSR?

Part I: Trotsky and state capitalism

The Russian Revolution and the subsequent establishment of the USSR as a

‘workers’ state’, has dominated political thinking for more than three

generations.

In the past, it seemed enough for communist revolutionaries to define

their radical separation with much of the ‘left’ by denouncing the

Soviet Union as state capitalist.[1] This is no longer sufficient, if it

ever was. Many Trotskyists, for example, now feel vindicated by the

‘restoration of capitalism’ in Russia. To transform society we not only

have to understand what it is, we also have to understand how past

attempts to transform it failed. In this and future issues we shall

explore the inadequacies of the theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state and the various versions of the theory that the USSR was

a form of state capitalism.

Introduction

The question of Russia once more

In August 1991 the last desperate attempt was made to salvage the old

Soviet Union. Gorbachev, the great reformer and architect of both

Glasnost and Perestroika, was deposed as President of the USSR and

replaced by an eight man junta in an almost bloodless coup. Yet, within

sixty hours this coup had crumbled in the face of the opposition led by

Boris Yeltsin, backed by all the major Western powers. Yeltsin’s triumph

not only hastened the disintegration of the USSR but also confirmed the

USA as the final victor in the Cold War that had for forty years served

as the matrix of world politics.

Six years later all this now seems long past. Under the New World

(dis)Order in which the USA remains as the sole superpower, the USSR and

the Cold War seem little more than history. But the collapse of the USSR

did not simply reshape the ‘politics of the world’ — it has had

fundamental repercussions in the ‘world of politics’, repercussions that

are far from being resolved.

Ever since the Russian Revolution in 1917, all points along the

political spectrum have had to define themselves in terms of the USSR,

and in doing so they have necessarily had to define what the USSR was.

This has been particularly true for those on the ‘left’ who have sought

in some way to challenge capitalism. In so far as the USSR was able to

present itself as ‘an actually existing socialist system’, as a viable

alternative to the ‘market capitalism of the West’, it came to define

what socialism was.

Even ‘democratic socialists’ in the West, such as those on the left of

the Labour Party in Britain, who rejected the ‘totalitarian’ methods of

the Lenin and the Bolsheviks, and who sought a parliamentary road to

socialism, still took from the Russian model nationalization and

centralized planning of the commanding heights of the economy as their

touchstone of socialism. The question as to what extent the USSR was

socialist, and as such was moving towards a communist society, was an

issue that has dominated and defined socialist and communist thinking

for more than three generations.

It is hardly surprising then that the fall of the USSR has thrown the

left and beyond into a serious crisis. While the USSR existed in

opposition — however false — to free market capitalism, and while social

democracy in the West continued to advance, it was possible to assume

that history was on the side of socialism. The ideals of socialism and

communism were those of progress. With the collapse of the USSR such

assumptions have been turned on their head. With the victory of ‘free

market capitalism’ socialism is now presented as anachronistic, the

notion of centralized planning of huge nationalized industries is

confined to an age of dinosaurs, along with organized working class

struggle. Now it is the market and liberal democracy that claim to be

the future, socialism and communism are deemed dead and gone.

With this ideological onslaught of neo-liberalism that has followed the

collapse of the USSR, the careerists in the old social democratic and

Communist Parties have dropped all vestiges old socialism as they lurch

to the right. With the Blairite New Labour in Britain, the Clintonite

new Democrats in the USA and the renamed Communist Parties in Europe,

all they have left is to openly proclaim themselves as the ‘new and

improved’ caring managers of capitalism, fully embracing the ideals of

the market and modern management methods.

Of course, for the would-be revolutionaries who had grown up since the

1960s, with the exception of course of the various Trotskyist sects, the

notion that the USSR was in anyway progressive, let alone socialist or

communist, had for a long time seemed ludicrous. The purges and show

trials of the 1930s, the crushing of the workers’ uprisings in East

Germany in 1953 and in Hungary in 1956, the refusal to accept even the

limited liberal reforms in Czechoslovakia in 1968 and the continued

repression of workers’ struggles in Russia itself, had long led many on

the ‘revolutionary left’ to the conclusion that whatever the USSR was it

was not socialist. Even the contention that, for all its monstrous

distortions, the USSR was progressive insofar as it still developed the

productive forces became patently absurd as the economic stagnation and

waste of the Brezhnev era became increasingly apparent during the 1970s.

For those ultra-leftists[2] and anarchists who had long since rejected

the USSR as in anyway a model for socialism or communism, and who as a

result had come to reassert the original communist demands for the

complete abolition of wage labour and commodity exchange, it has long

since become self-evident that the USSR was simply another form of

capitalism. As such, for both anarchists and ultra-leftists the notion

that the USSR was state capitalist has come as an easy one — too easy

perhaps.

If it was simply a question of ideas it could have been expected that

the final collapse of the USSR would have provided an excellent

opportunity to clear away all the old illusions in Leninism and social

democracy that had weighed like a nightmare on generations of socialists

and working class militants. Of course this has not been the case, and

if anything the reverse may be true. The collapse of the USSR has come

at a time when the working class has been on the defensive and when the

hopes of radically overthrowing capitalism have seemed more remote than

ever. If anything, as insecurity grows with the increasing deregulation

of market forces, and as the old social democratic parties move to the

right, it would seem if anything that the conditions are being lain for

a revival of ‘old style socialism’.

Indeed, freed from having to defend the indefensible, old Stalinists are

taking new heart and can now make common cause with the more critical

supporters of the old Soviet Union. This revivalism of the old left,

with the Socialist Labour Party in Britain as the most recent example,

can claim to be making just as much headway as any real communist or

anarchist movement.

The crisis of the left that followed the collapse of the USSR has not

escaped communists or anarchists. In the past it was sufficient for

these tendencies to define their radical separation with much of the

‘left’ by denouncing the Soviet Union as state capitalist and denying

the existence of any actually existing socialist country. This is no

longer sufficient, if it ever was. As we shall show, many Trotskyists,

for example, now feel vindicated by the ‘restoration of capitalism’ in

Russia. Others, like Ticktin, have developed a more sophisticated

analysis of the nature of the old USSR, and what caused its eventual

collapse, which has seriously challenged the standard theories of the

USSR as being state capitalist.

While some anarchists and ultra-leftists are content to repeat the old

dogmas concerning the USSR, most find the question boring; a question

they believe has long since been settled. Instead they seek to reassert

their radicality in the practical activism of prisoner support groups

(‘the left never supports its prisoners does it’),[3] or in the

theoretical pseudo-radicality of primitivism. For us, however, the

question of what the USSR was is perhaps more important than ever. For

so long the USSR was presented, both by socialists and those opposed to

socialism, as the only feasible alternative to capitalism. For the vast

majority of people the failure and collapse of the USSR has meant the

failure of any realistic socialist alternative to capitalism. The only

alternatives appear to be different shades of ‘free market’ capitalism.

Yet it is no good simply denouncing the USSR as having been a form of

state capitalism on the basis that capitalism is any form of society we

don’t like! To transform society we not only have to understand what it

is, we also have to understand how past attempts to transform it failed.

Outline

In this issue and the next one we shall explore the inadequacies of

various versions of the theory that the USSR was a form of state

capitalism; firstly when compared with the standard Trotskyist theory of

the Soviet Union as a degenerated workers’ state, and secondly, and

perhaps more tellingly, in the light of the analysis of the USSR put

forward by Ticktin which purports to go beyond both state capitalist and

degenerated workers’ state conceptions of the nature of the Soviet

Union.

To begin with we shall examine Trotsky’s theory of the USSR as a

degenerated workers’ state, which, at least in Britain, has served as

the standard critical analysis of the nature of the Soviet Union since

the 1930s. Then we shall see how Tony Cliff, having borrowed the

conception of the USSR as state capitalist from the left communists in

the 1940s, developed his own version of the theory of the USSR as a form

of state capitalism which, while radically revising the Trotskyist

orthodoxy with regard to Russia, sought to remain faithful to Trotsky’s

broader theoretical conceptions. As we shall see, and as is well

recognized, although through the propaganda work of the SWP and its

sister organizations world wide Cliff’s version of the state capitalist

theory is perhaps the most well known, it is also one of the weakest.

Indeed, as we shall observe, Cliff’s theory has often been used by

orthodox Trotskyists as a straw man with which to refute all state

capitalist theories and sustain their own conception of the USSR as a

degenerated workers’ state.

In contrast to Cliff’s theory we shall, in the next issue, consider

other perhaps less well known versions of the theory of the USSR as

state capitalist that have been put forward by left communists and other

more recent writers. This will then allow us to consider Ticktin’s

analysis of USSR and its claim to go beyond both the theory of the USSR

as state capitalist and the theory of the USSR as a degenerated workers’

state.

Having explored the inadequacies of the theory that the USSR was a form

of state capitalism, in the light of both the Trotskyist theory of the

Soviet Union as a degenerated workers’ state and, more importantly,

Ticktin’s analysis of the USSR, we shall in Aufheben 8 seek to present a

tentative restatement of the state capitalist theory in terms of a

theory of the deformation of value.

Trotsky’s theory of the Soviet Union as a degenerated workers’ state

Introduction

It is now easy to deride those who have sought, however critically, to

defend the USSR as having been in some sense ‘progressive’. Yet for more

than a half a century the ‘defence of the Soviet Union’ was a central

issue for nearly all ‘revolutionary socialists’, and is a concern that

still persists today amongst some. To understand the significance of

this it is necessary to make some effort to appreciate the profound

impact the Russian Revolution must have had on previous generations of

socialists and working class militants.

I The Russian Revolution

It is perhaps not that hard to imagine the profound impact the Russian

Revolution had on the working class movements at the time. In the midst

of the great war, not only had the working masses of the Russian Empire

risen up and overthrown the once formidable Tsarist police state, but

they had set out to construct a socialist society. At the very time when

capitalism had plunged the whole of Europe into war on an unprecedented

scale and seemed to have little else to offer the working class but more

war and poverty, the Russian Revolution opened up a real socialist

alternative of peace and prosperity. All those cynics who sneered at the

idea that the working people could govern society and who denied the

feasibility of communism on the grounds that it was in some way against

‘human nature’, could now be refuted by the living example of a workers’

state in the very process of building socialism.

For many socialists at this time the revolutionary but disciplined

politics of Bolsheviks stood in stark contrast to the wheeler-dealing

and back-sliding of the parliamentary socialism of the Second

International. For all their proclamations of internationalism, without

exception the reformist socialist parties of the Second International

had lined up behind their respective national ruling classes and in

doing so had condemned a whole generation of the working class to the

hell and death of the trenches. As a result, with the revolutionary wave

that swept Europe following the First World War, hundreds of thousands

flocked to the newly formed Communist Parties based on the Bolshevik

model, and united within the newly formed Third International directed

from Moscow. From its very inception the primary task of the Third

International was that of building support for the Soviet Union and

opposing any further armed intervention against the Bolshevik Government

in Russia on the part of the main Western Powers. After all it must have

seemed self-evident then that the defence of Russia was the defence of

socialism.

II The 1930s and World War II

By the 1930s the revolutionary movements that had swept across Europe

after the First World War had all but been defeated. The immediate hopes

of socialist revolution faded in the face of rising fascism and the

looming prospects of a second World War in less than a generation. Yet

this did not diminish the attractions of the USSR. On the contrary the

Soviet Union stood out as a beacon of hope compared to the despair and

stagnation of the capitalist West.

While capitalism had brought about an unprecedented advance in

productive capacity, with the development of electricity, washing

machines, vacuum cleaners, cars, radios and even televisions, all of

which promised to transform the lives of everyone, it had plunged the

world into an unprecedented economic slump that condemned millions to

unemployment and poverty. In stark contrast to this economic stagnation

brought about by the anarchy of market forces, the Soviet Union showed

the remarkable possibilities of rational central planning which was in

the process of transforming the backward Russian economy. The apparent

achievements of ‘socialist planning’ that were being brought about under

Stalin’s five-year plans not only appealed to the working class trapped

in the economic slump, but also to increasing numbers of bourgeois

intellectuals who had now lost all faith in capitalism.

Of course, from its very inception the Soviet Union had been subjected

to the lies and distortions put out by the bourgeois propaganda machine

and it was easy for committed supporters of the Soviet Union, whether

working class militants or intellectuals, to dismiss the reports of the

purges and show trials under Stalin as further attempts to discredit

both socialism and the USSR. Even if the reports were basically true, it

seemed a small price to pay for the huge and dramatic social and

economic transformation that was being brought about in Russia, which

promised to benefit hundreds of millions of people and which provided a

living example to the rest of the world of what could be achieved with

the overthrow of capitalism. While the bourgeois press bleated about the

freedom of speech of a few individuals, Stalin was freeing millions from

a future of poverty and hunger.

Of course not everyone on the left was taken in by the affability of

‘Uncle Joe’ Stalin. The purge and exile of most of the leaders of the

original Bolshevik government, the zig-zags in foreign policy that

culminated in the non-aggression pact with Hitler, the disastrous

reversals in policy imposed on the various Communist Parties through the

Third International, and the betrayal of the Spanish Revolution in 1937,

all combined to cast doubts on Stalin and the USSR.

Yet the Second World War served to further enhance the reputation of the

Soviet Union, and not only amongst socialists. Once the non-aggression

pact with Germany ended in 1940, the USSR was able to enter the war

under the banner of anti-fascism and could claim to have played a

crucial role in the eventual defeat of Hitler. While the ruling classes

throughout Europe had expressed sympathy with fascism, and in the case

of France collaborated with the occupying German forces, the Communist

Parties played a leading role in the Resistance and Partisan movements

that had helped to defeat fascism. As a result, particularly in France,

Italy, Yugoslavia and Greece, the Communist Parties could claim to be

champions of the patriotic anti-fascist movements, in contrast to most

of the Quisling bourgeois parties.

III The 1950s

The Second World War ended with the USA as the undisputed superpower in

the Western hemisphere, but in the USSR she now faced a formidable

rival. The USSR was no longer an isolated backward country at the

periphery of world capital accumulation centred in Western Europe and

North America. The rapid industrialization under Stalin during the 1930s

had transformed the Soviet Union into a major industrial and military

power, while the war had left half of Europe under Soviet control. With

the Chinese Revolution in 1949 over a third of human kind now lived

under ‘Communist rule’!

Not only this. Throughout much of Western Europe, the very heartlands

and cradle of capitalism, Communist Parties under the direct influence

of Moscow, or social democratic parties with significant left-wing

currents susceptible to Russian sympathies, were on the verge of power.

In Britain the first majority Labour government came to power with 48

per cent of the vote, while in Italy and France the Communist Parties

won more than a third of the vote in the post-war elections and were

only kept from power by the introduction of highly proportional voting

systems.

What is more, few in the ruling circles of the American or European

bourgeoisie could be confident that the economic boom that followed the

war would last long beyond the immediate period of post-war

reconstruction. If the period following the previous World War was

anything to go by, the most likely prospect was of at best a dozen or so

years of increasing prosperity followed by another slump which could

only rekindle the class conflicts and social polarization that had been

experienced during 1930s. Yet now the Communist Parties, and their

allies on the left, were in a much stronger starting position to exploit

such social tensions.

While the West faced the prospects of long term economic stagnation,

there seemed no limits to the planned economic growth and transformation

of the USSR and the Eastern bloc. Indeed, even as the late as the early

1960s Khrushchev could claim, with all credibility for many Western

observers, that having established a modern economic base of heavy

industry under Stalin, Russia was now in a position to shift its

emphasis to the expansion of the consumer goods sector so that it could

outstrip the living standards in the USA within ten years!

It was this bleak viewpoint of the bourgeoisie, forged in the immediate

post-war realities of the late 1940s and early 1950s, which served as

the original basis of the virulent anti-Communist paranoia of the Cold

War, particularly in the USA; from the anti-Communist witch-hunts of the

McCarthy era to Reagan’s ‘evil empire’ rhetoric in the early 1980s.

For the bourgeoisie, expropriation by either the proletariat or by a

Stalinist bureaucracy made little difference. The threat of communism

was the threat of Communism. To the minds of the Western bourgeoisie the

class struggle had now become inscribed in the very struggle between the

two world superpowers: between the ‘Free World’ and the ‘Communist

World’.[4]

This notion of the struggle between the two superpowers as being at one

and the same time the final titanic struggle between capital and labour

was one that was readily accepted by many on the left. For many it

seemed clear that the major concessions that had been incorporated into

the various post-war settlements had been prompted by the fear that the

working class in the West, particularly in Western Europe, would go over

to Communism. The post-war commitments to the welfare state, full

employment, decent housing and so forth, could all be directly

attributed to the bourgeoisie’s fear of both the USSR and its allied

Communist Parties in the West. Furthermore, despite all its faults, it

was the USSR who could be seen to be the champion the millions of

oppressed people of the Third World with its backing for the various

national liberation movements in their struggles against the old

imperialist and colonial powers and the new rapacious imperialism of the

multinationals.

In this view there were only two camps: the USSR and the Eastern bloc,

which stood behind the working class and the oppressed people of the

world, versus the USA and the Western powers who stood behind the

bourgeoisie and the propertied classes. Those who refused to take sides

were seen as nothing better than petit-bourgeois intellectuals who could

only dwell in their utopian abstractions and who refused to get their

hands dirty in dealing with current reality.

Of course, by the early 1950s the full horrors and brutality of Stalin’s

rule had become undeniable. As a result many turned towards reformist

socialism embracing the reforms that had been won in the post-war

settlement. While maintaining sympathies for the Soviet Union, and being

greatly influenced by the notion of socialism as planning evident in the

USSR, they sought to distance themselves from the revolutionary means

and methods of bolshevism that were seen as the cause of the

‘totalitarianism’ of Russian Communism. This course towards ‘democratic

socialism’ was to be followed by the Communist Parties themselves 20

years later with the rise of so-called Euro-communism in the 1970s.

While many turned towards ‘democratic socialism’, and others clung to an

unswerving commitment to the Communist Party and the defence of the

Soviet Union, there were those who, while accepting the monstrosities of

Stalinist and post-Stalinist Russia, refused to surrender the

revolutionary heritage of the 1917 Revolution. Recognising the

limitations of the post-war settlement, and refusing to forget the

betrayals experienced the generation before at the hands of reformist

socialism,[5] they sought to salvage the revolutionary insights of Lenin

and the Bolsheviks from what they saw as the degeneration of the

revolution brought about under Stalin. The obvious inspiration for those

who held this position was Stalin’s great rival Leon Trotsky and his

theory of the Soviet Union as a degenerated workers’ state.

Leon Trotsky

It is not that hard to understand why those who had become increasingly

disillusioned with Stalin’s Russia, but who still wished to defend Lenin

and the revolutionary heritage of 1917 should have turned to Leon

Trotsky. Trotsky had played a leading role in the revolutionary events

of both 1905 and 1917 in Russia. Despite Stalin’s attempts to literally

paint him out of the picture, Trotsky had been a prominent member of the

early Bolshevik Government, so much so that it can be convincingly

argued that he was Lenin’s own preferred successor.

As such, in making his criticisms of Stalinist Russia, Trotsky could not

be so easily dismissed as some bourgeois intellectual attempting to

discredit socialism, nor could he be accused of being an utopian

ultra-leftist or anarchist attempting to measure up the concrete

limitations of the ‘actually existing socialism’ of the USSR against

some abstract ideal of what socialism should be. On the contrary, as a

leading member of the Bolshevik Government Trotsky had been responsible

for making harsh and often ruthless decisions necessary to maintain the

fragile and isolated revolutionary government. Trotsky had not shrunk

from supporting the introduction of one-man management and Taylorism,

nor had he shied away from crushing wayward revolutionaries as was

clearly shown when he led the Red Army detachments to put down both

Makhno’s peasant army during the civil war and the Kronstadt sailors in

1921.Indeed, Trotsky often went beyond those policies deemed necessary

by Lenin and other Bolshevik leaders as was clearly exemplified by his

call for the complete militarization of labour.[6]

Yet Trotsky was not merely a practical revolutionary capable of taking

and defending difficult decisions. Trotsky had proved to be one of the

few important strategic and theoretical thinkers amongst the Russian

Bolsheviks who could rival the theoretical and strategic leadership of

Lenin. We must now consider Trotsky’s ideas in detail and in their own

terms, reserving more substantial criticisms until later.

Trotsky and the Orthodox Marxism of the Second InternationalIn what

follows some readers may think we are treating Trotsky’s theory with too

much respect. For some it is enough to list his bad deeds. Some focus on

his actions in 1917–21, others more on Trotsky’s later failure to

maintain revolutionary positions which culminated with his followers

taking sides in the Second World War. From this it often concluded that

Trotsky’s Marxism was always counter-revolutionary or, as many left

communists argue, that at some point Trotsky crossed the class line and

became counter-revolutionary. Either way Trotsky’s theory of a

degenerated workers’ state can be summarily dismissed as a position

outside the revolutionary camp. For us, however, Trotsky’s theory of the

USSR, and its dominant hold over many critical of Stalinism, reflects

fundamental weaknesses of orthodox Marxism that should be grasped and

overcome. There are very powerful reasons why heterodox Marxists have

found it hard to grasp the USSR as capitalist. In rejecting Trotsky’s

theory of the USSR as a degenerated workers’ state it is not for us a

matter of showing how he ‘betrays the true revolutionary heritage of

pre-1914 social democracy and orthodox Marxism’, but rather it involves

recognizing how true he was to this tradition.

There is little doubt that Trotsky remained committed throughout his

life to the orthodox view of historical materialism which had become

established in the Second International. Like most Marxists of his time,

Trotsky saw history primarily in terms of the development of the forces

of production. While class struggle may have been the motor of history

which drove it forward, the direction and purpose of history was above

all the development of the productive powers of human labour towards its

ultimate goal of a communist society in which humanity as a whole would

be free from both want and scarcity.

As such, history was seen as a series of distinct stages, each of which

was dominated by a particular mode of production. As the potential for

each mode of production to advance the productive forces became

exhausted its internal contradictions would become more acute and the

exhausted mode of production would necessarily give way to a new more

advanced mode of production which would allow the further development of

the productive powers of human labour.

The capitalist mode of production had developed the forces of production

far beyond anything that had been achieved before. Yet in doing so

capitalism had begun to create the material and social conditions

necessary for its own supersession by a socialist society. The emergence

of modern large scale industry towards the end of the nineteenth century

had led to an increasing polarization between a tiny class of

capitalists at one pole and the vast majority of proletarians at the

other.

At the same time modern large scale industry had begun to replace the

numerous individual capitalists competing in each branch of industry by

huge joint stock monopolies that dominated entire industries in a

particular economy. With the emergence of huge joint stock monopolies

and industrial cartels, it was argued by most Marxists that the

classical form of competitive capitalism, which had been analysed by

Marx in the mid-nineteenth century, had now given way to monopoly

capitalism. Under competitive capitalism what was produced and how this

produced wealth should be distributed had been decided through the

‘anarchy of market forces’, that is as the unforeseen outcome of the

competitive battle between competing capitalists. With the development

of monopoly capitalism, production and distribution was becoming more

and more planned as monopolies and cartels fixed in advance the levels

of production and pricing on an industry-wide basis.

Yet this was not all. As the economy as a whole became increasingly

interdependent and complex the state, it was argued, could no longer

play a minimal economic role as it had done during the competitive stage

of capitalism. With the development of large scale industry the state

increasingly had to intervene and direct the economy. Thus for orthodox

Marxism, the development towards monopoly capitalism was at one and the

same time a development towards state capitalism.

As economic planning by the monopolies and the state replaced the

‘anarchy of market’ in regulating the economy, the basic conditions for

a socialist society were being put in place. At the same time the basic

contradiction of capitalism between the increasingly social character of

production and the private appropriation of wealth it produced was

becoming increasingly acute. The periodic crises that had served both to

disrupt yet renew the competitive capitalism of the early and

mid-nineteenth century had now given way to prolonged periods of

economic stagnation as the monopolists sought to restrict production in

order to maintain their monopoly profits.

The basis of the capitalist mode of production in the private

appropriation of wealth based on the rights of private property could

now be seen to be becoming a fetter on the free development of

productive forces. The period of the transition to socialism was fast

approaching as capitalism entered its final stages of decline. With the

growing polarization of society, which was creating a huge and organized

proletariat, all that would be needed was for the working class to seize

state power and to nationalize the major banks and monopolies so that

production and distribution could be rationally planned in the interests

of all of society rather than in the interests of the tiny minority of

capitalists. Once the private ownership of the means of production had

been swept away the development of the forces of production would be set

free and the way would be open to creating a communist society in which

freedom would triumph over necessity.

Of course, like many on the left and centre of the Second International,

Trotsky rejected the more simplistic versions of this basic

interpretation of historical materialism which envisaged the smooth

evolution of capitalism into socialism. For Trotsky the transition to

socialism would necessarily be a contradictory and often violent process

in which the political could not be simply reduced to the economic.

For Trotsky, the contradictory development of declining capitalism could

prompt the revolutionary overthrow of the capitalist class long before

the material and social preconditions for a fully developed socialist

society had come into being. This possibility of a workers’ state facing

a prolonged period of transition to a fully formed socialist society was

to be particularly important to the revolution in Trotsky’s native

Russia.

Trotsky and the theory of permanent revolutionTrotsky originally

developed the theory of permanent revolution in collaboration with

Parvus. After Parvus withdrew from Marxist politics the theory

eventually became ascribed to Trotsky.

While Trotsky defended the orthodox Marxist interpretation of the nature

of historical development he differed radically on its specific

application to Russia, and it was on this issue that Trotsky made his

most important contribution to what was to become the new orthodoxy of

Soviet Marxism.

The orthodox view of the Second International had been that the

socialist revolution would necessarily break out in one of the more

advanced capitalist countries where capitalism had already created the

preconditions for the development of a socialist society. In the

backward conditions of Russia, there could be no immediate prospects of

making a socialist revolution. Russia remained a semi-feudal empire

dominated by the all powerful Tsarist autocracy which had severely

restricted the development of capitalism on Russian soil. However, in

order to maintain Russia as a major military power, the Tsarist regime

had been obliged to promote a limited degree of industrialization which

had begun to gather pace by the turn of century. Yet even with this

industrialization the Russian economy was still dominated by small scale

peasant agriculture.

Under such conditions it appeared that the immediate task for Marxists

was to hasten the bourgeois-democratic revolution which, by sweeping

away the Tsarist regime, would open the way for the full development of

capitalism in Russia, and in doing so prepare the way for a future

socialist revolution. The question that came to divide Russian Marxists

was the precise character the bourgeois-democratic revolution would take

and as a consequence the role the working class would have to play

within it.

For the Mensheviks the revolution would have to be carried out in

alliance with the bourgeoisie. The tasks of the party of the working

class would be to act as the most radical wing of the democratic

revolution which would then press for a ‘minimal programme’ of political

and social reforms which, while compatible with both private property

and the limits of the democratic-bourgeois revolution, would provide a

sound basis for the future struggle against the bourgeoisie and

capitalism.

In contrast, Lenin and the Bolsheviks believed that the Russian

bourgeoisie was far too weak and cowardly to carry out their own

revolution. As a consequence, the bourgeois-democratic revolution would

have to be made for them by the working class in alliance with the

peasant masses. However, in making a revolutionary alliance with the

peasantry the question of land reform would have to be placed at the top

of the political agenda of the revolutionary government. Yet, as

previous revolutions in Western Europe had shown, as soon as land had

been expropriated from the landowners and redistributed amongst the

peasantry most of the peasants would begin to lose interest in the

revolution and become a conservative force. So, having played an

essential part in carrying out the revolution, the peasantry would end

up blocking its further development and confine it within the limits of

a bourgeois-democratic revolution in which rights of private property

would necessarily have to be preserved.

Against both these positions, which tended to see the historical

development of Russia in isolation, Trotsky insisted that the historical

development of Russia was part of the overall historical development of

world capitalism. As a backward economy Russia had been able to import

the most up to date methods of modern large scale industry ‘ready made’

without going through the long, drawn out process of their development

which had occurred in the more advanced capitalist countries. As a

result Russia possessed some of the most advanced industrial methods of

production alongside some of the most backward forms of agricultural

production in Europe. This combination of uneven levels of economic

development meant that the bourgeois-democratic revolution in Russia

would be very different from those that had previously occurred

elsewhere in Europe.

Firstly, the direct implantation of modern industry into Russia under

the auspices of the Tsarist regime had meant that much of Russian

industry was either owned by the state or by foreign capital. As a

consequence, Russia lacked a strong and independent indigenous

bourgeoisie. At the same time, however, this direct implantation of

modern large scale industry had brought into being an advanced

proletariat whose potential economic power was far greater than its

limited numbers might suggest. Finally, by leaping over the intermediary

stages of industrial development, Russia lacked the vast numbers of

intermediary social strata rooted in small scale production and which

had played a decisive role in the democratic-bourgeois revolutions of

Western Europe in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.

On the basis of this analysis Trotsky concluded as early as 1904 that

the working class would have to carry out the democratic-bourgeois

revolution in alliance with the peasant masses because of the very

weakness of the indigenous Russian bourgeoisie. To this extent Trotsky’s

conclusions concurred with those of Lenin and the Bolsheviks at that

time. However, Trotsky went further. For Trotsky both the heterogeneity

and lack of organization amongst the peasant masses meant that, despite

their overwhelming numbers, the Russian peasantry could only play a

supporting role within the revolution. This political weakness of the

peasantry, together with the absence of those social strata based in

small scale production, meant that the Russian proletariat would be

compelled to play the leading role in both the revolution, and in the

subsequent revolutionary government. So, whereas Lenin and the

Bolsheviks envisaged that it would be a democratic workers-peasant

government that would have to carry out the bourgeois revolution,

Trotsky believed that the working class would have no option but to

impose its domination on any such revolutionary government.

In such a leading position, the party of the working class could not

simply play the role of the left wing of democracy and seek to press for

the adoption of its ‘minimal programme’ of democratic and social

reforms. It would be in power, and as such it would have little option

but to implement the ‘minimal programme’ itself. However, Trotsky

believed that if a revolutionary government led by the party of the

working class attempted to implement a ‘minimal programme’ it would soon

meet the resolute opposition of the propertied classes. In the face of

such opposition the working class party would either have to abdicate

power or else press head by abolishing private property in the means of

production and in doing so begin at once the proletarian-socialist

revolution.

For Trotsky it would be both absurd and irresponsible for the party of

the working class to simply abdicate power in such a crucial situation.

In such a position, the party of the working class would have to take

the opportunity of expropriating the weak bourgeoisie and allow the

bourgeois-democratic revolution to pass, uninterrupted, into a

proletarian-socialist revolution.

Trotsky accepted that the peasantry would inevitably become a

conservative force once agrarian reform had been completed. However, he

argued that a substantial part of the peasantry would continue to back

the revolutionary government for a while, not because of any advanced

‘revolutionary consciousness’ but due to their very ‘backwardness’;[7]

this, together with the proletariats’ superior organization, would give

the revolutionary government time. Ultimately, however, the

revolutionary government’s only hope would be that the Russian

revolution would trigger revolution throughout the rest of Europe and

the world.

Trotsky and the perils of transition

While Trotsky’s theory of permanent revolution may have appeared

adventurist, if not a little utopian, to most Russian Marxists when it

was first set out in Results and Prospects in 1906, its conclusions were

to prove crucial eleven years later in the formation of the new

Marxist-Leninist orthodoxy which came to be established with the Russian

Revolutions of 1917.

The revolution of February 1917 took all political parties and factions

by surprise. Within a few days the centuries old Tsarist regime had been

swept away and a situation of dual power established. On the one side

stood the Provisional Government dominated by the various liberal

bourgeois parties, on the other side stood the growing numbers of

workers and peasant soviets. For the Mensheviks the position was clear:

the organizations of the working class had to give critical support to

the bourgeois Provisional Government while it carried out its democratic

programme. In contrast, faced with a democratic-bourgeois Government

which they had denied was possible, the Bolsheviks were thrown into

confusion. A confusion that came to a virtual split with the return of

Lenin from exile at the beginning of April.

In his April Theses Lenin proposed a radical shift in policy, which,

despite various differences in detail and emphasis, brought him close to

the positions that had been put forward by Trotsky with his theory of

permanent revolution. Lenin argued that the Bourgeois Government would

eventually prove too weak to carry out its democratic programme. As a

consequence the Bolsheviks had to persuade the soviets to overthrow the

Provisional Government and establish a workers’ and peasants’ government

which would not only have the task of introducing democratic reform, but

which would eventually have to make a start on the road to socialism.

With this radical shift in position initiated by the April Theses, and

Trotsky’s subsequent acceptance of Lenin’s conception of the

revolutionary party, the way was opened for Trotsky to join the

Bolsheviks; and, together with Lenin, Trotsky was to play a major role

not only in the October revolution and the subsequent Bolshevik

Government but also in the theoretical elaboration of what was to become

known as Marxist-Leninism.

While both Lenin and Trotsky argued that it was necessary to overthrow

the Provisional Government and establish a workers’ government through a

socialist-proletarian revolution, neither Lenin nor Trotsky saw

socialism as an immediate prospect in a backward country such as Russia.

The proletarian revolution that established the worker-peasant

dictatorship was seen as only the first step in the long transition to a

fully developed socialist society. As Trotsky was later to argue,[8]

even in an advanced capitalist country like the USA a proletarian

revolution would not be able to bring about a socialist society all at

once. A period of transition would be required that would allow the

further development of the forces of production necessary to provide the

material basis for a self-sustaining socialist society. In an advanced

capitalist country like the USA such a period of transition could take

several years; in a country as backward as Russia it would take decades,

and ultimately it would only be possible with the material support of a

socialist Europe.

For both Lenin and Trotsky then, Russia faced a prolonged period of

transition, a transition that was fraught with dangers. On the one side

stood the ever present danger of the restoration of capitalism either

through a counter-revolution backed by foreign military intervention or

through the re-emergence of bourgeois relations within the economy; on

the other side stood the danger of the increasing bureaucratization of

the workers’ state. As we shall see, Trotsky saw the key to warding off

all these great perils of Russia’s transition to socialism in the

overriding imperative of both increasing production and developing the

forces of production, while waiting for the world revolution.

In the first couple of years following the revolution many on the left

wing of the Bolsheviks, enthused by the revolutionary events of 1917 and

no doubt inspired by Lenin’s State and Revolution, which restated the

Marxist vision of a socialist society, saw Russia as being on the verge

of communism. For them the policy that had become known as War

Communism, under which money had been effectively abolished through

hyper-inflation and the market replaced by direct requisitioning in

accordance with the immediate needs of the war effort, was an immediate

prelude to the communism that would come with the end of the civil war

and the spread of the revolution to the rest of Europe.[9]

Both Lenin and Trotsky rejected such views from the left of the Party.

For them the policy of War Communism was little more than a set of

emergency measures forced on the revolutionary government which were

necessary to win the civil war and defeat armed foreign intervention.

For both Lenin and Trotsky there was no immediate prospect of socialism

let alone communism[10] in Russia, and in his polemics with the left at

this time Lenin argued that, given the backward conditions throughout

much of Russia, state capitalism would be a welcome advance. As he

states:

Reality tells us that state capitalism would be a step forward. If in a

small space of time we could achieve state capitalism, that would be a

victory. (Lenin’s Collected Works Vol. 27, p. 293)

Trotsky went even further, dismissing the growing complaints from the

left concerning the bureaucratization of the state and party apparatus,

he argued for the militarization of labour in order to maximize

production both for the war effort and for the post-war reconstruction.

As even Trotsky’s admirers have to admit, at this time Trotsky was

clearly on the ‘authoritarian wing’ of the party, and as such distinctly

to the right of Lenin.[11]

It is not surprising, given that he had seen War Communism as merely a

collection of emergency measures rather than the first steps to

communism, that once the civil war began to draw to a close and the

threat of foreign intervention began to recede, Trotsky was one of the

first to advocate the abandonment of War Communism and the restoration

of money and market relations. These proposals for a retreat to the

market were taken up in the New Economic Policy (NEP) that came to be

adopted in 1921.

The NEP and the Left Opposition

By 1921 the Bolshevik Government faced a severe political and economic

crisis. The policy of forced requisitioning had led to a mass refusal by

the peasantry to sow sufficient grain to feed the cities. Faced with

famine, thousands of workers simply returned to their relatives in the

countryside. At the same time industry had been run into the ground

after years of war and revolution. In this dire economic situation, the

ending of the civil war had given rise to mounting political unrest

amongst the working class, both within and outside the Party, which

threatened the very basis of the Bolshevik Government. Faced with

political and economic collapse the Bolshevik leadership came to the

conclusion that there was no other option but make a major retreat to

the market. The Bolshevik Government therefore abandoned War Communism

and adopted the New Economic Policy (NEP) which had been previously

mooted by Trotsky.

Under the NEP, state industry was broken up in to large trusts which

were to be run independently on strict commercial lines. At the same

time, a new deal was to be struck with the peasantry. Forced

requisitioning was to be replaced with a fixed agricultural tax, with

restrictions lifted on the hiring of labour and leasing of land to

encourage the rich and middle-income peasants to produce for the

market.[12] With the retreat from planning, the economic role of the

state was to be mainly restricted to re-establishing a stable currency

through orthodox financial polices and a balanced state budget.

For Trotsky, the NEP, like War Communism before it, was a policy

necessary to preserve the ‘workers’ state’ until it could be rescued by

revolution in Western Europe. As we have seen, Trotsky had, like Lenin,

foreseen an alliance with the peasantry as central to sustaining a

revolutionary government, and the NEP was primarily a means of

re-establishing the workers-peasants alliance which had been seriously

undermined by the excesses of War Communism. However, as we have also

seen, Trotsky had far less confidence in the revolutionary potential of

the peasantry than Lenin or other Bolshevik leaders. For Trotsky, the

NEP, by encouraging the peasants to produce for the market, held the

danger of creating a new class of capitalist farmers who would then

provide the social basis for a bourgeois counter-revolution and the

restoration of private property. As a consequence, from an early stage,

Trotsky began to advocate the development of comprehensive state

planning and a commitment to industrialization within the broad

framework of the NEP.

Although Trotsky’s emphasis on the importance of planning and

industrialization left him isolated within the Politburo, it placed him

alongside Preobrazhensky at the head of a significant minority within

the wider leadership of the Party and state apparatus which supported

such a shift in direction of the NEP, and which became known as the Left

Opposition. As a leading spokesman for the Left Opposition, and at the

same time one of the foremost economists within the Bolshevik Party,

Preobrazhensky came to develop the Theory of Primitive Socialist

Accumulation which served to underpin the arguments of the Left

Opposition, including Trotsky himself.

Preobrazhensky’s theory of primitive accumulation

As we have already noted, for the orthodox Marxism of the Second

International whereas capitalism was characterized by the operation of

market forces — or in more precise Marxist terms the ‘law of value’ —

socialism would be regulated by planning. From this Preobrazhensky

argued that the transition from capitalism to socialism had to be

understood in terms of the transition from the regulation of the economy

through the operation of the law of value to the regulation of the

economy through the operation of the ‘law of planning’. During the

period of transition both the law of value and the law of planning would

necessarily co-exist, each conditioning and competing with the other.

Under the New Economic Policy, most industrial production had remained

under state ownership and formed the state sector. However, as we have

seen, this state sector had been broken up into distinct trusts and

enterprises which were given limited freedom to trade with one another

and as such were run on a profit-and-loss basis. To this extent it could

be seen that the law of value still persisted within the state sector.

Yet for Preobrazhensky, the power of the state to direct investment and

override profit-and-loss criteria meant that the law of planning

predominated in the state sector. In contrast, agriculture was dominated

by small-scale peasant producers. As such, although the state was able

to regulate the procurement prices for agricultural produce, agriculture

was, for Preobrazhensky, dominated by the law of value.

From this Preobrazhensky argued that the struggle between the law of

value and the law of planning was at the same time the struggle between

the private sector of small-scale agricultural production and the state

sector of large-scale industrial production. Yet although large-scale

industrial production was both economically and socially more advanced

than that of peasant agriculture the sheer size of the peasant sector of

the Russian economy meant that there was no guarantee that the law of

planning would prevail. Indeed, for Preobrazhensky, under the policy of

optimum and balanced growth advocated by Bukharin and the right of the

Party and sanctioned by the Party leadership, there was a real danger

that the state sector could be subordinated to a faster growing

agricultural sector and with this the law of value would prevail.

To avert the restoration of capitalism Preobrazhensky argued that the

workers’ state had to tilt the economic balance in favour of

accumulation within the state sector. By rapid industrialization the

state sector could be expanded which would both increase the numbers of

the proletariat and enhance the ascendancy of the law of planning. Once

a comprehensive industrial base had been established, agriculture could

be mechanized and through a process of collectivization agriculture

could be eventually brought within the state sector and regulated by the

law of planning.

Yet rapid industrialization required huge levels of investment which

offered little prospects of returns for several years. For

Preobrazhensky there appeared little hope of financing such levels of

investment within the state sector itself without squeezing the working

class — an option that would undermine the very social base of a

workers’ government. The only option was to finance industrial

investment out of the economic surplus produced in the agricultural

sector by the use of tax and pricing policies.

This policy of siphoning off the economic surplus produced in the

agricultural sector was to form the basis for a period of Primitive

Socialist Accumulation. Preobrazhensky argued that just as capitalism

had to undergo a period primitive capitalist accumulation, in which it

plundered pre-capitalist modes of production, before it could establish

itself on a self-sustaining basis, so, before a socialist society could

establish itself on a self-sustaining basis, it too would have to go

through an analogous period of primitive socialist accumulation, at

least in a backward country such as Russia.

The rise of Stalin

With the decline in Lenin’s health and his eventual death in 1924, the

question of planning and industrialization became a central issue in the

power struggle for the succession to the leadership of the Party. Yet

while he was widely recognized within the Party as Lenin’s natural

successor, and as such had been given Lenin’s own blessing, Trotsky was

reluctant to challenge the emerging troika of Stalin, Kamenev and

Zinoviev, who, in representing the conservative forces within the state

and Party bureaucracy, sought to maintain the NEP as it was. For

Trotsky, the overriding danger was the threat of a bourgeois

counter-revolution. As a result he was unwilling to split the Party or

else undermine the ‘centrist’ troika and allow the right of the Party to

come to power, enabling the restoration of capitalism through the back

door.

Furthermore, despite Stalin’s ability repeatedly to out-manoeuvre both

Trotsky and the Left Opposition through his control of the Party

bureaucracy, Trotsky could take comfort from the fact that after the

resolution of the first ‘scissors crisis’[13] in 1923 the leadership of

the Party progressively adopted a policy of planning and

industrialization, although without fully admitting it.

By 1925, having silenced Trotsky and much of the Left Opposition, Stalin

had consolidated sufficient power to oust both Kamenev and Zinoviev[14]

and force them to join Trotsky in opposition. Having secured the

leadership of the Party, Stalin now openly declared a policy of rapid

industrialization under the banner of ‘building socialism in one

country’ with particular emphasis on building up heavy industry. Yet at

first Stalin refused to finance such an industrialization strategy by

squeezing the peasants. Since industrialization had to be financed from

within the industrial state sector itself, investment in heavy industry

could only come at the expense of investment in light industry which

produced the tools and consumer goods demanded by the peasantry. As a

result a ‘goods famine’ emerged as light industry lagged behind the

growth of peasant incomes and the growth of heavy industry. Unable to

buy goods from the cities the peasants simply hoarded grain so that,

despite record harvests in 1927 and 1928, the supply of food sold to the

cities fell dramatically.

This crisis of the New Economic Policy brought with it a political

crisis within the leadership of the Party and the State. All opposition

within the Party had to be crushed. Trotsky and Zinoviev were expelled

from the Party, with Trotsky eventually being forced into exile, leaving

Stalin to assume supreme power in both the Party and the state. To

consolidate and sustain his power Stalin was obliged to launch a reign

of terror within the Communist Party. This terror culminated in a series

of purges and show trials in the 1930s which led to the execution of

many of the leading Bolsheviks of the revolution.

Perhaps rather ironically, while Stalin had defended the New Economic

Policy to the last, he now set out to resolve the economic crisis by

adopting the erstwhile policies of the Left Opposition albeit pushing

them to an unenvisaged extreme.[15] Under the five year plans, the first

of which began in 1928, all economic considerations were subordinated to

the overriding objective of maximizing growth and industrialization.

Increasing physical output as fast as possible was now to be the number

one concern, with the question of profit and loss of individual

enterprises reduced to a secondary consideration at best. At the same

time agriculture was to be transformed through a policy of forced

collectivization. Millions of peasants were herded into collectives and

state farms which, under state direction, could apply modern mechanized

farming methods.

It was in the face of this about turn in economic policy, and the

political terror that accompanied it, that Trotsky was obliged to

develop his critique of Stalinist Russia and with this the fate of the

Russian Revolution. It was now no longer sufficient for Trotsky to

simply criticize the economic policy of the leadership as he had done

during the time of the Left Opposition. Instead Trotsky had to broaden

his criticisms to explain how the very course of the revolution had

ended up in the bureaucratic nightmare that was Stalinist Russia.

Trotsky’s new critique was to find its fullest expression in his seminal

work The Revolution Betrayed which was published in 1936.

Trotsky and the Leninist conception of party, class and the state

As we shall see, in The Revolution Betrayed, Trotsky concludes that,

with the failure of the revolution elsewhere in the world, the workers’

state established by the Russian Revolution had degenerated through the

bureaucratization of both the Party and the state. To understand how

Trotsky was able to come to this conclusion while remaining within

Marxist and Leninist orthodoxy, we must first consider how Trotsky

appropriated and developed the Leninist conception of the state, party

and class.

From almost the very beginning of the Soviet Union there had been those

both inside and outside the Party who had warned against the increasing

bureaucratization of the revolution. In the early years, Trotsky had

little sympathy for such complaints concerning bureaucratization and

authoritarianism in the Party and the state. At this time, the immediate

imperative of crushing the counter-revolutionary forces, and the

long-term aim of building the material basis for socialism, both

demanded a strong state and a resolute Party which were seen as

necessary to maximize production and develop the productive forces. For

Trotsky at this time, the criticisms of bureaucratization and

authoritarianism, whether advanced by those on the right or the left,

could only serve to undermine the vital role of the Party and the state

in the transition to socialism.

However, having been forced into opposition and eventual exile Trotsky

was forced to develop his own critique of the bureaucratization of the

revolution, but in doing so he was anxious to remain within the basic

Leninist conceptions of the state, party and class which he had

resolutely defended against earlier critics.

Following Engels, theorists within the Second International had placed

much store in the notion that what distinguished Marxism from all former

socialist theories was that it was neither an utopian socialism nor an

ethical socialism but a scientific socialism. As a consequence, Marxism

tended to be viewed as a body of positive scientific knowledge that

existed apart from the immediate experiences and practice of the working

class. Indeed, Marx’s own theory of commodity fetishism seemed to

suggest that the social relations of capitalist society inevitably

appeared in forms that served to obscure their own true exploitative

nature.[16] So, while the vast majority of the working class may feel

instinctively that they were alienated and exploited, capitalism would

still appear to them as being based on freedom and equality. Thus,

rather than seeing wage-labour in general as being exploitative, they

would see themselves being cheated by a particular wage deal. So, rather

than calling for the abolition of wage-labour, left to themselves the

working class would call for a ‘fair day’s pay for a fair day’s work’.

Trapped within the routines of their everyday life, the majority of the

working class would not be able by themselves to go beyond such a

sectional and trade union perspective. Hence one of the central tasks of

a workers’ party was to educate the working class in the science of

Marxism. It would only be through a thorough knowledge of Marxism that

the working class would be able to reach class consciousness and as such

be in a position to understand its historic role in overthrowing

capitalism and bringing about a socialist society.

In adapting this orthodox view of the Party to conditions prevailing in

Tsarist Russia Lenin had pushed it to a particular logical extreme. It

was in What is to be Done? that Lenin had first set out his conception

of a revolutionary party based on democratic centralism. In this work

Lenin had advocated a party made up of dedicated and disciplined

professional revolutionaries in which, while the overall policy and

direction of the party would be made through discussion and democratic

decision, in the everyday running of the party the lower organs of the

party would be completely subordinated to those of the centre. At the

time, Trotsky had strongly criticized What is to be Done?, arguing that

Lenin’s conception of the revolutionary party implied the substitution

of the party for the class.

Indeed, Trotsky’s rejection of Lenin’s conception of the party has often

been seen as the main dividing line between Lenin and Trotsky right up

until their eventual reconciliation in the summer of 1917. Thus, it has

been argued that, while the young Trotsky had sided with Lenin and the

Bolsheviks against the Mensheviks over the crucial issue of the need for

an alliance with the peasantry, he had been unable to accept Lenin’s

authoritarian position on the question of organization. It was only in

the revolutionary situation of 1917 that Trotsky had come over to

Lenin’s viewpoint concerning the organization of the Party. However,

there is no doubt that Trotsky accepted the basic premise of What is to

be Done?, which was rooted in Marxist orthodoxy, that class

consciousness had to be introduced from outside the working class by

intellectuals educated in the ‘science of Marxism’. There is also little

doubt that from an early date Trotsky accepted the need for a

centralized party. The differences between Lenin and Trotsky over the

question of organization were for the most part a difference of

emphasis.[17] What seems to have really kept Lenin and Trotsky apart for

so long was not so much the question of organization but Trotsky’s

‘conciliationism’. Whereas Lenin always argued for a sharp

differentiation between the Bolsheviks and the Mensheviks to ensure

political and theoretical clarity, Trotsky had always sought to re-unite

the two wings of Russian social democracy.

To some extent Lenin’s formulation of democratic centralism in What is

to be Done? was determined by the repressive conditions then prevailing

in Tsarist Russia; but it was also premised on the perceived cultural

backwardness of the Russian working class which, it was thought, would

necessarily persist even after the revolution. Unlike Germany, the vast

majority of the Russian working class were semi-literate and uneducated.

Indeed, many, if not a majority of the Russian working class were fresh

out of the countryside and, for socialist intellectuals like Lenin and

Trotsky, retained an uncouth parochial peasant mentality. As such there

seemed little hope of educating the vast majority of the working class

beyond a basic trade union consciousness.

However, there were a minority within the working class, particularly

among its more established and skilled strata, who could, through their

own efforts and under the tutelage of the party, attain a clear class

consciousness. It was these more advanced workers, which, organized

through the party, would form the revolutionary vanguard of the

proletariat that would be the spearhead of the revolution. Of course

this was not to say that rest of the working class, or even the

peasantry, could not be revolutionary. On the contrary, for Lenin and

the Bolsheviks, revolution was only possible through the mass

involvement of the peasants and the working class. But the instinctive

revolutionary will of the masses had to be given leadership and

direction by the party. Only through the leadership of the proletarian

vanguard organized in a revolutionary party would it be possible to

mediate and reconcile the immediate and often competing individual and

sectional interests of workers and peasants with the overall and

long-term interests of the working class in building socialism.

For Lenin, the first task in the transition to socialism had to be the

seizure of state power. During his polemics against those on the right

of the Bolshevik Party who had, during the summer of 1917, feared that

the overthrow of the bourgeois Provisional Government and the seizure of

state power might prove premature, Lenin had returned to Engels’

conception of the state in the stage of socialism.

Against both Lassalle’s conception of state socialism and the

anarchists’ call for the immediate abolition of the state, Engels had

argued that, while it would be necessary to retain the state as means of

maintaining the dictatorship of the working class until the danger of

counter-revolution had been finally overcome, a socialist state would be

radically different from that which had existed before. Under capitalism

the state had to stand above society in order both to mediate between

competing capitalist interests and to impose the rule of the bourgeois

minority over the majority of the population. As a result, the various

organs of the state, such as the army, the police and the administrative

apparatus had to be separated from the population at large and run by a

distinct class of specialists. Under socialism the state would already

be in the process of withering away with the breaking down of its

separation from society. Thus police and army would be replaced by a

workers’ militia, while the state administration would be carried out

increasingly by the population as a whole.

Rallying the left wing of the Bolshevik Party around this vision of

socialism, Lenin had argued that with sufficient revolutionary will on

the part of the working masses and with the correct leadership of the

party it would be possible to smash the state and begin immediately the

construction of Engels’ ‘semi-state’ without too much difficulty.[18]

Already the basis for the workers’ and peasants’ state could be seen in

the mass organizations of the working class — the factory committees,

the soviets and the trade unions, and by the late summer of 1917 most of

these had fallen under the leadership of the Bolsheviks.[19] Yet this

conception of the state which inspired the October revolution did not

last long into the new year.

Confronted by the realities of consolidating the power of the new

workers’ and peasants’ government in the backward economic and cultural

conditions then prevailing in Russia, it was not long before Lenin was

obliged to reconsider his own over-optimistic assessments for the

transition to socialism that he had adopted just prior to the October

revolution. As a result, within weeks of coming to power it became clear

to Lenin that the fledging Soviet State could not afford the time or

resources necessary to educate the mass of workers and peasants to the

point where they could be drawn into direct participation in the

administration of the state. Nor could the economy afford a prolonged

period of disruption that would follow the trials and errors of any

experiment in workers’ self-management. Consequently, Lenin soon

concluded that there could be no question of moving immediately towards

Engels’ conception of a ‘semi-state’, which after all had been envisaged

in the context of a socialist revolution being made in an advanced

capitalist country. On the contrary, the overriding imperative of

developing the forces of production, which alone could provide the

material and cultural conditions necessary for a socialist society,

demanded not a weakening, but a strengthening of the state — albeit

under the strict leadership of the vanguard of the proletariat organized

within the party.

So now, for Lenin, administrative and economic efficiency demanded the

concentration of day to day decision making into the hands of

specialists and the adoption of the most advanced methods of ‘scientific

management’.[20] The introduction of such measures as one-man management

and the adoption of methods of scientific management not only undermined

workers’ power and initiative over the immediate process of production,

but also went hand-in-hand with the employment of thousands of former

capitalist managers and former Tsarist administrators.

Yet, while such measures served to re-impose bourgeois relations of

production, Lenin argued that such capitalist economic relations could

be counter-balanced by the political control exercised over the

state-industrial apparatus by the mass organizations of the working

class under the leadership of the Party. Indeed, as we have already

noted, against the objections from the left that his policies amounted

to the introduction not of socialism but of state capitalism, Lenin,

returning to the orthodox formulation, retorted that the basis of

socialism was nothing more than ‘state capitalism under workers’

control’, and that, given the woeful backwardness of the Russian

economy, any development of state capitalism could only be a welcome

advance.

As the economic situation deteriorated with the onset of the civil war

and the intervention of the infamous ‘fourteen imperialist armies’,[21]

the contradictions between the immediate interests of the workers and

peasants and those of the socialist revolution could only grow. The need

to maintain the political power of the Party led at first to the

exclusion of all other worker and peasant parties from the workers’ and

peasants’ government and then to the extension of the Red Terror, which

had originally been aimed at counter-revolutionary bourgeois parties, to

all those who opposed the Bolsheviks. At the same time power was

gradually shifted from the mass organizations of the working class and

concentrated within the central organs of the Party.[22] As a result it

was the Party which had to increasingly serve as the check on the state

and the guarantee of its proletarian character.

The degeneration of the revolution

There is no doubt that Trotsky shared such Leninist conceptions

concerning the state, party and class, and with them the view that the

transition to socialism required both the strengthening of the state and

the re-imposition of capitalist relations of production. Indeed, this

perspective can be clearly seen in the way he carried out the task of

constructing the Red Army.[23] What is more, Trotsky did not balk at the

implications of these Leninist conceptions and the policies that

followed from them. Indeed, Trotsky fully supported the increasing

suppression of opposition both inside and outside the Party which

culminated with his backing for the suspension of Party factions at the

Tenth Party Congress in 1921 and his personal role in crushing the

Kronstadt rebellion in February 1921.

It can be argued that Trotsky was fully implicated in the Leninist

conceptions and policies, and that such conceptions and policies

provided both the basis and precedent for Stalinism and the show trials

of the 1930s. However, for Trotsky and his followers there was a

qualitative difference between the consolidation of power and repression

of opposition that were adopted as temporary expedients made necessary

due to the civil war and the threat of counter-revolution, and the

permanent and institutional measures that were later adopted by Stalin.

For Trotsky, this qualitative difference was brought about by the

process of bureaucratic degeneration that arose with the failure of

world revolution to save the Soviet Revolution from isolation.

In his final years Lenin had become increasingly concerned with the

bureaucratization of both the state and Party apparatus. For Lenin, the

necessity of employing non-proletarian bourgeois specialists and

administrators, who would inevitably tend to work against the revolution

whether consciously or unconsciously, meant that there would be a

separation of the state apparatus from the working class and with this

the emergence of bureaucratic tendencies. However, as a counter to these

bureaucratic tendencies stood the Party. The Party, being rooted in the

most advanced sections of the working class, acted as a bridge between

the state and the working class, and, through the imposition of the

‘Party Line’, ensured the state remained essentially a ‘workers’ and

peasants’ state’.

Yet the losses of the civil war left the Party lacking some of its

finest working class militants, and those who remained had been drafted

into the apparatus of the Party and state as full time officials. At the

same time Lenin feared that more and more non-proletarian careerist

elements were joining the Party. As a result, shortly before his death

Lenin could complain that only 10 per cent of the Party membership were

still at the factory bench. Losing its footing in the working class

Lenin could only conclude that the Party itself was becoming

bureaucratized.

In developing his own critique of Stalin, Trotsky took up these

arguments which had been first put forward by Lenin. Trotsky further

emphasized that, with the exhaustion of revolutionary enthusiasm, by the

1920s even the most advanced proletarian elements within the state and

Party apparatus had begun to succumb to the pressures of

bureaucratization. This process was greatly accelerated by the severe

material shortages which encouraged state and Party officials, of

whatever class origin, to place their own collective and individual

interests as part of the bureaucracy above those of working masses.

For Trotsky, the rise to power of the troika of Stalin, Kamenev and

Zinoviev following Lenin’s death marked the point where this process of

bureaucratization of the state and Party had reached and ensnared the

very leadership of the Party itself.[24] Drawing a parallel with the

course of the French Revolution, Trotsky argued that this point

represented the transition to the Russian Thermidor — a period of

conservative reaction arising from the revolution itself. As such, for

Trotsky, Russia remained a workers’ state, but one whose

proletarian-socialist policies had now become distorted by the

privileged and increasingly conservative strata of the proletariat that

formed the bureaucracy, and through which state policy was both

formulated and implemented.

For Trotsky, these conservative-bureaucratic distortions of state policy

were clearly evident in both the internal and external affairs.

Conservative-bureaucratic distortions were exemplified in foreign policy

by the abandonment of proletarian internationalism, which had sought to

spread the revolution beyond the borders of the former Russian empire,

in favour of the policy of ‘building socialism in one country’. For the

bureaucracy the disavowal of proletarian internationalism opened the way

for the normalization of diplomatic relations with the capitalist powers

throughout the rest of the world. For Trotsky, the abandonment of

proletarian internationalism diminished the prospects of world

revolution which was ultimately the only hope for the Russian Revolution

if it was to avoid isolation in a capitalist world and further

degeneration culminating in the eventual restoration of capitalism in

Russia. Domestically, the policy of building socialism in one country

had its counterpart in the persistence of the cautious economic policies

of balanced and optimal growth represented by the continuation of the

NEP, which for Trotsky, as we have already seen, threatened the rise of

a new bourgeoisie amongst the rich peasantry and with this the danger of

capitalist restoration.

However, just as the Thermidor period of conservative reaction had given

way to the counter-revolution of Napoleon Bonaparte which imposed the

dictatorship of one man, so the Russian Thermidor, which ended with the

crisis in the NEP, gave rise to Stalin as the sole dictator. For Trotsky

then, the dictatorship of Stalin represented a ‘Bonapartist

counter-revolution’ from within the revolution itself, which marked the

final stage in the degeneration of the Russian workers’ state. Yet, just

as Bonaparte’s counter-revolution was a political revolution which while

restoring the monarchy did so by preserving the transformation of

property relations achieved by the revolution, so likewise Stalin’s

counter-revolution preserved the fundamental gains of the Russian

Revolution in that it maintained public ownership of the means of

production along with state planning. Indeed, while Trotsky dismissed

Stalin’s claims that, with the collectivization of agriculture and

introduction of comprehensive centralized planning of the five year

plans, Russia had become fully socialist, he accepted that these were

major achievements in the transition towards socialism.

So, for Trotsky, however degenerated Stalin’s Russia had become, it

remained a workers’ state and as such preserved the fundamental gains of

the revolution. By preserving public ownership of the means of

production and state planning, which opened the way for the rapid

development of the forces of production, Stalin’s regime could be seen

to develop the objective social and material conditions necessary for

socialism. As such, for all its crimes, Stalin’s Russia objectively

represented a crucial historic advance over all capitalist countries.

Therefore, for Trotsky, Stalin’s Russia demanded critical support from

all revolutionaries.[25]

Yet, as we shall see, the increasing tension between the barbarism of

Stalin’s regime, which condemned millions of workers, peasants and

revolutionaries (including many of Trotsky’s own former comrades) to

death or hard labour, and Trotsky’s insistence of its objectively

progressive character, prompted many, including Trotsky’s own ardent

followers, to question his notion that Stalinist Russia was a

degenerated workers’ state.

The obvious objection was that the totalitarianism of Stalin’s regime

was virtually indistinguishable from that of Hitler’s which had also

gone a long way towards nationalizing the economy and bring it under

state planning. Trotsky dismissed any resemblance between Stalin’s

Russia and Hitler’s Germany as being merely superficial. For Trotsky,

during its period of decline capitalism would necessarily be forced into

an increasing statification of the economy which would give rise to

authoritarian and fascist regimes. This process towards state capitalism

had already reached an extreme in such countries as Italy under

Mussolini and Germany under Hitler but could also be seen in the growing

statism and authoritarianism in other ‘democratic’ countries such as

France. However, such statification of the economy and the growth in

public ownership of the means of production was being carried out as a

last ditch effort to preserve its opposite, private property. Stalin’s

Russia, on the other hand, was developing on the very basis of the

public ownership of the means of production itself. Stalinist Russia had

crossed the historical Rubicon of the socialist revolution. Thus, while

it may have appeared that Stalin’s Russia was similar to that of

Hitler’s Germany, for Trotsky they were essentially very different.

Bureaucracy and class

A more penetrating objection to Trotsky’s critical defence of Stalinist

Russia concerned the question of the nature of the Stalinist

bureaucracy. Against Trotsky, it could be argued that under Stalin, if

not before, the Soviet bureaucracy had established itself as a new

exploitative ruling class. If this was the case then it could no longer

be maintained that Stalinist Russia was in any sense a workers’ state,

however degenerated. Further, if the bureaucracy was not simply a strata

of the proletariat that had become separated from the rest of its class,

but a class in itself, it could no longer be claimed that the

bureaucracy ultimately ruled in the interests of the working class,

albeit in a distorted manner. The bureaucracy could only rule in its own

narrow and minority class interests. As a result it could be concluded

that either Russia had reverted back to a form of state capitalism, or

else had given rise to a new unknown mode of production; either way

there could be no longer any obligation for revolutionaries to give

Stalin’s monstrous regime ‘critical support’.

Given that this charge that the Stalinist’s bureaucracy constituted a

distinct exploitative class threatened to undermine the very basis of

his theory of Russia as a degenerated workers’ state, Trotsky was at

great pains to refute it. Of course, it was central to Trotsky’s

critique of the Soviet Union under Stalin that the bureaucracy had

emerged as a distinct social group that had come to dominate the working

class. Indeed, as Trotsky himself put it, the bureaucracy constituted ‘a

commanding and privileged social stratum’. Yet despite this Trotsky

denied that the bureaucracy could in any way constitute a distinct

exploitative class.

In denying that the Soviet bureaucracy constituted a distinct social

class Trotsky was able to directly invoke the orthodox Marxist

conceptions of class and bureaucracy. In doing so Trotsky was able to

claim at the same time that he was defending Marxism itself against the

revisionist arguments of his opponents; but, as we shall see, by

invoking the authority of Marx, Trotsky was spared the task of setting

out the basis of his own conception of the nature of class and

bureaucracy with any degree of clarity.

For both Marx and Engels social classes were constituted through the

social relations that necessarily arose out of the particular mode of

production upon which a given society was based. Indeed, for Marx and

Engels, the specific nature of any class society was determined by the

manner in which the exploitative classes extracted surplus labour from

the direct producers.

For orthodox Marxism, such social relations were interpreted primarily

in terms of property relations.[26] Hence, within the capitalist mode of

production the essential social relations of production were seen

primarily in terms of the private ownership of the means of production.

While the capitalist class was constituted through its private ownership

of the means of production, the working class was constituted through

its non-ownership of the means of production. Being excluded from the

ownership of the means of production, the working class, once it has

consumed its means of subsistence, had no option but to sell its labour

power to the capitalist class if it was to survive. On the other hand,

in buying the labour power of the working class the capitalist class

obtained the rights of possession of all the wealth that the working

class created with its labour. Once it had paid the costs of production,

including the costs of reproducing labour-power, the capitalist class

was left in possession of the surplus-labour created by the working

class, as the direct producers, in the specific social form of

surplus-value.[27]

On the basis of this orthodox interpretation of the nature of class,

backed up by various political writings of both Marx and Engels, it was

not hard to argue that, at least within capitalism, the state

bureaucracy could not constitute a distinct social class. The state

bureaucracy could clearly be seen to stand outside the immediate process

of production and circulation, and as such was not directly constituted

out of the social relations of production. Even insofar as the state was

able to go beyond its mere function as the ‘executive committee of the

bourgeoisie’ so that the state bureaucracy could act as a distinct

social group which was able to pursue its own ends and interests, the

state bureaucracy still did not constitute a distinct class since its

social position was not based in private property but in its

extra-economic political and administrative functions. So, even insofar

as the state bureaucracy was able to appropriate a share in the

surplus-value it did so not by virtue of its private ownership of the

means of production or capital but through extra-economic means such as

taxation and tariffs.

So, at least under capitalism, it seemed clear that the state

bureaucracy could not constitute a distinct social class. But what of

the transition from capitalism to socialism? For Trotsky, following

Marxist orthodoxy, the question was clear cut. The revolution of 1917

had swept away the private ownership of the means of production and with

it the basis for the exploitation of ‘man by man’ which had been

perfected under capitalism. With the nationalization of the means of

production and the introduction of social planning there was no basis

for the state bureaucracy to exist as an exploitative class.

Trotsky made clear his position at the very outset of his consideration

of the social position of the Soviet bureaucracy:

Classes are characterized by their position in the social system of

economy, and primarily by their relation to the means of production. In

civilized societies, property relations are validated by laws. The

nationalization of land, the means of industrial production, transport

and exchange, together with the monopoly of foreign trade, constitute

the basis of the social structure. Through these relations, established

by the proletarian revolution, the nature of the Soviet Union as a

proletarian state is for us basically defined. (The Revolution Betrayed,

p. 248)

To this extent Trotsky’s position is little different from that of

Stalin: the abolition of private property ends the exploitation of ‘man

by man’.[28]

Of course, Trotsky could not simply remain content with Stalin’s denial

that the Soviet bureaucracy constituted an exploitative class. Indeed

Stalin’s position even denied the existence of the bureaucracy as a

distinct social group. To make his critique of Stalin’s Russia, Trotsky

had to look beyond the formal and judicial transformation of property

relations brought about by the Russian Revolution in 1917. Trotsky

recognized that, although the nationalization decrees that followed the

October revolution had formally and juridically transferred the

ownership of the means of production from the hands of private

capitalists to society as a whole, this was not the same as the real

transfer of the ownership to the people as a whole. The nationalization

of production had merely transferred the ownership of the means of

production from the capitalist to the state, which, while a necessary

step in the transition to socialism, was not the same as real public

ownership. For Trotsky, in a real sense the ‘state owns the economy and

the bureaucracy owns the state’.

As Trotsky himself points out, the real property relations, as opposed

to the formal and juridical property relations, is a social reality

acutely apparent to the Soviet worker:

“The worker in our country is not a wage slave and is not a seller of a

commodity called labour-power. He is a free workman” (Pravda). For the

present period this unctuous formula is unpermissible bragging. The

transfer of the factories to the state changed the situation of the

worker only juridically. In reality, he is compelled to live in want and

work a definite amount of hours for a definite wage. Those hopes which

the worker formerly placed in the party and the trade unions, he

transferred after the revolution to the state created by him. But the

useful functioning of this implement turned out to be limited by the

level of technique and culture. In order to raise this level, the new

state resorted to the old methods of pressure upon the muscles and

nerves of the worker. There grew up a corps of slave drivers. The

management of industry became super-bureaucratic. The workers lost all

influence whatever upon management of the factory. With piecework

payment, hard conditions of material existence, lack of free movement,

with terrible police repression penetrating the life of every factory,

it is hard indeed for the worker to feel himself a free workman. (The

Revolution Betrayed, p. 241)

For Trotsky, the overriding need to develop the productive forces in the

backward conditions prevailing in Russia required the state ownership of

production. Through the state the Soviet bureaucracy had, in a sense,

taken real possession of the means of production and as such had come to

constitute a distinct social group. Just as Marx and Engels had observed

that under capitalism the state bureaucracy could in certain situations

obtain a relative degree of autonomy from the bourgeois ruling class, so

in the transition to socialism the state bureaucracy was able to obtain

a relative autonomy from the proletarian ruling class. Indeed, Trotsky

argues that the autonomy of the Soviet bureaucracy is all the greater

than its counterparts under capitalism since the working class is not an

inherently dominating class.

Thus, while the revolution had formally freed the worker from the

dictates of private property and made him a co-owner of the means of

production, in reality the worker found himself in a situation that

seemed little different from that under capitalism. Indeed, subordinated

to the demands of the state bureaucracy the worker may well feel just as

exploited as he had been under capitalism. But for Trotsky, although the

worker may subjectively feel exploited, objectively he was not. The

plight of the workers’ situation was not due to exploitation but to the

objective need to develop the forces of production. Of course, like all

bureaucracies the Soviet bureaucracy could abuse its position to obtain

material and personal advantages and this could reinforce the workers’

perception that the bureaucracy was exploiting them. But for Trotsky

such material and personal advantages were not due to the exploitation

of the working class by the state bureaucracy, but due to the

bureaucracy’s privileged position within the workers’ state.

Hence while the nationalization of the means of production by the

workers’ state had ended capitalist relations of production and thereby

ended exploitation, the backward conditions in Russia had allowed the

Soviet bureaucracy to gain a privileged and commanding position and

maintain bourgeois norms of distribution. The bureaucracy no more

exploited the working class than monopolist capitalists exploited other

capitalists by charging monopoly prices. All the Soviet bureaucracy did

was redistribute the surplus-labour of society in its own favour. This

is perhaps best illustrated by Trotsky’s own analogy with share-holding

in a market economy:

If we translate socialist relations, for illustration, into the language

of the market, we may represent the citizen as a stockholder in a

company which owns the wealth of country. If property belonged to all

the people, that would presume equal distribution of “shares”, and

consequently a right to the same dividend for all “shareholders”. The

citizens participate in the national enterprise, however, not only as

“shareholders”, but also as producers. On the lower stage of communism,

which we have agreed to call socialism, payments for labour are still

made according to bourgeois norms — that is, dependence upon skill and

intensity etc. The theoretical income of each citizen is thus composed

of two parts, a + b — that is, dividend plus wages. The higher the

technique and the more complete the organization of industry, the

greater is the place occupied by a as against b, and the less is the

influence of individual differences of labour upon the standard of

living. From the fact that wage differences in the Soviet Union are not

less, but greater than in capitalist countries, it must be inferred that

the shares of the Soviet citizen are not equally distributed, and that

in his income the dividend as well as the wage payment are unequal.

Whereas the unskilled labour receives only b, the minimum payment which

under similar conditions he would receive in a capitalist enterprise,

the Stakhanovist or bureaucrat receives 2a + b, or 3a + b, etc., while b

also in turn may become 2b, 3b, etc. The differences in income are

determined, in other words, not only by differences of individual

productiveness, but also by a masked appropriation of the products of

labour of others. The privileged minority of shareholders is living at

the expense of the deprived majority. (The Revolution Betrayed, p. 240).

So, for Trotsky, insofar as the revolution of 1917 had abolished the

private ownership of the means of production the basis for socialist

relations of production had been established. However, in the backward

conditions in which the revolution had been made, bourgeois norms of

distribution still persisted and had become exacerbated by the growing

power of the state bureaucracy in such conditions.

Trotsky and the question of transition

Trotsky’s attempt to develop a Marxist critique of Stalin’s Russia,

while at the same time denying that the Soviet bureaucracy constituted

an exploitative class, was far from being unproblematic. In developing

this critique of the Soviet Union through his polemics against

Stalinists on the one hand, and the left communists and some of his own

followers on the other, Trotsky had little time to present in detail the

theoretical foundations of his arguments. Instead, as we have already

noted, Trotsky for the most part appealed to the commonly accepted

tenets of orthodox Marxism. As a consequence Trotsky failed to set out

clearly his ideas on such fundamental matters as the connection between

the productive forces and the social relations of production, the social

relations of production and property relations, and between production

and distribution. As we have already indicated, perhaps the most

important weakness of Trotsky is his acceptance of the orthodox

reduction of social relations of production to simple property

relations, we shall briefly examine this now.

As we have seen, not only did Trotsky interpret the social relations of

production primarily in terms of property relations but, along with

Stalin, insisted that these property relations had to be given an

immediate expression in the juridical property relations that regulated

society. As Trotsky asserts: ‘In all civilized societies, property

relations are validated by laws’. But, as we have also seen, in order to

press home his critique of the Soviet bureaucracy Trotsky had to go

beyond the apparent legal property relations of the Soviet Union and in

doing so, at least implicitly, acknowledge that real property relations

may differ from their formal and juridical expression.

Of course, this disjunction between real and formal property relations

is not unknown in capitalism itself. With the development of the modern

corporation from the end of the nineteenth century there has arisen a

growing divergence between the ownership of the means of production and

their management. The modern joint stock company is formally owned by

its shareholders while the actual running of the company is left to the

senior management who can be said to have the real possession of the

means of production. For Trotsky, the social relations of production

would be transformed simply by nationalizing the firm so that it is run

for society as a whole rather than for a few shareholders. With

nationalization, legal ownership is transferred to the state while the

real possession of means of production may remain in the hands of the

management or bureaucracy. Hence, just as under certain circumstances

the management of joint stock company cream off some of the profits in

the form of huge salaries and share options, so under conditions of

underdevelopment the management of state enterprises may also be in a

position to cream of the economic surplus produced by the nationalized

industry.

Yet few would deny that while the management of a capitalist enterprise

may not themselves legally own the firm they still function as

capitalists with regard to the workers. The management functions to

extract surplus-value and as a consequence they function as the actual

exploiters of the workers. Within the Soviet enterprise the workers may

formally own the means of production but in real terms they are

dispossessed. They have to sell their labour-power for a wage. On the

other side the ‘socialist’ management are obliged to extract

surplus-labour just as much as their capitalist counterparts, as even

Trotsky admits. It would seem that the actual social relations of

production between the workers who are really dispossessed and the

management who have real possession of the means of production is the

same. What has changed is the merely the formal property relations which

affects the distribution of the surplus-labour, not its production.

In this view Trotsky’s position becomes inverted: the revolution of 1917

only went so far as to socialize the distribution of the economic

surplus while leaving the social relations of production as capitalist.

This line of argument provides the basis for a telling critique, not

only against Trotsky’s theory of a degenerated workers’ state, but also

the ‘politicism’ of the entire Leninist project which had been inherited

from the orthodox Marxism of the Second International.[29] Indeed, as we

shall see, this line of argument has often been taken up in various

guises by many anarchists and left communists opposed to the Leninist

conception of the USSR and the Russian Revolution. Yet, if we are to

grasp what has given Trotsky’s theory of a degenerated workers’ state

its hold as one of the principle critiques of the USSR it is necessary

to consider the importance of ‘transition’ to Trotsky.

As we have seen, the notion that the Soviet Union was in a state of

transition from capitalism to socialism was central for Trotsky. Indeed,

it is this very notion of transition which allowed Trotsky to defend the

orthodox Leninist and Marxist positions alongside Stalin, while at the

same time distancing himself sufficiently from Stalin to make a thorough

critique of the USSR. As we have already pointed out, both Stalin and

Trotsky supported the orthodox position that the real social relations

of production of any established mode of production would have to find

their immediate legal and formal expression. Yet, while Stalin asserted

that with the five year plans and the collectivization of agriculture

the USSR had become socialist, Trotsky insisted that the USSR was still

in a state of transition from capitalism to socialism. Since the USSR

was in transition from one mode of production to another, the formal and

legal property relations could be in advance of the real relations of

production. The disjunction between the real and formal property

relations of the USSR was the result of the real contradictions in the

transformation of capitalist social relations into those of socialism.

Of course for Trotsky, sooner or later formal property relations would

have to be brought into conformity with the real social relations of

production. Either the development of the productive forces would

eventually allow the formal property relations to be given a real

socialist content or else the USSR would collapse back into capitalism

with the restoration of the private ownership of the means of

production.

Furthermore, for Trotsky, it was this contradiction between the formal

property relations and the social relations of production that placed

the bureaucracy in a precarious and unstable position which prevented it

from constituting itself as a class. To defend its position the

bureaucracy had to defend state property and develop the forces of

production. Yet, while the social position of the individual capitalist

was rooted in the private ownership of the means of production that was

backed by law, the individual bureaucrat was simply an employee of the

state who owed his or her position to those higher up in the

bureaucracy. Unable to reproduce itself over the generations through

inheritance Trotsky believed that the Soviet bureaucracy could not last

long. The Soviet bureaucracy was merely a fleeting phenomena of

transition that would one way or another have to pass away.[30]

It was on this basis that Trotsky argued:

To the extent that, in contrast to decaying capitalism, it develops the

productive forces, [the bureaucracy] is preparing the economic basis of

socialism. To the extent that, for the benefit of an upper stratum, it

carries to more and more extreme expression bourgeois norms of

distribution, it is preparing a capitalist restoration. (The Revolution

Betrayed, p. 244)

So, for Trotsky, either the Soviet Union would make the transition to

socialism, in which case the bureaucracy would be swept away, or else it

would into capitalism and the bureaucracy would legalize their position

through the reintroduction of private property and capitalism, and in

doing so transform themselves into a new capitalist class.

Trotsky’s notion that the USSR was in a state of transition from

capitalism to socialism was central to his theory of Russia as a

degenerated workers’ state and, at the time of writing, seemed to give

his theory substantial explanatory power. Yet Trotsky’s prognosis that

the end of the Second World War would see the Soviet Union either become

socialist with the support of world revolution or else face the

restoration of capitalism was to be contradicted by the entrenchment of

the Soviet bureaucracy following the war. As we shall see, this was to

provoke a recurrent crisis amongst Trotsky’s followers.

The theory of the USSR as a form of state capitalism within

Trotskyism

Introduction

For Trotsky, the Stalinist system in the USSR could only be but a

transitory historical phenomena. Lacking a firm legal basis in the

ownership of the means of production, the Stalinist bureaucracy was

doomed to a mere fleeting appearance in the overall course of history.

Indeed, throughout the 1930s, Trotsky had been convinced that the days

of the Stalinist bureaucracy were numbered.

For Trotsky, world capitalism was in terminal decline. The economic

stagnation that had followed the Wall Street crash in 1929 could only

intensify imperialist rivalries amongst the great capitalist powers

which ultimately could only be resolved through the devastation of a

Second World War. Yet Trotsky firmly believed that, like the First World

War, this Second World War would bring in its wake a renewed

revolutionary wave that would sweep the whole of Europe if not the

world. In the midst of such a revolutionary wave the Russian working

class would be in a position to overthrow the Stalinist bureaucracy in a

political revolution which would then, with the aid of revolutions

elsewhere, open the way for Russia to complete its transition to

socialism. Even if the worst came to the worst, and the post-war

revolutionary wave was defeated, then the way would then be open for the

restoration of capitalism in Russia. With the defeat of the proletariat,

both in Russia and elsewhere, the Stalinist bureaucracy would soon take

the opportunity to convert itself into a new bourgeoisie through the

privatization of state industry. Either way the Stalinist bureaucracy

would soon disappear, along with the entire Stalinist system that had

arisen from the degeneration of the Russian Revolution.

As the approach of the Second World War became more and more apparent,

Trotsky became more convinced that Stalin’s day of reckoning would not

be far off. Yet not all of Trotsky’s followers shared his optimism.

Following his expulsion from Russia in 1929 Trotsky had sought to

re-establish the Left Opposition on an international basis seeking to

oppose Stalin within the Third International of Communist Parties.

However, in the face of Stalin’s resolute hold over the Third

International and its constituent Communist Parties Trotsky’s efforts to

build the International Left Opposition within the official world

Communist movement soon proved to be futile. In 1933 Trotsky decided to

break from the Third International and attempt to regroup all those

Communists opposed to Stalin in an effort to build a new Fourth

International.

With the international upturn in class struggle of the mid-1930s, which

culminated in the Spanish Revolution in 1936, increasing numbers of

Communists who had become disillusioned with Stalinism were drawn to

Trotsky’s project. By 1938 Trotsky had felt that the time had come to

establish the Fourth International. Although the various groups across

the world who supported the project of a Fourth International were still

very small compared with the mass Communists Parties of the Third

International, Trotsky believed that it was vital to have the

international organization of the Fourth International in place before

the onset of the Second World War. Trotsky believed that just as the

First World War had thrown the international workers’ movement into

confusion, with all the Socialist Parties of the Second International

being swept along in patriotic fervour, so the same would happen with

the onset of the Second World War. In such circumstances the Fourth

International would have to provide a resolute point of reference and

clarity in the coming storm which could then provide a rallying point

once the patriotic fever had given way to the urge for revolution

amongst the working class across the world.

Yet by 1938 the upturn in class struggle had more or less passed. The

Spanish Revolution had been defeated and Franco’s fascists were well on

their way to winning the Spanish Civil War. With fascism already

triumphant in Italy and Germany and advancing elsewhere in Europe the

situation was looking increasing bleak for those on the left that had

become disillusioned with Stalinism. Furthermore, few could have been as

convinced as Trotsky was that the onset of a Second World War, which

promised to be even more terrible than first, would bring in its wake a

renewed revolutionary situation in Europe, if not the world.

As a consequence, many, even within the Fourth International, came to

draw rather pessimistic conclusions concerning the world situation.

Within such a pessimistic perspective it was easy to conclude that the

socialist revolution had failed, both in Russia and the rest of Europe,

in the early 1920s. From this it was but a short step to argue that

capitalism was not being replaced by socialism, as Marx had foreseen,

but by a new and unforeseen form of society in which all political and

economic life was subsumed by a totalitarian state, which had become

evident not only in Mussolini’s Italy and Hitler’s Germany but also in

Stalin’s Russia. This new form of society now seemed destined to

dominate the world, just as capitalism had done before it. This view

found its expression in the various theories of ‘bureaucratic

collectivism’ that increasingly gained support amongst Trotskyists

towards the end of the 1930s.

The theory of bureaucratic collectivism was originally put forward by

Bruno Rizzi in the early 1930s. Yet it was in 1939 that this theory

became central to the first grave crisis in Trotskyism. As we have seen,

on the basis of his theory of the USSR as a degenerated workers’ state,

Trotsky had argued that, despite all the crimes perpetuated by the

Stalin’s regime, it was necessary, in order to defend the proletarian

gains of the Russian Revolution, to give critical support to the Soviet

Union. As we have also noted, this position became increasingly

difficult to defend as true nature of Stalin’s regime became apparent,

particularly after the Moscow show trials of the 1930s and the role of

the Stalinists in crushing the workers’ revolution in Spain in the May

Days of 1937. For many Trotskyists the last straw came when Stalin

signed a non-aggression pact with Hitler in August 1939. Here was the

USSR openly dealing with a fascist regime!

In September 1939 several leading members of the Socialist Workers’

Party of the USA, which, with several thousand members, was one of the

largest sections of the Fourth International, announced the formation of

an organized minority faction opposed to the official stance towards the

USSR. In their polemics with Trotsky and his supporters in the American

SWP the notion central to bureaucratic collectivism — that Stalin’s

Russia was little different from that of Hitler’s Germany — proved to be

a powerful weapon. Indeed, many of the leading figures in this

oppositional faction, which eventually split from the SWP in 1940 to

form the Workers’ Party, came to adopt the theory of bureaucratic

collectivism as their own. As such the theory of bureaucratic

collectivism came to pose the main challenge to orthodox Trotskyism from

within Trotskyism itself.

In his interventions in the fierce polemics that preceded the split in

the American SWP, Trotsky made it clear that he saw the theory of

bureaucratic collectivism as nothing less than a direct attack not

merely on his own ideas, but on Marxism itself. The notion that the

capitalist mode of production was destined to be surpassed, not by

socialism but by a form of society based on bureaucratic collectivism,

clearly broke with the fundamental understanding of history that had

underpinned Marxism from its very inception. Yet, if this was not bad

enough, none of the various versions of the theory of bureaucratic

collectivism went as far to provide an adequate materialist and class

analysis of what bureaucratic collectivism was and how it had come

about. As a result, as Trotsky ceaselessly pointed out, these theories

of bureaucratic collectivism were unable to go beyond the level of

appearance and as such remained merely descriptive.

Such criticisms were seen to be borne out by the eventual fate of the

various theories of bureaucratic collectivism and their leading

proponents. Having abandoned Marxism, the theories of bureaucratic

collectivism lacked any theoretical grounding of their own. As a

consequence they were obliged to look to various strands of bourgeois

sociology and ended up joining the growing stream of bourgeois theories

that saw the increasing totalitarianism and bureaucratization of modern

societies as an inevitable result of the complexities of industrial

society. This was perhaps best illustrated by one of the leading figures

in the split from the American SWP in 1940, James Burnham. As a

university professor, Burnham was recognized as one of the leading

intellectuals in the minority that split from the American SWP, but he

went on to become one of the originators of the theory of the

‘managerial society’ which was to become popular amongst bourgeois

sociologists in the ‘50s and ‘60s. Yet while the logic of bureaucratic

collectivism led Burnham to become a liberal, for Schachtman, who had

been one of the prime proponents of the theory of bureaucratic

collectivism, it meant eventually ending up as a virulent anti-Communist

who openly backed the McCarthy witch hunts of the 1950s. For those who

remained loyal to Trotsky the fate of these supporters of the

bureaucratic collectivism could only be taken as a stern lesson in the

dangers of straying too far from the teachings of Trotsky and Marxist

orthodoxy.

Yet it should be noted here that not all those who split from the

American SWP at this time were proponents of a theory of bureaucratic

collectivism or variants of one. From the very foundation of the Fourth

International there had been a significant minority with the Trotskyist

movement who had opposed Trotsky’s stance to the USSR by arguing that

Russia was not a degenerated workers’ state but was simply state

capitalist.[31] It was this theory of the USSR as being state capitalist

which was to re-emerge with greater force after the Second World War, as

we shall now see.

The theory of state capitalism and the second crisis in Trotskyism

Trotsky’s predictions for the end of the Second World War, which had

sustained the hopes of those who had remained loyal to him, were soon

proved to be false. There was no repeat of the great revolutionary wave

that had swept Europe at the end of the First World War; nor was the

grip of either Stalinism or social democracy on the workers’ movements

weakened. On the contrary, both Stalinism and social democracy emerged

from the Second World War far stronger than they had ever been.

As it became increasingly apparent that the realities of the immediate

post-war world contradicted the predictions that Trotsky had made before

his death in 1940, and with them the basic orientation of the Fourth

International, the strains within the Trotskyist movement between those

who sought to revise Trotskyism to meet these new realities and those

who feared such revisionism reached the point of crisis. In 1953, less

that eight years after the end of the war the Fourth International

finally split giving rise to the ’57 varieties’ of Trotskyism that we

find today. One of the crucial issues at the heart of this crisis within

Trotskyism was that of the question of the respective natures of the

USSR and Eastern Europe.

The retreat of the German armies during the final stages of the war had

prompted popular uprisings across Eastern Europe. For the most part

these uprisings had either been contained by the Stalinists, where they

provided the popular base on which to build broad-based anti-fascist

governments, or, to the extent that they could not be contained, they

were either crushed by the advancing Red Army, or else abandoned to the

vengeance of the retreating German forces.

At first Stalin did not seek to impose the economic or political model

of the Soviet Union on the countries of Eastern Europe. The broad-based

anti-fascist governments were elected on traditional

bourgeois-democratic lines and in most cases came to include not only

Communists and socialists but also liberals and representatives of the

peasant and rural classes. Although these governments were encouraged to

carry out nationalizations of key industries, and implement various

social and agrarian reforms, in many respects this differed little from

the policies of nationalization of ailing industry and welfare reforms

that were happening elsewhere in Europe. But as the Cold War began to

set in, and Europe began to polarize between East and West, Stalin began

to impose the Soviet economic and political model on to Eastern Europe.

If necessary, the post-war coalitions were pushed aside and the

wholesale nationalization of industry was carried out and the market was

replaced by centralized planning.

The initial phase of the post-war era in Eastern Europe had presented

Trotskyists with few problems. The uprisings at the end of the war could

be seen as portents of the coming world revolution, while the repression

by the Stalinists could be righteously condemned. Furthermore, the fact

that these uprisings had for the most part failed explained why Eastern

Europe remained capitalist. However, once the ‘Russification of Eastern

Europe’ began to take place, Trotskyist theory began to face a serious

dilemma.

Of course, the transformation of property relations that had been

brought about by the wholesale nationalization of industry and the

introduction of centralized planning could be seen to reaffirm Trotsky’s

insistence on the objectively progressive role of the Stalinist

bureaucracy. Indeed, it could now be argued that the Stalinist

bureaucracy had not only defended the proletarian gains of the Russian

Revolution but had now extended them to the rest of Eastern Europe.

Yet, if this was the case, did this not imply that the countries of

Eastern Europe had now become degenerated workers’ states like the USSR?

But how could you have a degenerated workers’ state when there had been

no revolution, and thus no workers’ state, in the first place?! It was

now no longer just that a workers’ state was supposed to exist where the

workers had no state power, as Trotsky had argued for Stalinist Russia,

but workers’ states’ were now supposed to exist where the working class

had never been in power! With the question of Eastern Europe the

fundamental dichotomy of Trotsky’s theory of a degenerated workers’

state, in which the objective interests of the working class are somehow

able to stand apart from and against the working class in the form of

the alien power of the bureaucracy, now stood exposed.

But if the countries of Eastern Europe were not admitted as being

degenerated workers’ states then what were they? The obvious answer,

given that the principle means of production had been simply

nationalized by the state without a workers’ revolution, was that they

were state capitalist. However, such an answer contained even greater

dangers for orthodox Trotskyists than the first. As Eastern Europe

became reconstructed in the image of the USSR it became increasingly

difficult to avoid the conclusion that if the countries of Eastern

Europe were state capitalist then so must the Soviet Union be nothing

other than a form of state capitalism.

After numerous attempts to resolve this dilemma the official line which

emerged within the leadership of the Fourth International was that the

uprising at the end of the war had all been part of a proletarian

revolution that had been mutilated and deformed by Stalinism. The

countries of Eastern Europe were therefore not degenerated workers’

states as such, but ‘deformed workers’ states’. Yet this attempted

solution still implied that the Stalinist bureaucracy was an active

agent in creating the objective conditions of socialism. As we have

seen, Trotsky had argued that the Stalinist bureaucracy was progressive

in that in defending its own basis in state property it was impelled to

defend the objective gains of the proletarian revolution, that is the

state ownership of the means of production. Now Trotskyism had come to

argue that the Stalinist bureaucracy not only defended such proletarian

gains but could now actually extend them! With the Stalinist bureaucracy

now deemed to be a primary agent in the transition to socialism the

importance of the revolutionary role of the working class became

diminished. The way was now opened for Trotskyists in the coming decades

to support all sorts of nationalist movements regardless of the role

within them of the proletariat.[32]

Cliff and the neo-Trotskyist theory of the USSR as state capitalist

Perhaps rather ironically, Tony Cliff was originally sent to Britain by

the leadership of the Fourth International in an effort to head off any

potential support within the British Section for the theory that Eastern

Europe and the USSR were in any way state capitalist. As it turned out,

it was not Gerry Healey, Ted Grant or any of the other leading figures

of the British Revolutionary Communist Party[33] at that time who came

to adopt the theory of state capitalism but none other than Cliff

himself.

Yet in coming to the viewpoint that it was not only Eastern Europe that

was state capitalist but also the USSR, Tony Cliff was determined not to

follow in the footsteps of so many former Trotskyists who, having

rejected Trotsky’s theory of Russia as a degenerated workers’ state, had

come to reject Trotsky and even Marxism itself. Instead, Cliff was

committed to developing a state capitalist theory of the USSR which

remained firmly within both the Trotskyist and orthodox Marxist

tradition. Against those who argued that the theory of the USSR as a

degenerated workers’ state was central to Trotsky’s Marxism, Cliff

replied by arguing that not only were there numerous examples in

Trotsky’s own writings where he indicated serious doubts concerning his

conclusion that the USSR was a degenerated workers’ state but that

towards the end of his life Trotsky had shown signs of moving away from

such conclusions altogether. Indeed, Cliff sought to claim that had

Trotsky lived then he too would have eventually come round to the

conclusion that the USSR had become state capitalist, and certainly

would not have dogmatically defended a position that flew in the face of

all the evidence as his loyal followers in the leadership of the Fourth

International had done.

Cliff originally presented his rather heretical ideas in 1948 in the

form of a duplicated discussion document entitled The Nature of

Stalinist Russia. After several editions and accompanying amendments and

additions, this text now takes the form of a book entitled State

Capitalism in Russia which provides us with a definitive statement of

Cliff’s position.

Cliff devoted much of the first third of State Capitalism in Russia to

presenting a mass of evidence with which he sought to show both the

exploitative and repressive nature of the USSR. Yet, as powerful an

indictment of the Stalinist regime as this may have been, the evidence

Cliff presented was far from sufficient to convince his opponents within

either the Revolutionary Communist Party or the broader Fourth

International. For orthodox Trotskyists such evidence could simply be

taken to confirm the extent of the degeneration of the Soviet Union and

did little to refute the persistence of Russia as essentially a workers’

state. As Cliff himself recognized, it was necessary to demonstrate that

the apparent exploitative and repressive character of the Soviet Union

necessarily arose, not from the degeneration of the Soviet Union as a

workers’ state but rather from the fact that under Stalin the USSR had

ceased to be a workers’ state and had become state capitalist. Yet to do

this Cliff had first of all to clarify what he meant by ‘state

capitalism’ and how such a conception was not only compatible with, but

rooted within the orthodox Marxist tradition.

For orthodox Marxism, capitalism had been defined as a class society

dominated by generalized commodity exchange which arises from the

private ownership of the means of production. On the basis of such a

definition it would appear, at least at first sight, that the notion of

state capitalism in the absolute sense was a contradiction in terms. If

all of the means of production are nationalized, the capitalist class

expropriated and the law of value and the market replaced by state

allocation and planning, then it would appear that capitalism must have

been, by definition, abolished. If it was accepted that, for the most

part, the Russian Revolution had led to the abolition of the private

ownership of the means of production, then it would seem clear that,

from a Marxist point of view, capitalism in any form could not exist in

the USSR. (And of course this is the common objection we find advanced

against all theories of state capitalism in the USSR.)

However, as Cliff was keen to point out, it had also been central to

orthodox Marxism that the capitalist mode of production was transitory.

Capitalism was merely a phase in human history whose very development

would eventually undermine its own basis. As capitalism repeatedly

revolutionized methods of production it advanced the forces of

production to an unprecedented degree. Yet in advancing the forces of

production capitalism was obliged to increasingly socialize production

as production was carried out on an ever larger and more complex scale.

The more social the production process became the more it came into

conflict with the private appropriation of the wealth that it produced.

As a result capitalism was obliged to negate its very own basis in the

private ownership of production and in doing so it prepared the way for

socialism.

As we have noted before, already by the end of the nineteenth century

most Marxists had come to the view that the classical stage of free

competitive capitalism, that had been described and analysed by Marx in

the 1860s, had given way to the final stages of the capitalist era. The

growth of huge cartels and monopolies and the increasing economic role

of the state was seen as negating the market and the operation of the

law of value. At the same time the emergence of joint stock companies

and the nationalization of key industries meant the replacement of

individual capitalist ownership of the means of production by collective

forms of ownership which implied the further negation of private

property. Indeed, as Engels argued, the development of both monopoly and

state capitalism was leading to the point that the capitalist class was

superfluous to the production process itself. Capital no longer needed

the capitalist. As Engels himself states:

[T]he conversion of the great organizations for production and

communication into joint-stock companies and state property show that

for this purpose the bourgeoisie can be dispensed with. All the social

functions of the capitalists are now carried out by salaried employees.

The capitalist has no longer any social activity save the pocketing of

revenues, the clipping of coupons and gambling on the stock exchange,

where different capitalists fleece each other of their capital. Just as

at first the capitalist mode of production displaced the workers, so now

it displaces the capitalists, relegating them, just as it did the

workers, to the superfluous population, even if in the first instance

not to the industrial reserve army.

But neither the conversion into joint stock companies nor into state

property deprives the productive forces of their character as capital.

In the case of joint stock companies this is obvious. And the modern

state, too, is only the organization with which bourgeois society

provides itself in order to maintain the general external conditions of

the capitalist mode of production against encroachments either by

workers or by individual capitalists. The modern state, whatever its

form, is an essentially capitalist machine; it is the state of

capitalists, the ideal collective body of all capitalists. The more

productive forces it takes over as its property, the more it becomes the

real collective body of all capitalists, the more citizens it exploits.

The workers remain wage earners, proletarians. The capitalist

relationship is not abolished; it is rather pushed to an extreme. But at

this extreme it is transformed into its opposite. State ownership of the

productive forces is not the solution of the conflict, but it contains

within itself the formal means, the key to the solution. (Engels,

Anti-DĂŒhring, p. 330)

So for the old orthodoxy of the Second International it was undoubtedly

accepted that there was an inherent tendency towards state capitalism.

Indeed it was this tendency which was seen as laying the basis for

socialism. Yet it had also been central for both Lenin and the new

Bolshevik orthodoxy. Not only did the increasing negation of private

property and the law of value indicate the ripeness for socialism, but

the fusion of the state and capital within state capitalism explained

the increasing imperialist rivalries that had led to the First World

War. As the competitive struggle between capital and capital became at

the same time a struggle between imperialist states, imperialist war

became inevitable. As Bukharin remarks in Imperialism and the World

Economy, which provided the theoretical basis for Lenin’s theory of

imperialism:

When competition has finally reached its highest stage, when it has

become competition between state capitalist trusts, then the use of

state power, and the possibilities connected with it play a very large

part. The state apparatus has always served as a tool in the hands of

the ruling classes of its country, and it has always acted as the their

“defender and protector” in the world market; at no time, however, did

it have the colossal importance that it has in the epoch of finance

capital and imperialist politics. With the formation of state capitalist

trusts competition is being almost entirely shifted onto foreign

countries; obviously the organs of the struggle that is to be waged

abroad, primarily state power, must therefore grow tremendously... If

state power is generally growing in significance the growth of its

military organization, the army and the navy, is particularly striking.

The struggle between state capitalist trusts is decided in the first

place by the relation between their military forces, for military power

of the country is the last resort of the struggling “national” groups of

capitalists. (Bukharin, p. 124)

So it could not be doubted that the notion that capitalism was

developing towards state capitalism, such that its very basis within

both the law of value and private property was increasingly becoming

negated, was clearly rooted within orthodox Marxism. The question then

was whether state capitalism in an absolute sense was possible. Could it

not be the case that after a certain point quantity would be transformed

into quality? Was it not the case that once the principle means of

production had been nationalized and the last major capitalist

expropriated capitalism had necessarily been objectively abolished? And

was this not the case for Russia following the October revolution?

To counter this contention, that could all too easily be advanced by his

Trotskyist critics, Cliff argued that the qualitative shift from

capitalism to the transition to socialism could not be simply calculated

from the ‘percentage’ of state ownership of the means of production. It

was a transition that was necessarily politically determined. As we have

seen, the tendency towards state capitalism was a result of the growing

contradiction between the increasingly social forms of production and

the private appropriation of wealth. Collective, and ultimately state

ownership of the means of production were a means to reconcile this

contradiction while at the same time preserving private appropriation of

wealth and with it private property. Thus the tendency towards state

capitalism involved the partial negation of private property on the

basis of private property itself.

So at the limit, state capitalism could be seen as the ‘partial negation

of capitalism on the basis of capitalism itself’. So long as the state

economy was run to exploit the working class in the interests of an

exploitative class then the economy remained state capitalist. However,

if the working class seized power and ran the state economy in the

interests of the people as whole then state capitalism would give way to

a workers’ state and the transition to socialism could begin. Thus state

capitalism was a turning point, it was the final swan song of

capitalism, but once the working class seized the state it would be the

basis for the transition to socialism.

However, it could be objected that many revolutionary Marxists,

including Trotsky himself, had explicitly denied that capitalism could

reach the limit of state capitalism. Indeed, against the reformists in

the Second International, who had argued that capitalism would naturally

evolve into state capitalism which could then be simply taken over by

democratically capturing the state, revolutionary Marxists had argued

that, while there was a tendency towards state capitalism, it could

never be fully realized in practice due to the rivalries between

capitalists and by the very threat of expropriation of the state by the

working class.

Cliff countered this by arguing that such arguments had only applied to

the case of the evolution of traditional capitalism into state

capitalism. In Russia there had been a revolution, that had expropriated

the capitalist class and introduced a workers’ state, and then a

counter-revolution, which had restored capitalism in the form of state

capitalism run in the interests of a new bureaucratic class. For Cliff,

the Russian Revolution had created a workers’ state, but, isolated by

the failure of socialist revolutions elsewhere in Europe, the workers’

state had degenerated. With the degeneration of the workers’ state the

bureaucracy increasingly became separated from the working class until,

with Stalin’s ascendancy, it was able to constitute itself as a new

exploitative class and seize state power. With the bureaucracy’s seizure

of power the workers’ state was over-turned and state capitalism was

restored to Russia.

This periodization of post-revolutionary era in Russia not only allowed

Cliff to overcome the objection that Trotsky had denied the possibility

of bourgeois society fully realizing the tendency towards state

capitalism, but also allowed him to accept most of Trotsky’s analysis of

the Russian Revolution and its aftermath. Cliff only had to part ways

with Trotsky for the analysis of the ten years following 1928, where

Trotsky maintained that the USSR has remained a degenerated workers’

state while Cliff argued that it had become state capitalist. Yet, as we

shall see, this periodization, despite all its advantages for Cliff’s

credibility as a Trotskyist, was to prove an important weak point in his

theory. But before looking at the weak points of Cliff’s theory of state

capitalism we must first examine more closely what Cliff saw as the

nature of state capitalism in Stalin’s Russia.

As we have seen, although Cliff uncritically defended the orthodox

Marxist definition of capitalism, he was able to counter the objections

that the USSR could not be in any sense capitalist because there was

neither the law of value nor private property, by arguing that state

capitalism was the ‘partial negation of capitalism on the basis of

capitalism itself’. So what did he mean by ‘the partial negation of

capitalism’? Clearly capitalism could not be completely negated

otherwise it would not be capitalism; so in what sense is the negation

of capitalism partial? With Cliff the meaning of the partial negation of

capitalism becomes most evident in terms of the law of value.

Following Marx, Cliff argued that under capitalism there is a two-fold

division of labour. First of all there is the division of labour that

arises between capitalist enterprises which is regulated by the law of

value that operates through the ‘anarchy of the market’. Secondly there

is the division of labour that arises within each capitalist enterprise

which is directly determined by the rational and conscious dictates of

the capitalists or their managers. Of course the second division of

labour is subordinated to the law of value insofar as the capitalist

enterprise has to compete on the market. However, the law of value

appears as external to it.

For Cliff the USSR acted as if it was simply one huge capitalist

enterprise. As such the law of value no longer operated within the USSR,

it had been negated with the nationalization of production and the

introduction of comprehensive state planning. But, insofar as the USSR

was obliged to compete both economically and politically within the

capitalist world system it became subordinated to the law of value like

any capitalist enterprise. In this sense, for Cliff, the law of value

was only ‘partially negated on the basis of the law of value itself’.

Yet, if neither market nor the law of value operated within the USSR

this implied that products were not really bought and sold within the

USSR as commodities, they were simply allocated and transferred in

accordance with administrative prices. If this was true then it also

implied that labour-power was not really a commodity; a conclusion that

Cliff was forced to accept. Indeed, as Cliff argued, if labour-power was

to be a commodity then the worker had to be free to sell it periodically

to the highest bidder. If the worker could only sell his ability to work

once and for all then he was little different from a slave since in

effect he sold himself not his labour-power. Yet in the USSR the worker

could only sell his labour-power to one employer, the state. Hence the

worker was not free to sell to the highest bidder and labour-power was

not really a commodity.

The flaws in Cliff’s theory of state capitalism

At first sight Cliff provides a convincing theory of state capitalism in

the USSR which not only remains firmly within the broad orthodox Marxist

tradition, but also preserves much of Trotsky’s contribution to this

tradition. As the post-war era unfolded leaving the Stalinist

bureaucracy more firmly entrenched than ever, Cliff’s analysis of the

USSR became increasingly attractive. Without the problems facing

orthodox Trotskyist groupings following the apparent failure of

Trotsky’s predictions of the fall of the Stalinist bureaucracy, Cliff,

under the slogan of ‘neither Washington nor Moscow’, was in a perfect

position to attract supporters with the revival of interest in Leninism

and Trotskyism of the 1960s and 1970s. Indeed, with the International

Socialists Group, which then became the Socialist Workers’ Party, Cliff

has been able to build one of the largest Leninist groupings in Britain

whose most distinctive feature has been its refusal to takes sides in

the Cold War.[34]

However, despite the attractiveness of Cliff’s theory of state

capitalism in the USSR, on close inspection we find his theory has vital

weaknesses which have been seized on by more orthodox Trotskyists.

Indeed, these weaknesses are so serious that many have concluded that

Cliff’s theory is fatally flawed. This opinion has even been recognized

within the SWP itself and has resulted in various attempts to

reconstruct Cliff’s original theory.[35] As we shall argue, these flaws

in Cliff’s theory arise to a large extent from his determination to

avoid critical confrontation with both Trotsky and the broader orthodox

Marxist tradition.

There are three main flaws within Cliff’s theory of state capitalism in

the USSR. The first concerns Cliff’s insistence that the final

ascendancy of Stalin, and with this the introduction of the first five

year plan, marked a counter-revolution which overthrew the workers’

state established by the October revolution and turned Russia over to

state capitalism. The issue of when the USSR became state capitalist is

clearly a sensitive one for Trotskyists since, if Cliff is unable to

hold the line at 1928, then what is to stop the date of the defeat of

the revolution being pushed right back to 1917? Lenin and Trotsky would

then be seen as leading a revolution that simply introduced state

capitalism into Russia! Such fears were clear expressed by Ted Grant in

his response to Cliff’s original presentation of his theory in The

Nature of Stalinist Russia. Then Ted Grant warned:

If comrade Cliff’s thesis is correct, that state capitalism exists in

Russia today, then he cannot avoid the conclusion that state capitalism

has been in existence since the Russian Revolution and the function of

the Revolution itself was to introduce this state capitalist system of

society. For despite his tortuous efforts to draw a line between the

economic basis of Russian society before the year 1928 and after, the

economic basis of Russian society has in fact remained unchanged. (Ted

Grant, The Unbroken Thread, p. 199)

The first line of attack that has been taken by orthodox Trotskyists has

been to argue that if there had been a counter-revolution against,

rather than from within, the revolution itself, which restored Russia to

capitalism, then the workers’ state would have to have been violently

smashed. Any attempt to argue for a gradual and peaceful restoration of

capitalism would, as Trotsky himself had said, simply be ‘running

backwards the film of revisionism’.[36] Yet, despite the expulsions of

Trotsky and the United and Left Oppositions in 1928, the leadership of

the Party and the state remained largely intact. Indeed there seems more

of a continuity within the state before 1928 and afterwards rather than

any sharp break that would indicate a counter-revolution, let alone any

violent coup d’état or violent counter-revolutionary action.

Cliff attempted to counter this line of attack by arguing that while it

is necessary for a proletarian revolution to smash the bourgeois state

in order to construct a new revolutionary proletarian state, it is not

necessarily the case that a counter-revolution has to smash an existing

workers’ state.[37] The example Cliff used was that of the army. In

order to create a workers’ state the bourgeois standing army has to be

transformed into a workers’ militia. But any such transformation

inevitably would be resisted by the officer corp. Such resistance would

have to be violently crushed. In contrast, the officers of a workers’

militia may become increasingly independent to the point at which they

become part of the bureaucracy thereby transforming the workers’ militia

into a bourgeois standing army. Such a process, in which a workers’

militia becomes transformed into a standing army, does not necessarily

meet any concerted resistance, and as a consequence may occur gradually.

Yet such an argument by itself fails to pin the counter-revolutionary

break on 1928. Indeed, Cliff’s example would seem to imply that the

counter-revolution was brought about by Trotsky himself when he took

charge of re-organizing the Red Army in 1918 on the lines of a

conventional standing army! The only overt political indication Cliff is

able to present for the bureaucratic counter-revolution is the Moscow

show trials and purges, which he claims were:

the civil war of the bureaucracy against the masses, a war in which only

one side was armed and organized. They witnessed the consummation of the

bureaucracy’s total liberation from popular control. (State Capitalism

in Russia, p. 195)

Yet the Moscow show trials occurred in the 1930s, not in 1928.

What was crucial about 1928 was that it was the year that marked the

beginning of the first five year plan and the bureaucracy’s commitment

to the rapid industrialization of Russia. For Cliff, by adopting the

overriding imperative of industrializing Russia, regardless of the human

cost this would involve, the Soviet bureaucracy had taken on the

historic role of the bourgeoisie. In adopting both the economic and

historic functions of the bourgeoisie the bureaucracy had transformed

itself into an exploitative class. Whereas before 1928 the bureaucracy

had simply been a privileged layer within a degenerated workers’ state

that was able to gain more than its fair share of the nation’s wealth,

after 1928 the bureaucracy became the state capitalists who collectively

exploited the working class.

Of course, it was not difficult for Cliff to show that there had been a

sharp decrease in the material conditions of the working class following

the introduction of the first five year plan as the bureaucracy sought

to make the proletariat pay the huge costs of the policy of rapid

industrialization. However, Cliff’s argument that this sharp decrease in

material conditions of the working class represented a qualitative shift

towards the exploitation of the working class by the bureaucracy was far

from convincing. If anything Cliff’s attempts to show a qualitative

shift in social relations of production only serve to indicate that

bureaucratic exploitation of the working class had existed before 1928.

Yet perhaps more devastating to the credibility of Cliff’s line of

argument among Trotskyists was that by suggesting that with the

imposition of the policy of rapid industrialization the bureaucracy had

finally transformed itself into an exploitative class, and in doing so

transformed Russia from a degenerated workers’ state into state

capitalism, Cliff was in effect attacking Trotsky! Had it not been the

main criticism advanced by Trotsky and the Left Opposition against

Stalin that he had not industrialized soon enough?! Was not the central

plank of Trotsky’s understanding of the Russian Revolution that the

productive forces had to be advanced as fast as possible if there was to

be any hope of socialism? If this was so, was not Cliff accusing Trotsky

of advocating state capitalism?! Ultimately Cliff is unable to

circumvent Trotsky’s intrinsic complicity with Stalin. As a consequence,

the failure to break with Trotskyism led to this vital flaw in Cliff’s

theory of state capitalism in Russia.

Yet this is not all. Cliff’s failure to critically confront orthodox

Marxism opened up another even more important weakness in his theory of

state capitalism which has been seized upon by his more orthodox

Trotskyist critics. This weakness stemmed from Cliff’s denial of the

operation of the law of value within the USSR.

As we have seen, for Cliff the USSR was constituted as if it was one

huge capitalist enterprise. As such there could be no operation of the

law of value internal to the USSR. However, as Marx pointed out, it is

only through the operation of the law of value that any capitalist

enterprise is constrained to act as capital. If there was no law of

value internal to the state economy of the USSR what made it act as if

it was a capitalist enterprise? The answer was the Soviet Union’s

relation to world capitalism. It was through the competitive political

and economic relation to the rest of the capitalist world that the

Soviet Union was subordinated to the law of value, and it was through

this subordination to the law of value that the capitalist nature of the

USSR became expressed.

However, as Cliff recognized, the Soviet Union, with its huge natural

resources, had become largely self-sufficient. Foreign trade with the

rest of the world was minimal compared with the amount produced and

consumed within Russia itself. As a result Cliff could not argue that

the international law of value imposed itself on the Russian economy

through the necessity to compete on the world market. Instead, Cliff had

to argue that the law of value imposed itself indirectly on the USSR

through the necessity to compete politically with the major capitalist

and imperialist powers. In order to keep up with the arms race,

particularly with the emergence of the Cold War with the USA, the USSR

had to accumulate huge amounts of military hardware. This drive for

military accumulation led the drive for accumulation elsewhere in the

Russian economy. Indeed, this military competition could be seen to spur

capital accumulation, and with it the exploitation of the working class,

just as much, if not more so, than any economic competition from the

world market could have done.[38]

However, as Cliff’s Trotskyist critics point out, for Marx the law of

value does not impose itself through ‘competition’ as such, but through

the competitive exchange of commodities. Indeed, it is only through the

exchange of commodities that value is formed, and hence it is only

through such exchange that the law of value can come to impose itself.

Military accumulation is not directly an accumulation of values but an

accumulation of use-values. In a capitalist economy such an accumulation

can become part of the overall process of the accumulation of value, and

hence of capital, insofar as it guarantees the accumulation of capital

in the future by protecting or else extending foreign markets. However,

in itself military accumulation is simply an accumulation of things, not

capital. So in capitalist countries military spending suppresses value

and the law of value temporarily in order to extend it later. Given that

the Soviet Union did not seek to expand value production through the

conquest of new markets, military production meant the permanent

suppression of value and the law of value in that it was simply the

production of use-values required to defend a system based on the

production of use-values.

For the more sophisticated Trotskyists, Cliff’s attempt to invoke

military competition as the means through which the USSR was

subordinated to the law of value exposed the fundamental theoretical

weakness of Cliff’s theory of state capitalism in Russia. The argument

put forward by Cliff that under state capitalism ‘the accumulation of

value turns into its opposite the accumulation of use-values’ is nothing

but a sophistry which strips away the specific social forms that are

essential to define a particular mode of production such as capitalism.

As they correctly point out, capital is not a thing but a social

relation that gives rise to specific social forms. The fact that

military hardware is accumulated is in no way the same thing as the

accumulation of capital. Without the production of commodities there can

be no value and without value there can be no accumulation of capital.

But Cliff argues there is no production of commodities in the USSR,

particularly not in the military industries, since nothing is produced

for a market, thus there can be neither value nor capital.

This point can be further pressed home once Cliff’s critics turn to the

question of labour-power. For Marx the specific nature of any mode of

production was determined by both the manner and forms through which the

dominant class are able to extract surplus-labour from the direct

producers. Within the capitalist mode of production surplus-labour is

extracted from the direct producers by the purchase of the worker’s

labour-power as a commodity. As a consequence, surplus-labour is

expropriated in the form of surplus-value which is the difference

between the value of labour-power (i.e. the costs of reproducing the

worker’s ability to work) and the value the worker creates through

working. However, for Cliff, labour-power was not a commodity in the

USSR and was not therefore really sold. But if labour-power was not a

commodity it could not have a value, and hence any surplus-labour

extracted could not take the form of surplus-value. If surplus-labour

did not take the form of surplus-value how could the USSR be in any

sense capitalist in strict Marxist terms?!

The third fatal flaw in Cliff’s theory of state capitalism in Russia,

and one that arises from his commitment to orthodox Marxism, is the view

that state capitalism is the highest stage of capitalism. As we have

seen, it is central for Cliff that state capitalism was the highest

stage of capitalism since it was from this premise that he could claim

that state capitalism was at the point of transition from capitalism to

socialism. But if state capitalism is the highest stage of capitalism,

and if it is accepted that the USSR is state capitalist, then this would

seem to imply that, in some fundamental sense, the USSR should be in

advance of Western capitalism. Of course, this may have seemed

reasonable in the late 1940s. After all, under Stalin the USSR had made

an unprecedented leap forward with the rapid industrialization of

Russia, and it seemed that the Soviet Union was set to out-perform most

of capitalist economies in the West in the post-war era. However, in the

following decades the economic stagnation and economic waste of the

‘Soviet system’ became increasingly apparent, culminating with the

collapse of the USSR in 1990. This, combined with the globalization of

capital, which has seriously undermined the efficacy of state

intervention in Western capitalism, has meant that the notion that

capitalism is tending towards state capitalism is now far less

convincing than it was fifty years ago. As we shall see in the next

issue, although Cliff did develop a theory to explain the economic

stagnation in the Soviet Union it proved insufficient to explain the

final crisis and collapse of the USSR. This point has been taken up with

relish by Cliff’s more orthodox critics, who now feel vindicated that

the Stalinist system has proved ephemeral and, as Trotsky predicted,

capitalism has been restored, albeit after some delay.

So, despite its practical appeal during the post-war era, Cliff’s theory

of state capitalism in Russia was theoretically, at least for orthodox

Trotskyists, fatally flawed. Indeed, for the more sophisticated

Trotskyists Cliff’s theory is usually dismissed with little more ado,

and then presented as an example of the weakness of all theories of

state capitalism. But Cliff’s theory of state capitalism in the USSR is

by no means the original or foremost one, although it is perhaps the

most well known. In the next issue we shall begin by considering other

theories of state capitalism in the USSR that have arisen amongst the

left communists before turning to examine Ticktin’s efforts to go beyond

both the theory of Russia as a degenerated workers’ state and state

capitalist theories.

Part II: Russia as a Non-mode of Production

Having disposed of the theory of the USSR as a 'degenerated workers'

state', Ticktin's theory presents itself as the most persuasive

alternative to the understanding of the USSR as capitalist.

Its strength is its attention to the empirical reality of the USSR and

its consideration of the specific forms of class struggle it was subject

to. However, while we acknowledge that the USSR must be understood as a

malfunctioning system, we argue that, because Ticktin doesn't relate his

categories of 'political economy' to the class struggle, he fails to

grasp the capitalist nature of the USSR.

Introduction

Here we present the second part of our article ‘What was the USSR?’. In

our last issue, we dealt with Trotsky’s theory that it was a

‘degenerated workers’ state’, and the best known theory of state

capitalism which has emerged within Trotskyism — that of Tony Cliff. Our

original intention was to follow that up by dealing with both the less

well-known theories of state capitalism developed by the left communists

and with Hillel Ticktin’s theory that sees itself as going beyond both

Trotsky’s theory and the state capitalist alternative. Due to

foreseeable circumstances totally within our control, we have been

unable to do this. Therefore we have decided not to combine these

sections, and instead here complete the trajectory of Trotskyism with an

account and critique of Ticktin’s theory, and put off our treatment of

the left communists till our next issue. However, this effective

extension of the article’s length leads us to answer some questions

readers may have. It can be asked: Why bother giving such an extended

treatment to this question? Isn’t the Russian Revolution and the regime

that emerged from it now merely of historical interest? Shouldn’t we be

writing about what is going on in Russia now? One response would be to

say that it is not possible to understand what is happening in Russia

now without grasping the history of the USSR. But, while that is true to

an extent, the detail we are choosing to give this issue does deserve

more explanation.

As Loren Goldner puts it, in a very interesting article published in

1991:

Into the mid-1970s, the ‘Russian question’ and its implications was the

inescapable ‘paradigm’ of political perspective on the left, in Europe

and the U.S. and yet 15 years later seems like such ancient history.

This was a political milieu where the minute study of the month-to-month

history of the Russian Revolution and the Comintern from 1917–1928

seemed the key to the universe as a whole. If someone said they believed

that the Russian Revolution had been defeated in 1919, 1921, 1923, 1927,

or 1936, or 1953, one had a pretty good sense of what they would think

on just about every other political question in the world: the nature of

the Soviet Union, of China, the nature of the world CPs, the nature of

Social Democracy, the nature of trade unions, the United Front, the

Popular Front, national liberation movements, aesthetics and philosophy,

the relationship of party and class, the significance of soviets and

workers’ councils, and whether Luxemburg or Bukharin was right about

imperialism.[39]

However, that period seems to be at a close. It seems clear that the

Russian Revolution and the arguments around it will not have the same

significance for those becoming involved in the revolutionary project

now as it did for previous generations.

Posing the issue slightly differently, Camatte wrote in 1972: “The

Russian Revolution and its involution are indeed some of the greatest

events of our century. Thanks to them, a horde of thinkers, writers and

politicians are not unemployed.“[40] Camatte usefully then draws

attention to the way that the production of theories on the USSR has

very often served purposes quite opposed to that of clarification of the

question. To be acknowledged as a proper political group or — as Camatte

would say — gang, it was seen as an essential requirement to have a

distinctive position or theory on the Soviet Union. But if Camatte

expressed reluctance to “place some new goods on the over-saturated

market”, he nonetheless and justifiably thought it worthwhile to do so.

But is our purpose as clear? For revolutionaries, hasn’t the position

that the Soviet Union was (state-) capitalist and opposed to human

liberation become fairly basic since ’68? Haven’t theories like

Trotsky’s that gave critical support to the Soviet Union been

comprehensively exposed? Well, yes and no. To simply assert that the

USSR was another form of capitalism and that little more need be said is

not convincing.

Around the same time as Camatte’s comments, the Trotskyist academic

Hillel Ticktin began to develop a theory of the nature and crisis of the

Soviet system which has come to hold a significant status and

influence.[41] Ticktin’s theory, with its attention to the empirical

reality of the USSR and its consideration of the specific forms of class

struggle it was subject to, is certainly the most persuasive alternative

to the understanding of the USSR as capitalist. But again it can be

asked who really cares about this issue? Ultimately we are writing for

ourselves, answering questions we feel important. To many it seems

intuitively the politically revolutionary position — to say the Soviet

Union was (state) capitalist and that is enough. We’d contend, however,

that a position appears to be revolutionary does not make it true, while

what is true will show itself to be revolutionary. For us, to know that

Russia was exploitative and opposed to human liberation and to call it

capitalist to make one’s condemnation clear is not enough. The

importance of Marx’s critique of political economy is not just that it

condemns capitalism, but that it understands it better than the

bourgeoisie and explains it better than moralistic forms of criticism.

The events in Russia at the moment, which reflect a profound failure to

turn it into an area for the successful accumulation of value, show that

in some ways the question of the USSR is not over. In dealing with this

issue we are not attempting to provide the final definitive solution to

the Russian question. Theory — the search for practical truth — is not

something that once arrived at is given from then on; it must always be

renewed or it becomes ideology.

The origins of Ticktin’s theory of the USSR

Introduction

In Part I we gave a lengthy treatment of what has probably been the best

known critical theory of the Soviet Union: Leon Trotsky’s theory of the

‘degenerated workers’ state’. While critical of the privileges of the

Stalinist bureaucracy, lack of freedom and workers’ democracy, Trotsky

took the view that the formal property relations of the USSR — i.e. that

the means of production were not private property but the property of a

workers’ state — meant that the USSR could not be seen as being

capitalist, but was instead a transitory regime caught between

capitalism and socialism which had degenerated. It followed from this

that, for Trotsky, despite all its faults and monstrous distortions, the

Soviet Union was ultimately progressive. As such, the Soviet Union was a

decisive advance over capitalism which, by preserving the proletarian

gains of the October Revolution, had to be defended against the military

and ideological attacks of the great capitalist powers.

However, as we saw, for Trotsky the Soviet Union’s predicament could not

for last long. Either the Russian working class would rise up and

reassert control over their state through a political revolution which

would depose the bureaucracy, or else the bureaucracy would seek to

preserve its precarious position of power by reintroducing private

property relations and restoring capitalism in Russia. Either way, for

Trotsky, the rather peculiar historical situation in which Russian

society found itself, stuck half-way between capitalism and socialism,

could only be a fleeting phenomena. Indeed, Trotsky believed that this

situation would be resolved one way or another in the immediate

aftermath of the second world war.

Yet, as we now know, Trotsky’s prediction that the Soviet Union would

soon be either overthrown by a workers’ revolution or else revert back

to capitalism with the bureaucracy converting itself into a new Russian

bourgeoisie failed to come about. Instead the USSR persisted for another

forty years rendering Trotsky’s theory increasingly untenable. As a

consequence many Trotskyists were led to break from the orthodox

Trotskyist position regarding Russia to argue that the USSR was state

capitalist. In Britain the main debate on the nature of Russia arose

between orthodox Trotskyism’s ‘degenerated workers’ state’ and the

neo-Trotskyist version of state capitalism developed by Tony Cliff. As

we pointed out in Part I, while the orthodox Trotskyist account

obviously had big problems, this alternative theory of state capitalism

had three vital weaknesses: 1) Cliff’s attempt to make the point of

counter-revolution and the introduction of state capitalism coincide

with Stalin’s first five year plan (and Trotsky’s exile); 2) his denial

that the law of value operated within the USSR; and 3) his orthodox

Marxist insistence that state capitalism was the highest stage of

capitalism which implied that the USSR was more advanced than Western

capitalism.[42]

As a result, throughout the post-war era, orthodox Trotskyists were able

dogmatically to defend Trotsky’s theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state; they were content that, while the rival state capitalist

theory may appear more politically intuitive, their own was more

theoretically coherent. Indeed, with the collapse of the Soviet Union in

1990, many Trotskyists felt vindicated in that Trotsky’s predictions of

the possible restoration of capitalism now seemed to have been proved

correct, albeit rather belatedly.[43]

However, there have been a few more sophisticated Trotskyists who, in

recognizing the inadequacies of the theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state, have sought to develop new conceptions of what the USSR

was and how it came to collapse. One of the most prominent of these has

been Hillel Ticktin.

Ticktin and the reconstruction of Trotskyism

By the 1970s, the chronic economic stagnation and gross economic

inefficiencies of Brezhnev’s Russia had become widely recognized. Few

‘sovietologists’ were not now sceptical of the production figures pumped

out by the Soviet authorities; and everyone was aware of the long queues

for basic necessities and the economic absurdities that seemed to

characterize the USSR.

Of course, Trotsky himself had argued that, in the absence of workers’

democracy, centralized state planning would lead to waste and economic

inefficiency. Yet, for Trotsky, it had been clear that, despite such

inefficiencies, bureaucratic planning would necessarily be superior to

the anarchy of the market. Yet it was now becoming apparent that the

gross inefficiencies and stagnation of the economy of the USSR were of

such a scale compared with economic performance in the West that its

economic and social system could no longer be considered as being

superior to free market capitalism.

In response to these perceptions of the USSR, orthodox Trotskyists,

while accepting the inefficiencies of bureaucratic planning, could only

argue that the reports of the economic situation in the Soviet Union

were exaggerated and obscured its real and lasting achievements. Yet it

was a line that not all Trotskyists found easy to defend.

As an academic Marxist specializing in the field of Russian and East

European studies, Ticktin could not ignore the critical analyses of the

Soviet Union being developed by both liberal and conservative

‘sovietologists’. In the face of the mounting evidence of the dire state

of the Russian economy it was therefore perhaps not so easy for Ticktin

to simply defend the standard Trotskyist line. As a result Ticktin came

to reject the orthodox Trotskyist theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state and the notion that the Soviet Union was objectively

progressive that this theory implied.

However, while he rejected the theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state, Ticktin refused to accept the notion that the USSR was

state capitalist. Immersed in the peculiarities of the Soviet Union,

Ticktin maintained the orthodox Trotskyist position that state

capitalist theories simply projected the categories of capitalism onto

the USSR. Indeed, for Ticktin the failure of all Marxist theories of the

Soviet Union was that they did not develop out of the empirical

realities of the USSR. For Ticktin the task was to develop a Marxist

theory of the USSR that was able to grasp the historical peculiarities

of the Soviet Union without falling foul of the shallow empiricism of

most bourgeois theories of the USSR.

However, in rejecting Trotsky’s theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state Ticktin was obliged to undertake a major re-evaluation of

Trotsky. After all, alongside his theory of permanent revolution and

uneven and combined development, Trotsky’s theory of the degenerated

workers’ state had been seen as central to both Trotsky and Trotskyism.

As Cliff’s adoption of a theory of state capitalism had shown, a

rejection of the theory of a degenerated workers’ state could prove

problematic for anyone who sought to maintain a consistent Trotskyist

position. However, as we shall see, through both his re-evaluation of

Trotsky and the development of his theory of the USSR, Ticktin has been

able to offer a reconstructed Trotskyism that, by freeing it from its

critical support for the Soviet Union, has cut the umbilical cord with a

declining Stalinism, providing the opportunity for a new lease of life

for Leninism in the post-Stalinist era.[44]

Ticktin and Trotsky’s theory of the transitional epoch

For orthodox Trotskyism, the theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state stood alongside both the theory of combined and uneven

development and the theory of permanent revolution as one of the central

pillars of Trotsky’s thought. For Ticktin, however, the key to

understanding Trotsky’s ideas was the notion of the transitional epoch.

Indeed, for Ticktin, the notion of the transitional epoch was the

keystone that held the entire structure of Trotsky’s thought together,

and it was only by fully grasping this notion that his various theories

could be adequately understood.

Of course, the notion that capitalism had entered its final stage and

was on the verge of giving way to socialism had been commonplace amongst

Marxists at the beginning of this century. Indeed, it had been widely

accepted by most leading theoreticians of the Second International that,

with the emergence of monopoly capitalism in the 1870s, the era of

classical capitalism studied by Marx had come to an end. As a result the

contradictions between the socialization of production and the private

appropriation of wealth were becoming ever more acute and could be only

be resolved through the working class coming to power and creating a new

socialist society.

Faced with the horrors and sheer barbarity of the first world war, many

Marxists had come to the conclusion that capitalism had entered its

final stage and was in decline. While nineteenth century capitalism,

despite all its faults, had at least served to develop the forces of

production at an unprecedented rate, capitalism now seemed to offer only

chronic economic stagnation and total war. As capitalism entered its

final stage the fundamental question could only be ‘war or revolution’,

‘socialism or barbarism’.[45]

Yet while many Marxists had come to the conclusion that the first world

war heralded the era of the transition from capitalism to socialism,

Ticktin argues that it was Trotsky who went furthest in drawing out both

the theoretical and political implications of this notion of the

transitional epoch. Thus, whereas most Marxists had seen the question of

transition principally in terms of particular nation-states, Trotsky

emphasized capitalism as a world system. For Trotsky, it was capitalism

as a world system that, with the first world war, had entered the

transitional epoch. From this global perspective there was not some

predetermined line of capitalist development which each nation-state had

to pass through before it reached the threshold of socialism. On the

contrary the development of more backward economies was conditioned by

the development of the more advanced nations.

It was to explain how the development of the backward nations of the

world were radically reshaped by the existence of more advanced nations

that Trotsky developed his theory of combined and uneven development. It

was then, on the basis of this theory of combined and uneven

development, that Trotsky could come to the conclusion that the

contradictions of the transitional epoch would become most acute, not in

the most advanced capitalist economies as most Marxists had assumed, but

in the more backward nations such as Russia that had yet to make the

full transition to capitalism. It was this conclusion that then formed

the basis of Trotsky’s theory of permanent revolution in which Trotsky

had argued that in a backward country such as Russia it would be

necessary for any bourgeois revolution to develop at once into a

proletarian revolution.

Thus, whereas most Marxists had assumed the revolution would break out

in the most advanced capitalist nations and, by destroying imperialism,

would spread to the rest of the world, Trotsky, through his notion of

the transitional epoch, had come to the conclusion that the revolution

was more likely to break out in the more backward nations. Yet Trotsky

had insisted that any such proletarian revolution could only be

successful if it served to spark proletarian revolution in the more

advanced nations. Without the aid of revolutions in these more advanced

nations any proletarian revolution in a backward country could only

degenerate.

Hence Trotsky was later able to explain the degeneration of the Russian

Revolution. The failure of the revolutionary movements that swept across

Europe following the end of the first world war had left the Russian

Revolution isolated. Trapped within its own economic and cultural

backwardness and surrounded by hostile capitalist powers, the Russian

workers’ state could only degenerate. With this then we have the basis

of Trotsky’s theory of the USSR as a degenerated workers’ state.

Yet the importance of Trotsky’s notion of transitional epoch was not

only that it allowed Trotsky to grasp the problems of transition on a

world scale, but also that it implied the possibility that this

transition could be a prolonged process. If proletarian revolutions were

more likely at first to break out in less advanced countries it was

possible that there could be several such revolutions before the

contradictions within the more advanced nations reached such a point to

ensure that such revolutionary outbreaks would lead to a world

revolution. Further, as happened with the Russian Revolution, the

isolation and subsequent degeneration of proletarian revolutions in the

periphery could then serve to discredit and thereby retard the

revolutionary process in the more advanced capitalist nations.

However, Ticktin argues that Trotsky failed to draw out such

implications of his notion of the transitional epoch. As a result

Trotsky severely underestimated the capacity of both social democracy

and Stalinism in forestalling world revolution and the global transition

to socialism. Armed with the hindsight of the post-war era, Ticktin has

sought to overcome this failing in the thought of his great teacher.

For Ticktin then, the first world war indeed marked the beginning of the

transitional epoch,[46] an epoch in which there can be seen a growing

struggle between the law of value and the immanent law of planning. With

the Russian Revolution, and the revolutionary wave that swept Europe

from 1918–24, the first attempt was made to overthrow capitalism on a

world scale. With the defeat of the revolutionary wave in Europe and the

degeneration of the Russian Revolution, capitalism found the means to

prolong itself. In the more advanced capitalist nations, under the

banner of social democracy, a combination of concessions to the working

class and the nationalization of large sections of industry allowed

capitalism to contain the sharpening social conflicts brought about by

the heightening of its fundamental contradiction between the

socialization of production and the private appropriation of wealth.

Yet these very means to prevent communism have only served to undermine

capitalism in the longer term. Concessions to the working class, for

example the development of a welfare state, and the nationalization of

large sections of industry have served to restrict and, as Radical

Chains put it, ‘partially suspend’ the operation of the law of

value.[47] With its basic regulatory principle — the law of value —

being progressively made non-operational, capitalism is ultimately

doomed. For Ticktin, even the more recent attempts by Thatcher and

‘neo-liberalism’ to reverse social democracy and re-impose the law of

value over the last two decades can only be short lived. The clearest

expression of this is the huge growth of parasitical finance capital

whose growth can ultimately only be at the expense of development truly

productive industrial capital.

As for Russia, Ticktin accepts Trotsky’s position that the Russian

Revolution overthrew capitalism and established a workers’ state, and

that with the failure of the revolutionary wave the Russian workers’

state had degenerated. However, unlike Trotsky, Ticktin argues that with

the triumph of Stalin in the 1930s the USSR ceased to be a workers’

state. With Stalin the bureaucratic elite had taken power. Yet, unable

to move back to capitalism without confronting the power of the Russian

working class, and unable and unwilling to move forward socialism since

this would undermine the elite’s power and privileges, the USSR became

stuck half-way between capitalism and socialism.

As a system that was nether fish nor foul — neither capitalism or

socialism — the USSR was an unviable system. A system that could only

preserve the gains of the October Revolution by petrifying them; and it

was a system that could only preserve itself through the terror of the

Gulag and the secret police.

Yet it was such a monstrous system that presented itself as being

socialist and demanded the allegiance of large sections of the world’s

working class. As such it came to discredit socialism, and, through the

dominance of Stalinism, cripple the revolutionary working class movement

throughout the world for more than five decades. Thus, although the USSR

served to restrict the international operation of the law of value by

removing millions from the world market, particularly following the

formation of the Eastern bloc and the Chinese Revolution, it also served

to prolong the transitional epoch and the survival of capitalism.

By drawing out Trotsky’s conception of the transitional epoch in this

way, Tictkin attempted finally to cut the umbilical between Trotskyism

and a declining Stalinism. Ticktin is thereby able to offer a

reconstructed Trotskyism that is free to denounce unequivocally both

Stalinism and the USSR. As we shall now see, in doing so Ticktin is led

to both exalt Trotsky’s theoretical capacities and pinpoint his

theoretical weaknesses.

Ticktin and the failure of Trotsky

Following Lenin’s death, and with the rise of Lenin’s personality cult,

Trotsky had endeavoured to play down the differences between himself and

Lenin. As a consequence, orthodox Trotskyists, ever faithful to the word

of Trotsky, had always sought to minimize the theoretical differences

between Lenin and Trotsky. For them Trotsky was merely the true heir to

Lenin.

However, by focusing on Trotsky’s key conception of the transitional

epoch, Ticktin is able cast new light on the significance of Trotsky’s

thought as a whole. For Ticktin, although he may well have been more

politically adept than Trotsky, Lenin’s overriding concern with

immediate Russian affairs constrained the development of his theoretical

thought at crucial points. In contrast, for Ticktin, the sheer

cosmopolitan breadth of Trotsky’s concerns in many respects placed

Trotsky above Lenin with regards to theoretical analysis.

But raising the standing of Trotsky as a theorist only serves to

underline an important question for Ticktin’s understanding of Trotsky.

If Trotsky was so intellectually brilliant why did he persist in

defending the USSR as a degenerated workers’ state long after lesser

intellects had recognized that such a position was untenable? To answer

this Ticktin puts forward several explanations.

First of all Ticktin argues that Trotsky made the mistake of regarding

Stalin as a ‘centrist’.[48] Throughout the period of the New Economic

Policy (NEP) what Trotsky feared more than anything was the restoration

of capitalism through the emergence of a new class of capitalist farmers

and middlemen. For Trotsky at this time, Stalin, and the bureaucratic

forces that he represented, was a bulwark against danger of capitalist

restoration. He was a lesser of two evils. Thus Trotsky had always ended

up deferring to Stalin rather than risk the triumph of the Right. It was

this attitude towards Stalin as a centrist that was carried through in

Trotsky’s perception of Stalin’s Russia throughout the 1930s.

While this immediate political orientation might explain the origin of

Trotsky’s position with regard to Stalin’s Russia of the 1930s it does

not explain why he persisted with it. To explain this Ticktin points to

the circumstances Trotsky found himself in. Ticktin argues that with his

exile from the USSR Trotsky found himself isolated. Being removed from

the centre of political and theoretical activity and dulled by ill

health and old age the sharpness of Trotsky’s thought began to suffer.

As a result, in the final few years of his life Trotsky could only cling

to the positions that he had developed up as far as the early 1930s.

The decline of Trotsky’s thought was further compounded by the weakness

of rival theories of the USSR with the Trotskyist movement. As we saw in

Part I, Trotsky was easily able to shoot down the theory originally put

forward by Bruno Rizzi, and later taken up by the minority faction

within the American SWP, which argued that the USSR was a new mode of

production that could be described as bureaucratic collectivism. The

ease with which Trotsky was able to dismiss such rival theories of the

nature of the USSR as being unMarxist meant that he was not obliged

seriously to reconsider his own position on the Soviet Union.

Yet, as Ticktin recognizes, while such circumstantial explanations as

old age, exile and lack of credible alternatives may have contributed to

an understanding of why Trotsky failed to radically revise his theory of

the nature of Stalin’s Russia they are far from constituting a

sufficient explanation in themselves. For Ticktin there is a fundamental

theoretical explanation for Trotsky’s failure to develop his theory of

the USSR at this time which arises due Trotsky’s relation to

Preobrazhensky.

For Ticktin, the fundamental obstacle which prevented Trotsky from

developing his critique of the USSR is to be found in the very origins

of this critique. As we saw in Part I, Trotsky’s theory of the USSR as a

degenerated workers’ state originated from earlier criticisms of the

Party leadership and the NEP that had been advanced by the Left

Opposition during the 1920s. In advancing these criticisms, there had

been a distinct division of labour. Trotsky, as the sole member of the

Left Opposition within the Politburo, had concentrated on the broad

political issues and detailed questions of policy. Preobrazhensky, on

the other hand, had been left to set out the ‘economics’ which underlay

these political and policy positions of the Left Opposition.

As we saw in Part I, Preobrazhensky had sought to develop a political

economy for the period of the transition of Russia from capitalism to

socialism in terms of the struggle between the two regulating mechanisms

of capitalism and socialism that had been identified by the classical

Marxism of the Second International. For the orthodox Marxism of the

Second International, the basic regulating principle of capitalism was

the blind operation of the ‘law of value’. In contrast, the basic

regulating principle of socialism was to be conscious planning. Form

this Preobrazhensky had argued that during the period of transition from

capitalism to socialism these two principles of economic organization

would necessary co-exist and as such would be in conflict with each

other.

However, for Preobrazhensky, in the relatively backward conditions

prevailing in Russia there was no guarantee that the principle of

planning would prevail over the law of value on purely economic grounds.

Hence, for Preobrazhensky, it was necessary for the proletarian state to

actively intervene in order to accelerate accumulation in those sectors

of the economy, such as state industry, where the principle of planning

predominated at the expense of those sectors, such as peasant

agriculture, where the law of value still held sway. It was this theory

of ‘primitive socialist accumulation’ which had underpinned the Left

Opposition’s criticisms of the NEP and their advocacy of an alternative

policy of rapid industrialization.

When Stalin finally abandoned the NEP in favour of centralized planning

embodied in the five year plans many members of the Left Opposition,

including Preobrazhensky himself, took the view that the Party

leadership had finally, if rather belatedly, come round to their

position of rapid industrialization. As a consequence, Preobrazhensky

along with other former members of the Left Opposition fully embraced

Stalin’s new turn and fell in line with leadership of the Party.

Trotsky, on the other, maintained a far more critical attitude to

Stalin’s new turn.

Of course, even if he had wanted to, Trotsky was in no position to fall

in behind Stalin and the leadership of the Party. Trotsky was too much

of an enemy and rival to Stalin for that. However, Trotsky’s broader

political perspective allowed him to maintain and develop a critique of

Stalin’s Russia. While Trotsky welcomed Stalin’s adoption of a policy of

centralized planning and rapid industrialization he argued that it was

too long delayed. The sudden zig-zags of policy from one extreme

position to another were for Trotsky symptomatic of the

bureaucratization of the state and Party and indicated the degeneration

of Russia as a workers’ state.

Through such criticisms Trotsky came to formulate his theory of the USSR

as a degenerated workers’ state. Yet while Trotsky was able to develop

his critique of the new Stalinist regime in political terms, that is as

the political domination of a distinct bureaucratic caste that had taken

over the workers’ state, he failed to reconsider the political economy

of Stalin’s Russia. In accordance with the old division of labour

between himself and Preobrazhensky, Trotsky implicitly remained content

with the political economy of transition that had been advanced in the

1920s by Preobrazhensky.

For Ticktin it was this failure to develop Preobrazhensky’s political

economy of transition in the light of Stalin’s Russia that proved to be

the Achilles’ heel of Trotsky’s theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state. Of course, given that Trotsky could at the time

reasonably expect the USSR to be a short-lived phenomenon he could

perhaps be excused from neglecting the long and arduous task of

developing a political economy of the USSR. For Ticktin, his followers

have had no such excuse. As we shall now see, for Ticktin the central

task in developing Trotsky’s analysis of the nature of the Soviet Union

has been to develop a political economy of the USSR.

Ticktin and the political economy of the USSR

So, for Ticktin, the Achilles’ heel of Trotsky’s theory of the USSR as a

degenerated workers’ state was his failure to develop a political

economy of Stalinist Russia. Yet, at the same time, Ticktin rejected the

notion that the USSR was in any way capitalist. For him, Trotsky had

been correct in seeing the October revolution, and the subsequent

nationalization of the means of production under a workers’ state, as a

decisive break from capitalism. As such any attempt to develop a

political economy of the USSR could not simply apply the categories

developed by Marx in his critique of capitalism since the USSR had

ceased to be capitalist. Instead it was necessary to develop a new

political economy of the USSR as a specific social and economic system.

Ticktin began his attempt to develop such a political economy of the

USSR in 1973 with an article entitled ‘Towards a political economy of

the USSR’ which was published in the first issue of Critique. This was

followed by a series of articles and polemics in subsequent issues of

Critique and culminated, 19 years later, with his Origins of the Crisis

in the USSR: Essays on the Political Economy of a Disintegrating System.

Although Ticktin’s work undoubtedly provides important insights into

what the USSR was and the causes of its crisis and eventual collapse —

and as such provides an important challenge to any alternative theory of

the USSR — after all these years he fails to provide a systematic

political economy of the USSR. As the subtitle to Origins of the Crisis

in the USSR indicates, his attempt to develop a political economy of the

USSR was overtaken by events and all we are left with is a series of

essays which seek to link his various attempts to develop a political

economy of the USSR with an explanation of the Soviet Union’s eventual

demise.

As we shall argue, this failure to develop a systematic presentation of

a political economy of the USSR was no accident. For us it was a failure

rooted in his very premise of his analysis which he derives from

Trotsky. Yet before considering such an argument we must first of all

briefly review Ticktin’s attempt to develop a political economy of the

USSR.

A Question of Method?

The task facing Ticktin of developing a Marxist political economy of the

USSR was not as straightforward as it may seem. What is political

economy? For Marx, political economy was the bourgeois science par

excellence. It was the science that grew up with the capitalist mode of

production in order to explain and justify it as a natural and objective

social and economic system. When Marx came to write Capital he did not

aim to write yet another treatise on political economy of capitalism —

numerous bourgeois writers had done this already — but rather he sought

to develop a critique of political economy.

However, even if we admit that in order to make his critique of

political economy Marx had to develop and complete bourgeois political

economy, the problem remains of how far can a political economy be

constructed for a mode of production other than capitalism? After all it

is only with the rise capitalism, where the social relations come to

manifest themselves as relations between things, that the political

economy as an objective science becomes fully possible. But this is not

all. Ticktin is not merely seeking to develop a political economy for a

mode of production other than capitalism but for system in transition

from one mode of production to another — indeed for a system that

Ticktin himself comes to conclude is a ‘non-mode of production’!

Unfortunately Ticktin not only side-steps all these preliminary

questions, but he also fails to address the most important

methodological questions of how to begin and how to proceed with his

proposed ‘political economy’ of the USSR. Instead he adopts a rather

heuristic approach, adopting various points of departure to see how far

he can go. It is only when these reach a dead end that we find Ticktin

appealing to questions of method. As a result we find a number of false

starts that Ticktin then seeks to draw together. Let us begin by briefly

examine some of these false starts.

Class

In Origins of the Crisis in the USSR, Ticktin begins with an analysis of

the three main groups and classes that could be identified within the

USSR: namely, the elite, the Intelligentsia and the working class.

Through this analysis Ticktin is then able to develop a framework

through which to understand the social and political forces lying behind

the policies of Glasnost and Perestroika pursued in the final years of

the USSR’s decline. Yet, despite the usefulness such class analysis may

have in explaining certain political developments within the USSR, it

does not itself amount to a ‘political economy of the USSR’. Indeed, if

we take Marx’s Capital as a ‘model of a political economy’, as Ticktin

surely does, then it is clear that class analysis must be a result of a

political economy not its premise.[49]

Laws

If ‘class’ proves to be a non-starter in developing a political economy

of the USSR then a more promising starting point may appear to be an

analysis of the fundamental laws through which it was regulated. Of

course, as we have seen, this was the approach that had been pioneered

by Preobrazhensky and adopted by Trotsky and the Left Opposition in the

1920s. Preobrazhensky had argued that the nature of the transition from

capitalism to socialism had to be grasped in terms of the conflict

between the two regulating mechanism of capitalism and socialism: that

is between the law of value and the law of planning. Indeed, as we have

also seen, one of Ticktin’s most important criticisms of Trotsky was his

failure to develop Preobrazhensky’s political economy of the Soviet

Union after the triumph of Stalin in the early 1930s.

It is not surprising then that we find Ticktin repeatedly returning to

this line of approach in his various attempts to develop a political

economy of the USSR. Ticktin proceeds by arguing that Preobrazhensky’s

theory was correct for Russia up until the collectivization of

agriculture and the first five year plan. Up until then there had

existed a large market-oriented peasant agricultural sector alongside a

state-owned and planned industrial sector (although even this was still

based on quasi-autonomous enterprises run on a ‘profit and loss’

criteria). As such, the ‘law of planning’[50] and the law of value

co-existed as distinct regulating mechanisms — although they both

conflicted and conditioned each other through the relations both between

and within the industrial and the agricultural sectors of the economy.

With the abolition of peasant agriculture through forced

collectivization, and the introduction of comprehensive central planning

geared towards the rapid industrialization of Russia, the two laws could

no longer co-exist as distinct regulatory mechanisms that predominated

in different sectors of the economy. The two laws ‘interpenetrated’ each

other, preventing each other’s proper functioning. As a result there

emerged under Stalin a system based neither on the law of value nor on

the law of planning. Indeed, for Ticktin these laws degenerated, the law

of planning giving rise to the ‘law of organization’ and the law of

value giving rise to the ‘law of self-interest of the individual unit’.

Yet it soon becomes clear that as the number of laws in Ticktin’s

analysis proliferate their explanatory power diminishes. In the Origins

of the Crisis in the USSR, where he pursues this line of argument the

furthest, Ticktin is eventually obliged to ask the question what he

means by a ‘law’. He answers that a law is the movement between tow

poles of a contradiction but he does not then go on consider the ground

of these contradictions.

Waste

Perhaps Ticktin’s most promising point of departure is that of the

problem of the endemic waste that was so apparent even for the least

critical of observers of the USSR. This became most clearly evident in

the stark contrast between the increasing amounts the Soviet economy was

able to produce and the continued shortages of even the most basic

consumer goods in the shops.

Following the rapid industrialization of the USSR under Stalin the

Soviet Union could boast that it could rival any country in the world in

terms of absolute levels of production of industrial products. This was

particularly true for heavy and basic industries. Russia’s production of

such products as coal, iron, steel, concrete and so forth had grown

enormously in merely a few decades. Yet alongside such colossal advances

in the quantity of goods produced, which had accompanied the startling

transformation of Russia from a predominantly peasant society into an

industrialized economy, the standard of living for most people had grown

very slowly. Despite repeated attempts to give greater priority to the

production in consumer industries from the 1950s onwards, the vast

majority of the population continued to face acute shortages of basic

consumer goods right up until the demise of the USSR.

So while the apologists of the USSR could triumphantly greet the

publication of each record-breaking production figure, their critics

merely pointed to the lengthy shopping queues and empty shops evident to

any visitor to Russia. What then explained this huge gap between

production and consumption? For Ticktin, as for many other theorists of

the USSR, the reason clearly lay in the huge waste endemic to the

Russian economic system.

Although Russian industry was able to produce in great quantities, much

of this production was substandard. Indeed a significant proportion of

what was produced was so substandard as to be useless. This problem of

defective production became further compounded since, in an economy as

integrated and self-contained as the USSR, the outputs of each industry

in the industrial chain of production became the inputs of tools,

machinery or raw materials for subsequent industries in the chain.

Indeed. in many industries more labour had to be devoted to repairing

defective tools, machinery and output than in actual production!

As a result, waste swallowed up ever increasing amounts of labour and

resources. This, together with the great resistance to the introduction

of new technology and production methods in existing factories, meant

that huge amounts of labour and resources had to be invested in heavy

industry in order to provide the inputs necessary to allow just a small

increase in the output of consumer goods at the end of the industrial

chain of production.

Taking this phenomenon of ‘waste’, Ticktin sought to find a point of

departure for a political economy of the USSR analogous to that which is

found in the opening chapter of Marx’s Capital. In Capital Marx begins

with the immediate appearance of the capitalist mode of production in

which wealth appears as an ‘immense accumulation of commodities’. Marx

then analysed the individual commodity and found that it is composed of

two contradictory aspects: exchange-value and use-value. By examining

how this contradictory social form of the commodity is produced Marx was

then able to develop a critique of all the categories of political

economy.

Likewise, Ticktin sought to take as his starting point the immediate

appearance of the Soviet economic system. However, for Ticktin, this

economic system did not present itself as an immense accumulation of

commodities. Indeed, for Ticktin, wealth did not assume the specific

social form of the commodity as it does for capitalist societies.

Of course, as Bettelheim has pointed out, although all production is

formally state owned actual production is devolved into competing units.

These units of production, the enterprise and the various trusts, buy

and sell products to each other as well as selling products to

consumers. Therefore the market and commodities still persisted in the

USSR. In response, Ticktin argues that such buying and selling was

strictly subordinated to the central plan and were more like transfers

of products rather than real sales. While money was also transferred as

a result of these product transfers such transactions were simply a form

of accounting with strict limits being placed on the amount of profits

that could be accumulated as a result. Furthermore, the prices of

products were not determined through the market but were set by the

central plan. These prices were as a result administered prices and were

therefore not a reflection of value. Products did not therefore assume

the form of commodities nor did they have a value in the Marxist sense.

Hence, for Ticktin, the wealth did not present itself as an immense

accumulation of commodities as it does under capitalism but rather as an

immense accumulation of defective products.

So, for Ticktin, since products did not assume the form of commodities,

the elementary contradiction of Soviet political economy could not be

that between use-value and value, as it was within the capitalist mode

of production. Instead, Ticktin argued that the elementary contradiction

of the Soviet system presented itself as the contradiction between the

potential use-value of the product and its real use-value. That is, the

product was produced for the purpose of meeting a social need determined

through the mediation of the bureaucracy’s ‘central plan’; as such, it

assumed the ‘administered form’ of an intended or potential use-value.

However, in general, the use-value of the product fell far short of the

intended or potential use-value — it was defective. Thus as Ticktin

concludes:

The waste in the USSR then emerges as the difference between what the

product promises and what it is. The difference between the appearance

of planning and socialism and the reality of a harsh bureaucratised

administration shows itself in the product itself.

(Origins of the Crisis in the USSR, p. 134)

The question then arises as to how this contradiction emerged out of the

process of production which produced such products.

For Marx the key to understanding the specific nature of any class

society was to determine the precise way in which surplus-labour was

extracted from direct producers. With the capitalist mode of production,

the direct producers are dispossessed of both the means of production

and the means of subsistence. With no means of supporting themselves on

their own accord, the direct producers are obliged to sell their

labour-power to the capitalist class which owns the means of production.

However, despite how it may appear to each individual worker, in buying

the labour-power of the workers the capitalists do not pay according to

the amount of labour the workers perform, and thus the amount of value

the workers create, but they pay the level of wages required to

reproduce the labour-power of the workers as a whole. Since workers can

create products with a value greater than the value they require to

reproduce their own labour-power, the capitalists are able to extract

surplus-labour in the form of the surplus-value of the product the

workers produce.

Thus for Marx the key to understanding the essential nature of the

capitalist mode of production was the sale of the worker’s labour-power

and the consequent expropriation of surplus-labour in the specific

social form of surplus-value by the class of capitalists. For Ticktin,

however, the workers in the USSR did not sell their labour-power.[51]

Yet, although he denies that labour-power was sold in the USSR, Ticktin

does not deny that the working class was dispossessed of the means of

production. There is no question that Ticktin rejects any idea that the

workers somehow owned their means of production due to the persistence

of some form of ‘degenerated workers’ state’. Indeed, it is central to

Ticktin’s argument that the workers alienate the product of their

labour.

However, the dispossession of the direct producers of the means of

production is not the only essential pre-condition for the sale of

labour-power. The other all-important pre-condition of the capitalist

mode of production is that there exists generalized commodity exchange.

If, as Ticktin maintains, there was no generalized commodity exchange in

the USSR — and thus, as he infers, neither value nor real money — how

could labour-power itself assume the form of a commodity that could be

sold?

Of course, Ticktin admits that workers were formally paid wages in the

USSR, just as goods were bought and sold, but for him this did not

amount to the real sale of labour-power. To understand why Ticktin

thought this, it is necessary to look at his conception of the wage and

money in the USSR.

Under capitalism the principal if not exclusive means of obtaining

wealth is money. For the worker, money assumes the form of the wage.

However, in the USSR, money, and therefore the wage, was far from being

a sufficient or exclusive means of obtaining the worker’s needs. Other

factors were necessary to obtain the goods and services the worker

needed — such as time to wait in queues, connections and influence with

well-placed people in the state or Party apparatus, and access to the

black market. Such factors, together with the fact that a large

proportion of the workers’ needs were provided for free or were highly

subsidized — such as housing, child-care, and transport — meant that the

wage was far less important to the Russian worker than to his or her

Western counterpart. In fact it could be concluded that the wage was

more like a pension than a real wage.

Under capitalism the wage appears to the individual worker as the price

of their labour. The more that individual workers labour the more they

are paid. As a consequence, the wage serves as a direct incentive for

each individual worker to work for the capitalist.[52] In the USSR, the

wage, being little more than a pension, was a far weaker incentive for

the Soviet worker.

But not only was the wage an inadequate carrot, management lacked the

stick of unemployment. Under capitalism the threat of the sack or

redundancy is an important means through which management can discipline

its workforce and ensure its control over production. In the USSR,

however, the state guaranteed full employment. As a result, managers,

facing chronic labour shortages, had little scope to use the threat of

dismissals to discipline the work force.

Lacking both the carrot of money-wages and the stick of unemployment,

management was unable to gain full control of the workers’ labour. From

this Ticktin concludes that, although the workers may have been paid

what at first sight appears as a wage, in reality they did not sell

their labour-power since the workers retained a substantial control over

the use of their labour. As the old British Rail workers’ adage had it:

“management pretends to pay us and we pretend to work!”

However, although for Ticktin the workers in the USSR did not sell their

labour-power, and therefore did not alienate their labour, Ticktin still

argues that the workers alienated the product of their labour. Since the

workers were alienated from the product of their labour they had no

interest in it. Therefore the workers’ main concern in exercising their

control over their own labour was to minimize it. On the other side,

management, although taking possession of the final product of the

labour process, lacked full control over the labour process that

produced it. As a result, the elite lacked control over the production

of the total product of the economy, and with this the production of

surplus-product necessary to support itself.

It is with this that Ticktin locates the basis of the fundamental

contradiction of the Soviet system. On the one side stood the demands of

the elite for increased production necessary to secure the extraction of

a surplus-product; on the other side, and in opposition to it, stood the

negative control of the working class over the labour process which

sought to minimize its labour. The resolution of this contradiction was

found in defective production.

Through the imposition of the central plan, the elite sought to

appropriate the products of the labour of the working class necessary

both to maintain its own privileged position and for the expanded

reproduction of the system as a whole. To ensure the extraction of a

surplus-product that would be sufficient to meet its own privileged

needs, and at the same time ensure the expansion of the system, the

elite was obliged to set ambitious and ever-increasing production

targets through the system of central planning.

However, the actual implementation of the central plan had to be

devolved to the management of each individual enterprise. Faced with the

ambitious production targets set out in the central plan on the one side

and the power of the working class over the labour process on the other,

the management of the enterprise were obliged to strike a compromise

with its workers which in effect subverted the intentions of the plan

while at the same time appearing to fulfil its specifications. To do

this, management sought to meet the more verifiable criteria of the

plan, which were usually its more quantifiable aspects, while

surrendering the plan’s less verifiable qualitative criteria. As a

consequence, quality was sacrificed for quantity, leading to the

production of defective products.

Yet this was not all. In order to protect itself from the

ever-increasing unrealizable demands of the central planners, the

management of individual enterprises resorted to systematically

misinforming the centre concerning the actual conditions of production

at the same time as hoarding workers and scarce resources. Without

reliable information on the actual conditions of production, the

production plans set out in the central plan became increasingly

divorced from reality, which led to the further malfunctioning of the

economic system which compounded defective production through the

misallocation of resources.

Thus, for Ticktin, because the Russian workers did not sell their

labour-power, although they alienated the product of their labour, the

elite was unable fully to control the labour process. As a consequence

the economic system was bedevilled by waste on a colossal scale to the

point where it barely functioned. As neither capitalism nor socialism,

the USSR was in effect a non-mode of production. As such, the crucial

question was not how the USSR functioned as an economic system but how

it was able to survive for so long. It was in addressing this problem

that Ticktin came to analyse the crisis and disintegration of the USSR.

The question of commodity fetishism and ideology in the USSR

Despite the fact that the capitalist mode of production is based on

class exploitation, capitalist society has yet to be torn apart and

destroyed by class antagonisms. The reason for the persistence of

capitalist society is that the capitalist mode of production gives rise

to a powerful ideology that is rooted in its very material existence.

The basis of this ideology lies in commodity fetishism.[53] In a society

based on generalized commodity exchange, the relations between people

appear as a relation between things. As a result, social relations

appear as something objective and natural. Furthermore, in so far as

capitalism is able to present itself as a society of generalized

commodity exchange, everyone appears as a commodity-owner/citizen. As

such, everyone is as free and equal as everyone else to buy and sell.

Thus it appears that the worker, at least in principle, is able to

obtain a fair price for his labour, just as much as the capitalist is

able to obtain a fair return on his capital and the landlord a fair rent

on his land.

So capitalist society appears as a society which is not only natural but

one in which everyone is free and equal. However, this ‘free market’

ideology is not simply propaganda. It arises out of the everyday

experience of the capitalist mode of production in so far as it exists

as a market economy. It is therefore an ideology that is rooted in the

everyday reality of capitalism.[54] Of course, the existence of

capitalism as a ‘market economy’ is only one side of the capitalist mode

of production and the more superficial side at that. Nevertheless it

provides a strong and coherent foundation for bourgeois ideology.

However, if, as Ticktin maintains, there was no commodity exchange in

the USSR there could no basis for commodity fetishism. Furthermore,

lacking any alternative to commodity fetishism which could obscure the

exploitative nature of the system, there could be no basis for a

coherent ideology in the USSR. Instead there was simply the ‘big lie’

which was officially propagated that the USSR was a socialist

society.[55] But this was a lie which no one any longer really believed

— although everyone was obliged to pretend that they did believe it.[56]

As a consequence, Ticktin argues that the nature of social relations

were fully transparent in the USSR. With their privileged access to

goods and services, everyone could see the privileged position of the

elite and their exploitative and parasitical relation to the rest of

society. At the same time, given the blatant waste and inefficiency of

the system, no one had any illusions in the efficacy of ‘socialist

planning’. Everyone recognized that the system was a mess and was run in

the interests of a small minority that made up the elite of the state

and Party bureaucracy.

But if the was no ideology in the USSR, what was it that served to hold

this exploitative system together for more than half a century? Ticktin

argues there were two factors that served to maintain the USSR for so

long. First, there were the concessions made to the working class. The

guarantee of full employment, free education and health care, cheap

housing and transport and an egalitarian wage structure all served to

bind the working class to the system. Second, and complementing the

first, there was brutal police repression which, by suppressing the

development of ideas and collective organization not sanctioned by the

state, served to atomize the working class and prevent it from becoming

a revolutionary class for-itself.

It was through this crude carrot-and-stick approach that the elite

sought to maintain the system and their privileged place within it.

However, it was an approach that was riven by contradictions and one

that was ultimately unviable. As we have seen, it was these very

concessions made to the working class, particularly that of full

employment, which meant that the elite were unable to gain full control

of the labour process and which in turn resulted in the gross

inefficiency of the system. Unwilling to surrender their own privileged

position, the Soviet elite were unable to move towards socialism.

Therefore the elite’s only alternative to maintaining the grossly

inefficient system of the USSR was to move towards capitalism by

introducing the market. But such a move towards the market necessarily

involved the introduction of mass unemployment and the withdrawal of the

elite’s concessions to the working class.

The elite therefore faced a continual dilemma. On the one side it sought

to move away from its inefficient economic system by introducing market

reforms; but on the other side it feared that the introduction of such

reforms would cause a revolutionary response in the Russian working

class. Ticktin argues that it was this dilemma which underlay the

history of the USSR following the death of Stalin and which explains the

crisis that confronted Gorbachev and the final demise of the USSR.

Ticktin’s analysis of the history of the USSR and its final crisis and

demise does not concern us here.[57] We now need to examine the problems

of Ticktin’s ‘political economy’ of the USSR.

Problems of Ticktin’s ‘political economy of the USSR’

We have devoted considerable space to Ticktin’s theory of the USSR since

it provides perhaps the most cogent explanation of the nature of the

USSR and the causes of its decline which has arisen out of the

Trotskyist tradition. Shorn of any apology for Stalinism, Ticktin is

able to develop a theory which seeks to show the specific internal

contradictions of the Soviet system. As such, it is a theory that not

only goes beyond the traditional Trotskyist theory of the USSR as a

degenerated workers’ state, it also provides a formidable challenge to

any approach which sees the USSR as having been in some sense a

capitalist system.

Indeed, it would seem to us that any attempt to develop a theory of the

USSR as being essentially a capitalist system must take on board and

develop a critique of some of the central positions put forward by

Ticktin. Perhaps most importantly, after Ticktin and of course the

collapse he describes, it is obvious that the USSR can in no way be seen

as some higher and more developed stage of capitalism, as some state

capitalist theories might imply. What becomes clear from Ticktin is that

any understanding of the USSR must start from its malfunctioning: it

must explain the systematic waste and inefficiencies that it produced.

If the USSR was in any way capitalist it must have been a deformed

capitalism, as we shall argue.

However, while we accept that Ticktin provides a powerful theory of the

USSR, we also argue that it has important deficiencies which lead us

ultimately to reject his understanding of the nature of the USSR.

When we come to develop and present our own theory of the USSR, we will

necessarily have to critique in detail the central premise of Ticktin’s

theory — that the USSR was in transition from capitalism to socialism.

For the moment, however, we will confine ourselves to criticizing the

problems that arise within the theory itself.

As we have already noted, Ticktin not only fails to present a systematic

presentation of a ‘political economy of the USSR’, he also fails to

clarify his methodological approach. As a result, Ticktin is able to

escape from addressing some important logical questions regarding the

categories of his political economy.

Although he attacks state capitalist theories for projecting categories

of capitalism onto the Soviet Union, Ticktin himself has to admit that

many categories of bourgeois political economy appeared to persist in

the USSR. Categories such as ‘money’, ‘prices’, ‘wages’ and even

‘profits’. In capitalism these categories are forms that express a real

content even though they may obscure or deviate from this content. As

such they are not merely illusions but are real. Ticktin, however, fails

to specify how he understands the relation between the essential

relations of the political economy of the USSR and how these relations

make their appearance, and is therefore unable to clarify the

ontological status of such apparent forms as ‘money’, ‘prices’, ‘wages’

and ‘profits’. Indeed, in his efforts to deny the capitalist nature of

the USSR, Ticktin is pushed to the point where he has to imply that such

categories are simply relics of capitalism, empty husks that have no

real content. But, of course, if they have no real content, if they are

purely nominal, how is that they continue to persist? This failure to

address fully the question of form and content becomes most apparent

with the all important example of the wage and the sale of labour-power.

The Wage-Form

As we have seen, the crux of Ticktin’s analysis of the USSR was his

contention that, although they alienated the product of their labour,

Soviet workers did not sell their labour-power. So, although they were

paid what at first sight appears as a wage, on close inspection what the

workers received was in fact more akin to a pension.

However, in his attempt to compare and contrast the form of the wage as

it exists under capitalism with what existed in the USSR in order to

deny the application of capitalist categories to the Soviet Union,

Ticktin fails to gasp the full complexities of the wage-form as it

exists within the capitalist mode of production. As we have already

noted, under capitalism workers are obliged to sell their labour-power

to the capitalists. However, to both the individual capitalist and the

individual worker, this sale of labour-power appears in the wage-form as

not the sale of labour-power as such but the sale of labour;[58] that

is, the worker appears not to be paid in accordance to the value of his

labour-power (i.e. the value incorporated in the commodities required to

reproduce the worker’s capacity to work), but in terms of labour-time

the worker performs for the capitalist.

There is, therefore, a potential contradiction between the wage-form and

its real content — the sale of labour-power — which may become manifest

if the wages paid to the workers are insufficient to reproduce fully the

labour-power of the working class. There are two principal situations

where this may occur. First, an individual capitalist may be neither

willing nor able to offer sufficient hours for an individual worker to

be able to earn a ‘living wage’. Second, the individual capitalist may

pay a wage sufficient to reproduce the individual worker but not enough

to meet the cost of living necessary for the worker to bring up and

educate the next generation of workers. In this case, the individual

capitalist pays a wage that is insufficient to reproduce the

labour-power in the long term.

In both these cases the interests of the individual capitalist conflicts

with the interests of capital in general which requires the reproduction

of the working class as a whole. Of course, this is also true in the

case of unemployment. An individual capital has little interest in

paying workers a wage if it has no work for them to do that can make it

a profit; however, social capital requires an industrial reserve army of

the unemployed — unemployed labour-power — in order to keep wages down,

and this has to be maintained. The result is that the state has to

intervene, often under pressure from the working class itself, in order

to overcome the conflict of interest between individual capitals and

social capital. It was through this imperative that the welfare state

was formed. Health care, free state education and welfare benefits all

have to be introduced to overcome the deficiencies of the wage-form in

the social reproduction of the working class.

Thus, under capitalism, there is always an underlying tension within the

wage-form between the wage being simply a payment for labour-time and

the wage as a payment to cover the needs of the worker and her family.

As a result, under capitalism, the payments made to ensure the

reproduction of the labour-power of the working class is always composed

not only of the wage but also benefits and payments in kind. In this

light, the USSR only appears as an extreme example in which the needs of

social capital have become paramount and completely subsume those of the

individual capital.

Labour-Power as a Commodity

Yet, in denying the capitalist nature of the USSR, Ticktin also argues

that the working class did not sell its labour-power in the USSR because

labour-power did not exist as a commodity. But then again, as Ticktin

fails to recognize, labour-power does not exist immediately as a

commodity under capitalism either. A commodity is some thing that is

alienable and separable from its owner which is produced for sale.

However, labour-power is not produced primarily for sale, although the

capitalist may regard it as such, but for its own sake. It is after all

simply the potential living activity of the worker and is reproduced

along with the worker herself: and as such it also inseparable from the

worker.

Labour-power is therefore not immediately a commodity but must be

subsumed as such in its confrontation with capital. Labour-power

therefore is a commodity which is not a commodity; and this does not

simply cease to be the case when it is sold. Normally when someone buys

a commodity they obtain the exclusive possession and use of it as a

thing — the commodity ceasing to have any connection with its original

owner. But this cannot be the case with labour-power. Labour-power, as

the subjective activity of the worker, is inseparable from the worker as

a subject. Although the worker sells her labour-power to the capitalist,

she must still be present as a subject within the labour process where

her labour-power is put to use by the capitalist.

Capital must continue to subsume labour-power to the commodity form and

this continues right into the labour process itself. The struggle

between capital and labour over the labour process is central to the

capitalist mode of production. The attempt to overcome the power of the

working class at the point of production is the driving force of

capitalist development, with the capitalists forced to revolutionize the

methods of production in order to maintain their upper hand over the

resistance of their workers.

The fact that the workers in the USSR were able to assert considerable

control over the labour process does not necessarily mean that they did

not sell their labour-power. It need only mean that, given the state

guarantee of full employment, the workers enjoyed an exceptionally

favourable position with regard to management and were able to resist

the full subsumption of labour-power to the commodity form within the

labour process.

Again, as with the case of the wage-form, it could be argued that the

difference between the USSR and the capitalism that exists in the West,

at least in terms of the essential relation of wage-labour, was simply a

question of degree rather than of kind. The failure to recognize this

and grasp the full complexities of the wage-form and the commodification

of labour-power could be seen as a result of Ticktin’s restrictive

understanding of capitalism which he inherits from objectivist orthodox

Marxism.

First, in accordance with orthodox Marxism, Ticktin sees the essential

nature of capitalism in terms of the operation of the ‘law of value’.

Hence, for Ticktin, if there is no market there can be no operation of

the ‘law of value’ and hence there can be no capitalism. Having shown

that products were not bought and sold in the USSR, Ticktin has all but

shown that the USSR was not capitalist. The demonstration that even

labour-power was not really sold simply clinches the argument.

However, we would argue that the essence of capitalism is not the

operation of the ‘law of value’ as such but value as alienated labour

and its consequent self-expansion as capital. In this case, it is the

alienation of labour through the sale of labour-power that is

essential.[59] The operation of the ‘law of value’ through the sale of

commodities on the market is then seen as merely a mode of appearance of

the essential relations of value and capital.

Second, Ticktin fails to grasp the reified character of the categories

of political economy. As a consequence, he fails to see how

labour-power, for example, is not simply given but constituted through

class struggle. For Ticktin, there is the ‘movement of the categories

and the movement of class struggle’ as if they were two externally

related movements. As a result, as soon as the working class becomes

powerful enough to restrict the logic of capital — for example in

imposing control over the capitalist’s use of labour-power — then

Ticktin must see a decisive shift away from capitalism. Ticktin is led

to restrict capitalism in its pure and unadulterated form to a brief

period in the mid-nineteenth century.[60]

The Question of the Transitional Epoch

As Ticktin admits, contemporary capitalism has involved widespread

nationalization of production and the administration of prices, the

provision of welfare and the social wage; moreover, in the two decades

following the second world war, capitalism was able to maintain a

commitment to near full employment. As such, contemporary capitalism,

particularly in the years following the second world war, had features

that were strikingly familiar to those in the USSR. However, for

Ticktin, such social democratic features of twentieth century capitalism

were simply symptoms of the decline of capitalism in the transitional

epoch. The USSR was therefore only like contemporary capitalism insofar

as both Russia and Western capitalism were part of the same transitional

epoch: the global transition of capitalism into socialism. Whereas in

the USSR the ‘law of value’ had become completely negated, in the West

the advance of social democracy meant only the partial negation of the

‘law of value’.

The problem of Ticktin’s notion of the transitional epoch is not simply

the restrictive understanding of capitalism which we have already

mentioned, but also its restrictive notion of socialism and communism.

For Ticktin, in the true tradition of orthodox Marxism, socialism is

essentially the nationalization of production and exchange combined with

democratic state planning. As a consequence, for Ticktin, the Russian

Revolution must be seen as a successful socialist revolution in that it

abolished private property and laid the basis for state planning under

workers’ control. It was only subsequently that, due to the backwardness

and isolation of the Soviet Union, the workers’ state degenerated and as

a result became stuck half-way between capitalism and socialism.

Yet, as many anarchists and left communists have argued, the Russian

Revolution was never a successful proletarian revolution. The revolution

failed not simply because of the isolation and backwardness of Russia —

although these may have been important factors — but because the Russian

working class failed fully to transform the social relations of

production. This failure to transform the relations of production meant

that, even though the working class may have taken control through the

Bolsheviks’ seizure of power and established a ‘workers’ state’, they

had failed to go beyond capitalism. As a result, the new state

bureaucracy had to adopt the role of the bourgeoisie in advancing the

forces of production at all costs.

If this position is correct and Russia never went beyond capitalism,

then the basic assumption, which Ticktin himself admits is the very

foundation of his analysis, that the USSR was stuck half-way between

capitalism and socialism, falls to the ground. Nevertheless, Ticktin’s

notion that the USSR was a distorted system due it being in transition

from one mode of production to another is an important insight. However,

as we shall argue in Part IV of this article, the USSR was not so much

in transition to socialism as in transition to capitalism. However,

before considering this we shall in Part III look in more detail at the

various theories of state capitalism that have arisen within the left

communist tradition.

Part III: Left Communism and the Russian Revolution

In the previous articles we examined various Trotskyist and

neo-Trotskyist positions on the nature of the USSR.

We now turn to the theories of the less well known but more interesting

Communist Left, who were among the first revolutionary Marxists to

distance themselves from the Russian model by deeming it state

capitalist or simply capitalist. The Russian Left Communists' critique

remained at the level of an immediate response to how capitalist

measures were affecting the class, whereas in both the German/Dutch and

Italian Lefts, we see real attempts to ground revolutionary theory in

Marx's categories in a way distinct from Second International orthodoxy.

Introduction

Any analysis of the USSR necessarily involves an underlying conception

of what the Russian Revolution was. The Trotskyist approaches that we

have previously considered are all based on the conception of the

Russian Revolution as being an essentially proletarian revolution that

somehow degenerated. By contrast a consideration of Left Communist

theories allow us to question this underlying assumption, and as a

result provides vital insights into the development of a theory of what

the USSR was.

The Russian revolution seemed to show for the first time that workers

could actually overthrow a bourgeois capitalist state and run society

themselves. After almost all of the socialist parties and trade unions

of the mainstream Second International workers movement patriotically

supported the slaughter of the first world war, the Bolsheviks it seemed

had reasserted an internationalist revolutionary Marxism. But if the

Russian revolution was initially a massive inspiration to proletarians

across the world, being a first outbreak in the revolutionary wave that

ended the war, its impact after that is more ambiguous. The word

‘communist’ became associated with a system of state control of the

means of production, coupled with severe repression of all opposition.

The workers movement across the world was dominated by this model of

‘actually existing socialism’, and the parties who oriented themselves

to it. The role of these regimes and parties was to do more to kill the

idea of proletarian revolution and communism than ordinary capitalist

repression had ever been able to. So those in favour of proletarian

revolution had to distinguish themselves from these official communist

parties and to make sense of what had happened in Russia. A group that

did so was the Left Communists or Communist Left.

Who was this communist left?

The Communist Left emerged out of the crisis of Marxist Social Democracy

that became acutely visible during the war. Left Communist currents

emerged across the world. Those with politics that we and Lenin could

describe as left communist were generally the first revolutionary

militants from their respective countries attracted to the Russian

Revolution and to the Communist International (Comintern) set up in

1919. In some countries notably Germany, Italy a majority of those who

formed their respective communist parties had left communist politics.

However their experience was — sooner or later — to find themselves in

disagreement with the policies promoted from Moscow and eventually

excluded from the Communist International.

Two main wings of the Communist Left managed to survive the defeat of

the revolutionary wave as traditions: the German/Dutch Left[61]

(sometimes known as Council Communists) and the Italian Left (sometimes

referred to as Bordigists after a founding member). While their analyses

were not the same on all points, what really defined them was a

perception of the need for communist revolutionary politics to be a

fundamental break from those of Social Democracy. Such a break

necessarily implied an attempt to overcome the dichotomy between the

political and the economic that was central to the theory of the Second

International.

Although they disagreed at what time it occurred, their perception was

that the Bolshevik party slipped back into, or never quite left Social

Democratic positions. Identifying themselves as revolutionary and as

Marxist the common problem for these currents was to understand what had

happened in a way that was true to both. While saying the Soviet Union

was capitalist allowed a revolutionary position to be taken up against

it, they found it necessary to do this in a way that made sense in terms

of Marx’s categories and understanding of capitalism. Out of their

different experiences they developed very different theories of the

degeneration of the Russian Revolution and of the capitalism that

developed in the USSR.

However these oppositions to the Moscow line were largely eclipsed by

the strength of Stalinism in the workers’ movement and by a later

opposition to this that grew up around Leon Trotsky, the exiled leader

of the Russian Communist Party and state. Due to the revolutionary

credentials and prestige of its founder, Trotskyism established itself

as the most visible and numerous opposition to the left of the official

‘Communist’ movement. Particularly in Britain, which has not really

generated its own left Marxist tradition, it managed to plausibly

present itself against Stalinism as the genuine revolutionary Marxism.

For this reason we devoted the previous articles to a presentation and

critique of theories of the USSR coming out of Trotskyism: the orthodox

Trotskyist theory of the degenerated workers state, Tony Cliff’s version

of state capitalism, and Hillel Ticktin’s recently influential theory of

Russia as a specifically distorted and untenable society.[62]

We argued that a weakness of all these theories was that they moved

within a certain kind of orthodox Marxism. Identifying with the Soviet

state under Lenin and Trotsky, they assumed that, on the basis of the

traditional Marxist premise that socialism is the abolition of private

property in the means of production through its wholesale

nationalisation by the state, that there had been a successful socialist

revolution in Russia which in some way had degenerated. They disagreed

on what type of system had emerged, but they generally saw it as hinging

on the lack of workers’ democratic control of nationalised property. For

Trotskyism, Leninism is the revolutionary alternative to the Second

International, and Trotskyism was the revolutionary continuation of

Leninism against Stalinism. The existence of a Communist Left threatens

this picture. It shows that Trotskyism was by no means the only Marxist

opposition to Stalinism. In fact, as we’ll see, it questions whether

Trotskyism has been a ‘revolutionary’ opposition at all.

However while Trotskyism, through the flexible tactics it was willing to

adopt, could exist on the fringes of a Stalinist and social democratic

dominated workers’ movement, the left communists, their politics

fundamentally oriented to revolutionary situations, were reduced by the

thirties to a far smaller and more isolated existence. It was only after

Stalinism’s hold on the revolutionary imagination began to break in 1956

and with the wave of struggles beginning in the sixties that there was a

resurgence of interest in revolutionary tendencies to the left of

Trotskyism, like the Communist Left. The focus on Councils and workers’

self-activity that was basic to the German Left was taken up by groups

like Socialism or Barbarism (and its linked British group Solidarity)

and by the Situationist International.[63] The German Communist Left

which declared itself anti-Leninist was more immediately attractive to

those rejecting Stalinism and the critical support given it by

Trotskyism than the Italian Left which, because it emphasised the party,

seemed like another version of Leninism. However after ’68 partly due to

a perceived weakness of a merely ‘councilist’ or ‘libertarian’

opposition to Leninism, there was a renewal of interest in the Italian

Left which was the other main Communist left to have handed down a

tradition.[64]

In this article we shall look at the various theories of the Russian,

German/Dutch and Italian Communist Left. We shall ignore certain other

communist lefts because either they have not managed to pass down any

theoretical writings on the question or because as, say, with the

British Left they largely followed the German/Dutch left on the question

of the Russian Revolution.[65] Our point of departure is that Communist

Left which developed within the Russian Revolution itself and which

received Lenin’s wrath before the rest. Though the Russian Left cannot

be said to have developed the same body of coherent theory as the other

two, its very closeness to the events gives its considerations a certain

importance.

The Russian Left Communists

What is striking about the Russian Left Communist current is that it

emerged out of an environment that was both dissimilar and similar to

the their European counterparts. As we will see in the following

sections, the German and Italian Communist Lefts emerged as an

opposition to social democracy’s accommodation with and incorporation

into bourgeois society. In Russia the situation was somewhat different.

Still being an overwhelmingly agricultural and peasant country under the

autocratic rule of the tsar, bourgeois society had not become dominant,

let alone allowed the establishment of social democracy within it. In

fact, the very repressive character of the tsarist regime meant that the

gradualist approach of stressing legal parliamentary and trade union

methods that prevailed in Western Europe was largely absent in Russia,

and there was a general acceptance of the need for a violent revolution.

This need was confirmed by the 1905 revolution, which saw mass strikes,

the setting up of soviets, wide-spread peasant uprisings — in general a

violent confrontation of revolutionary workers and peasants with the

forces of the state. But whilst this context set the Russian Social

Democrats apart from their European counterparts, there was also an

underlying continuity between the two. In fact, Lenin throughout tried

to stay true to the orthodoxies of Second International Marxism, and

accepted Kautsky, the chief theorist of German social democracy, as an

ideological authority.[66] Basic to this form of Marxism was the notion

of history inevitably moving in the right direction by concentrating and

centralising the productive forces, so that socialism would be simply

the elimination of the private control of those forces by the capture of

state power and social democratic administration of them in the interest

of the whole of society. But whereas the developed character of West

European capitalism meant that in these countries this theory

dove-tailed with a gradualist and parliament centred approach, due to

the backwardness of Russian society, it took a revolutionary form.

The revolutionary side of Lenin’s Marxism, as against other European

social democrat leaders, was expressed most clearly when he took an

uncompromising position of revolutionary opposition to the war.[67] On

this fundamental issue Russian left communists had no reason for

disagreement with Lenin. Nevertheless, this was to occur on other

issues, such as Lenin’s position on nationalism, and his view (until

1917) that Russia could only have a bourgeois-democratic revolution.

Consequently, an opposing left fraction around Bukharin[68] and Pyatakov

formed within the Bolsheviks. They contended that the war had prompted

great advances of finance capital and state capitalism in Russia that

made socialist revolution a possibility.. Fundamentally they saw the

issue as one of world revolution of which Russia could be part. A key

text for them was Bukharin’s Imperialism and World Economy. In it he

drew heavily on the essentially reformist Hilferding to argue that world

capitalism, including Russia, was moving in the direction of state

capitalist trusts where the state became appropriated by a finance

capital elite. However, he took a much more radical interpretation of

the political significance of these developments. The ‘symbiosis of the

state and finance capital elite’ meant that the parliamentary road of

Social Democracy was blocked and socialists had to return to the

anti-statist strand in Marx’s thought. The state had to be destroyed as

a condition of socialism. However for the Russian situation, what was

key about Bukharin’s analysis of imperialism and state capitalism was

that it allowed Russian left communists to abandon the classical Marxist

line (held by both the Mensheviks and the Bolsheviks) that Russia was

only ready for a bourgeois-democratic revolution..

But despite Lenin’s initial hostility to the heretical ideas coming out

of this left fraction,[69] after the February revolution he showed that

he would not let his orthodoxy prevent him from being open to events.

Just as the Bolshevik leadership thought that a long period of

development of bourgeois society was on the horizon, it was clear from

the continuing actions of the workers and peasants that the

revolutionary period was by no means over. Workers were setting up

factory committees and militantly contesting capitalist authority at the

point of production; peasant soldiers were deserting the front and

seizing land. Responding to this, and against the Bolshevik leadership,

Lenin in 1917 seemed to take up all the essential positions of the left

communist tendency within the party. In the April Theses he called for

proletarian socialist revolution. To give this a Marxist justification,

he argued in The Impending Catastrophe and How to Avoid It that the war

had revolutionised Russian society by developing state capitalism.

Meanwhile, he was writing State and Revolution, which saw him at his

most un-social democratic; he even acknowledged the Dutch left

communist, Pannekoek. Due to the now clearly revolutionary line of the

Bolshevik party, it consequently became the pole of re-groupment for

revolutionary Social Democrats and for radicalised workers. All those

against the war and for taking the revolution forward were drawn to the

Bolsheviks: Trotsky’s followers, many left Mensheviks, but most

importantly vast numbers of radicalised workers. Thus revolutionaries

with politics closest to the European left communists were not as with

them, fairly small minorities fighting within Social Democratic parties

against their clearly non-revolutionary politics, but instead were a

sizeable part of a party — the Bolsheviks — whose leader Lenin seemed to

accept many of their theoretical positions, and what’s more brought the

party to act on these by overthrowing the provisional government and

declaring ‘All Power to the Soviets’.

Organic Reconstruction: Back to Orthodoxy

But if the revolutionary side of Lenin seemed in 1917 to break from

social democratic orthodoxy — if it seemed to the left that he had

become one of them — soon after October, they were to doubt it. A

dichotomy between political and economic aspects of the revolution

became apparent in his thinking. For Lenin, the proletarian character of

the revolution was assured in the political power of a proletarian

party; ‘economic’ issues, like the relations at the point of production,

were not of the essence. More and more Lenin’s attention returned to

Russia’s backwardness, its unripeness for immediate social

transformation and thus the paradoxical notion that state capitalist

economic developments under the proper political guidance of the party

might be the best path towards socialism. This turn in Lenin’s thinking

was obscured at first by another question: how to respond to Germany’s

terms for peace at the Brest Litovsk negotiations. Whilst the group

known as the Left Communists were for rejecting these conditions and

turning the imperialist war into, if not an outright revolutionary war,

then a defensive revolutionary partisan war,[70] Lenin insisted on

accepting Germany’s terms for peace. Peace, he argued, was needed at any

price to consolidate the revolution in Russia; to win ‘the freedom to

carry on socialist construction at home’.[71]

The Left responded again by stressing the internationalist perspective,

and argued that an imperialist peace with Germany would carry as much

danger as the continuation of the imperialist war. Such a peace, by

strengthening Germany — which had faced a massive wave of wildcat

strikes in early 1918 — would act against the prospects of world

revolution. Hence, Lenin’s apparent choice of temporarily prioritising

the consolidation of the Russian revolution over spreading the world

revolution was, for them, a false one. By taking a limited nationally

oriented perspective at Brest Litovsk what would be consolidated, they

argued, was not ‘socialist construction’ but the forces of

counter-revolution within Russia. As such, the left communists were then

the earliest proponents of the view that you cannot have socialism in

one country.

But whilst the Left Communists position initially had majority support

from the Russian working class, this support faded as Germany launched

an offensive. Lenin’s arguments, which he pursued with vigour, then

prevailed leading to the treaty of Brest Litovsk, under which the

Bolshevik government agreed to German annexation of a vast part of the

area in which revolution had broken out including the Baltic nations,

the Ukraine and a part of White Russia.[72]

The sacrifice of pursuing world revolution for national ‘socialist

construction’ became all the greater as it became clear exactly what

Lenin meant by this term. In face of the Bolsheviks not having a very

clear plan of what to do economically after seizing power, the first

five months were characterised by the self-activity and creativity of

the workers. The workers took the destruction of the provisional

government as the signal to intensify and extend their expropriation of

the factories and replacement of capitalist control by forms of direct

workers control. This process was not initiated by the Bolshevik

government, but by the workers themselves through the Soviets and

especially the factory committees. The Bolsheviks reluctantly or

otherwise had to run with the tide at this point. This period was a high

point of proletarian self activity: a spontaneous movement of workers

socialisation of production, which the Bolsheviks legitimized (one might

argue recuperated) after the event with the slogan ‘Loot the Looters’,

and their decrees on Workers Control and the nationalisation of

enterprises. The workers were euphoric with the communist possibilities

of abolishing exploitation and controlling their own destinies.

However, by spring (as the treaty of Brest Litovsk was signed), Lenin

pushed the Bolsheviks to initiate a different economic policy called the

New Course involving a more conciliatory attitude towards “creative

elements” in the business community’. While Lenin didn’t disown entirely

what the workers had done, there was the clear message they had gone too

far. Their acts should now be curtailed and controlled. In their place,

he talked of setting up joint state/private capitalist trusts. The basic

idea seemed essentially to be a mixed economy with co-operation between

public and private sectors. Although the Mensheviks welcomed these

measures as the abandonment of the ‘illusory chase after socialism’ and

a turn to a more moderate realistic path, Lenin still tried to

differentiate himself from the Mensheviks, by stating that as long as

the state remains in the hand of the proletarian party, the economy

would not degenerate into normal state capitalism. Significantly, the

other side of this focus on the ‘proletarian state’ was that Lenin,

while wanting a return to capitalist methods of economic organisation

saw no need for the other main Menshevik demand: for independent workers

organisation. As Lenin put it, “defence of the workers’ interests was

the task of the unions under capitalism, but since power has passed to

the hands of the proletariat the state itself, in its essence the

workers state, defends the workers interests.’

It is this New Course which the Left Communists were to oppose in their

theses[73] published in response to the peace treaty. In it they

identified the peace treaty as a concession to the peasants, and as a

slide towards ‘petty bourgeois politics of a new type’. They saw

bureaucratic centralisation as an attack on the independent power of the

soviets, and on the self-activity of the working class, and warned that

by such means something very different from socialism was about to be

established. The New Course talk of accommodation with capitalist

elements in Russia was seen as expressive of what had become clear

earlier with Lenin’s willingness to compromise with imperialism over

Brest Litovsk, namely an overall drift towards compromise with the

forces of international and internal capital. The left communists warned

that behind the argument for saving and defending Soviet power in Russia

for international revolution later, what would happen was that “all

efforts will be directed towards strengthening the development of

productive forces towards ‘organic construction’, while rejecting the

continued smashing of capitalist relations of production and even

furthering their partial restoration.”[p10] What was being defended in

Russia was not socialist construction, but a ‘system of state capitalism

and petty bourgeois economic relations. The defence of the socialist

fatherland’ will then prove in actual fact to be defence of a petty

bourgeois motherland subject to the influence of international

capital.”[p9]

Lenin’s Arguments for State Capitalism Versus the Left Communists

It is not surprising that Lenin was forced to reply to this accusation

of pursuing state capitalist economic policies. What is revealing though

is that when he did so in Left Wing Childishness and Immediate Tasks, it

was not by justifying the recent measures as a form of socialism, but by

fully endorsing state capitalism and arguing it would be an advance for

Russia. He now brought into question his prior arguments that Russia was

part of a world state capitalism and thus ripe for socialism, which had

seemed necessary to justify proletarian revolution in 1917. Lenin again

returned to the notion of Russia’s backwardness. A theory of transition

based on the Second International acceptance of unilinear ‘progressive’

stages came to the fore. He noted that all would agree that Russia being

in transition meant that it contained elements of socialism and

capitalism, but he now said the actual situation was even more

complicated. In a model that we will see was key to his understanding,

Lenin argued that Russia’s backwardness meant it actually combined five

types of economic structure:

peasants who sell their grain);

Russia, he claimed, while having advanced politically was not

economically advanced enough for direct advances towards socialism. The

state capitalism, that he had earlier seemed to agree with the left

communists had arrived in Russia was, now he said only a shell pierced

by the lower forms of economy. The real battle in Russia, he contended,

was not that of socialism and capitalism, but of state capitalism and

socialism on one side versus all the other economies on the other.

Economic growth and even economic survival he contended depended on

state capitalist measures. The ones he argued for included the paying of

high salaries to bourgeois specialists, the development of rigid

accounting and control with severe penalties for those who break it,

increased productivity and intensity of labour, piece work and the

‘scientific and progressive’ elements of the Taylor system.

The overarching repeated demand from Lenin was for ‘discipline,

discipline, discipline’ and he identified this with the acceptance by

the workers of one-man management — that is ‘unquestioned obedience to

the will of a single person.’ The arguments of the left that this was

suppressing class autonomy and threatened to enslave the working class

was just dismissed by Lenin with the insistence that there was

“absolutely no contradiction in principle between Soviet (that is,

socialist) democracy and the exercise of dictatorial powers by

individuals.” [ p 268] All it was apparently, was a matter of learning

“to combine the “public meeting” democracy of the working people —

turbulent, surging, overflowing its banks like a spring flood — with

iron discipline while at work, with unquestioning obedience to the will

of a single person, the Soviet leader, while at work.’” [ p 271] The

point for Lenin was that as long as it was a proletarian state that

introduced these measures it could prevent regression down the rungs of

the ladder and prepare for the eventual movement up towards socialism.

Left wing opposition to Lenin’s line at this point had two main thrusts,

which in part reflected a division in the 1918 left communists. One side

we might call ‘technocratic’, emphasised opposition to precisely what

the Mensheviks welcomed, namely the suggested compromises with private

capitalists. They argued that whoever controlled the economy would

control politics, capitalist economic power would dissolve the power of

the Soviets and ‘a real state capitalist system’ and the rule of finance

capital would be the result. The other thrust of left communist

criticism was against the re-employment of authoritarian capitalist

relations and methods within production. As Ossinsky in particular

argued, one man management and the other impositions of capitalist

discipline would stifle the active participation of workers in the

organisation of production; Taylorism turned workers into the appendages

of machines, and piece-wages imposed individualist rather than

collective rewards in production so installing petty bourgeois values

into workers. In sum these measures were rightly seen as the

re-transformation of proletarians within production from collective

subject back into the atomised objects of capital. The working class, it

was argued, had to consciously participate in economic as well as

political administration. In this best tendency within the 1918 Left

Communists, there was an emphasis on the problem with capitalist

production being the way it turned workers into objects, and on its

transcendence lying in their conscious creativity and participation,

that is reminiscent of Marx’s critique of alienation. It is the way the

Russian left communists arguments expressed and reflected workers

reactions and resistance to the state capitalist direction of the

Bolsheviks and workers aspirations to really transform social relations,

that there importance lay. Such sentiments ran through the left

oppositions, even if until 1921 their loyalty to the party generally

stopped them supporting workers practical expressions of resistance. As

Ossinsky put it:

“We stand for the construction of the proletarian society by the class

creativity of the workers themselves, not by the ukases of the captains

of industry. If the proletariat itself does not know how to create the

necessary prerequisites for the socialist organisation of labour, no one

can do this for it and no one can compel it to do this. The stick, if

raised against the workers, will find itself in the hands of a social

force which is either under the influence of another social class or is

in the hands of the soviet power.. Socialism and socialist organisation

will be set up by the proletariat itself, or they will not be set up at

all: something else will be set up — state capitalism.“[74]

These arguments of Ossinsky represented the best element in the left

communists’ positions: a recognition that the mass creativity and

autonomy of the workers was essential to any move towards communism,

thus that nationalisation or statisation of production was not enough.

Lenin’s view was that direct workers control of their own activity was

an issue for the future and that in the meantime iron discipline was

required.

‘War Communism’

The conditions of civil war and imperialist invasion that Russia fell

into in the second half on 1918, altered the conditions of debate and

broke the Left Communists as a cohesive opposition. On the one hand,

where the alternative to the Bolsheviks was White armies committed to

the restoration of the old order, criticism by workers and peasants of

the measures the party was taking, was tempered. But apart from this

pragmatic issue, the civil war also exposed the inadequate foundation

much the left communist criticism had been based on. Considering that,

for many left communists, their critique of the New Course, and the

consequent accusation of state capitalism, was based mainly on the

notion of compromise with private capitalists, and perceived concessions

to the peasantry, in the face of what was to be called ‘war communism’

they had very little left to criticise. Not only did a whole wave of

nationalisations take place, virtually wiping out the previous role of

the private capitalist, but if there was one thing war communism was

not, it was system based on concessions to the peasants. It consequently

became difficult for them to describe Russia as state capitalist.

In fact, the technocratic wing of the Left Communist even went as far as

welcoming ‘war communism’ as a real advance to communism. And when war

communism resulted in mass inflation virtually wiping out money, they

equally saw it as a general move to an economy in kind with all sorts of

transactions, even wages, ceasing to use money. The self-emancipatory

wing, (which was to provide both the original arguments as well as

personnel of the later left oppositions of the Democratic Centralists

and the Workers Opposition) took a more cautious stand. They had tended

to focus their criticism on the excessive centralisation of power and

the bureaucratic capitalist methods of the state economy, to which they

counter-posed a restoration of power and local initiative to the soviets

and other workers’ bodies. But without the other components of their

earlier critique, and considering that Lenin himself had described state

capitalism — with all its management methods — as playing a progressive

part, the left oppositions ceased to describe it as such.

The mistake of confusing the war-time measures as a step in the

direction of socialism became clear as the war came to an end and the

Bolsheviks tried to step up the war economy measures.[75] The fallacy of

associating state-control with socialism, despite the intensification of

capitalistic production relations, became clear as workers and peasants

reacted to their material situation with a wave of strikes and

uprisings. The Kronstadt revolt in particular showed the giant gulf

between the state and the working class. Despite this general

discontent, both outside and within the party, Lenin responded with, on

the one hand, the New Economic Policy (NEP), and on the other, the

banning of factions with the famous statement that was to characterise

the regime thereafter: ‘Here and there with a rifle, but not with

opposition; we’ve had enough opposition’.

New Economic Policy: New Opposition

It is important then to grasp that the NEP, which was essentially a

return to the moderate state capitalism championed by Lenin in the New

Course debate, did not mark an abandonment of communism, but merely a

change in the form of state capitalism. Central to the New Economic

Policy (NEP) was a changed relation to the peasantry with a progressive

tax in kind replacing state procurement and leaving the peasants free to

trade for a profit anything left above this. Free trade which had not

disappeared was now legal. On the industrial front small scale

production was totally denationalised and many, though not the largest

factories, leased back to their former owners to run on a capitalist

basis. For the working class there was reintroduced payment of wages in

cash and charges for previously free services. The command economy of

the ‘war communism’ years was abandoned in favour of the running of the

economy on a commercial basis. Nevertheless the commanding heights of

the economy remained under state control and the basis for systematic

state planning in terms of forecasting etc. continued to be developed.

In fact, the very continuity between the New Course and the NEP also

showed up in the fact that Lenin, in trying to justify the NEP in the

pamphlet Tax in Kind, reprinted large parts of his earlier critique of

the Left Communists, including the ‘5 socio-economic structures’ model

of the Russian economy.

In 1921 Lenin gave the same reply to Workers Opposition accusations of

state capitalism as he had to the Left Communists in 1918, namely that

state capitalism would be a tremendous step forward from what Russia

actually was, which was a ‘petty producer capitalism with a

working-class party controlling the state.’[76] The key thing about the

regime developing at the time of NEP was that, accompanying economic

concessions to private capitalism, was intensified political repression,

the banning of factions in the party, and non-toleration of any

independent political tendencies in the working class. As Ciliga later

observed, before the NEP the intensity of repression of left opposition

had varied, after this date all opposition was repressed on principle

and the treatment of prisoners grew worse.[77]

It was in this context of political repression and economic

re-imposition of capitalist forms that a number of small opposition

groups emerged, which again took up the notion of state capitalism. What

was common to these new groups was that, unlike the previous left

communist tendency and the later left opposition of Trotsky, these

groups did make a decisive break from the Bolshevik party. One such

group that emerged was the Workers Truth centred around an old left

adversary of Lenin, Bogdanov. In issuing an Appeal, starting with Marx’s

famous ‘the liberation of the workers can only be the deed of the

workers themselves’, they argued that the Bolshevik party was no longer

a proletarian party, but rather the party of a new ruling class, and

thus they called for a new party.[78]

With at first a little less theoretical clarity, it was however, the

Workers Group, centred around Miasnikov, that made the biggest impact on

the class. The main opposition strand had been the Workers Opposition,

which while appearing to support the working class, had essentially been

demanding a transfer of power from one party faction to another, namely

that organised in the trade unions. Miasnikov and his supporters had at

this point rejected both the state economic bodies and the trade unions

as bureaucratised forms, and in arguing for a return of power to the

soviets, had implicitly questioned the party. Miasnikov stood out even

more by not supporting the repression of Kronstadt, which he described

as an abyss the party had crossed. This willingness to break with the

party was crucial because oppositions until then, though reflecting

discontent outside the party, had remained wedded to it seeking refuge

in organisational fixes that failed conspicuously to deliver.

In 1923 they produced a Manifesto appealing to both the Russian and

international proletariat. Rather than theoretical considerations their

description of the NEP as standing for the ‘New Exploitation of the

Proletariat’ simply tries to express the conditions that the workers

were facing. They denounced the attacks on the working class the

Bolshevik regime was carrying out making a point that echoed

Luxemburg:[79] “the bourgeoisie has, and will have, no better advocate’

than the ‘socialists of all countries’ because they have the ability to

disorientate the proletariat with their phrases. Or again: ‘a very great

danger threatens the achievements of the Russian proletarian revolution,

not so much from outside as from inside itself.’ Expressing this

emphasis on the world proletarian movement the workers group took a

resolutely internationalist line. They were sure that the Russian

proletariat’s only hope lay in aid from revolution elsewhere. They

argued that the Bolshevik policies of a ‘socialist united fronts’ and

workers governments were acting against that hope of world

revolution.[80]

However, the real significance of the group was the fact that they took

their criticism of the state capitalist direction of the Bolsheviks to

its logical conclusion of supporting proletarian opposition to the

regime. In late ’23 a wave of strikes broke out and the Workers Group

became involved gaining an influence for their Manifesto among the

proletariat and prompting their suppression by the secret police. Soon

their existence was relegated to the prison camps or in exile. It was

here that they moved away from their focus on the NEP, and started to

question war communism. There their state capitalist analysis became

more and more influential in the camps where, as Ciliga observed, a

political life repressed elsewhere continued. They extended their

critique to the sort of ‘socialism’ that the Bolsheviks had tried to

create even before NEP, arguing that because it was based on coercion

over the working class and not the free creation of the class, was in

reality a bureaucratic state capitalism.

We have looked then at those arguments of the Russian Left most

illuminating for an understanding of the Revolution. The importance of

the 1918 Left Communists was not just the fact that they right from an

early stage argued that there was a danger that not socialism, but

capitalism would emerge from the revolution, but also because in his

battles with them, Lenin most explicitly revealed his own support for

‘state capitalism’. The importance of Miasnikov’s Workers Group lay in

them being the most significant of the post 1921 groups who took their

criticism of the state capitalist direction of the Bolsheviks to its

logical conclusion of supporting proletarian opposition to the regime.

Their confrontation with the Russian state was far more consistent and

coherent than that of Trotsky’s Left opposition. However we cannot say

that they provided the theoretical arguments to solidly ground a theory

of state capitalism. We will turn now to the tendencies in Europe, with

whom they made contact, to see if they had more success.

The German/Dutch Communist Left

In Germany the beginning of the century was characterised by a tension

between official and unofficial expressions of working class strength.

On the one hand, the Social Democratic Party (SPD), which had founded

and dominated the Second International, had grown to an unprecedented

scale (almost becoming a ‘state within a state’), and was receiving

steadily larger proportion of votes in elections. On the other, there

was also an increased militancy and radicalisation of class struggle,

manifesting itself in more and more strikes and lockouts[81] — struggles

that in many cases went beyond economic demands and took on a mass and

political character. While a left radical current within the SPD was to

see these as a way the class was developing towards revolution, the

mainstream party and trade union leadership set itself against these new

forms of class struggle. In the years to come these two expression of

the working class were to drastically clash. Indeed the direct struggle

between class and capital would become that of revolutionary tendency of

the proletariat and social democracy siding with and representing

capital.

The counter-revolutionary character of the gradualist practice of the

SPD first came brutally to light when, in the interest of preparing for

the next election, the party stepped in to demobilise a wave of

industrial struggles and suffrage agitation that swept Prussia in 1910.

Although leading to some fierce arguments over strategy between Kautsky

and the emerging radical left tendency, it was only with the war that

these oppositions made moves towards a split with the party. Despite

always having had a position of opposing imperialist wars, the SPD and

the unions turned to social patriotism — the party voted for war credits

and the unions signed a pact to maintain war production and prevent

strikes. As a result, two main opposition tendencies emerged: the

left-communist tendency that split from the party, and the Spartacists

that at first tried to stay within the party and reform it from within.

However, their different responses to the SPD’s turn to social

patriotism, was emblematic of what was to follow. Whilst the left

communists throughout put themselves on the side of revolution, the

Spartacist leadership never entirely managed to break from social

democratic conceptions.

The German Revolution: Breaking from Social Democracy

But whilst SPD’s support for the war was important in generating a

radical left tendency, it was only in the face of the German Revolution

that the overtly counter-revolutionary character of social democracy

became clear to large numbers of workers. The Russian Revolution had

been a massive inspiration for revolutionaries and the class struggle in

Germany. In early 1918 there was a wave of mass wildcat strikes. And

although the SPD put a lid on these struggles, the opposition kept

growing. Finally in November, revolution broke out when sailors mutinies

and a generalised setting up of workers councils ended the first world

war. The ruling class, knowing that it could in no way contain the

revolutionary wave, turned to social democracy to save the nation, and

appointed the SPD leader as chancellor. Knowing that direct

confrontation would get them nowhere, they set themselves to destroy the

councils from within. The Spartacists, trapped within a ‘centrist’

faction of social democracy, could only watch while it helped the SPD in

this task. The SPD thus managed to get a majority vote at the first

National Congress of Workers and Soldiers Councils in favour of

elections to a constituent assembly and for dissolving the councils in

favour of that parliament. At the same time the trade unions worked hand

in hand with management to get revolutionary workers dismissed and to

destroy independent council activity in the factories. Councils against

parliament and trade unions became the watch word of revolutionaries.

Recognising the depth of their failure, the Spartacists broke from

social democracy and joined the left communists to form the Communist

Party of Germany (KPD). And in January 1919, within days of this

founding conference, the KPD was tested in combat. Prematurely provoked

to action by the government, revolutionary workers in Berlin attempted

to overthrow the SPD government in favour of a council republic. The KPD

put itself on the side of the insurrection, which was crushed by the SPD

minister Noske’s freicorps — a volunteer army of proto-fascist

ex-officers and soldiers. The Spartacist leaders, Luxemburg and

Liebknecht, were arrested and murdered. Over the next months

revolutionary attempts in Bavaria, Bremen, Wilhemshaven and other

places, were likewise defeated in isolation. Social democracy, through

armed force when necessary, but more fundamentally through the

ideological hold it and its trade unions had over the working class, had

defeated the revolution and saved German capitalism.

However, within the class there was also a process of radicalisation.

Large numbers of workers, recognising the counter-revolutionary role of

the SPD and the unions, and having fought SPD troops and police on the

streets, rejected the parliamentary system and left the unions. As an

alternative they formed factory organisations to provide a means for

united proletarian action, and to be ready for the re-formation of

revolutionary council power. While the majority of the KPD, including

the rank and file Spartacists, supported these developments, the

Spartacist leadership still wanted to participate in elections and the

trade unions. In mid-1919, by a series of bureaucratic manoeuvres they

managed to exclude the majority from the party. The Bolsheviks

essentially sided with this rump leadership. The basis of the split

between the German communist left and the Bolsheviks was prepared.

In March/April 1920 the split in the KPD was to become permanent. At

this time the freicorps that the SPD had used to crush the revolution,

turned on their masters and launched a coup: the Kapp putsch. The trade

unions called a general strike, which the working class responded to

solidly, bringing the country to a stop. The coup collapsed, but workers

were now mobilised across the country. In the revolutionary stronghold

of the Ruhr the workers had formed a 80,000 strong Red Army that refused

to disarm. Although having been saved by this revolutionary upsurge, the

SPD saw their role as the same as it had been a year previously, namely

to make sure than the struggles did not develop into full scale

revolution. Only this time, they did not have the same working class

credibility that had previously allowed them to control the situation.

Faced by this, they chose a dual strategy: to re-establish their

socialist credibility they talked of forming a government composed only

of workers parties, whilst at the same time sending in their — now loyal

once more — troops to attack and disarm the Ruhr.

The two sides of German ‘communism’ reacted totally differently to these

events. The excluded majority of the party put themselves with the

working class reaction from the beginning and supported the Red Army in

the Ruhr when the SPD troops attacked it. The rump leadership of the

KPD, while it had initially said it would not ‘lift a finger’ for the

SPD government, quickly changed its position to total support. It

offered itself a ‘loyal opposition’ to the proposed ‘workers

government’, and called on the armed workers to not to resist the SPD

troops. Thus the revolutionary potential of the situation was defeated

by social democracy with the support of the Moscow supported KPD, who

claimed to be a revolutionary break from social democracy. The left

communist side of the KPD, feeling no rapprochement was possible with a

group that had tacitly supported the violent suppression of the class,

formed itself as the Communist Workers Party of Germany (KAPD),

orientated totally towards the councils. The question is of course how

these lessons affected their view of the Russian Revolution.

The German Left and the Comintern

For these revolutionaries the history of the German workers movement had

shown the fundamental opposition between the methods of social democracy

and revolution. It had seemed to them that ‘Bolshevik principles’ such

as the suppression of bourgeois democracy and its replacement by the

dictatorship of the proletariat through workers councils, were key to

overcoming the opportunism of the SPD and winning the revolution in

Germany. It was in this sense that ‘Bolshevism’ had helped their break

from Social Democracy. The fact that the line coming out of Moscow

seemed to favour some of the social democratic elements the left

communists were breaking from, was merely seen as being based on their

unfamiliarity with the West European situation. They thought the

Bolsheviks were falsely generalising from the Russian situation, in

which the use of parliamentary methods etc. might have been necessary,

to the west European situation where the break with parliamentary

practices, and the emphasis on councilism was essential for the

revolution to succeed. Even when Lenin launched Left-Wing Communism — An

Infantile Disorder a vicious polemic against them and in support of the

KPD line, they still thought it was a matter of Lenin not understanding

the conditions for revolution in the West. Even when [Otto] Ruhle, their

delegate to the Second Congress of the Comintern, returned arguing that

Russia was ‘soviet’ only in name, the majority opposed his view.

However, Ruhle’s councilist argument that what Russia showed was that

party-rule was a bourgeois form, that ‘revolution was not a party

affair’, but a matter of councils and unitary factory organisations

only, was later to become the dominant position of the remains of the

German Left.

However, at this time, it was only when the Comintern adopted a line of

a ‘united front’, and ordered the KAPD to liquidate and re-join the KPD,

which had by then merged with left social democrats, did they start to

rethink their position. By late 1921 — as a result of hearing about the

NEP, the suppression of strikes, as well as Russia’s willingness to make

commercial and military treaties with capitalist powers — they decided

that the Bolsheviks and the Comintern had left the field of revolution.

They began to consider that there might have been internal conditions

forcing the counter revolutionary policies abroad. The White

counter-revolution had failed, yet Russia was acting in a capitalist way

both at home and abroad. What was the explanation for this?

The spectre of Menshevism: October, a bourgeois revolution?

In 1917, when the German Social Democrats had supported the Menshevik

line that Russia was only ready for a bourgeois revolution, the German

Left had welcomed October as the first crack in bourgeois power — the

start of world revolution. Now with it appearing that the Bolsheviks

were retreating from the proletarian socialist path, the German Left

started a move back to orthodoxy. Starting with a revised notion that

October was a dual revolution, they were to end by deciding it was a

bourgeois revolution through and through. Key to their understanding was

the perceived dominance of the peasants in Russia.

This first manifested itself when, in the Manifesto of the International

they tried to set up as a revolutionary alternative to the Comintern,

they not only qualified their previous view of the socialist character

of the revolution by going for a notion of dual revolution, but drew the

further conclusion that the end result had not been socialism, but state

capitalism. As Gorter put it, “in the large towns it was a change from

capitalism to socialism, in the country districts a change from

feudalism to capitalism. In the large towns the proletarian revolution

came to pass: in the country the bourgeois revolution.“[82] The

reference to the passing of the socialist side of the revolution was a

reference to how, as they argued, the NEP had not merely been a

‘concession’ to the peasantry, as the Bolsheviks talked of it, but had

been a complete capitulation to the peasant — for them, bourgeois — side

of the revolution. The effect was that the proletarian side of the

revolution had been sacrificed, and what had been put in its place was

instead a form of state capitalism.

Back to Luxemburg?

It was the central, if implicit, role of the Agrarian Question and the

Internationalist perspective was to play in their theories that led them

to return, ironically to Luxemburg. In 1918 she wrote a text — The

Russian Revolution — in which, while declaring solidarity with the

Bolsheviks, she made some deep criticisms of their actions in Russia,

nearly all of which the German Left were to take up as their own.

Written before the German Revolution, her condemnation of the Bolsheviks

was, however, secondary to her condemnation of the passivity of the

German Social Democrats for not following their revolutionary example.

She had no time for the Menshevik line echoed by the Social Democrats in

Germany that Russia was only ready for a bourgeois revolution. Instead

she insisted that the problems of the Russian Revolution were “a product

of international developments plus the Agrarian Question’ which ‘cannot

possibly be solved within the limits of bourgeois society’ and thus that

the fate of the revolution depended on the international proletariat,

especially the German proletariat without which aid the Russian

Revolution could not fail to become distorted, becoming ‘tangled in a

maze of contradictions and blunders.’ (p. 29) The German Left — not

guilty like the Social Democrats of betraying the Russian revolution —

could see itself as theoretically untangling these contradictions and

blunders which the failure of world revolution had led the Russian

Revolution into.

The blunders Luxemburg criticized the Bolsheviks for were: their line on

national self determination; their suppression of the constituent

assembly and voting; their tendency towards a Jacobin Party dictatorship

rather than a real dictatorship of the proletariat involving the masses;

and their land policy which she said would create ‘a new and powerful

layer of popular enemies of socialism on the countryside, enemies whose

resistance will be much more dangerous and stubborn than that of the

noble large landowners.” [p 46] Giving this last point decisive

importance, the German Left supported all of Luxemburg criticisms except

for her position on the Constituent Assembly.

In fact the importance they attached to this last point became even

clearer when Gorter, in drawing upon Luxemburg’s assessment of the party

dictatorship, nevertheless put a different slant on it. This came out

when in The International Workers Revolution,[83] started by quoting her

statement: “Yes: dictatorship... but this dictatorship must be of the

work of the class and not that of a leading minority in the name of the

class: that is to say, it must, step by step, arise from the active

participation of the class, remain under its direct influence, and be

subordinated to the control of publicity and be the outcome of the

political experience of the whole people.” In other words, Gorter agreed

with Luxemburg that the dictatorship of the proletariat was not the

undemocratic dictatorship of the party, but rather the quite democratic

dictatorship of the whole class. However he added that what she ‘did not

understand’ was ‘that all this could not happen in Russia; that no class

dictatorship was possible there, because the proletariat was too small

and the peasantry too mighty.’ This orientation to the need for a

majority proletariat had thus taken him to question the possibility of

socialist revolution in Russia.

Gorter moved to the view that the bourgeois measures the Bolsheviks had

made were being forced by Russia’s backwardness. He argued that the

minority status of the proletariat in Russia had forced a ‘party

dictatorship’, and stated that despite not being organised, the

‘elementary power’ of the peasantry ‘forced the Bolsheviks — even men

like Lenin — to stand against the class from which it had sprung, and

which was inimical to the peasantry.’ But what he did criticise the

Bolsheviks for, however, was their programme and the action they had

prescribed to the proletariat in advanced countries, which had blocked

the world revolution, and hence made the building up of world capitalism

possible. It was only because of the latter that the bourgeois measures

in Russia had become unredeemable.

Ruhle was to go even further than Gorter in this fatalistic direction.

Going away from Gorter’s notion of a dual revolution, he argued that the

revolution had been bourgeois from the start. He grounded this view on

what he called ‘the phaseological development as advocated by Marx, that

after feudal tsarism in Russia there had to come the capitalist

bourgeois state, whose creator and representative was the bourgeois

class.’[84] So considering the historical circumstances, the Russian

Revolution could only have been a bourgeois revolution. Its role was to

get rid of tsarism, to smooth the way for capitalism, and to help the

bourgeoisie into the saddle politically. It was in this context that the

Bolsheviks, regardless of the subjective intentions, ultimately had to

bow for the historical forces at play. And their attempt to leap a stage

of development had not only showed how they had forgotten the ‘ABC of

Marxist knowledge’ that socialism could only come from mature

capitalism, but was also based ‘the vague hope of world revolution’ that

Ruhle now characterised as unjustified ‘rashness.’

But whilst this move to a semi-Menshevik position was indeed a move back

to the exact same position they had previously criticised the Social

Democrats for having, it also had its merits. Where the earlier German

Left focus on the New Course and NEP as a reversion to capitalism had

the deeply unpleasant implications that both war communism and Stalin’s

‘left turn’ was a return to socialism, the rigidly schematic position of

Ruhle’s theory allowed him to question the measures of nationalisation

used in both these periods:

‘nationalisation is not socialisation. Through nationalisation you can

arrive at a large scale, tightly run state capitalism, which may exhibit

various advantages as against private capitalism. Only it is still

capitalism. and however you twist and turn, it gives no way of escape

from the constraint of bourgeois politics’.

It was Ruhle’s semi-Menshevik and fatalistic interpretation of Russia

that, like his full blown councilism, was at first resisted, but then

largely accepted by the German Left. This came out in what was its

closest to a definitive statement on the Russian question: the Theses on

Bolshevism.[85]

Theses on Bolshevism

The position the German Left was arriving at, and which came out in

their Theses, was that the class and production conditions in Russia,

first forced the dictatorship to be a party rather than class one, and

second forced that party dictatorship to be a bourgeois capitalist one.

But where this general idea, in Ruhle, had been solely confined to

describing the historical forces that were at play behind the backs of

the Bolsheviks, and regardless of their subjective intentions, in the

Theses it took a more conspiratorial form. The Bolsheviks had not merely

been forced into a position of unwittingly carrying out a bourgeois

revolution, but had done so intentionally. From the very start they had

been a ‘jacobinal’ organisation of the ‘revolutionary petty

bourgeoisie’, who had been faced with a bourgeoisie that neither had the

collective will nor strength to carry out a bourgeois revolution. So by

manipulating the proletarian elements of society, they had been able to

carry out a bourgeois revolution against the bourgeoisie. Consequently,

‘the task of the Russian Revolution [had been] to destroy the remnants

of feudalism, industrialize agriculture, and create a large class of

free labourers’. But despite this rather conspiratorial element of the

theory of the German Left, they escaped arguing that if the

revolutionary proletariat had just realised the true nature of the

Bolsheviks, they could have avoided the fate that was awaiting them.

Rather, the fact that the Bolsheviks had taken the form of a

revolutionary bourgeoisie was precisely because of the backwardness of

Russia, and the consequent development had been inevitable.

It was this notion of the Bolsheviks taking the role of the bourgeoisie

that allowed them, like Ruhle had done, to avoid seeing Stalin’s ‘left

turn’ as a step in the right direction, and instead they saw it as an

attempt by the Soviet state to master the contradictory tension of the

two forces it had been riding: a ‘bolshevistic, bureaucratically

conducted state economy’ based on a regimented terrorised proletariat,

and the peasant economy which ‘conceals in its ranks the private

capitalist tendencies’ of the economy. [p57] Or in other words, not as

with Trotsky’s Left Opposition, a tension between the socialist and

capitalist sectors, but between the state capitalist and petty

capitalist sides of the economy.

So like the Russian left communist current, the German Left was to end

up characterising Russia as state capitalist, or as they called it

‘state production with capitalist methods.’ Whilst the commanding

heights of the economy were bureaucratically conducted by the Bolshevik

state, the underlying character was essentially capitalist. This they

grounded by arguing that ‘it rests on the foundation of commodity

production, it is conducted according to the viewpoint of capitalist

profitability; it reveals a decidedly capitalist system of wages and

speedup; it has carried the refinements of capitalist rationalisation to

the utmost limits.’ Furthermore, the state form of production, they

argued, was still based on squeezing surplus value out of the workers;

the only difference being that, rather than a class of people

individually and directly pocketing the surplus value, it was taken by

the ‘bureaucratic, parasitical apparatus as a whole’ and used for

reinvestment, their own consumption, and to support the peasants.

These arguments were a statement of the classic state capitalist case:

Russia was capitalist because all the categories of capitalism continued

to exist only with the state appropriating the surplus value and the

bureaucrats playing the role of capitalists. And in keeping with the

notion of state capitalism postulated by Marx and Engels, they ended up

grasping it as a higher stage of capitalism. As they argued, ‘The

Russian state economy is therefore profit production and exploitation

economy. It is state capitalism under the historically unique conditions

of the Bolshevik regime, and accordingly represents a different and more

advanced type of capitalist production than even the greatest and most

advanced countries have to show.’[58–59]

However, the problems with grounding the accusation of state capitalism

on the basis that all the capitalist categories continued to exist soon

became apparent. To say that production was oriented to capitalist

profitability seemed questionable when the immediate aim seemed to be

the production of use-values, particularly of means of production with

no concern for the immediate profitability of the enterprise. Also to

say that goods were produced as commodities when it was the state

direction rather than their exchange value which seemed to determine

what and how many goods were produced, also required more argument.

While the state unquestionably seemed to be extracting and allocating

surplus products based on exploitation of surplus labour, to say that it

took the form of surplus value seemed precisely a point of contention.

It was these apparent differences between Russian and western capitalism

that led them to use the terms ‘state capitalism’ and ‘state socialism’

interchangeably. And it was these theoretical problems of the German

Left that Mattick was later to try and solve. However, the main

direction of German Left theoretical effort in relation to the Russia

question was not to analyse the system in the USSR, but to build

alternative models of transition to the statist one they identified as

responsible for the Russian disaster. On the one hand, they were tempted

by a mathematical model of labour accounting that was supposed to

overcome money and value,[86] on the other, they made elaborate plans of

how workers councils could run society instead of the a party-state.[87]

Mattick: Its capitalism, Jim, but not as we know it

Seeing his role as one of continuing the German council communist

tradition, and preserving its insights, Mattick first made explicit what

had been implicit in their assessment of Bolshevik policies.[88]

Recognising that Leninism was merely a variant of Kautskyist social

democracy, he made it clear that the Bolshevik conception of socialism

was from the start very different from, and in opposition to, the one

coming out of the councilist left. The reality of what Russia turned out

to be was not merely a reflection of the particular historical

circumstances it was faced with, but was embedded in the very ideology

of the Bolsheviks. This essentially Second International ideology had

seen the fundamental contradiction of capitalism as consisting in it

being, on the one hand, an anarchic system in which the law of value

regulated the market ‘behind people’s back’ and, on the other hand,

having a tendency towards the socialisation of the productive forces,

and the development of more and more centralised planning and control.

Socialism was thus seen as the rational solution to this anarchy through

the appropriation, by a workers party, of the planning and

centralisation that capitalism was itself developing.

Mattick, following the councilist tradition, saw this statist vision as

having entirely lost the perspective of socialism as the abolition, by

the workers themselves, of their separation from the means of

production; of the abolition of the capital/labour relation and their

consequent ability to control the conditions of life — to establish a

society based on the free association of producers, as Marx had called

it. It was this perspective that allowed him, like previous left

communists, to say that the Bolsheviks, by taking the means of

production into the hands of the state, had not achieved socialisation,

but only the ‘nationalisation of capital as capital’ ownership by

government rather than private capitalists. It was in this way that he,

against Trotsky and Stalin, could make the obvious point that the means

of production were not controlled by society as a whole, but still

existed vis a vis the workers as alien capital, and as such Russia had

not abolished the capital/labour relation fundamental to capitalism.

However, while this point was important, it was not enough proof in

Marxian terms of the existence of capitalism. The questions remained:

how did the system operate?, what was its drive or regulating

principles?, what laws governed it? And on these questions he was

orthodox enough a Marxist to accept that complete statification of the

means of production was a modification of capitalism with serious

implications for the validity of fundamental value categories.

Specifically the problem consisted in to what extent the law of value

still governed the economy in Russia. As Marx had argued, one of the

main defining characteristics of capitalism is that the market is

governed by the law of value. This means that instead of having a system

in which production is consciously planned so as to meet people’s needs,

we have a system in which these needs are only meet indirectly through

the exchange of commodities on the market. And the only regulatory

principle on the market is that of supply and demand. Against the

previous left communist tendency to classify Russia as state capitalist

without trying to ground it in the categories of value, Mattick even

made the further point that “to speak of the law of value as the

‘regulator’ of the economy in the absence of specifically capitalist

market relations can only mean that the terms ‘value’ and ‘surplus

value’ are retained, though they express no more than a relation between

labour and surplus labour.” [p321] The problem for Mattick was of course

that, considering he took Russia at face value and thought it was a

genuinely planned system, it became difficult to at the same time call

it capitalist. Considering that the market would no longer be run along

the lines of indirect forms of commodity exchange governed by the law of

value, but would be directly planned according to need, it would be

problematic to say that the law of value existed at all.

Ultimately, this led Mattick to concede that state capitalism in Russia

lacked what was a defining feature of capitalism, namely the law of

value. No longer having this option open to him, Mattick reverted back

to his previous reasons for calling Russia capitalist, coupled with the

vague point that it was ‘a system of exploitation based on the direct

control of a ruling minority over the ruled majority.’[p321]. But while

he still insisted on the continuity of exploitative social relations,

the fact that Mattick thought that the law of value had ceased to exist,

led him to affirm the argument of the previous German Left that Russia

was an advanced form of capitalism. This even to the extent that it had

overcome some of the main problems of private-property capitalism,

namely competition, crises and, as a result of the consequent stability,

to some extent class antagonisms.

The notion that Russia could not have a problem with crisis sounds

ironic today. There is also the further irony that while the main point

of Mattick’s book — on which it succeeded pretty well — was to attack

the view, so prevalent in the post-war boom, that Keynesianism had

resolved capitalism’s crisis tendency. But a more pressing problem with

his theory of Russia lies exactly with what he set out to prove, namely

that Russia, despite its apparent differences from western capitalism

was still capitalist in Marx’s terms. Although trying to say that what

he was describing was just a change in the form of capitalism, from

‘market’ to ‘state-planned’, this was open to the objection that value

relations such as those that occur through the market are not incidental

— they are of the very essence of the capital relation. And although

Mattick rightly pointed to the fact that Russia was still based on the

exploitation of the majority by the minority, one could easily argue

that the defining point about capitalism is exactly that this

exploitation occurs through the indirect form of commodity exchange with

all its mystifications. Indeed, it could be argued that Mattick

virtually implied that Russia was a non-capitalist form of exploitation

that used capitalist forms to cover up the arbitrary nature of its

exploitation. It is in the light of the major concessions to the

differences between the state system and normal capitalism Mattick was

willing to make, that critics would be justified in doubting the

validity of the term at all. Hence instead of solving the problems of

the theory of the German Left, that led them to use the terms ‘state

capitalist’ and ‘state socialist’ interchangeably, he merely exposed

them.

In a 1991 interview, his son Paul Mattick (Jnr) speculated that the

collapse of the USSR might have indicated that his father was wrong and:

whether it wasn’t a mistake of all the people, members of this

ultra-left current, among whom I would include myself, to think of the

Bolshevik form, the centralized, state controlled economy, as a new

form, which we should think of as coming after capitalism, as

representing, say, a logical end point of the tendency to monopolization

and centralization of capital, which is a feature of all private

property capitalist systems. Instead, it seems to really have been a

kind of preparation for capitalist, development, a pre-capitalist form,

if you want. ’

This is exactly what the leading thinker of the Italian Left had argued.

The Italian Left

Origins

We now turn to the other main left communist position, that of the

Italian left. Like the German and Dutch Lefts the Italian Left

originated, in the years before the first world war as a left opposition

within a Second International party, in their case the Socialist Party

of Italy (PSI). But whereas German social democracy had exposed itself

as both reactionary and actively counter-revolutionary, the very

radicality of the Italian working class, and consequent strength of the

Left, meant that reformism in the PSI was not as hegemonic as in the

SPD. In 1912 the party even expelled an ultra-reformist wing over its

support for Italy’s Libyan war, and when the world war broke out and the

Italian working class responded with a Red Week of riots across the

country reaching insurrectionary proportions in Ancona, the PSI alone

among the western Social democratic parties did not rally to the nation.

Their apparent difference from the SPD further came out when in 1919 the

PSI affiliated to the Comintern. The enemy of the Italian Left was thus

not an obviously counter-revolutionary party, but one dominated by the

revolutionary posture of ‘Maximalism’, that is, combining verbal

extremism with opportunist economic and political practice, or more to

the point, inaction. This discontinuity between the social democracy in

Italy and Germany was to greatly influence their theoretical

developments. Where the German Left had very quickly reacted to the

current events by making a final break with social democracy and going

for a full blown councilist line, the Italian Left remained much more

favourable to partyism. In a sense we could say that while the German

Left tendency was to overcome the social democratic separation of the

‘political’ and ‘economic’ struggle by putting their trust in a

revolutionary ‘economic’ struggle, the solution that the Italian Left

moved to was an absolute subordination of political and economic

struggles to a genuinely communist ‘political’ direction.

The determination to decisively politically break from all reformism

developed in the context of Italy’s experience of the revolutionary wave

— the Biennio Rosso (Red Two Years). This was a period in which workers

set up factory councils, poor peasants and demobilised soldiers seized

land, and where demonstrations, street actions, rioting, strikes and

general strikes were regular occurrences. From the summer of 1919, when

the state nearly buckled in the face of near insurrectionary food riots

and syndicalist forms of redistribution and counter power, to the

Occupations of the Factories in September 1920, revolution seemed almost

within their reach. However, instead of taking an active part in this

revolutionary wave, the PSI and its linked unions refused to act and at

times even actively sabotaged the class struggle. However, where the

German Left had reacted to similar occurrences by breaking with the SPD

and identifying with the council movement, the reaction within the

Italian party was, on the one hand, the Abstentionist Communist Fraction

around Bordiga struggling to eliminate the reformists from the party,

and on the other hand, the L’Ordine Nuovo (L’ON) centred around Gramsci

and orientated to councils, but who saw no need to break from the

‘Maximalism’ of the PSI.

The adequate basis for the break with ‘Maximalism’ was finally provided

when, in the context of this intense class struggle, the Italian PSI

delegates, including Bordiga, went to the 2^(nd) Congress of the

Comintern in mid-1920. Key to this Congress was the setting of 21

conditions for membership of affiliating parties. Although Bordiga’s

group had to renounce their abstentionism, the overall target was the

‘centrist’ and opportunist tendencies of the PSI. Seeing that the

overall tendency within the Comintern was in their favour, Bordiga even

managed to beef up the disciplinary measures so that complying with the

directives given by the Comintern was a condition for affiliation.

Consequently, the Second Congress turned out to be massively helpful to

them in their battle with the centre/right, and as such their attempts

to forge a genuinely revolutionary communist party in Italy. They came

away strengthened in their fight with the PSI by Lenin’s authority, and

felt that their fight for a revolutionary party was in convergence with

the Bolsheviks. Consequently, the ideas beginning to emerge within the

German Left — that Bolshevik prescriptions for the Western proletariat

were not necessarily appropriate; that there might even be a

contradiction between Bolshevism and revolutionary politics; and that

the good of the World Revolution was being sacrificed to the national

needs of the Russian state — not only failed to resonate with the

Italian Left, but quite the opposite seemed to be the case.

With this reinforcement from Moscow the Italian Left finally made their

break with the PSI. This was prompted by the movement of factory

occupations, that exposed the bankruptcy of the PSI and its CGL unions.

As a wage dispute by members of the Metal workers union developed into a

massive wave of factory occupations, and everybody could see that the

situation was critical and had moved beyond economic demands, the PSI

and the unions responded by exposing their absolute inability to act for

revolution. Instead of taking any revolutionary initiative, the PSI

passed the bug to the CGL, who had a vote on whether to go for

revolution or not. The outcome was 409,000 for revolution and 590,000

against. But where the break from social democracy had led the Germans

to a full blown councilist approach, in Italy the defeat of the factory

occupations also marked the end of the councilist approach of Gramsci’s

L’ON group. Bordiga’s analysis on the need for a principled break with

PSI’s ‘Maximalism’ was now accepted by nearly all revolutionaries in the

party, and in early 1921 they formed the Communist Party of Italy (PCI)

under his leadership.

However, the coming together of the communist elements came too late.

Not only was the Bienno Rosso a failed revolution, but a fascist

counter-revolution was on the cards. With the tacit support of the

democratic state, fascist squadrista moved from their rural strongholds

to attack workers neighbourhoods and worker organisations. Although

communist and other workers formed armed detachments to fight back, the

sort of working class reaction that in Germany defeated the Kapp putsch

did not materialise, and by the end of 1922 Mussolini was in power.

Revolutionary setbacks, however, were not just confined to Italy, but

was a general international phenomenon. But instead of recognising this

as being the result of social democracy (or the failure of these parties

to lead the struggles in a revolutionary direction, as the Italian Left

saw it), the Comintern responded by imposing its policy of a ‘united

front’. For Italy the ‘united front’ line meant demanding the PCI fuse

with Serrati’s PSI, only asking that it first expel its right wing

around Turatti. For Bordiga and the PCI, after their hard fought battle

to disentangle themselves from the pseudo revolutionary maximilism of

Serrati, the demand they unite with him was anathema.[89] They felt that

in the turn to these flexible tactics, the communist political programme

they had arrived at was in danger of being diluted or lost.

But where this, in Germany, led to the final break with Bolshevism, in

Italy it resulted in a total Bolshevisation of the PCI. Ironically it

was the Italian Left that had not only fought to make the Italian Party

Bolshevik (in terms of their perception of the meaning of that term),

but had also insisted on the Comintern’s disciplinary role on national

sections. But now they were to become one of the main victims of that

discipline. Their insistence that socialism was only possible if carried

out on a world-scale and led by an international revolutionary party, as

well as their failure to see that the Comintern was largely dominated by

Russia and used for its own national purposes, meant that they still

perceived the Comintern as this international and revolutionary agent.

Ultimately, this meant that they were willing to accept the rigors of

discipline to policies they totally opposed and indeed felt were

betraying the communist programme, in order to hold on for as long as

possible. This even to the extent that Bordiga, despite his overall

majority in the PCI, conceded leadership to a small faction of the party

led by Gramsci, which was willing to obey Moscow and impose

‘Bolshevisation’ on the party. Later Bordiga and the fraction around him

were forced out of the party they had created.[90] Still, it would be

many years before would fully identify Russia as capitalist.

Bordiga’s theory

So where the Germans, in their councilism, had taken an outright

anti-Leninist stance, the Italian Left took a much more Leninist

approach. Indeed when the Italian Left had finally, in exile, started to

question the nature of Russia, it was in a manner that seemed at first

closer to that of Trotsky’s, rather than the theories coming out of left

communists elsewhere. Against the German left communists, they had

insisted that the argument that the Russian Revolution had been

bourgeois from the start, was a loss of the whole international

perspective that had been shared by all the revolutionary fractions at

the time. But whilst this point certainly allowed the Italians not to

lose the revolutionary significance of October, their logic that if the

revolution had been a proletarian revolution, the state was a

proletarian state that had degenerated, had the down-side of appearing

to be a version of Trotsky’s theory of a degenerated workers state.

The ‘Leninist’ side of the Italian Left became especially clear with

Bordiga when, in his attempt to gain an understanding of the nature of

Russia, put great emphasis on the very text that Lenin had used to

attack the Russian Left Communists, namely the Tax in Kind pamphlet. By

returning to the Agrarian Question Bordiga bypassed a lot of state

capitalist concerns. Looked at economically, he argues, Russia did not

have the prerequisites for socialism or communism, and the tasks that

faced it were bourgeois tasks, namely the development of the productive

forces for which resolving the Agrarian Question was essential. However,

the war that Russia was part of was an imperialist war that expressed

that the capitalist world as a whole was ready for socialist revolution

and Russia had not only a proletariat who carried out the revolution,

but a proletarian party oriented to world revolution had been put in

power. Thus on the ‘primacy of the political’ October was a proletarian

revolution. But insofar as Bordiga assumed that, economically speaking,

there was no other path to socialism than through the accumulation of

capital, the role of the proletarian party was simply to allow but at

the same time keep under control the capitalist developments necessary

to maintain social life in Russia.

Ironically however, it was exactly in emphasising Lenin’s notion that

capitalism under workers control of the party was the best Russia could

have, that Bordiga could go beyond not only the Trotskyism, that the

Italian Left theory of Russia had initially seemed close to, but more

importantly maybe, the theory of the German Left. As was shown in the

previous article of this series, Trotsky took the nationalisation of

land and industry as well as the monopoly on foreign trade, as evidence

for Russia in fact having the socio-economic foundations for socialism —

hence his notion that the revolution was congealed in ‘property forms’.

And relying on Preobrazensky’s contrast between what he saw as the ‘law

of planning’ of the state sector versus the law of value of the peasant

sector, he argued that one of the main obstacles that had to be dealt

with before arriving at socialism proper, was the capitalist features of

the peasant sector. As such he argued that Russia was a more advanced

socialistic transitional economy. The German Left, although differing

from Trotsky’s view in the sense that they maintained that the

revolution had been bourgeois from the start, was in essence very close

to it. This was insofar as they, in line with the traditional state

capitalist argument, saw Russia as a more advanced, concentrated version

of capitalism, leading Mattick virtually to a third system conception.

Bordiga, exactly by returning to Lenin’s emphasis on the political,

could avoid going down that path. The clashes between the state

industrial sector and the peasant sector was not, as Trotsky and

Preobrazhensky had argued, the clash between socialism and capitalism.

Rather, as Bordiga argued, it was the clash between capitalism and

pre-capitalist forms. And here lay the real originality of Bordiga’s

thought: Russia was indeed a transitional society, but transitional

towards capitalism. Far from having gone beyond capitalist laws and

categories, as for instance Mattick had argued, the distinctiveness of

Russian capitalism lay in its lack of full development.

This was grounded on Russia’s peripheral status versus the core

capitalist economies. In a period when world capitalism would otherwise

have prevented the take off of the capitalist mode of production,

preferring to use underdeveloped areas for raw materials, cheap labour

and so on, Russia was an example of just such an area, that through

extreme methods of state protectionism and intervention secured

economical development and as such prevented the fate of being assigned

a peripheral status on the world market. It is this role of the

Bolsheviks as the enforcer of capitalist development that explains why

the USSR became a model for elites in ex-colonial and otherwise less

developed countries.

The failure of both Trotsky and the German Left to see this also showed

up in their confusion with regard to Stalin’s ‘left-turn’. Never having

accepted the Primitive Socialist Accumulation thesis of Preobrazhensky,

Bordiga could make the rather obvious judgement that what Stalin carried

out in the thirties — the forced collectivisation of peasants and the 5

year plans — was a savage primitive capitalist accumulation: a ‘Russian

capitalism Mark 2’. Stalin’s ‘left turn’ was then neither a product of

his impulses nor represented him being forced to defend the ‘socialist’

gains of the economy’. Rather it came from the pressing need for capital

accumulation felt by Russia as a competing capitalist state. And the

Stalinist excesses of the thirties — “literally a workers’ hell, a

carnage of human energy.“[91] — were but a particular expression of the

“general universal conditions appropriate to the genesis of all

capitalism.” For Bordiga once the proletarian political side went, what

was striking was the continuity of the problems facing the emerging

capitalism in Russia whether its government be Tsarist or Stalinist:

that of attempting to develop the capitalist mode of production in a

backward country facing world imperialism. In 1953 he states: “The

economic process underway in the territories of the Russian union can be

defined essentially as the implanting of the capitalist mode of

production, in its most modern form and with the latest technical means,

in countries that are backward, rural, feudal and asiatic-oriental.”

[p43]

Indeed, as Bordiga recognised, the problems involved with the crash

course in capitalist development that the Bolsheviks imposed, also

resulted in certain measures that were to obstruct the full expressions

of a capitalist development. He centred this on its inadequate

resolution of the sin qua non of capitalism: the Agrarian Revolution.

Despite its brutality, Bordiga noted that the collectivisation process

involved a compromise by which the peasants did not become entirely

property-less, but were allowed to retain a plot of land and sell its

produce through market mechanisms. This, as Bordiga saw it, re-produced

the capitalist form of the small-holder, but without the revolutionary

progressive tendency to ruin and expropriate these producers, because

‘the little that belongs to him is guaranteed by law. The collective

farmer is therefore the incarnation of the compromise between the

ex-proletarian state and the small producers past on in

perpetuity.’[25–6] While collectivisation did produce the proletarians

necessary for state industry, Soviet agriculture remained a hybrid form,

an achilles heel of the economy never attaining full subordination to

capitalist laws.

This view of the Russian state being in the service of developing

capitalism in Russia also allowed Bordiga to go beyond the focus on

bureaucracy of Trotsky’s theory, and its mirror in most state capitalist

theories, such as the Germans, of identifying these new state officials

as a new ruling class. Bordiga felt that the obsession with finding

individual capitalist or substitutes for capitalists had lost Marx’s

understanding of capital as above all an impersonal force. As Bordiga

said ‘determinism without men is meaningless, that is true, but men

constitute the instrument and not the motor.’[92] Such a point also

applies to the state: as Bordiga argued, ‘it is not a case of the

partial subordination of capital to the state, but of ulterior

subordination of the state to capital’[p.7] State despotism in Russia

was at the service of the capitalist mode of production pushing its

development in areas that resisted it. However, a weakness of Bordiga’s

analysis was that whereas he looked under the surface of the Soviet

claims about agriculture, he tended to base his view that the state

sector was governed by the law of value simply on the appearance of

forms, like commodities and money, and on Stalin’s claims that value

exists under socialism. So although the Italian Left seemed at first

closer to the Trotsky’s notion of a degenerated workers state, it was

through Bordiga’s literal interpretation of Lenin on the Russian

economy, he could go beyond both Trotsky and the German Left.

Conclusion

As stated in the introduction, any analysis of the Russian revolution

and the society that emerged from it cannot be separated from a

conception of what communism is. Indeed one way in which all the left

communists, unlike Trotsky, could go beyond Second International

Marxism, was by insisting that neither the transition to communism nor

communism itself should in any way be identified with state-control of

the means of production. Indeed nothing short of their proper

socialisation or communisation would do. It was this perspective that

allowed them to distance themselves from, and criticise Russia as being

state capitalist or, as Bordiga put it, simply capitalist.

However, with regard to their specific answers to the question of what a

genuine communisation process would have consisted in, the situation was

slightly more ambiguous. The Germans (and to some extent the Russians),

in their focus on the economic sphere, ultimately ended up with a notion

of communism consisting in workers’ self-management. The important

differentiation between capitalism and communism was correctly seen to

lie in workers overcoming their separation from the means of production.

The idea was that only in the factory, only at the point of production

could workers overcome the domination maintained by bourgeois politics,

cease to act as isolated bourgeois individuals and act as a socialised

force, as a class. This slipped into a factoryism which neglected the

fact that the enterprise is a capitalist form par excellence and that if

the class is united, there it is united as variable capital. It was this

councilist approach that led them to work out rather mathematical

accounting schemes[93] for how the transition to communism could work

and elaborate schemes for how the councils could link up.

The problem with this self-management approach was of course that it

seemed to imply that as long as the enterprises were managed by the

workers themselves, it did not matter that capitalist social relations

continued to exist. It is in this sense that the German Left never

managed to make a full break from Second International Marxism’s

identification with the development of the productive forces and with

the working class as working class.

It was in this respect that the importance of the Italian Left came out.

In emphasising the ‘primacy of the political’, they could take a more

social and holistic standpoint. Communism was not just about replacing

the party with the councils, and state-control with workers control.[94]

Communism, they argued, was not merely about workers managing their own

exploitation, but about the abolition of wage labour, the enterprise

form and all capitalist categories. The fundamental question was not so

much that of ‘who manages?’ but about ‘what is managed?’

But whilst the German Left’s focus on the economic had led them into the

self-management trap, one thing it did allow them to do was to emphasise

the subjectivity of the working class as an agent of change. This notion

of subjectivity was, if not entirely absent in the theory of the Italian

Left, then reserved only for the party.

The absurdities involved in rejecting any notion of working class

subjectivity became especially clear in the Italian Left’s assessment of

Russia. There, they argued, communism could be represented in the

correct political line of a ruling party managing a system of capitalist

social relations — a ridiculously unmaterialist position — arguing that

what mattered was not the social relations in a country, but the

subjective intentions of those in power (a perfect justification for

repression based on the notion that ‘it was for their own good they were

massacred’). And it was in this respect that the Italian Left had not

completely broken from the politicism/partyism of the Second

International.

Indeed, it was the blind spots in each theory that led to their mutual

incomprehension: whilst the Italian Left saw the Germans as nothing more

than a Marxoid form of anarcho-syndicalism, the Germans in turn merely

saw the Italians as a bunch of Leninists. But if the dogmatic sides of

their respective theories merely served to push them further apart, it

was ultimately the one-sidedness of their respective approaches that

resulted in them not breaking entirely away from the dogmatism of the

Second International. Whilst the Italian Left had arrived at a more

adequate notion of the content of communism, it was the German Left that

was to provide the form through which emancipation could be reached.

In different ways, both the German and Italian left communist currents

managed to maintain a correct political perspective. While the German

Left emphasised workers’ self-emancipation, the Italian Left provide a

better angle on what communism would consist in. Yet, in terms of a

‘scientific’ account of the kind of society developing in the USSR, both

fell down.[95]

On the one hand, the German Left slipped into a conception of ‘state

capitalism’ that was not grounded in value. Without this essential

category they tended, like Tony Cliff and the Trotskyists, to see the

USSR as a ‘higher’, crisis-free type of economy. Bordiga’s theory, on

the other hand, did not fall into the trap of seeing the USSR as a more

advanced form of capitalism. Instead he recognised that Russia was in

transition towards capitalism. As we shall see, this is an important

insight into understanding the nature of the USSR.

But Bordiga did not really concern himself with value categories. He

largely assumed that the obvious signs of capital accumulation must be

based on commodities, money and wage-labour, all playing the same role

as in the West. It is thus Mattick who exposed the issue more

conscientiously. And if we are really to grasp the capitalist nature of

the USSR, both before and since the fall of ‘communism’, we must, on the

value question, provide a different answer than his. This will be

explored in our final Part of this article in the next issue.

Part IV: Towards a theory of the deformation of value

So our saga on the nature of the USSR draws to a close. While some

readers have awaited avidly for each exciting instalment, others from

the beginning thought we gave disproportionate space to this rather

tired old topic.[96] Another dissatisfied group may be the partisans of

particular theories which were not given the recognition they feel they

deserved.[97] This was unavoidable considering the sheer number of

theories one could have dealt with. The list of political tendencies

which have considered that the USSR was a variety of capitalism includes

‘anarchism, council communism, “impossibilism”, many types of Leninism

(including Bordigism, Maoism and a number arising out of Trotskyism),

libertarian socialism, Marxist-Humanism, Menshevism, the Situationist

International and social democracy.[98] Some might also question why, of

our previous parts, only one dealt with (state-)capitalist theories

outside Trotskyism. Yet what is striking in looking at these

alternatives is that none dealt adequately with the ‘orthodox Marxist’

criticisms coming from Trotskyism. If Trotskyism itself has been

politically bankrupt in its relation to both Stalinism and social

democracy — and this is not unrelated to its refusal to accept the USSR

was capitalist — at a certain theoretical level it still posed a

challenge. We restate the issues at stake in the first few pages below.

While fragmented ideological conceptions satisfy the needs of the

bourgeoisie, the proletariat must acquire theory: the practical truth

necessary for its universal task of self-abolition which at the same

time abolishes class society. Clearing some of the bullshit and

clarifying issues around one of the central obstacles to human

emancipation that the 20^(th) century has thrown up, namely the

complicity of the Left with capital, may help the next century have done

with the capitalist mode of production once and for all.

Introduction

The problem of determining the nature of the USSR was that it exhibited

two contradictory aspects. On the one hand, the USSR appeared to have

characteristics that were strikingly similar to those of the actually

existing capitalist societies of the West. Thus, for example, the vast

majority of the population of the USSR was dependent for their

livelihoods on wage-labour. Rapid industrialisation and the forced

collectivisation of agriculture under Stalin had led to the break up of

traditional communities and the emergence of a mass industrialised

society made up of atomised individuals and families. While the

overriding aim of the economic system was the maximisation of economic

growth.

On the other hand, the USSR diverged markedly from the laissez-faire

capitalism that had been analysed by Marx. The economy of the USSR was

not made up of competing privately owned enterprises regulated through

the ‘invisible hand’ of the market. On the contrary, all the principal

means of production were state owned and the economy was consciously

regulated through centralised planning. As a consequence, there were

neither the sharp differentiation between the economic nor the political

nor was there a distinct civil society that existed between family and

state. Finally the economic growth was not driven by the profit motive

but directly by the need to expand the mass of use-values to meet the

needs of both the state and the population as a whole.

As a consequence, any theory that the USSR was essentially a capitalist

form of society must be able to explain this contradictory appearance of

the USSR. Firstly, it must show how the dominant social relations that

arose in the peculiar historical circumstance of the USSR were

essentially capitalist social relations: and to this extent the theory

must be grounded in a value-analysis of the Soviet Union. Secondly it

must show how these social relations manifested themselves, not only in

those features of the USSR that were clearly capitalist, but also in

those features of the Soviet Union that appear as distinctly at variance

with capitalism.

The capitalist essence of the USSR

As we saw in Part III, there were a number of theories that emerged out

of the Communist Left following the Russian Revolution that came to

argue that the USSR was essentially a form of capitalism. Most of these

early theories, however, had focused on the question of the class nature

of the Russian Revolution and had failed to go far in developing a

value-analysis of the Soviet System.[99] However, following Mattick’s

attempt to analyse the USSR of value-forms there have been a number of

attempts to show that, despite appearances to the contrary, the dominant

social relations of the USSR were essentially capitalist in nature.

Of course, any theory that the USSR was in some sense capitalist must

reject the vulgar interpretation of orthodox Marxism which simply sees

capitalism as a profit driven system based on private property and the

‘anarchy of the market’. The essence of capitalism is the dominance of

the social relations of capital. But what is capital? From Marx it can

be argued that capital was essentially the self-expansion of alienated

labour: the creative and productive powers of human activity that

becomes an alien force that subsumes human will and needs to its own

autonomous expansion.

Yet the alienation of labour presupposes wage-labour which itself

presupposes the separation of the direct producers from both the means

of production and the means of subsistence. Of course, in the ‘classical

form’ of capitalism private property is the institutional means through

which the direct producers are separated from both the means of

production and the means of subsistence. The class of capitalists owns

both the means of production and the means of subsistence in the form of

the private property of each individual capitalist. In confronting the

private property of each individual capitalist the worker finds himself

excluded from access to the means through he can either directly or

indirectly satisfy his needs. As a consequence he is obliged to sell his

labour-power to one capitalist so that he can then buy his means of

subsistence from another. Yet in selling their labour-power to

capitalists the working class produce their future means of subsistence

and their future means of production as the private property of the

capitalist class. In doing so they end up reproducing the relation of

capital and wage-labour.

Yet this social relation is not fundamentally altered with the

institution of the state ownership of both the means of production and

the means of subsistence. Of course the Stalinist apologists would claim

that the state ownership of means of production meant the ownership of

by the entire population. But this was quite clearly a legal formality.

The Soviet working class no more owned and controlled their factories

than British workers owned British Steel, British Coal or British

Leyland in the days of the nationalised industries. State ownership,

whether in Russia or elsewhere, was merely a specific institutional form

through which the working class was excluded from both the means of

production and the means of subsistence and therefore obliged to sell

their labour-power.

In selling their labour-power to the various state enterprises the

Russian workers did not work to produce for their own needs but worked

in exchange for wages. Thus in a very real sense they alienated their

labour and hence produced capital. Instead of selling their labour-power

to capital in the form of a private capitalist enterprise, the Russian

working class simply sold their labour-power to capital in the form of

the state owned enterprise.

Whereas in the ‘classical form’ of capitalism the capitalist class is

constituted through the private ownership of the means of production, in

the USSR the capitalist class was constituted through the state and as

such collectively owned and controlled the means of production.

Nevertheless, by making the Russian working class work longer than that

necessary to produce the equivalent of their labour-power the Russian

State enterprises were able to extract surplus-value just as the

counterparts in the West would do. Furthermore, while a part of this

surplus-value would be used to pay for the privileges of the ‘state

bourgeoisie’, as in the West, the largest part would be reinvested in

the expansion of the economy and thus ensuring the self-expansion of

state-capital.

Hence by penetrating behind the forms of property we can see that the

real social relations within the USSR were essentially those of capital.

The USSR can therefore be seen as having been capitalist — although in

the specific form of state capitalism. However politically useful and

intuitive correct this classification of the USSR may be, the problem is

that by itself this approach is unable to explain the apparently

non-capitalist aspects of the USSR. As anyone acquainted with Hegel

might say ‘the essence must appear!’. Capital may be the self-expansion

of alienated labour but it is labour in the form of value. How can we

speak of value, or indeed surplus-value, when there is no production of

commodities, since without markets there was no real production for

exchange?

These criticisms of state capitalist theories of the USSR have emerged

out of the Trotskyist tradition. It is to this tradition that we must

now turn to explore the limits of the state capitalist theories of the

USSR.

The Trotskyist approach

The more sophisticated Trotskyist theorists have criticised the method

of state capitalist theories of the USSR. They argue it is wrong to seek

to identify an abstract and ahistorical essence of capitalism and seek

to identify its existence to a concrete historical social formation such

as the USSR. For them the apparent contradiction between the

non-capitalist and capitalist aspects of the USSR was a real

contradiction that can only be understood by grasping the Soviet Union

as a transitional social formation.

As we saw in Part I, for Trotskyists, the Russian Revolution marked a

decisive break with capitalism. As a consequence, following 1917, Russia

had entered a transitional period between capitalism and socialism. As

such the USSR was neither capitalist nor socialist but had aspects of

the two which arose from the struggle between the law of value and of

planning.

As a result Trotskyist never denied the existence of capitalist aspects

of the USSR. Indeed they accepted the persistence of capitalist forms

such as money, profits, interest and wages. But these were decaying

forms — ‘empty husks’ — that disguised the emerging socialist relations

in a period of transition. This becomes clear, they argue if we examine

these ‘capitalist forms’ more closely.

Firstly, it may appear that in the USSR that production took the form of

production for exchange and hence products took the form of commodities.

After all, different state enterprises traded with each other and sold

products to the working class. But for the most part such exchange of

products was determined by the central plan not by competitive exchange

on the market. As a consequence, while the state enterprises formally

sold their outputs and purchased their inputs such ‘exchanges’ were in

content merely transfers that were made in accordance with the central

plan. Hence production was not for exchange but for the plan and thus

products did not really assume the form of commodities.

Secondly, since there was no real commodity exchange, but simply a

planed transfer of products, there could be no real money in USSR. While

money certainly existed and was used in transactions it did not by any

means have the full functions that money has under capitalism. Money

principally functioned as a unit of account. Unlike money under

capitalism, which as the universal equivalent, was both necessary and

sufficient to buy anything, in the USSR money may have been necessary to

buy certain things but was often very far from being sufficient. As the

long queues and shortages testified what was needed in USSR to obtain

things was not just money but also time or influence.

Thirdly, there were the forms of profits and interest. Under capitalism

profit serves as the driving force that propels the expansion of the

economic system, while interest ensures the efficient allocation of

capital to the most profitable sectors and industries. In the USSR the

forms of profit and interest existed but they were for the most part

accounting devises. Production was no more production for profit than it

was production for exchange. Indeed the expansion of the economic system

was driven by the central plan that set specific targets for the

production of use-values not values.[100]

Finally and perhaps most importantly we come to the form of wages. To

the extent that Trotskyist theorists reject the Stalinist notion that

the Russian working class were co-owners of the state enterprises, they

are obliged to accept that the direct producers were separated from both

their means of subsistence and the means of production. However, in the

absence of general commodity production it is argued that the Russian

worker was unable to sell her labour-power as a commodity. Firstly,

because the worker was not ‘free’ to sell her labour power to who ever

she chose and secondly because the money wage could not be freely

transformed into commodities. As a consequence, although the workers in

the USSR were nominally paid wages, in reality such wages were little

more than pensions or rations that bore scant relation to the labour

performed. The position of the worker was more like that of a serf or

slave tied to a specific means of production that a ‘free’ wage worker.

We shall return to consider this question of ‘empty capitalist forms’

later. What is important at present is to see how the Trotskyist

approach is able to ground the contradictory appearance of the USSR as

both capitalist and non-capitalist in terms of the transition from

capitalism to socialism. To this extent the Trotskyist approach has the

advantage over most state capitalist theories that are unable to

adequately account for the non-capitalist aspects of the USSR. This

failure to grasp the non-capitalist aspects of the USSR has been exposed

in the light of the decay and final collapse of the USSR.

Capitalist crisis and the collapse of the USSR

One of the most striking features of the capitalist mode of production

is its crisis ridden mode of development. Capitalism has brought about

an unprecedented development of the productive forces, yet such

development has been repeatedly punctuated by crises of overproduction.

The sheer waste that such crises could involve had become clearly

apparent in the great depression of the 1930s. On the one side millions

of workers in the industrialised countries had been plunged into poverty

by mass unemployment while on the other side stood idle factories that

had previous served as a means to feed and clothe these workers. In

contrast, at that time Stalinist Russia was undergoing a process of

rapid apparently crisis free industrialisation that was to transform the

USSR from a predominantly agrarian economy into a major industrial and

military power.[101]

In the 1930s and the decades that followed, even bourgeois observers had

come to accept the view that the Stalinist system of centralised

planning had overcome the problem of economic crisis and was at least in

economic terms an advance over free market capitalism. The only question

that remained for such observers was whether the cost in bourgeois

freedom that the Stalinist system seemed to imply was worth the economic

gains of a rationally planned economy.

While it became increasingly difficult for Trotskyists to defend the

notion that the USSR was a degenerated workers state on the grounds that

the working class was in any sense in power, the USSR could still be

defended as being progressive in that it was able to develop the forces

of production faster than capitalism. To the extent that the rapid

development of the forces of production was creating the material

conditions for socialism then the USSR could still be seen as being in

the long term interests of the working class.

Many of the state capitalist theorists shared this common view that the

USSR was an advance over the free market capitalism of the West. While

they may have disagreed with the Trotskyist notion that the Russian

Revolution had led to a break with capitalism they still accepted that

by leading to the eventual introduction of a predominantly state

capitalist economy it had marked an advance not only over

pre-Revolutionary Russia but also over Western capitalism.

This view seemed to be confirmed by the post Second World War

development in Western capitalism. The emergence of Keynesian demand

management, widespread nationalisation of key industries, indicative

planning[102] and the introduction of the welfare state all seemed to

indicate an evolution towards the form of state capitalism. For many

bourgeois as well as Marxist theorists of the 1950s and 1960s there was

developing a convergence between the West and the East as the state

increasingly came to regulate the economy. For Socialism or Barbarism

there was emerging what they termed a ‘bureaucratic capitalism’ that had

overcome the problems of economic crisis.

As we noted in Part III, Mattick as one of the leading state capitalist

theorist of the German left, rejected the claims that Keynesianism had

resolved the contradictions of capitalism. Yet nevertheless he took the

claims that the USSR had itself resolved the problems of economic crisis

through rational planning at face value.

However, as we saw in Part II, by the 1970s it had become increasingly

clear that the USSR had entered a period of chronic economic stagnation.

By the time of the collapse of the USSR in 1990 only the most hard line

Stalinist could deny that the USSR had been a bureaucratic nightmare

that involved enormous economic waste and inefficiency.

State capitalist theories have so far proved unable to explain the

peculiar nature of the fundamental contradictions of the USSR that led

to its chronic stagnation and eventual downfall.[103] If the USSR was

simply a form of capitalism then the crisis theories of capitalism

should be in some way applicable to the crisis in the USSR. But attempts

to explain the economic problems of the USSR simply in terms of the

falling rate and profit, overproduction and crisis etc. have failed to

explain the specific features of the economic problems that beset the

USSR. The USSR did not experience acute crisis of overproduction but

rather problems of systematic waste and chronic economic stagnation,

none of which can be explained by the standard theories of capitalist

crisis.

As a consequence of this limitation of state capitalist theories,

perhaps rather ironically, the most persuasive explanation of the

downfall of the USSR has not arisen from those traditions that had most

consistently opposed the Soviet Union, and which had given rise to the

theories that Soviet Union was a form of State Capitalism, but from the

Trotskyist tradition that had given the USSR its critical support. As we

saw in Part II, it has been Ticktin that has given the most plausible

explanation and description of the decline and fall of the USSR.

Although in developing his theory of the USSR Ticktin was obliged to

ditch the notion that the USSR remained a degenerate workers state, he

held on to the crucial Trotskyist notion that the Soviet Union was in a

transitional stage between capitalism and socialism. For Ticktin,

Russia’s transition to socialism was part of the global transition from

capitalism to socialism. With the failure of the world revolution

following the First World War Russia was left in isolation and was

unable to complete the transition to socialism. As a consequence, the

USSR became stuck in a half-way position between capitalism and

socialism. The USSR subsequently degenerated into a ‘non-mode of

production’. While it ceased to be regulated by the ‘law of value’ it

could not adequately regulated through the law of planning without the

participation of the working class.

As we saw in Part II, it is within this theoretical framework that

Ticktin argued that the USSR was the first attempt to make the

transition from capitalism to socialism within the global epoch of the

decline of capitalism that Ticktin was able to develop his analysis of

the decline and fall of the USSR. However, as we also saw while his

analysis is perhaps the most plausible explanation that has been offered

for the decline and fall of the USSR it has important failings. As we

have argued, despite twenty years and numerous articles developing his

analysis of the USSR, Ticktin has been unable to develop a systematic

and coherent methodological exposition of his theory of the Soviet Union

as a non-mode production. Instead Ticktin is obliged to take up a number

of false starts each of which, while often offering important insights

into the nature and functioning of the USSR, runs into problems in its

efforts to show that the Soviet Union was in some sense in transition to

socialism. Indeed, he is unable to adequately explain the persistence

and function of capitalist categories in the USSR.

If we are to develop an alternative to Ticktin theory which is rooted in

the tradition that has consistently seen the USSR as being state

capitalist[104] it is necessary that we are able to explain the

non-capitalist aspects of the USSR that previous state capitalist

theories have failed to do. To do this we propose to follow Ticktin and

consider the USSR as a transitional social formation, but, following the

insights of Bordiga and the Italian Left, we do not propose to grasp the

USSR as having been in transition from capitalism but as a social

formation in transition to capitalism.

But before we can do this we must first consider particular nature of

the form of state capitalism.

The historical significance of state capitalism

Within the traditional Marxism of both the Second and Third

Internationals state capitalism is viewed as the highest form of

capitalism. As Marx argued, the prevalent tendency within the

development of capitalism is the both the concentration and

centralisation of capital. As capital is accumulated in ever large

amounts the weak capitals are driven out by the strong. Capital becomes

centralised into fewer and fewer hands as in each industry the

competition between many small capitals becomes replaced by the monopoly

of a few.

By the end of the nineteenth century the theorists of the Second

International had begun to argue that this tendency had gone so far that

the competitive laissez-faire capitalism that Marx had analysed in the

mid-nineteenth century was giving way to a monopoly capitalism in which

the key industries were dominated by national monopolistic corporation

or price-fixing cartels. It was argued that the development of such

monopolies and cartels meant that the law of value was in decline.

Output and prices were now increasingly being planed by the monopolies

and cartels rather than emerging spontaneously from the anarchy of a

competitive market.

Furthermore it was argued that in order to mobilise the huge amounts of

capital now necessary to finance large scale productive investments in

leading sectors such those of the steel, coal and rail industries,

industrial capital had begun to ally, and then increasingly fuse, with

banking capital to form what the leading economic theorist Hilferding

termed finance capital. Within finance capital the huge national

monopolies in each industry were united with each other forming huge

national conglomerates with interests in all the strategic sectors of

the economy. The logical outcome of this process was for the

centralisation of finance capital to proceed to the point where there

was only one conglomerate that owned and controlled all the important

industries in the national economy.

However, the growth of finance capital also went hand in hand with the

growing economic importance of the state. On an international scale the

development of finance capital within each nation state led to

international competition increasingly becoming politicised as each

state championed the interests of its own national capitals by military

force if necessary. Against rival imperial powers each state had begun

to carve out empires and spheres of influence across the globe to ensure

privileged access to markets and raw materials necessary to its domestic

capital. At the same time the development of huge monopolies and finance

capital forced the state to take a far more active role in regulating

the economy and arbitrating between the conflicting economic interests

that could no longer be mediated through the free operation of

competitive markets.

As a consequence, the development of finance capital implied not only a

fusion between industrial and banking capital but also a fusion between

capital and the state. Capitalism was remorselessly developing into a

state capitalism in which there would be but one capital that would

dominate the entire nation and be run by the state in the interests of

the capitalist class as a whole. For the theorist of the Second

International it was this very tendency towards state capitalism that

provided the basis of socialism. With the development of state

capitalism all that would be needed was the seizure of the state by the

working class. All the mechanisms for running the national economy would

then be in the hands of the workers government who could then run the

economy in the interests of the working class rather than a small group

of capitalists.

But this notion that state capitalism was the culmination of the

historical development of capitalism, and hence that it was capitalism’s

highest stage, arose out of the specific conditions and experience of

Germany at the end of the nineteenth century. Germany’s rapid

industrialisation following its unification in 1866 had meant that by

the end of the nineteenth century it was seriously challenging Britain

as Europe’s foremost economic power. At the same time the rapid

emergence of an industrial proletariat had given rise to the German

Social Democratic Party which was not only the first but also the

largest and most important mass workers party in the world and as such

dominated the Second International. It is perhaps no surprise then that

the Marxist theorists of the Second International, whether German or

not, should look to Germany. But their generalisation of the development

of capitalism of Germany to a universal law was to prove an important

error.

This error becomes clear if we consider the other two leading capitalist

powers at the end of the nineteenth century: Britain that had been the

leading capitalist power throughout the century, and the USA, along with

Germany were rapidly overtaking Britain in economic development. Of

course, in both Britain and the USA capitalist development had seen the

prevalence of the tendency of the centralisation and concentration of

capital that was to lead to the growth of huge corporations and

monopolies. Furthermore, partly as a result of such a concentration and

centralisation of capital, and partly as a result of the class conflict

that accompanied it, the state was to take on increasing

responsibilities in managing the economy in the twentieth century.

However, there was no fusion between banking and industrial capital nor

was their a fusion between the state and capital on any scale comparable

that which could be identified in Germany either at the end of the

nineteenth century or subsequently in the twentieth century.

The international orientation of British capital that had become further

consolidated with the emergence of the British Empire in the late

nineteenth century, meant there was little pressure for the emergence of

finance capital in Hilferding’s sense. British industrial capital had

long established markets across the world and was under little pressure

to consolidate national markets through the construction of cartels or

national monopolies.

Equally British banking capital was centred on managing international

flows of capital and investing abroad and was far from inclined to make

the long term commitments necessary for a merger with industrial

capital. British industrial capital raised finance principally through

the stock market or through retained profits not through the banks as

their German counterparts did. While the British state pursued an

imperial policy that sought to protect the markets and sources of raw

materials for British capital it stop short there. The British State

made little effort to promote the development of British capital through

direct state intervention since in most sectors British capital still

retained a commanding competitive advantage.

In the USA the concentration of banking capital was restricted. As a

consequence there could be no fusion between large scale banking capital

and large scale industrial capital. As a continental economy there was

far more room for expansion in the USA before capitals in particular

industries reached a monopolistic stage and when they did reach this

stage they often faced anti-trust legislation. Furthermore, the relative

geo-economic isolation of the USA meant that protectionist measures were

sufficient to promote the development of American industry. There was

little need for the US government to go beyond imposing tariffs on

foreign imports in order to encourage the development of domestic

industry. As a consequence there was not only no basis for the fusion of

industrial and banking capital but there was also little basis for the

fusion of the state with capital.

In the twentieth century it was the USA, not Germany, that took over

from Britain as the hegemonic economic power. While it is true that the

tendency towards the concentration and centralisation of capital has

continued in the USA, that both state regulation and state spending has

steadily increased, and that with the emergence of the

industrial-military complex there has grown increasing links between the

state and certain sectors of industry, the USA, the most advanced

capitalist power, can hardly be designated as having a state capitalist

political-economy. Indeed, with the rise of global finance capital and

the retreat of the autonomy of the nation state, the notion that state

capitalism is the highest stage of capitalism has become increasingly

untenable.

If state capitalism is not the highest stage of capitalism as was argued

by the theorists of the Second and Third Internationals then what was

its historical significance? To answer this we must first of all briefly

consider the particular development of industrial capitalism in Germany

which were provided the material conditions out of which this notion

first arose.

Germany and the conditions of late industrialisation

As Marx recognised, Britain provided the classic case for the

development of industrial capitalism. After nearly four centuries of

evolution the development of mercantile and agrarian capitalism had

created the essential preconditions for the emergence of industrial

capitalism in Britain by the end of the eighteenth century. Centuries of

enclosures had dispossessed the British peasantry and created a large

pool of potential proletarians. At the same time primitive accumulation

had concentrated wealth in the hands of an emerging bourgeoisie and

embourgeoified gentry who were both willing and able to invest it as

capital.

The early decades of the nineteenth century saw the rapid

industrialisation and urbanisation of Britain. By the mid-nineteenth

century Britain had established itself as the ‘workshop of the world’.

Britain’s manufacturers flooded the world markets, particularly those of

Europe. The development of the factory system and the subsequent

application of steam power meant that the products of British industry

were far cheaper than those of European industries that were for the

most part still based on handicraft production.

As a consequence much of the proto-industrial craft production that had

grown up across Europe during the previous two centuries faced ruin from

British industrial production. Whereas in Britain the emergence of

industrial capitalism had seen a retreat in the role of the state and

the emergence of laissez-faire, on the continent the ruinous competition

of British industry forced the European states to take measures to

protect and foster domestic industry. Indeed British economic

competition meant there was no option for the gradual evolution into

capitalism. On the contrary the European ruling classes had to

industrialise or be left behind. If the domestic bourgeois proved to

weak too carry out industrialisation then the state had to carry out its

historical mission for it.

The 1870s marked a crucial turning point in the development of the

formation of the world capitalist economy, particularly in Europe. The

period 1870–1900 marked a second stage in industrialisation that was to

divided the world between a core of advanced industrialised countries

and periphery of underdeveloped countries. A division that for the most

part still exists today.

The first stage of industrialisation that had begun in Britain in the

late eighteenth century, and which had been centred on the textile

industries, had arisen out of handicraft and artisanal industry that had

grown up in the previous manufacturing period. The machinery that was

used to mechanise production was for the most part simply a

multiplication and elaboration of the hand tools that had been used in

handicraft production and were themselves the product of handicraft

production. At the same time the quantum of money-capital necessary to

set up in production was relatively small and was well within the

compass of middle class family fortunes.

The second stage of industrialisation that emerged in the final decades

of the nineteenth century was centred around large scale steel

production, and heavy engineering. Industrial production now presupposed

industrial production. Industrial machinery was now no longer the

product of handicraft production but was itself the product of

industrial production. Industrial production had grown dramatically in

scale and in cost. The quantum of capital necessary to set up in

production was now often well beyond the pockets of even the richest of

individuals. Money-capital had to be concentrated through the

development of joint-stock companies and banks.

In Britain, and perhaps to a lesser extent France, the period of early

industrialisation had created the presuppositions for the future

industrialisation of the second stage. An industrial base had already

been established while the accumulation of capital and the development

of the financial institutions provide the mass of money capital

necessary for further industrialisation. In contrast the division of

Germany into petty-statelets that was only finally overcome with its

unification in 1866 had retarded the development of industrial capital.

As a consequence, Germany had to summon up out of almost nothing the

preconditions for the second stage of industrialisation if it was not to

fall irrevocably behind. This required a forced concentration of

national capital and the active intervention of the state.

This was further compounded by Germany’s late entrance into the race to

divide up the world. The new industries that began to emerge in the late

nineteenth century demanded a wide range of raw materials that could

only be obtained outside of Europe. To secure supplies of these raw

materials a race developed to divide up the world and this led to the

establishment of the vast French and British Empires of the late

nineteenth century. Excluded from much of the world, German capital

found itself compressed within the narrow national confines of Germany

and its immediate eastern European hinterland.

It was this forced concentration and centralisation of German capital

and its confinement within the narrow national boundaries of Germany and

eastern Europe that can be seen as the basis for the tendencies towards

the fusion both between industrial and banking capital and between the

state and capital that were peculiar to Germany at the end of the

nineteenth century. As such the tendency towards state capitalism that

was identified by the theorist of the Second International owed more to

Germany’s late industrialisation than to any universally applicable

tendency towards state capitalism. Indeed, the twentieth century has

shown, those economies that have managed to overcome the huge

disadvantages of late industrialisation — such as Japan and more

recently the ‘Newly Industrialising Countries’ (NICs) such as South

Korea, Taiwan, Indonesia, Brazil and Mexico — state-led development has

played a crucial part in their success.[105]

However, state capitalism only remained a tendency in Germany. In the

USSR the fusion of the state and capital can be seen to have been fully

realised. We must therefore turn to consider the case of the late

development of Russia.

Russia and late Development

As we saw in Part I, the Russian autocracy had made repeated efforts to

‘modernise’ and ‘industrialise’ the Russian economy. With the abolition

of serfdom in 1866 and the introduction of the Stolypin agrarian reforms

in the early 1900s the Tzarist Governments had sought to foster the

growth of capitalist agriculture. At the same time the Tzarist regime

encouraged foreign investment in the most modern plant and machinery.

However, the Tzarist efforts to modernise and industrialise the Russian

Empire were tempered by the danger that such modernisation and

industrialisation would unleash social forces that would undermine the

traditional social and political relations upon which the Russian

imperial autocracy was founded. Indeed, the prime motive for promoting

the industrialisation of the Russian Empire was the need for an

industrial basis for the continued military strength of the Russian

Empire. As military strength increasingly dependent on industrially

produced weapons then it became increasingly important for the Russian

State to industrialise.

As a consequence, the industrialisation of pre-Revolutionary Russia was

narrowly based on the needs of military accumulation. While Russia came

to possess some of the most advanced factories in the world the vast

bulk of the Russian population was still employed in subsistence or

petty-commodity producing agriculture. It was this economic structure,

in which a small islands of large scale capitalist production existed in

a sea of a predominantly backward pre-capitalist agriculture, that the

Bolsheviks inherited in the wake of the October Revolution.

The Russian Revolution of 1917 was a dual revolution. On the one hand it

was a proletarian revolution. It was the urban working class that

brought down the Tzarist regime in February, defeated the Kornilov’s

counter-revolution in August and then, through the political form of the

Bolshevik Party, seized political power in October. Yet although the

Russian proletariat, in alliance with the peasantry, succeeded in

sweeping away the Tzarist autocracy, and uprooting the semi-feudal

aristocratic ruling class on which it rested the proletarian revolution

was ultimately defeated.

The Russian proletariat failed to go beyond the situation of dual power

in the streets and the factories that had arisen during period between

the February and October Revolution. Unable to take over and directly

transform the social relations of production the contradictions involved

in the situation of dual power were resolved in favour of

nationalisation rather than the communisation of the means of

production. The consequences of which soon became clear with the

re-introduction of Taylorism and the imposition of one man management in

the Spring of 1918.

The Bolshevik Party, which had been the political form through which the

Russian proletariat had triumphed, then became the form through which it

suffered its defeat. The Leninists could only save the revolution by

defeating it. The emergency measures employed to defend the gains of the

revolution — the crushing of political opposition, the re-employment

Tzarist officials, the reimposition of capitalist production methods and

incentives etc., only served to break the real power of the Russian

working class and open up the gap between the ‘workers’ Government’ and

the Workers. This process was to become further consolidated with the

decimation of the Revolutionary Russian proletariat during the three

years of civil war.

Yet, on the other hand, while the Russian Revolution can be seen as a

failed proletarian revolution it can also be seen as a partially

successful ‘national bourgeois’ revolution. A national bourgeois

revolution, neither in the sense that it was led by a self-conscious

Russian bourgeoisie, nor in the sense that it served to forge a

self-conscious Russian bourgeoisie, but in the sense that by sweeping

away the Tzarist absolutist state it opened the way for the full

development of a Russian capitalism.

In the absence of the Russian Revolution, the Russian Empire would have

probably gone the way of the Austrian-Hungarian Empire. The Russian

Empire would have been broken up in the face of international

competition. The more advanced parts may have then been reintegrated

within the orbit of European capitalism, while the rest would have been

dumped in the economically undeveloped world. However, the Russian

Revolution had forged a strong state that, unlike the previous Tzarist

regime, was able to fully develop the forces of production.

In the backward conditions that prevailed in Russia, capitalist economic

development could only have been carried out by through the forced

development of the productive forces directed by the concentrated and

centralised direction and power of the state. It was only through

state-led capitalist development that both the internal and external

constraints that blocked the development of Russian capitalism could be

overcome.

In Russia, the only way to industrialise — and hence make the transition

to a self-sustaining capitalist economy — was through the fusion of

state and capital — that is through the full realisation of state

capitalism. Yet to understand this we must briefly consider the external

and internal constraints that had blocked the capitalist development of

Russia at the beginning of the twentieth century.

Underdevelopment

In The Communist Manifesto Marx remarks:

The bourgeoisie, by the rapid improvement of all instruments of

production, by the immensely facilitated means of communication. draws

all, even the most barbarian, nations into civilisation. The cheap

prices of its commodities are the heavy artillery with which it batters

down all Chinese walls, with which it forces the barbarians’ intensely

obstinate hatred of foreigners to capitulate. It compels all nations, on

pain of extinction, to adopt the bourgeois mode of production; it

compels them to introduce what it calls civilisation into their midst

i.e., to become bourgeois themselves. In one word, it creates a world

after its own image.[106]

Of course, capital’s inherent tendency to reproduce itself on an ever

greater scale has led to the relentless geographical expansion of

capitalism to the point where its has long since encompassed the entire

globe. However, this process has been a highly uneven one. The

concentration and centralisation of capital that has led to rapid

capitalist development in one region of the world has presupposed the

plunder and de-development of other regions of the world.

As we have already noted, in the late nineteenth century the development

of industrial capitalism in Western Europe and North America imposed an

international division of labour that still divides the world a hundred

years later. The economic relations that served to promote the rapid

accumulation of capital in the ‘core’ of world capitalism at the same

time served to block the full development of industrial capitalism in

the periphery of world capitalism. To this extent world capitalism

became polarised.

In this process of polarisation Russia found itself in a peculiar

position. On the one hand, as the impact of industrial capitalism spread

eastwards across Europe from Britain, Russia was the last European

country to confront the need to industrialise. As such it was the last

of the late European industrialisers. On the other hand, Russia can be

seen as the first of the non-western countries that sought to resist the

impact of underdevelopment.

To understand this peculiar position that Russia found itself in at the

beginning of the twentieth century, and how it shaped the transition to

capitalism in Russia, we must briefly consider the question of

underdevelopment.

Mercantile and Industrial capitalism

Capitalism, or more precisely the capitalist mode of production, only

becomes established with the emergence of industrial capital. It is only

when capital takes full possession of the means of production and

transforms them in accordance with its own needs that capitalism becomes

a self-sustaining economic system that can dominate society. However,

where ever there has been the widespread use of money arising from the

exchange of commodities capital has emerged in the distinct form of

mercantile capital.

Mercantile capital has had an independent existence since the early

period of antiquity. However, in pre-capitalist modes of production it

has been ultimately parasitic. Mercantile capitalism is driven by

profit. But it is a profit not based on the direct expropriation of

surplus-value but on unequal exchange — buying cheap in order to sell

dear. Mercantile capital was therefore always ultimately dependent on

the predominant means of surplus extraction in any particular society.

Following the crisis in European feudalism in the fourteenth century and

the subsequent emergence of the world market in the sixteenth century

mercantile capitalism came in to its own and began to rapidly expand it

influence. As such it had two contradictory effects. On the one side,

mercantile capitalism brought with it an increase in the production and

circulation of money and commodities and in doing so served to undermine

the traditional pre-capitalist social relations. To this extent it

prepared one of the essential preconditions for the development of the

capitalist mode of production — the creation of an economy based on

generalised commodity exchange. On the other side, insofar mercantile

capitalism remained dependent on the traditional structures of society,

it became a conservative force that blocked the development of an

industrial capitalism.

Mercantile capitalism had grown up hand in hand with the development of

the Absolutist State. In order to free itself from the feudal nobility

the absolutist state was increasingly dependent on loans and money taxes

that had become possible with the monatrisation of the feudal economy

that was being brought about by the rise of mercantile capitalism. Yet,

while the absolute monarchy was dependent on merchants and their bankers

for loans and taxes, they in turn were dependent on the state for the

defence of their monopolies and access to foreign markets.

However, although there was a certain symbiosis in the development of

the Absolutist State and mercantile capitalism, the absolute state was

careful to contain the development of mercantile capitalism. The

excessive development of mercantile capitalism always threatened to

undermine the existing social order on which the Absolutist State rested

as traditional relations of authority were replaced by the cynical and

impersonal relations of the market. Thus while the state encouraged

merchants to profiteer at the expense of foreigners they were far less

inclined to allow such profiteering to cause social discord at home.

Hence the Absolutist State was keen to intervene to regulate trade, not

only to protect the monopoly positions of the favoured merchants, but

also to maintain social peace and stability.

In order to secure its sources of supply mercantile capital had from an

early stage involved itself in production. To this extent the

development of commerce led to the development of industry and commodity

production. However, for the most part mercantile only formally subsumed

production. Mercantile capital left unaltered the traditional craft

based methods of production.

In the late eighteenth century, however, industrial capital began to in

to its own with the rise of factory production and the application of

steam powered machinery. Industrial capital directly expropriated

surplus-value through its domination of the production process. As such

it had no need for the privileges of bestowed by the state on merchant

capital in order to make a profit. Indeed such privileges and monopolies

became a block to industrial capital’s own self-expansion. Under the

banners of liberty and laissez-faire the industrial bourgeoisie

increasingly came into conflict with the conservatism of mercantile

capital and the established ruling classes that it upheld.

In the course of the nineteenth century industrial capital triumphed in

Western Europe over mercantile capital and its aristocratic allies. As a

consequence, mercantile capital became subordinated to industrial

capital. It became merely a distinct moment in the circuit of industrial

capital; dealing in the sale and distribution of commodities produced by

industrial capital. The profits of mercantile capital no longer came to

depend on state privileges but derived from the surplus-value produced

by industrial capital in production. However, although mercantile

capital became integrated with industrial capital in Western Europe its

relation to industrial capital in other parts of the world was

different.

From the sixteenth century mercantile capital had come to encompass the

entire world. However, while in Europe the corrosive effects of

mercantile capitalism on the established social order had been held in

check by the state, in much of the rest of the world the impact of

mercantile capitalism had been devastating:

In America and Australia whole civilisations where wiped out; West

Africa was reduced to a slave market and no society escaped without

being reduced to a corrupt parody of its former self.[107]

The conditions created by mercantile capitalism in these parts of the

world were far from being conducive for the development of industrial

capital. Industrial capitalism developed in Western Europe, and

subsequently North America where capital had already been concentrated

and where conditions were more favourable. As a consequence, industrial

capital left mercantile capital to its own devises in the rest of the

world. However, as Geoffrey Kay argues:

If merchant capital retained its independence in the underdeveloped

world, it was no longer allowed to trade solely on its own account but

was forced to become the agent of industrial capital. In other words,

merchant capital in the underdeveloped countries after the establishment

of industrial capitalism in the developed countries in the nineteenth

century existed in its two historical forms simultaneously. At one and

the same moment it was the only form of capital but not the only form of

capital. This apparent paradox is the specifica differentia of

underdevelopment, and its emergence as a historical fact in the course

of the nineteenth century marks the beginning of underdevelopment as we

know it.[108]

As the agent of industrial capital merchant capital plundered the

underdeveloped world for cheap raw materials while providing lucrative

outlets for industrial commodities produced in the developed world. To

the extent that it retained its independence mercantile capital shored

up the conservative elites and blocked the development of industrial

capital in the underdeveloped world. Hence:

The consequences were doubly depressing for the underdeveloped world: on

the one side the tendency of merchant capital to repress general

economic development in proportion to its own independent development;

on the other the reorganisation of whole economies to the requirements

of external economic interests.[109]

The emergence of a world polarised between a core of industrially

advanced economies and a periphery of underdeveloped economies was

further compounded with the rise of international moneyed capital.

As we saw previously, the growth in the sheer scale of industrial

production meant that the mass of capital required to set up in

production increased beyond the means of most private individuals.

Furthermore, the further development of industrial production itself

presupposed the existence of industrial production. This had important

consequences on the polarisation of the world economy and the process of

underdevelopment.

Firstly, whereas in England and Western Europe industrial capital had

been able grow up on the basis of the pre-existent craft production. In

contrast undeveloped economies, like the late developing economies in

Europe itself, could not simply repeat the evolutionary stages through

which industry had involved in the core economies since they would be

uncompetitive in the world market. Instead they had to make the leap and

introduce modern plant and machinery. But such modern plant and

machinery was the product of industrial production that for the most

part did not exist in the underdeveloped world. It therefore had to be

imported from the advanced industrial economies.

Secondly, the underdeveloped economies lacked the concentration and

centralisation of capital necessary to finance of the most advanced

capitalist enterprises. It therefore not only had to import productive

capital in order to industrialise, it had to import moneyed capital

either in the form of direct foreign investments by industrial capitals

of the core economies or borrow money-capital from the international

banks and financial institutions.

To the extent that the underdeveloped economies were able to attract

foreign investment or loans it was able develop it industry. But such

industrialisation was for the most part limited and orientated towards

producing commodities demanded by the needs of capital accumulation in

the more advanced industrialised economies. Its serfdom contributed to

the creation of an industrial base on which a self-sufficient national

accumulation of capital could occur. Furthermore, in the long term the

interest or profits on such foreign investments were repatriated to the

core economies and did not contribute to the further national

accumulation of capital in the underdeveloped economies themselves.

Russia and the problem of underdevelopment

The defeat of the Russian Revolution as a proletarian revolution, and

the subsequent failure of the world revolution that followed the First

World War, left the Bolsheviks isolated and in charge of a predominantly

backward and underdeveloped economy. The very existence of the Russian

state, and with it the survival of the ‘Soviet Government’, now depended

on the Bolsheviks carrying through the tasks of the national bourgeois

revolution — that is the development of national industrial capital.

Yet in order to carry through such tasks the Bolsheviks had to overcome

the formidable problems of underdevelopment that reinforced the internal

obstacles to the modernisation and industrialisation of Russia. The two

most pressing internal obstacles to the development of a national

industrial capital were the problem of finance and the problem of

agriculture.

Russian agriculture was predominantly based on small scale subsistence

or petty-commodity production. This had two important consequences for

industrialisation. Firstly, it blocked the formation of an industrial

proletariat since the bulk of the population was still tied to the land.

Secondly, the inefficient and backward nature of Russian agriculture

prevented it from producing a surplus that could feed an expanding

industrial proletariat.

To the extent that the Russian peasants could be encouraged to produce

for the world market then there could be expected the gradual

development of a capitalist agriculture. As production for profit led to

an increasing differentiation in the peasantry some would grow rich

while others would become poor and become proletarianised. But this was

likely to be a long drawn out process. Profits would be small given the

mark ups of the international merchants and the need to compete with

more efficient capitalist agriculture on the world market. Furthermore,

to the extent that the Russian peasantry produced for the world market,

it could not provide cheap food for an expanding Russian proletariat.

The second important obstacle to industrialisation was finance. The

backward character of Russian capitalism meant that there was little

internal capital that had been accumulated. To the extent that Russia

had industrialised it had been promoted by the state and financed

through foreign investments. But with the revolution the Bolsheviks had

repudiated all the foreign loans taken out under Tzarist regime and had

expropriated foreign owned capital in Russia. Once bitten the

international financiers were going to be twice shy about financing

Russian industrialisation.

If the national development of industrial capital was to be achieved in

Russia, if Russia was to make the transition to capitalism, then

Bolsheviks had to subordinate the fleeting and transnational forms of

capital — money and commodities — to the needs of national productive

capital — the real concrete capital of factories, plant, machinery and

human labour, rooted in Russian soil. This required that the Russian

State take charge of capital accumulation — that is that the transition

to a fully developed capitalism had to take the form of state

capitalism.

Hence, while at the end of the eighteenth century the French Revolution

had opened the way for the development of French capitalism by freeing

capital from the embrace of the state, in Russia at the beginning of the

twentieth century the Revolution opened the way for the development of

capitalism by increasing the embrace of the state over capital.

The deformation of Value

The problem of the nature of the USSR restated

As we seen, the traditional Marxism of the Second and Third

Internationals saw state capitalism as the highest stage of capitalism.

As such state capitalism could be seen as the first step in the

transition to socialism. As a consequence, Lenin could consistently

argue against the Left Communists — from the imposition of one-man

management and the reintroduction of Taylorism to the introduction of

the New Economic Policy — that the immediate task of the Revolutionary

Government, given the backward conditions in Russia, was first and

foremost the development of state capitalism.

Of course, for Lenin the nationalisation of the means of production and

the introduction of state planning introduced by the Revolution marked a

decisive advance. Under the control of a Workers’ State, state

capitalism would be superseded by socialism. Subsequently, with the

introduction of the five year plans and the collectivisation of

agriculture Stalin could announce that the USSR had at last reached the

stage of socialism and was on the way to a communist society. Trotsky

was more circumspect. While acknowledging the rapid development of the

forces of production that was being made under Stalin, he still saw this

as a stage of primitive socialist accumulation that, while being an

advance over capitalism, had yet to reach socialism.

To the extent that theorist of the capitalist nature of the USSR have

accepted this conception of state capitalism they have been obliged to

argue either that Russia never went beyond state capitalism in the first

place or that at some point their was a counter-revolution that led to

the USSR falling back into state capitalism. Yet, either way, by

accepting that state capitalism is the highest stage of capitalism such

theorists are led to the position of considering the USSR as an advance

over western capitalism. This, as we have seen, is a position that was

to become increasingly difficult to defend in the light the chronic

economic stagnation of the USSR and its eventual decline and collapse.

Indeed, such theories have been unable to explain the contradictions

within the USSR that finally led to its downfall.

In contrast, we have argued that state capitalism, far from being the

highest stage of capitalism, is a specific form for the late development

of capitalism. Yet this presupposes that the USSR was indeed such a form

of capitalism. To demonstrate this we must develop a value analysis of

the USSR.

As we have seen, state capitalist theorists have argued that the USSR

was essentially capitalist in that it was based on wage-labour. The

workers in the USSR were divorced from both the means of subsistence and

the means of production. As a consequence, in order to live, the Soviet

workers had to sell their labour-power to the state enterprises. Having

sold their labour-power the workers found themselves put to work. They

found themselves external to their own subject activity. They did not

work to produce their own needs, nor for the needs of their own families

or communities, but for some alien other. While the workers worked as a

means to obtain a wage through which they could survive, their labour

became independent of them, directed towards aims that were not their

own. In producing products that were not their own they served to

reproduce their position as workers on an ever expanding scale.

Hence, like their counter-parts in the west, the Russian workers were

subordinated to a process of production that was designed and developed

to maximise production with scant regard to the living experience of the

worker in production. As such the worker was reduced to a mere

instrument of production. Like their counter-parts in the West, the

Russian workers worked longer than that necessary to reproduce the

equivalent of their labour-power. Thus, like the their counter-parts in

the West, the Russian workers alienated their labour and were exploited.

If the relations of production were those of self-expanding alienated

labour then they were the productive relations of capital. As such, in a

fundamental sense the USSR was capitalist. But, as we have seen, the

more sophisticated Trotskyist object. Capitalism can not be taken to be

simply the apparent predominance of wage-labour. Capitalist production

presupposes, both historically and logically, generalised commodity

production in which labour-power itself has become a commodity. But, the

Trotskyists insist, products did not assume the form of commodities in

the USSR since there was no market. But if products did not assume the

form of commodities then there can have been no real wage-labour since

labour-power, as a commodity, can not be exchanged for other

commodities. Wages were merely a means of rationing products.

The problem then can be stated as follows. Production in the USSR would

seem to have been essentially a form of capitalist production, being

based on waged labour; but capitalist production presupposes general

commodity exchange. In the absence of the market it would seem that the

exchange and circulation of wealth in the USSR did not assume the

commodity-form and as such was distinctly non-capitalist. But if

commodities did not exist neither could capital.

To resolve this problem we must first look at the unity of production

and exchange that we find in fully developed capitalism. To do this we

shall examine the Circuits of Industrial Capital that Marx sets out at

the beginning of Volume II of Capital.

The circuits of industrial capital

As self-expanding value capital passes successively through three

distinct forms: the money-capital, commodity-capital and

productive-capital. Depending on which form of capital is taken as the

starting point in analysing the overall circulation of capital we can

identify three distinct circuits of capital each of which reveals

different aspects of the circulation of capital.

The first circuit is that of money-capital (M...M’):

M — Cmop + Clp ...P...C’- M’

Here capital in the form of money (M) is used to buy means of production

(Cmop) and labour-power (Clp) necessary to commence production. Hence

with the exchange M — C capital is transformed from money into the form

of commodities. These commodities (labour-power and the means of

production) are then used in the process of production. As such they

become productive capital, (P) which produces commodities of a greater

value C’. These commodities are then sold for a sum of money M’ which is

greater than the original capital advanced M.

With this circuit capitalism appears clearly as a system based driven by

profit. The circuit begins and ends with capital as money, and since

money is homogenous, the only aim of this circuit is the quantitative

expansion of capital as money, that is the making of a profit.

But this circuit not only shows how capitalist production is merely a

means through which ‘money makes more money’, it also shows how

capitalist production necessarily both presupposes commodity exchange

and reproduces commodity-exchange. The circuit begins with the commodity

exchange M — C, the purchase of means of production and labour-power

(which of course is at the same time the sale of labour-power and means

of production by their owners) and ends with a the commodity exchange C’

— M’, in which the sale of the commodities produced realises the

capital’s profit.

However, the process of ‘money making more money’ can only become

self-sustaining if it at the same time involves the expansion of real

wealth. This becomes apparent if we examine the circulation of capital

from the perspective of the circuit of productive-capital (P...P’).

P...C’ — M’ — C’ ...P’

Here capital in production produces an expanded value of commodities C’

which are then sold for an expand sum of money M’ that can then be used

to buy more means of production and labour-power in the commodity-form

C’. This then allows an expanded productive capital P’ to be set in

motion in the following period of production From the perspective of

productive capital, the circulation of capital appears as the

self-expansion of productive capacity of capital — the self-expansion of

the productive forces.

Capitalism now appears not so much as ‘production of profit’ but

‘production for production’s sake’. Capitalist production is both the

beginning and the end of the process whose aim is the reproduction of

capitalist production on an expanded scale. The commodity circulation

(C’ — M’ — C’) now appears as a mere mediation. A mere means to the end

of the relentless expansion capitalist production.

The final circuit that Marx identifies is that of commodity-capital

(C’...C’).

C’ — M’ — C ...P ...C’

With this circuit we can see the unity of capital in circulation and

capital in production. Capital as the circulation of commodities C’ — M’

— C appears side by side with the production of ‘commodities by means of

commodities’. The overall process of capitalist circulation therefore

appears as both the production and the circulation of commodities.

An analysis of these three circuits of industrial capital would seem at

first to confirm the Trotskyist position that capitalist production

necessarily presupposes generalised commodity exchange. However, these

circuits describe the fully developed capitalist mode of production not

its historical emergence.

As we have argued, the national development of Russian capitalism had

been impeded by its subordinate position in the world economic order.

The independent development of capital in its cosmopolitan forms of

merchant capital and moneyed-capital had acted to block the development

of industrial capital. National capitalist development demanded capital

in the real productive forms of factories, plant and machinery and the

labour of a growing industrial proletariat. As a consequence, if Russia

was to break free from its underdeveloped position imposed through the

world market, productive-capital had to be developed over and against

the independent development of capital-in-circulation i.e. money-capital

and commodity-capital. The free exchange of money-capital and

commodity-capital through the free operation of the market had to be

restricted to allow for the development of productive-capital. Hence the

free market was replaced by the central plan.

Hence, in taking up the ‘historic tasks of the bourgeoisie’ the

state-party bureaucracy adopted the perspective of productive-capital.

The more productivist elements of the Marxism of the Second

International were adapted to the ideology of productive-capital. The

imperative for the relentless drive to develop the productive forces

over and against the immediate needs of the Russian working class was

one that was not merely voiced by Stalin and his followers. Trotsky was

even more of a superindustrialiser than Stalin. Indeed he criticised

Stalin for not introducing planning and collectivisation of agriculture

earlier.

The question that now arises where what were the implications of this

subordination of capital-in-circulation to the development of

productive-capital? We shall argue that these value-forms existed in the

USSR, not as ‘husks’ as those in the Trotskyist tradition maintain, but

rather as repressed and undeveloped forms.

To what extent did the Commodity-form exist in the USSR?

As we have seen, Trotskyist theorists place great importance on property

forms when it comes to the question of the nationalisation of the means

of production. State ownership of the means of production, and hence the

abolition of private property, is seen as constituting the crucial

advance over capitalism. However, although the state owned all the

principal means of production in the USSR, the actual legal possession

and operation of the means of production was left to the state

enterprises and trusts, each of which was constituted as a distinct

legal entity with its own set of accounts and responsibilities for

production.

While Trotskyists have tended to gloss over this, seeing these legal

forms of the state enterprises as being merely formal, Bettleheim has

argued that the existence of these separate state enterprises, which

traded with each other and sold products to the working class, meant

that commodity-exchange did exist in the USSR. However, for Bettleheim,

this separation of economic activity into a multitude of state

enterprises was merely a result of the level of development of the

forces and relations of production. The USSR had yet to develop to the

point where the entire economy could be run as a giant trust as had been

envisaged by Bukharin. It was therefore unable as yet to overcome the

commodity-form. In contrast, we shall argue that this division of the

economy into distinct state enterprises was an expression of the

essentially capitalist relations of production.

What is a commodity? The simplest answer is that a commodity is

something that is produced in order that it may be sold. But by itself

this simple definition is inadequate for an understanding of the

commodity as a distinct social form. It is necessary to probe a little

deeper to grasp the implications of the commodity-form.

Any society requires that individuals act on and within the material

world in order to appropriate and produce the material conditions

necessary for the reproduction of themselves as social individuals. As

such social reproduction necessarily entails the constitution and

appropriation of material objects of social needs. However, in a society

dominated by commodity production this process is carried out in a

peculiar manner that gives rise to specific social forms.

Firstly, as commodity producers, individuals do not produce for their

own immediate needs but for the needs of others that are both

indifferent and separate from themselves. The results of their human

activity — their labour — are thereby divorced from their own activity.

The results of their labour stand apart from them as commodities that

are to be sold. Secondly, as commodity consumers, objects of an

individuals need do not emerge out of their own activity as social

individuals but as the ready made property of some other — the producer

— who is separated from them. As a consequence they find themselves

immediately separated from their own social needs through the

non-possession of material objects in the form of commodities.

As a consequence labour — the human activity of the producer — is

separated from need — the needs of the consumer. Hence, for each

particular commodity, producers are separated from consumers and are

only subsequently united through the sale or exchange of the commodity.

The relation between the consumer and the producer is therefore mediated

through the exchange commodities — that is they are mediated through the

exchange of things. To the extent that commodity exchange becomes

generalised then the relations between people manifests themselves as a

multitude of relations between things.

Because the relations of between human beings assume the form of the

relations between things then these things assume the particular social

form of the commodity. In producing a commodity the producer produces

something for sale — that is the producer produces something that can be

exchanged. What is important for the producer is that what is produced

has the social quality that makes it exchangeable. In other words what

is important for the producer is the value of the commodity. In

contrast, for the consumer, what is important is that the commodity has

a number natural properties that meet his own needs as a social

individual but which he is excluded from by the non-possession of the

commodity as an object — that is that it confronts him as a use-value.

The separation of social needs from social labour is thereby reflected

in the commodity-form as the opposition of use-value and value.

The commodity-form is therefore constituted through the opposition of

its use-value and value, which manifests in material form the underlying

opposition of labour from needs in a society, based on commodity

production. However, although objects of need must exist in all

societies — that is we must have access to distinct things, such as

food, clothes and shelter, in order to live — use-values can only exist

in opposition to value. Value and use-value mutually define each other

as polar opposites of the commodity-form. A commodity can only have a

value if it can be sold, but to sell it must have a use-value that some

other needs to buy. But equally a commodity has a use-value only insofar

as the qualities that meets the needs of the consumer confront that

consumer as the ready made products of another’s labour, and hence as

natural properties from which they are excluded except though the act of

exchange of another commodity with an equivalent value.

With commodity production social relations become reified. Society

becomes broken up into atomised individuals. Indeed, as Marx argues,

commodity relations begin where human community ends. Historically

commodities were exchanged between communities and only occurred when

different communities came in to contact. As commodity exchange develops

traditional human societies break up, ultimately giving rise to the

modern atomised capitalist societies.[110]

The society of the USSR would have seemed to be no less atomised and

reified than those of western capitalism. To what extent was this a

result of the prevalence of commodity relations? To answer this we shall

first of examine whether there was commodity production in the USSR and

then look at the question of the existence of commodity exchange.

To what extent did commodity-production exist in the USSR?

Under capitalism the worker, having sold his labour-power to the

capitalist, works for the capitalist. As such the worker does not work

for his own immediate needs but for a wage. The labour of the work is

therefore external to him. It is alienated labour.

However, unlike the serf, the servant or the domestic slave, the

wage-worker does not work for the immediate needs of the capitalist. The

capitalist appropriates the labour of the wage-worker to produce

something that can be sold at a profit. As such the prime concern of the

capitalist is to make his workers produce a mass of commodities that are

worth more than the labour-power and raw materials used up in their

production. Hence, for both the capitalist and the worker, the product

is a non-use-value — it is something that is produced for the use of

someone else.

A commodity can only be sold insofar as it is a use-value for some

others. Therefore the capitalist is only concerned with the use-value of

the commodity that he produces to the extent that is a necessary

precondition for its sale. For the capitalist then, use-value is merely

the material form within which the value the commodity is embodied.

This twofold nature of the commodity as both a use-value and a value is

the result of the twofold nature of commodity production. Commodity

production is both a labour process, which serves to produce use-values,

and a valorisation process that produces value of then commodity.

Through the concrete labour appropriated from the worker the raw

materials of production are worked up into the specific form of the

product that gives it a socially recognised use-value. Through this

concrete labour the value already embodied in the means of production is

preserved in the new product. At the same time value is added to the

product through the abstract labour of the worker.

In the USSR these relations of production were essentially the same. The

workers alienated their labour. As such they did not produce for their

own immediate needs but worked for the management of the state

enterprise. Equally, the management of the state enterprise no more

appropriated the labour from its workers for it own immediate needs any

more than the management of a capitalist enterprise in the West. The

labour appropriated from the workers was used to produce products that

were objects of use for others external to the producers.

Like in any capitalist enterprise, the management of the state

enterprises in the USSR, at least collectively, sought to make the

workers produce a mass of products that were worth more than the

labour-power and means of production used up in their production. As

such the labour process was both a process of exploitation and

alienation just as it was a two-old process of both abstract and

concrete labour that produced products with both a use-value and a value

i.e. as commodities.

Production in the USSR can therefore be seen as the capitalist

production of commodities. However, while production in the USSR can be

seen as a production for some alien other to what extent can it be

really be seen as a the production of things for sale? This brings us to

the crucial question of the existence of commodity exchange and

circulation in the USSR.

To what extent did commodity exchange exist in the USSR?

As we have seen, within the circuit of productive-capital, (P...P’),

exchange is primarily confined within the simple circulation of

commodities (C — M — C) necessary to bring about the renewal of

production on an expanded scale. Commodities are sold (C — M) by those

who produce them and are purchased (M — C) by those who need them for

the next cycle of production.

From the perspective of productive-capital commodity exchange is

therefore a mere technical means that allows for the expansion of

productive capital. A necessary means for overcoming the division of

producers that arises out of the social division of labour of commodity

production. However, the circulation of commodities is more than a mere

technical matter. The buying and selling of commodities is the alienated

social form through which human labour alienated from human needs is

reunited with human needs alienated from human labour.

Under the classical form of capitalism this social form is market

constituted through the collision of self-interested competing

individuals. As Marx argues:

Circulation as the realisation of exchange-value is implies: (1) that my

product is a product only in so far as it is for others; hence suspended

singularity, generality; (2) that it is a product for me only in so far

as it has been alienated, become for others; (3) that it is for the

other only in so far he himself alienates his product; which already

implies; (4) that production is not an end in itself for me, but a

means. Circulation is the movement in which the general alienation

appears as general appropriation and general appropriation appears as

general alienation. As much, then, as the whole of this movement appears

as a social process, and as much as individual moments of this movement

arise from the conscious will and particular purposes of individuals, so

much does the totality of the process appear as an objective

interrelation, which arises spontaneously from nature; arising, it is

true, from the mutual influence of conscious individuals on one another,

but neither located in their consciousness, nor subsumed under them as a

whole. Their collisions with one another produce an alien social power

standing above them, produce their mutual interaction as a process and

power independent of them.[111]

Through the alien power of the market alienated labour is brought into

conformity with alienated human needs. Products that do not meet needs

expressed through the market do not sell. Labour embodied in a commodity

that is excess of that which is socially necessary is not recognised. At

the same time, the imposition of the commodity form on human needs

serves to incorporate such needs into the accumulation of capital. New

needs that give rise to new forms of commodities expands the range of

material forms through which value can be embodied and expanded. To this

extent the market brings human needs into conformity with alienate

labour within the commodity form.

Yet while the alien power of the market arises out the conflicting

social and technical needs of the individuals that make up society the

alien power of the state does not. The state plan is necessarily imposed

from outside the social-economy. There was thus a fundamental problem

with reconciling social needs with alienated labour. This was reflected

in the relation of use-value and value and the form and functions of

money.

To what extent did Money exist in the USSR?

For Proudhon and his followers, the problems of capitalism arose from

the existence of money as an independent form of value. For them, it was

through the intermediation of money that capitalists were able to make

profits and extract interest. As a consequence, Proudhonists proposed

the direct expression of the value of commodities in terms of the labour

time required for their production. Money denominated in units of labour

time would simply act as a means of circulation that would in effect

allow for the direct exchange of commodities in accordance with the

labour expended in their production. Money would not be able to develop

into a social power independent of the direct producers. However,

through his critique of such Proudhonist proposals Marx showed that in a

society of independent commodity producers money must necessarily assume

an independent form of value distinct from all other commodities.

The labour embodied in a commodity is immediately private labour — or

more precisely it is asocial labour. It is only with the sale of the

commodity that this labour is recognised as being part of the total

abstract social labour of society as a whole. Hence the value of a

commodity is only realised or validated as such through the process of

exchange. In production the value remains potential value — a potential

based on previous cycles of production and exchange. When the commodity

reaches the market it has an ideal price based on its potential value

but this is not realised until the commodity is actually sold.

If too much of a particular commodity is produced in relation to social

demand or if the quality is defective than some commodities are not sold

or have to be sold at a discount. In cases such as these the actual

labour embodied in commodities is not realised as abstract social

labour. Indeed it is through this social mechanism that a commodity

economy is regulated. If production of private commodity producers is to

be brought into conformity with social demand than money can not be

simply the direct expression of the labour embodied in commodities. It

must exist as the independent form of value through which the labour

embodied in commodities is socially recognised and validated as abstract

social labour and hence as value.

As a consequence, Marx concluded that money as an independent form of

value could only be abolished if the economy of independent commodity

producers gave way to the planned production of freely associated

producers. In this way the regulation of production by the market would

be replaced by a social plan that would make labour immediately social.

As we have argued, the forced development of productive-capital in the

USSR required the suppression of the development of money-capital and

this involved the restriction of the development of money itself as an

independent form. To this end the regulation of production by the market

was replaced by economic planning. But this was not the planning of a

classes society of ‘freely associated producers’ but a plan developed

out of a society of atomised individuals based on class exploitation. As

such the alien power of the market that stands above society was

replaced by the alien power of the state. The imperatives of the state

plan confronted the producers as an external force just as the external

imperatives of the competitive market. The plan replaced the market as

the regulator of commodity production but as such it did not over come

the separation of labour from social needs that remained alienated from

each other.

Money in the USSR: In so far as simple commodity circulation existed as

a part of the circuit of productive capital in the USSR money entered as

merely a means of circulation facilitating the exchange of outputs of

the previous cycle of production for the inputs necessary for the next

cycle of production. But whereas under fully developed capitalism such

circulation could break down — a sale without a purchase or a purchase

without a sale — in the USSR this was precluded by the state plan.

The state imposed plan that allocated capital to each industry,

determined the output and set prices. To this extent the value of the

commodities produced by each capital were not validated or realised

through the act of their transformation into money but were

pre-validated by their recognition as values by the state. Hence

commodities had to be bought and money had to buy. The regulation of the

commodity producers by the law of value was replaced by the state plan.

Yet while the alien power of the market arises out the conflicting

social and technical needs of the individuals that make up society the

alien power of the state does not. The state plan is necessarily imposed

from outside the social-economy. There was thus a fundamental problem

with reconciling social needs with alienated labour. This was reflected

in the relation of use-value and value. This had important implications

for the form and functions of money as it existed within the circuit of

productive capital.

To consider this in a little more detail let us consider the two

transactions that make up the simple circulation of commodities —

firstly the sale of commodities produced by productive capital (C — M),

and then the purchase, (M — C), which ensures the continued reproduction

of productive capital. The commodities that have been produced by

productive capital enter the market with an expanded value and a given

specific use-value. The opposition of value and use-value within the

commodity finds it expression in the external relation of money and the

commodity. The commodity has a price, which is it express its value in a

certain sum of money, and is a certain kind of commodity defined by its

use-value. Thus money appears as the independent and external form of

the value of the commodity while the commodity itself stands as it own

use-value.

For example, let us take an enterprise producing tractors. At the end of

the production period the enterprise will have produced say 100 tractors

that are priced ÂŁ10,000 each. The hundred tractors express their value

as a price that is in the ideal form of a sum of money — £1million. This

ideal money -the price of the tractors — stand opposed to use-value

represented by the material form of the tractors themselves.

However, this ideal money, the price of the tractors which serves as the

external measure the value of the tractors must be realised. The

tractors must be sold. Given that the tractors can be sold then the

expanded value of the tractors will now be transformed into the form of

real money. The tractors will have been transformed into ÂŁ1million. As

such the abstract labour will find its most adequate and universal form

— money.

With money the enterprise can now buy commodities for the next period of

production. As the independent and universal form of value, money can

buy any other commodity, which is it is immediately exchangeable with

any other commodity. Yet our tractor firm only needs those specific

commodities necessary for the future production of tractors say 10 tons

of steel. Money need therefore only act as a mere means of circulation

that allows 100 tractors to be exchanged for 10 tons of steel.

In the USSR money was constrained to the functions necessary for the

phase of the simple circulation of commodities within the circuit of

productive capital — that is as an ideal measure of value and as a means

of circulation — and precluded money emerging fully as an independent

form of value. Firstly, as we have seen, the value of commodities was

prevalidated. The ideal price of the tractors was immediately realised

as the value of the tractors since the sale was already prescribed by

the plan. Thus while money acted as an ideal measure of the value of the

commodities for sale it had no independence.

Furthermore, the money received from the sale had to be spent on the

particular commodities necessary for the reproduction of that particular

circuit of productive capital. The ÂŁ1million brought by the sale of the

tractors had to be spent on the 10 tons of steel (or similar inputs). As

such money did not function as an independent and universal form of

value. It was tied to the specific circuit of productive capital (in our

case tractor production). It could not be withdrawn and then thrown into

another circuit. It merely served as a means of circulation that

facilitated the exchange of one specific set of commodities with another

set of commodities.

With the restriction of money to a mere fleeting means of circulation,

and with the pre-validation of the value of commodities, money could not

function as the independent form of value. The commodity did not express

its own value in the external form of money independent of itself but

rather its value was expressed in terms of the commodities use-value. As

a consequence the expansion of value did not find its most adequate

expression in the quantitative expansion of value in the purely

quantitative and universal form money but in the quantitative expansion

of value in the qualitative and particular forms use-values. Value and

use-value were compounded leading to the deformation of both value and

use-value.

Indeed, in the USSR accumulation of productive-capital, that is the

self-expansion of value, became immediately expressed in terms of the

quantities of use-values that were produced (100s of tractors, tons of

steel etc.). However, without the full development of money as money —

money as the independent form of value — the content of such use-values

did not necessarily conform to the needs of social reproduction. Money

had to buy; it had to allow the exchange of commodities. It could not

therefore refuse to buy sub-standard commodities. The quality of the

use-values of commodities was ensured, not by money and hence the

purchaser, but by the state plan. But the state plan, as we have argued,

stood in an external if not an antagonistic position with regard to the

various economic agents whether they were workers or state enterprises.

As a consequence, the use-values prescribed and ratified by the plan did

not necessarily conform to social needs.

The consequences of constrained money: As we have seen, the existence of

money as the independent and universal form of value ensures that

use-values conform to social needs. But furthermore, money as the

independent form of value is also a diffused form of social power.

However, as we have argued, in the USSR money was constrained to the

functions strictly necessary for the circuit of productive-capital and

social needs were prescribed by the state plan. This had two important

implications. The persistence of non-capitalist social forms such as

blat and endemic defective production.

Insofar as technical and social needs developed outside the framework

prescribed by the state plan they had to be articulated by something

other than by money. Money could only buy within the limit established

by the plan. The purchasing power of money was limited. While everyone

needed money, it was insufficient to meet all needs. As a consequence,

non-monetary social relations had to be persevered. Influence and

favours with those in authority, client relations’ etc. — that is the

system known as blat — became salient features of the Soviet bureaucracy

as means of gaining access to privileged goods or as a means of getting

things done.

As such blat emerged because of the restrictions placed on the functions

of money due to its subordination to productive capital. As such blat

was a distinctly non-capitalist — if not pre-capitalist — social form

that involved direct personal and unquantifiable relations between

people.[112]

However, as we noted the inadequacy of money in the USSR — it failure to

function as the universal and independent form of value — also led to

the endemic production of defective use-values which were to finally

bring the demise of the USSR. This, as we shall see, was directly

related to the class relations of production that arose from capitalist

form of commodity production in the USSR. But before we consider this

fatal contradiction of the USSR we must briefly consider the question of

wages and the sale of labour-power.

The sale of labour-power

The reproduction of labour-power is of course an essential condition for

the reproduction of capital. The reproduction of labour-power can be

described as a simple epi-cycle in the circuits of capital as follows:

Lp — W — Cs

The worker sells his labour-power (Lp) for a wage (W), which he then

uses to buy the commodities (Cs) necessary to reproduce himself as a

worker.[113] In essence this epi-cycle is the same as the simple

circulation of commodities.

However, as we have seen, one of the most telling criticisms advanced by

the Trotskyist critics of state capitalist theories of the USSR has been

the argument that workers in the USSR did not sell their labour-power.

Firstly, because if labour-power was to be considered a commodity then

it must be able to exchange with other commodities but, as we have seen,

Trotskyists denied that there were any other commodities in the USSR.

Secondly worker was not free to sell his labour-power.

However, as we have argued, there was commodity production in the USSR

and there was a restricted form of commodity circulation thus

labour-power could be exchanged with other commodities via the wage.

Nevertheless it is true that the freedom of workers to sell their labour

was restricted. Through various restrictions, such as the internal

passport system the movement of workers was restricted. To the extent

that these restrictions on the movement of labour tied workers to a

particular means of production then they can perhaps be considered more

industrial serfs than wage-slaves.

But on closer inspection these legal restrictions on the movement of

labour appear more as a response to exiting situation which were

honoured more in the breach than in their implementation. With the drive

to maximise production in accordance with the logic of the circuit of

productive-capital labour-power had to be fully used. Indeed, full

employment became an important element in the maintenance the political

and social cohesion of the USSR from Stalin onwards. However, the

maintenance of full employment led a chronic shortage of labour-power.

The fact that in reality workers were to a limited but crucial extent

free to sell their labour-power is shown in the strategy of the managers

of state enterprises to hoard labour. Indeed, the managers of state

enterprises actively colluded with workers to overcome the restrictions

to their mobility in their attempts secure sufficient labour-power to

meet their production targets. Hence the legal restrictions to the free

movement of labour-power were just that: attempts to restrict workers

who were essentially free to sell their labour-power.

Ticktin was well aware of the importance of the chronic shortage of

labour-power and consequence practice of labour hoarding by the state

enterprises. However, Ticktin persisted in denying that labour-power was

sold as a commodity in the USSR on the grounds that the wage was not

related to the labour performed. For Ticktin, although workers often

worked for piece rates which nominally tied their wages to amount they

worked, in reality workers were paid what amounted to a pension that

bore little relation to the amount of labour they performed.

As we argued in Part II, this argument overlooks the contradictory

aspects of labour-power and its expression in the form of a wage.

Labour-power is both a commodity and not a commodity. Although

labour-power is sold as if it was a commodity it is neither produced or

consumed as a commodity since it is not a thing separable from the

person who sells it — but the workers own living activity.

The worker does not produce labour-power as something to sell. On the

contrary he reproduces himself as a living subject of whom his living

activity is an essential an inseparable aspect. Equally, having bought

labour-power, capital can not use it in absence of the worker. The

worker remains in the labour process as an alien subject alongside his

alienated labour.

It is as a result of this contradictory nature of labour-power that the

wage-form emerges. In buying labour-power capital buys the worker’s

capacity to work. But capital has still to make the worker work both

through the sanction of unemployment and through the incentive of wages

linked to amount the worker works. However, while the wage may be linked

to the amount the labour the worker performs it is essentially the money

necessary for the average worker to buy those commodities necessary for

the reproduction of their labour-power. The extent to which the

capitalist can make individual workers work harder by linking the

payment of wages to the labour performed, rather than as a simple

payment for the reproduction of labour-power, depends on the relative

strengths of labour and capital.

Hence the fact that wages may have appeared like ‘pensions’ paid

regardless of the work performed, rather than as true wages that appear

as a payment tied to the work performed, does not mean that labour-power

was not sold in the USSR. All that it indicates is the particular power

of the working class in the USSR that, as we shall now see, was to have

important implications.

Contradictions in the USSR: the production of defective use-values

As we saw in Part II, Ticktin has ably described the distortions in the

political economy of the USSR. But rather than seeing such distortions

as arising from the degeneration of a society stuck in the transition

from capitalism to socialism they can be more adequately seen as

distortions arising from an attempt to make a forced transition to

capitalism from a position of relative underdevelopment. The drive to

towards the development of the productive-capital that led to the fusion

of the state and the replacement of the law of value by the law of

planning can be seen to have led to the gross distortions and

contradictions of the USSR.

Let us consider more explicitly the class basis of such distortions and

contradictions.

Firstly, with the suppression of money as an independent form of value

that could command any commodity the subjectively determined needs of

the workers could not be expressed through the money form. The needs of

the workers were instead to a large extent prescribed by the state. Thus

as the wage did not act as an adequate form that could provide an

incentive. After all why work harder if the extra money you may can not

be spent?

Secondly, as we have seen, the forced development of productive-capital

that precluded crisis led to the chronic shortage of labour. In

conditions of full employment where state enterprises were desperate for

labour-power to meet their production targets the sack was an

ineffective sanction.

As a consequence, as Ticktin points out, the management of the state

enterprises lacked both the carrot and sticks with which control their

workforce. Indeed the workers were able to exercise a considerable

degree of negative control over the labour process. Confronted by the

imperative to appropriate surplus-value in the form of increased

production imposed through the central plan on the one hand, and the

power of the workers over the labour-process on the other hand, the

management of the state enterprises resolved the dilemma by sacrificing

quality for quantity. This was possible because the technical and social

needs of embodied in the use-values of the commodities they produced

were not derived from those who were to use these commodities but were

prescribed independently by the central plan.

As a result, the quantitative accumulation of capital in the form of

use-values led to the defective production of use-values. As defective

use-values of one industry entered into the production of commodities of

another, defective production became endemic leading to the chronic

production of useless products.

Hence, whereas in a fully developed capitalism the class conflicts at

the point of production are resolved through the waste of recurrent

economic crises which restore the industrial reserve army and the power

of capital over labour, in the USSR these conflict were resolved through

the chronic and systematic waste of defective production.

Conclusion

As we pointed out in Part I, the Russian Revolution and the

establishment of the first ‘workers state’ has had a profound impact in

shaping our world. At first the apparent success of the Russian

Revolution showed that there was a realistic alternative to capitalism.

It showed that capitalism could be overthrown by the working classes and

that a socialist, if not communist, society could be constructed on its

ruins. As such it inspired generations of socialists and workers in

their conflicts with the capitalism system, defining both their aims and

methods.

However, as the true nature of the USSR began to emerge the perception

that it was ‘actually exiting socialism’ became an increasing barrier to

the development of an opposition to capitalism. If the socialist

alternative to capitalism was a totalitarian police state in which you

still had to work for a boss then most workers concluded that it might

be better to merely reform capitalism. At the same time the attempts of

the Stalinist Communist Parties across the world to subordinate the

worker class movements to the foreign policy needs of the USSR further

compounded this problem.

The struggle against both Stalinism and social democracy demanded an

understanding of the USSR. The question of what was the USSR therefore

became a central one throughout much of the twentieth century. It was a

question, which as we have seen, was bound up with the associated

questions of what is socialism and communism? What was the Russian

Revolution? And indeed what is the essential nature of Capitalism?

Although from a communist perspective that takes as its touchstone the

abolition of wage-labour as the defining feature of communism it would

seem intuitive that the USSR was a form of capitalism, we have seen that

the theories that the USSR was state capitalist have proved inadequate

compared with the more sophisticated theories that have developed out of

the Trotskyist tradition. To the extent that they have shared the

tradition Marxist conception of the Second and Third Internationals that

state capitalism is highest form of capitalism, state capitalist

theories of the USSR have proved unable to explain either the apparently

non-capitalist aspects of the USSR nor its decline and eventual

collapse.

Indeed, while the Trotskyist theory of the USSR as a degenerated

workers’ state has become untenable given the chronic economic

stagnation of USSR that became increasingly apparent after the 1960s,

and which culminated in the collapse of the USSR in 1990, it has been

Ticktin’s radical reconstruction of this theory that has so far provided

the most convincing understanding of the Soviet system and its decline

and fall.

However, as we showed in Part II, Ticktin’s theory still falls short of

the mark. Rather than seeing the USSR as being a social system stuck in

the transition between capitalism and socialism, we have taken up the

point of departure suggested by Bordiga to argue that the USSR was in

transition to capitalism.

We have argued that in order to break out of its backwardness and

subordinate position within the world division of labour the state

bureaucracy, which had formed after the Russian Revolution, sought to

make the transition to capitalism through the transitional form of state

capitalism. In its efforts to industrialise the Russian state sought the

forced development of productive-capital that required the suppression

of the more cosmopolitan and crisis ridden forms of money and commodity

capital. However, while such forced capitalist development allowed an

initial rapid industrialisation the distortions it produced within the

political economy of the USSR eventual became a barrier to the complete

transition to capitalism in Russia.

As such we have argued that the USSR was essentially based on capitalist

commodity-production. However as a consequence of the historical form of

forced transition to capitalism there was dislocation between the

capitalist nature of production and its appearance as a society based on

commodity-exchange. This dislocation led to the deformation of value and

the defective content of use-values that both provided the basis for the

persistence of the distinctly non-capitalist features of the USSR and

led to the ultimate decline and disintegration of the USSR.

As we saw in the last issue in relation to the war in Kosovo the

question of Russia remains an important one on the geo-political stage.

The economic and political problems of breaking up and reintegrating the

Eastern bloc in to the global structure of capitalism is one that has

yet to find a solution, and this is particularly true of Russia itself.

The forced development of productive-capital for over half a century has

left Russia with an economy based on huge monopolies unable to compete

on the world market. At the same time the insistence by the ideologists

of Western capitalism that all that Russia needed was deregulation and

liberalisation has simply given rise to the emergence of money-capital

in its most parasitical and predatory form. As a consequence, Russia

re-subordination to the dictates of the international law of value has

left it with one part of its economy reverting back to barter while the

other is dominated by a mafia-capitalism that is blocking any further

economic development. Hence, despite all the efforts of the USA and the

IMF Russia still remains mired in its transition to capitalism.

[1] For convenience we shall at times use the term ‘state capitalism’

for all theories that consider the Soviet Union to have been capitalist.

As N. Fernandez points out in a forthcoming book, Capitalism and Class

Struggle in the USSR, many theories, for example those of Bordiga and

more recently Chattopadhyay, have for good theoretical reasons avoided

the term ‘state capitalism’ in their accounts of the USSR. We will deal

with some of the issues raised by the term ‘state capitalism’ in more

detail in Aufheben 8.

[2] ‘Ultra-left’ is a loaded and ambiguous term. It was originally a

term of abuse used by Lenin against communists and revolutionaries,

particularly in West European countries such as Holland, Germany and

Italy, who refused to accept the Bolshevik model of revolution and the

right of the Russian Communist Party to determine the tactics and

leadership of the world Communist movement. These communists were among

the first to put forward the idea that Russia was a form of state

capitalism. We shall examine such theories in the next issue. On the

term itself it should be noted that most people accused of ultra-leftism

by Leninists would argue that they are simply communists and that the

left, including their accusers, are not. The matter is further confused

by the tendency of Leninists to denounce each other for ‘ultra-leftism’

for such heinous crimes as not voting Labour. Perhaps more importantly

for us, the term ‘ultra-leftism’ indicates an acceptance, along with

Trotskyism, of the idea of tracing one’s tradition back to the social

democracy of the Second and Third Internationals. While we will happily

restate our position that the German, Dutch and Italian left communists

did maintain some important lessons from the revolutionary wave

following the First World War, we do not think they had the last word on

what revolutionary theory and practice is for us today. This will become

clearer once we come to examine their theories of the Soviet Union.

[3] Of course, prisoner support work is an important part of any serious

movement against the state, and in the particular circumstances of the

anti-poll tax movement when Militant threatened to grass people to the

police it did define a radical engagement in the struggle. But there is

nothing inherent in leftism that leads it to ignore prisoners. Simply

criticising the ‘left’ for not supporting prisoners ends up as little

better than ritual denunciation of the left for being ‘boring middle

class wankers’, a poor excuse for a proper critique. Yet it is perhaps

little surprise that prisoner support has become an almost definitive

position amongst many anarchists now that denouncing the left for

supporting the USSR is no longer viable.

[4] There is little doubt that it was the fear that the whole of Western

Europe might go over to the Eastern Bloc in the years following the

Second World War which prompted the American bourgeoisie to pour

billions of dollars into shattered West European economies in the form

of Marshall Aid.

[5] It should be remembered that the reformist parties of the Second

International not only betrayed their commitment to opposing the First

World War and, as such, were complicit in the decimation of a whole

generation of the European working class, but they also played an

important role in crushing the revolutions that swept much of Europe

following the war. For example, it was under the orders of a Social

Democratic government that the German Revolution was crushed and such

revolutionary leaders as Rosa Luxemburg and Karl Liebknecht killed. Such

crimes could not be that easily forgotten.

[6] Of course, at this point some may object that Trotsky’s record

proves that he was a counter-revolutionary and, as a consequence,

dismiss any detailed consideration of his theory of the USSR as a

degenerated workers’ state. For us an extensive consideration of

Trotsky’s theory of the USSR as a degenerated workers’ state is

important not only because this theory has become a central reference

point for criticisms of the Soviet Union, but also because it is

important to show how Trotsky’s theory emerged directly from the

objectivism of orthodox Marxism and was in no way a betrayal of such

traditions. Hence our focus will remain on the political economy that

developed in the USSR, rather than offering a blow by blow account of

the revolution/ counter-revolution. For details on the 1917–21 period

that undermine the Leninist account of the Russian Revolution see M.

Brinton The Bolsheviks and Workers’ Control (London: Solidarity). For a

more general critique of the orthodox Marxism of both the Second and

Third Internationals see Guy Debord, The Society of the Spectacle,

Chapter IV (Detroit: Black and Red, 1974).

[7] Trotsky is himself not very clear at this point as to why the very

backwardness of peasantry would lead a substantial part of this class to

maintain its support for a workers’ government committed to introducing

socialist policies. However, this apparently paradoxical position can be

resolved if we consider a little more closely Trotsky’s view of the

peasantry. For Trotsky the backwardness and heterogeneity of the

peasantry meant that it was inherently incapable of developing a

coherent organization that could formulate and advance its own distinct

class interests. As a consequence the peasantry could only accept the

leadership of other classes i.e. either the bourgeoisie or the

proletariat. From this Trotsky could conclude that once the peasantry

had accepted the leadership of the proletariat it would have little

option but to be swept along by the policies of a workers’ government,

even beyond the point where such policies began to impinge on the

peasants’ own immediate class interests, since they would be unable to

formulate any viable alternative.

[8] See The Revolution Betrayed by Leon Trotsky (Pathfinder Press,

1972).

[9] We shall give more attention to the ideas Lenin’s left communist

opponents in Aufheben 8.

[10] Following Engels, it was generally accepted within orthodox Marxism

that there could be no leap from capitalism to a fully fledged communist

society in which the state, money and wage-labour had been abolished. It

was envisaged that any post-capitalist society would have to pass

through a lower stage of communism during which the state, money and

wage-labour would gradually whither away as the conditions for the

higher stage of communism came into being. This lower stage of communism

became known as socialism.

[11] For example, in his Leon Trotsky’s Theory of Revolution, John

Molyneux says ‘Suffice it to say that in the early years of the

revolution Trotsky stood on the authoritarian wing of the party’. Of

course, as Kowalski has pointed out, the divisions of left/right,

libertarian/ authoritarian may over simplify the complex of political

positions taken up among the Bolsheviks during this period. However, it

is quite clear that Trotsky was neither on the left nor the libertarian

wings of the Party at this time.

[12] As both Engels and Kautsky had pointed out in relation to Germany,

the fundamental barrier to the development of industrial capitalism was

the low productivity of traditional forms of small-scale peasant

agriculture. If the urban populations necessary for industrialization

were to be fed then the peasants had to produce an agricultural surplus

over and above their own immediate needs. So long as traditional forms

of agriculture persist the total amount of agricultural produce is

limited. Thus the only way to produce the surplus necessary for

industrialization is to depress the living standards of the peasantry

through such means as high rents and taxation. Yet the scope for

squeezing the peasants’ already impoverished living standards is

limited. Sooner or later there has to be an agricultural revolution

which, by concentrating production in large scale farms, allows the

introduction of modern mechanized production methods. Under capitalism

this occurred either through the landlords or the richer peasants

appropriating land and transforming themselves into capitalist farmers.

The socialist alternative was to collectivize agriculture. By grouping

peasants together in collectives large scale production would be made

possible without dispossessing vast numbers of poor peasants. In Russia

this agrarian problem was particularly acute. Before the revolution the

peasants had been forced to produce for the market in order to pay rents

and taxes to the landlords and the state. This surplus had then been

used both to feed the urban populations and for export to earn the

foreign currency needed to pay for the import of foreign capital

required for industrialization. However, with the Stolypin reforms of

1906, the Tsarist regime had made a decisive effort to encourage the

development of capitalist agriculture amongst the richer peasants. But

this ‘wager on the strong’ peasant was cancelled by the revolution. The

expropriation of the landlords and the redistribution served to

reinforce small-scale subsistence agriculture. With neither the

compulsion nor any incentive to produce a surplus on the part of the

peasant, food supplies to the urban areas fell. It had been this that

had compelled the Bolshevik Government to introduce direct

requisitioning under War Communism. With the NEP, the Bolshevik

Government now sought to provide incentives for the richer peasants to

produce for the market. Collectivization was ruled out since for it to

succeed on a large scale it required a sufficient level of

industrialization to allow the mechanization of agriculture. To this

extent the NEP represented, in part, a retreat to the Tsarist policy of

encouraging the growth of capitalist agriculture amongst the rich

peasants. We shall examine further this crucial agrarian question in

more detail in the next issue.

[13] Trotsky coined the phrase ‘scissors crisis’ in his speech to the

12^(th) Party Congress in April 1923. Trotsky argued that, left to the

market, the uneven development between agriculture and industry could

only lead to violent fluctuations between the prices of industrial goods

and agricultural prices which could only undermine the NEP. Although

agricultural production recovered rapidly after the introduction of the

NEP, industrial production lagged behind. As a result the price of

industrial goods had risen far faster than agricultural prices, ‘opening

the price scissors’ and threatening to undermine the incentives for the

peasants to produce for the market in the following season. By October

the predicted crisis struck home with the sales of grain plummeting.

Following this ‘scissors crisis’, measures were introduced to control

industrial prices.

[14] While Stalin had established his power-base as head of the

organization of the Party through out the USSR, Zinoviev had built his

power-base as head of the Party in Leningrad, and Kamenev had his

power-base as the head of the Moscow Party.

[15] During the industrialization debate in the mid 1920s, Trotsky,

along with the rest of the Left Opposition, was repeatedly attacked by

Stalin and his followers for being a ‘super-industrializer’ who wished

to abandon the NEP and industrialize at the expense of the peasantry.

This has been a common accusation made against Trotsky by Stalinists

ever since. But it has also been a criticism taken up by anarchists and

others to the left of Trotsky who argue that in adopting the policy of

forced industrialization and forced collectivization after 1928 Stalin

was simply implementing Trotsky’s own ideas. In this way the essential

complicity between Stalin and Trotsky can be demonstrated. In his

article ‘The Myth of the Super-Industrializer’, which was originally

published under a different title in Critique, 13, and now reprinted in

The Ideas of Leon Trotsky edited by Michael Cox and Hillel Ticktin,

Richard Day has sought to defend Trotsky from such accusations by both

distancing him from the more polemical positions of Preobrazhensky and

stressing his support for the workers’ and peasants’ alliance embodied

in the NEP. But this does not prove much. None of the main protagonists

in the industrialization debate, not even Preobrazhensky, argued for the

abandonment of the NEP and the workers’ and peasants’ alliance. What is

telling is Trotsky’s own criticisms of Stalin’s eventual policy of

forced industrialization and collectivization. In The Revolution

Betrayed, Trotsky does not criticize Stalin’s industrialization policy

as such — indeed he is careful to praise the great achievements made by

Stalin under this policy — but rather the ‘zig-zags’ made in bringing

this policy about. For Trotsky the problem was that Stalin’s reluctance

to adopt the policy of industrialization put forward by the Left

Opposition in the mid-1920s meant a sharper ‘turn to the left’ and a

more rushed and unbalanced industrialization later in order to solve the

crisis of 1928. But the crucial question is: if Stalin had shifted the

burden of industrialization onto the peasantry a few years earlier,

would this have been really sufficient to have averted the grain

procurement crisis in 1928 and avoided the disaster of forced

collectivization in which millions of peasants died?

[16] For a critique of orthodox Marxist interpretations of Marx’s theory

of commodity fetishism see ‘The Myth of Working Class Passivity’ by

David Gorman in Radical Chains, 2.

[17] It should be noted that What is to be Done? was a particularly

extreme formulation of democratic centralism that emerged out of a

polemic against those Marxists who had argued that the class

consciousness of the working class would necessarily develop out of

economic struggles during a period of retreat in the class struggle.

However, Lenin’s position concerning democratic centralism can be seen

to have undergone sharp shifts in emphasis depending on the political

circumstances. At various points before 1917 Lenin’s position would have

been little different from that of Trotsky.

[18] As well as Bolshevik left communists, many anarchists were also

taken in by the ‘libertarian flavour’ of the conception of

post-revolutionary power outlined in Lenin’s State and Revolution. This

led to accusations that Lenin’s actions after seizing power were a

betrayal of the ideas he had himself set out in State and Revolution,

and it is then suggested that Lenin had never really believed in them.

But while it is undoubtedly true that Lenin did abandon some of the

measures he called for in State and Revolution, that text was itself

ambiguous, calling for a ‘socialist revolution with subordination,

control, and foremen and accountants’.

[19] See for example ‘Can the Bolsheviks Retain State Power?’ in Lenin’s

Collected Works, vol. 26, p. 87.

[20] The methods of ‘scientific management’ advocated by Lenin were

based on those developed by the most advanced capitalist enterprises in

the West and which had become known as Taylorism. Taylorism had been

specifically developed to break the control of the skilled worker over

the immediate production process. Under Taylorism the production process

was re-organized and rationalized in a way which removed the initiative

of the individual worker and concentrated the overall knowledge and

control of how things were produced into the hands of specialized

managers. Lenin’s enthusiasm for Taylorism, an enthusiasm shared by

Trotsky, is perhaps one of the areas where Lenin most clearly

distinguishes his position from a communist one.

[21] It should be recognized that most of these armies did not seriously

fight the Bolsheviks. The civil war, as a war between organized armies,

was a battle between the Red Army and the Whites, who had material

support from the West. But, as well as this, vast numbers of peasants

and deserters fought both sides. Indeed, one could say the 1918–21

period was as much a peasant war as anything else.

[22] The introduction of one-man management and scientific management,

together with the consequent transfer of power away from the factory

committees to, first the trade unions and then to the Party, is well

documented in The Bolsheviks and Workers’ Control by M. Brinton. As

Brinton shows this process began at a very early stage in the

Revolution, well before the start of the civil war in the Summer of

1918.

[23] Given the task of organising the military defence of the revolution

Trotsky spent little time in abandoning the Red Guard militias that had

been formed immediately after the October Revolution in favour of

building a conventional standing army. At first Trotsky sought to

recruit from volunteers amongst the more advanced sections of the

working class, and in accordance with the procedures established within

the Red Guards, allowed officers to be elected directly from Soldiers’

committees and assemblies. However, once he had established a reliable

core for the new Red Army, Trotsky introduced conscription drawing

recruits from the broad masses of peasants and workers. With what he

considered as less reliable troops, Trotsky abandoned the direct

election of officers in favour of the appointment of professional

commanders which were mostly drawn from the former Tsarist army. To

oversee and check any counter-revolutionary tendencies amongst this

officer corp., Trotsky appointed political officers, or commissars,

drawn from the Party each of whom were attached to a particular military

commander.

[24] As Knei-Paz has pointed out, the idea that the emergence of the

bureaucracy represented a Russian Thermidor had been first advanced by

the Democratic-Centralist Opposition in the early 1920s. At that time,

when he still held a leading position within the Party, Trotsky had

firmly rejected the idea of a Russian Thermidor as being

‘ultra-leftist’. However, by 1929, facing disgrace and exile, Trotsky

began to come round to the idea and it was only by the mid-1930s that

came to fully formulate it within his criticisms of Stalinism. See B.

Knei-Paz, The Social and Political Thought of Leon Trotsky (Oxford:

Clarendon Press), pp. 394–5.

[25] Trotsky’s ‘orthodox Marxist’ and objectivist idea of history as

fundamentally about the progressive development of the productive forces

is perhaps the key to understanding the underlying weakness of his

theory of the degenerated workers’ state. For Trotsky’s lyrical accounts

of how Stalinist Russia developed the forces of production we need go no

further than the opening pages of The Revolution Betrayed. On page 8 of

this work Trotsky declares: ‘With the bourgeois economists we no longer

have anything to quarrel over. Socialism has demonstrated its right to

victory, not in the pages of Das Kapital, but in an industrial arena

comprising a sixth of the earth’s surface — not in the language of

dialectics, but in the language of steel, cement and electricity’.

[26] With the publication of Marx’s early writings, particularly the

Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, it is clear that for Marx the

basis of capitalism is not private property but alienated labour. This

point, as we shall see, is vital not only in making a critique of

orthodox Marxism but in any attempt to develop a materialist theory of

the USSR.

[27] Of course, at a more concrete level, it is clear that not all of

the capitalist class directly exploit the working class. Bankers and

merchant capitalists, for example, draw a share of the surplus-value

produced by the industrial capitalists by virtue of their special

functions in financing production, and by circulating the commodities

subsequently produced. Yet these functions can themselves be seen to be

rooted in private property. The bank advances money to finance

production as a loan of its own private property, and duly obtains a

share in the surplus-value in the form of interest. Likewise, by buying

the commodities produced by the industrial capitalist, the merchant

capitalists advance their own money-capital to realize the value

produced for the industrial capitalist ahead of the commodities’ actual

circulation. In doing so the merchant capitalists appropriate a slice of

the surplus-value expropriated by the industrial capitalists in the form

of the difference between what they pay the industrial capitalists and

what they sell the commodities for to the consumers.

[28] See The New Constitution of the USSR.

[29] As we have already noted, the notion that the concentration and

centralization of capital inevitably led towards the fusion of state and

capital had been central to the orthodox Marxism of the Second

International. It had followed from this that the decisive shift from

capitalism to socialism occurred with the working class seizing state

power. The main question that then divided orthodox Marxism was whether

this seizure of state power required a revolution or whether it could be

achieved through peaceful democratic means. In What is to be Done? Lenin

came to define his own position regarding the primacy of the political.

Against the ‘economism’ of those who saw socialist revolution arising

directly out the economic struggles of the working class, Lenin had

argued for importance of establishing a political party which could

seize state power. Of course, it was the basis of this ‘politicism’

which, by implying that the realm of the political can to some extent

determine the nature of society, has allowed Leninists to argue that the

USSR was a workers’ state while at the same time admitting that the

social relations of production may have remained capitalist. As we shall

see in the next issue, it was the inability of most left communists to

fully break from this ‘politicism’ that undermines their critique of the

Bolsheviks.

[30] It was this very transitional character of the Soviet bureaucracy

which meant that it was difficult to define what it was. So although

Trotsky settled on calling it a ‘caste’ he accepted this was an

unsatisfactory categorization of the Soviet bureaucracy.

[31] One of the first groups to develop a proper theory was the ‘state

capitalist’ minority within the Workers’ Party. This minority later

emerged as the Johnson-Forest Tendency after the pseudonyms of its main

theorists — C.L.R. James and Raya Dunayevskaya. With the collection of

previously unavailable writings we can now see that this theory is much

stronger than it appears from some of their earlier published works and

is far superior to Cliff’s version. See The Marxist-Humanist Theory of

State Capitalism, by R. Dunayevskaya, (Chicago: News & Letters, 1992).

Since the Johnson-Forest Tendency quickly broke from Trotskyism by

rejecting vanguardism and emphasizing workers’ autonomy we shall deal

with them in more detail in the next issue.

[32] See C. Hobson and R. Tabor, Trotskyism and the Dilemma of Socialism

(Westport: Greenwood, 1988).

[33] The Revolutionary Communist Party subsequently broke up and should

not be confused with the Revolutionary Communist Party that is around

today.

[34] Though this has not stopped the SWP giving ‘critical support’ to

some nationalist and Stalinist movements in ‘non-imperialist’ parts of

the world.

[35] For a critique of Cliff’s theory of state capitalism from a

Trotskyist point of view see the collection of articles on the nature of

the USSR in Open Polemic, 4 & 5.

[36] That is the reformism that had been put forward by Bernstein and

his followers in the debates in the Second International that there

could be a peaceful transition to socialism through democratically won

reforms.

[37] Cliff was able to cite Trotsky’s reaction to Stalin’s constitution

where he argued that it was the basis for the restoration of capitalism

in the USSR as support for the possibility of peaceful

counter-revolution.

[38] While most Trotskyists in the 1940s clung on to the belief that the

immediate post-war economic boom would be short lived and as a

consequence repeatedly predicted an imminent return to an economic

slump, Cliff was one of the first to seek to explain the persistence of

the post-war economic boom. Central to this explanation was Cliff’s

theory of ‘a permanent arms economy’ in which high levels of military

spending acted to defer the full effects of the overaccumulation of

capital which had led to the great slump of the 1930s. The notion that

the permanent arms economy was mirrored in the Soviet Union fitted

neatly into Cliff’s overall emphasis on the importance of military

accumulation for modern capitalism.

[39] Loren Goldner, Communism is the Material Human Community

(Collective Action Notes, POB 22962, Balto., MD 21203, USA.). Also

published as ‘Amadeo Bordiga, the Agrarian Question and the

International Revolutionary Movement’, in Critique, 23, 1991.

[40] Jacques Camatte, Community and Communism in Russia.

[41] This influence is not confined to the Leninist left. The recent

book from Neil Fernandez — Capitalism and Class Struggle in the USSR —

while opposed to Ticktin’s Leninism acknowledges his work as a ‘major

theoretical achievement’ in terms of grasping the forms taken by the

class struggle in the Soviet Union. The journal Radical Chains has

attempted to develop revolutionary critique by combining some of

Ticktin’s ideas with others from the autonomist and left communist

traditions.

[42] With the growing crisis in the USSR in the 1980s, there were

several attempts by leading theoreticians within the Socialist Workers

Party to revise Cliff’s theory of state capitalism to overcome its

inherent weaknesses.

[43] The collapse of the USSR has forced a major rethink amongst both

Trotskyists and Stalinists. One of the first attempts to draw together

the various positions on the USSR was made in Open Polemic, 4 & 5.

[44] In fact, Ticktin’s theory has assumed a strong role among the

remnants of the British far left that goes beyond just Trotskyism. The

ideological crisis that has accompanied the collapse of the USSR has led

the smaller groups to some fairly serious rethinking. Ticktin’s theory

seems to offer the best hope of keeping their Leninist assumptions while

fundamentally disentangling themselves from what has happened in Russia.

Showing some of the strange realignments that have followed the collapse

of the USSR, a Ticktinite analysis of the USSR seems now to be the

dominant position within the ex-Stalinist group previously known as the

Leninist. Having reclaimed the CPGB title abandoned by the old

Euro-Stalinists (now New Labourites), this group seems to be attracting

quite a few homeless leftists to a project based on going back to the

1920 formation of the original CPGB before the split of Trotskyism and

Stalinism. However, we’d suggest that, for Leninists, now that the USSR

has collapsed, overcoming the division of Stalinism and Trotskyism is

not too hard; understanding much less crossing the gap between Leninism

and communism is a more difficult task.

[45] For a discussion of the different ways Trotskyism and left

communism interpreted the meaning of these slogans, see our article

‘Decadence: The Theory of Decline or the Decline of Theory? Part I’ in

Aufheben 2 (Summer 1993).

[46] See, again, our article ‘Decadence’ in Aufheben 2.

[47] See ‘The Leopard in the 20^(th) Century: Value, Struggle and

Administration’ in Radical Chains, 4.

[48] The notion of centrism had originally been applied to those within

the Second International who sought to combine a commitment to

proletarian revolution with a reformist practice — a position best

exemplified by Karl Kautsky.

[49] In Marx’s Capital the question of class is not presented until the

very end of Volume III.

[50] For a critique of this identification of communism with ‘a law of

planning’, or indeed even with planning per se, see ‘Decadence Part III’

in Aufheben 4 (Summer 1995).

[51] Tony Cliff Puts Forward a Similar Position That in the USSR the

Workers Did Not Really Sell Their Labour-Power.

[52] Under capitalism, the individual worker can earn more by working

harder or longer than the average or norm. However, if the individual

worker’s colleagues follow suit, the average or norm of working will be

increased and the individual worker will soon find his wages revised

down to the value of his labour-power.

[53] Focusing on commodity fetishism helps one avoid the mistake of

seeing ideology as predominantly a creation of state and other

ideological apparatuses or institutions. To make people work for it,

capital neither has to rely on direct force nor on somehow inserting the

idea that they should work into people’s heads. Their needs, plus their

separation from the means of production and each other, makes working

for capital a necessity for proletarians. Commodity fetishism in one

sense, then, is not in itself an ideology but an inseparable part of the

social reality of a value- and commodity-producing society: “to the

producers, therefore, the social relations between their private labours

appear as what they are, i.e., they do not appear as direct social

relations between persons in their work, but rather as material

[dinglich] relations between persons and social relations between

things” (Capital, vol. 1, Chapter 1, Section 4). On the other hand,

people generate ideology to make sense of their alienated practice; to

the extent that most people’s existence most of the time is within

capitalist relations, they generate and adopt ideas to rationalize and

make sense of this existence. Because that reality is itself

contradictory, their ideas can both be incoherent and quite functional

for them. The point here, though, is that no ‘battle of ideas’ will

disabuse them of such ideas which are expressive of their reality. Only

in relation to practical struggle, when the reified appearance of

capitalist relations is exposed as vulnerable to human interference, are

most people likely to adopt revolutionary ideas. On the other hand,

leftist intellectuals attempt to be both coherent and critical of this

society. It is in relation to such ‘critical ideas’ that, following Marx

and the Situationists, we oppose revolutionary theory to revolutionary

ideology.

[54] There is a key passage in Marx’s Capital that would seem at first

to support Ticktin’s argument that the lack of normal market relations

in the USSR meant that it did not generate the powerful ‘dull compulsion

of everyday life’ that the worker experiences in the West:

"the advance of capitalist production develops a working class which by

education, tradition and habit looks upon the requirements of that mode

of production as self-evident natural laws. The organization of the

capitalist process of production, once it is fully developed, breaks

down all resistance. The constant generation of a relative surplus

population keeps the law of the supply and demand of labour, and

therefore wages, within narrow limits which correspond to capital’s

valorization requirements. The silent compulsion of economic relations

sets the seal on the domination of the capitalist over the worker.

Direct extra-economic force is still of course used, but only in

exceptional cases. In the ordinary run of things, the worker can be left

to the “natural laws of production”, i.e. it is possible to rely on his

dependence on capital, which springs from the conditions of production

themselves and is guaranteed in perpetuity by them." (Capital, vol. 1,

Chapter 28).

But the lines that immediately follow suggest a quite different way of

grasping the Russian situation:

"It is otherwise during the historical genesis of capitalist production.

The rising bourgeoisie needs the power of the state, and uses it to

“regulate” wages, i.e. to force them into the limits suitable for making

a profit, to lengthen the working day, and to keep the worker himself at

his normal level of dependence. This is an essential aspect of so-called

primitive accumulation."

A lot of the strange features of the USSR vis-a-vis ‘normal’ capitalism

become clear when one sees it as attempting to make the transition

towards capitalism.

[55] The observation that there was a fundamental contradiction between

the reality of the Soviet regime and what it said about itself is hardly

new. The original title of The Russian Enigma by Anton Ciliga, which

brilliantly combines an account of his personal experiences of the

Stalinist regime and its camps with his reflections on the nature of its

economic system, was Au Pays du Grand Mensonge: ‘In the Country of the

Big Lie’.

[56] It is interesting to contrast the views of Ticktin with Debord on

the Soviet lie.

Ticktin argues that, unlike the false consciousness of the Western

bourgeoisie, the set of doctrines promoted by the Soviet elite doesn’t

even partially correspond to reality and thus the system has no

ideology. Ticktin’s motivation to deny that these falsehoods are an

ideology is theoretical: ‘Systematic, conscious untruthfulness is a

symptom of a system that is inherently unstable’ (Origins of the Crisis

in the USSR, p. 18). His view that it is not a viable system leads him

polemically to assert that it has no ideology; for something that is not

a mode of production does not generate a coherent false consciousness.

Debord (Society of the Spectacle, Theses 102–111) similarly describes

Soviet society as based on a lie that no one believes and which has thus

to be enforced by the police. He also points at the way that its

reliance on falsification of the past and present means that it suffers

“the loss of the rational reference which is indispensable to the

historical society, capitalism”, making it a poor imitation of the West

in terms of industrial production (108). However Debord does not feel

the need to say that, because it has become manifestly incoherent,

Stalinist ideology is no longer ideology; rather, it is for him an

extreme victory of ideology.

While it has a theoretical consistency, Ticktin’s polemical insistence

that there was no ideology in the USSR imposes a very restricted sense

on the notion of ideology. Essentially it limits the meaning of ideology

to that false consciousness generated by a mode of production which

partially grasps the reality of the world which that mode produces and

which is thus functional to those identifying with that world. However,

ideology can also infect the thought of those who see themselves as

critical of and wishing to go beyond that mode of production. For

example, the Marxism of the Second International, of which Leninism is

essentially a variant, absorbed bourgeois conceptions of the relation of

knowledge to practice, of the need for representation and hierarchical

organization and of progress, which made it into a revolutionary

ideology. Ticktin’s limited conception of ideology allows him to escape

the questions of the relation of the Soviet Union’s ideology of

‘Marxism-Leninism’ to its origins in Leninism, and the ideological

assumptions Trotskyism shares with Stalinism. Debord however, grasps the

totalitarian falsehood of Soviet ideology as a dialectical development

of the revolutionary ideology of Leninism. As he puts it: “As the

coherence of the separate, the revolutionary ideology, of which Leninism

was the highest voluntaristic expression, governed the management of a

reality that was resistant to it; with Stalinism, this ideology

rediscovered its own incoherent essence. Ideology was no longer a weapon

but an end in itself. But a lie which can no longer be challenged

becomes a form of madness” (105).

[57] On the basis of this dilemma for the Russian elite, Ticktin is able

to provide a persuasive account of the post-war history of the USSR

which in many respects is far superior to most attempts by state

capitalist theorists to explain the crisis of the Soviet Union.

[58] See Part VI of Volume I of Capital.

[59] We shall take this point up in far more detail in ‘What was the

USSR? Part IV’.

[60] Again, see ‘Decadence Part III’ in Aufheben 4 (Summer 1995).

[61] The German and Dutch Communist Lefts were theoretically and

practically intertwined. Two of the most prominent theorists of the

German Communist Workers Party — Pannekoek and Gorter — were Dutch.

Exiled German Left activists often took refuge in Holland. In what

follows we will generally use the term’ German Left to indicate the

whole political current.

[62] ‘Trotsky’s theory of the Soviet Union as a degenerated workers

state’,and ‘The theory of state capitalism from within Trotskyism’ in

Aufheben 6,1997,and ‘Russia as a non mode of Production’ in Aufheben

7,1998.

[63] Surprisingly perhaps the most interesting and dynamic appropriation

of the Communist Left has not been made in Germany or Italy but in

France. After ’68 in particular a modem ‘ultra left’ tradition has

emerged there in a way unlike other countries. Within this a different

less ‘partyist’ appropriation of the Communist left has been made. The

recently republished Eclipse and Re-Emergence of the Communist Movement

(Dauve & Martin, Antagonism Press) is an example of this.

[64] A main way the Communist left is known in Britain is through the

publications and activities of groups emerging in the early seventies,

which claimed to defend the positions of the Communist Left. These

groups on the surface appear to the uninitiated as Party oriented groups

not so different from some of the smaller Trotskyist sects. In most

other countries where it has a presence the Communist left has a similar

type of existence

[65] The history and positions of Communist lefts that developed in some

countries have been effectively destroyed, e.g. those of the Bulgarian

left. The British communist left was represented by Sylvia Pankhursts

group around the Workers Dreadnought (previously the Woman’s

Dreadnought) and the Spur group in Glasgow of whom Guy Aldred was the

leading spokesman. They largely following the German left on the Russian

question so we will not treat them here.There is a good account of them

in Mark Shipway’s Anti- Parliamentary Communism: The Movement for

Workers Councils in Britain, 1917–45 (Macmillan, 1988)

[66] In Leninist mythology the clear sighted Lenin split with the

Russian Social Democratic Party on the question of organisation and by

so doing created a line of revolutionary Marxism that foresaw and would

be immune to the betrayal of revolution that both the Mensheviks and

European social democrats would fall prey to. However, as both Debord

and Dauve, has pointed out, Lenin was always a loyal Kautskyist — even

when he accused his master of betrayal.

[67] Lenin’s clear line on this led to an alliance of the Bolsheviks

with European left communist — the Zimmerwald left — this broke down

because of Lenin’s refusal to work with those who rejected the right

[68] Bukharin is better known for the right wing positions he took in

the twenties. Up to ’21 he was however a leading figure of the left of

the party, in many ways closer to European Left communists than to

Lenin’s very Russian perspectives.

[69] Lenin particularly scorned the position that Pyatakov painted of

revolution: “We picture this process [the social revolution] as the

united action of the proletarians of all [!] countries, who wipe out the

frontiers of the bourgeois [!] state, who tear down the frontier posts

[in addition to ‘wiping out the frontiers’?], who blow up [!] national

unity and establish class unity.” {Lenin’s ‘comments’ } To which Lenin

replies ‘The social revolution cannot be the united action of the

proletarians of all countries for the simple reason that most of the

countries and the majorities of the world’s population have not even

reached, or have only just reached, the capitalist stage of

development... Only the advanced countries of Western Europe and North

America have matured for socialism. The social revolution can come only

in the form of an epoch in which are combined civil war by the

proletariat in the advanced countries and a whole series of democratic

and revolutionary movements... in the undeveloped, backward and

oppressed nations. “Lenin ‘The nascent trend of Imperialist Economism

October 1916 p 50–52

[70] The Left Communists reason for changing their position from one of

proposing revolutionary war to that of defensive revolutionary partisan

war, in fact resides in the openness for Lenin’s arguments, when he

pointed out that it would be a rather unrealistic to go for

revolutionary in the face of massive war weariness and peasant desertion

of the front this was a quite unrealistic position.

[71] Speech 28/7/18: CW vol.28, p29.

[72] 60 million people, half the industrial firms, three quarters of the

steel mills and nearly all the coal mines were in this area.

[73] Theses on the Current Situation (1918), Critique, Glasgow,1977.

Also in Daniels Documentary History of Communism. References are to

these numbers.

[74] ‘On the Building of Socialism’ Kommunist no2,April 1918,in Daniels

p 85.

[75] Trotsky’s support for militarisation of labour is a classic

example. See Terrorism and Communism.

[76] “The Tax in Kind (NEP)’ CW 32 pp.329–369 here he analyses relation

of petty producer capitalism to state capitalism in 1921. This text will

be key to Bordiga’s understanding of the USSR

[77] In fact at some of the worst times in the civil war the Bolsheviks

gave other socialists and anarchists more freedom. The changing relation

to Makhno’s partisans being a case in point. See Ciliga in his The

Russian Enigma p251

[78] Appeal of the workers truth Group in Daniels Documentary History of

Communism p 221

[79] Luxemburg referring to the German SDP says ‘the troops of the old

order, instead of intervening in the name of the ruling classes,

intervene under the banner of a ‘social-democratic party.”’ The workers

group were making the obvious and necessary extension of this critique

of the SDP to the more radical Social Democracy that the Bolsheviks were

turning out to represent.

[80] As they so eloquently put it: ‘why does Zinoviev offer Scheidman

and Noske [social democrats responsible for defeating the German

revolution] a ministerial seat instead of a gibbet.’

[81] Between 1890 and 1899, 450,000 were involved in strikes and

lockouts; between 1900–04,475,000. In 1905 alone, 500,000.

[82] In 8/10/21

[83] In Workers Dreadnought Feb 24

[84] From the Bourgeois to the Proletarian Revolution,p 7

[85] This text was written by the GIK in 1934 and published in English

by the APCF as the The Bourgeois Role of Bolshevism.References are to

these numbers.

[86] Fundamental principles of Communist Production and Distribution

[87] Pannekoek’s Workers Councils

[88] See Anti-Bolshevik Communism and Marxism: Last Refuge of the

Bourgeoisie

[89] When a fusion was eventually forced through the PSI demoralized by

fascism only comprised 2000 members confirming the Italian left argument

that it was an exhausted tradition

[90] Bordiga,either imprisoned or under surveillance by the fascist

police,withdrew from politics at this time. The Banner of the Italian

Left was upheld by the fraction in exile in Belgium and France

[91] Quoted in Camatte’s Community and Communism in Russia,p 9–10

[92] See Fundamentals of Communist Production and Distribution (Apple &

Mejer, 1990, Movement for Workers’ Councils).

[93] See Dauve ‘Leninism and the Ultra Left’ (Eclipse and Re-Emergence

of the Communist Movement. Op. Cit.)

[94] One is not saying that communism can exist in one country or area

before world revolution has generalised but that we can only say that

revolution has triumphed there if a process of suppression of capitalist

relations has begun.

[95] Camatte has attempted to synthesise the positive sides of both

theories. By engaging in a detailed study of what Marx meant by the

party’, he argued that this should not be identified with the

traditional formal party associated with Leninism and social democracy.

The ‘party’ was in no way something external to the working class

introducing it to a communist consciousness and organisation it was

incapable of generating by itself. Rather, the ‘party’ should be

understood as an expression of the class, its production of a communist

consciousness of those people who identified with and tried to act for

communism. Rather than in the Leninist vision where spontaneity and

organisation/consciousness are rigidly opposed Camatte returned to

Marx’s understanding that the party is something spontaneously generated

out of the class. It was by relativising this Leninist notion of the

party-form that Camatte could return to the notions of working class

subjectivity of the German Left, whilst as the same time adopting the

more holistic standpoint of the Italian Left. That is, he managed to

overcome the dichotomy between the economic and the political, which had

not only led to their mutual incomprehension, but more importantly in

this context, to very different perception of the nature of Russia. It

is by taking away the foundations on which the German and Italian Left

based their theories of Russia, that Camatte’s discussion of the

party-form did have an indirect relevance for left communist theories of

the Russian Revolution. (Camatte 1961 The Origin and Function of the

Party Form).

[96] Our introduction to the second article in Aufheben 7 was a response

to the second group.

[97] The ICC for example, complained that in out treatment of the

Italian Left we fail to mention the contribution of the particular

branch with which they identify, namely the Left Communists of France

who refused to join the International Communist Party formed by

‘Bordigists’ in Italy in 1943. As it happens we have read the article

they refer to — ‘The Russian Experience: Private Property and Collective

Property’ (in Internationlisme, 10, 1946, reprinted in International

Review, 61, 1990) and do consider it quite good. Its insight that the

form of ownership may change, but the content — past labour dominating

living labour — remains is a basic one shared with many other theories

of state capitalism. But it is only a starting point. Unfortunately we

see no sign that the ICC has managed to advance from this sound

beginning. In a way the article in question points back to the

theoretical rigour and openness of Bilan (Italian Left group in the

‘30s) rather than forwards towards the present sclerotic organisation

which claims this heritage.

[98] Capitalism and Class Struggle in the USSR: A Marxist Theory by Neal

Fernandez (Aldershot: Ashgate, 1997). We have found this book useful for

its comprehensive overview of the debate; its treatment of the strengths

and weaknesses of the different theories; and its identification of the

key problems that must be faced by a theory of the USSR grounded in

Marx’s critique of political economy. When it comes to the author’s own

‘new theory of bureaucratic capitalism’, however, we are not convinced —

we touch on this in footnote 16 below.

[99] Indeed, when the foremost council-communist theorist, Paul Mattick,

looked at the issue of value, his traditional Marxist assumptions along

with his theoretical integrity led him actually to undermine the German

Left’s theory of state capitalism by accepting that value did not really

exist in the USSR.

[100] One state capitalist theory that accepted that ‘profit’ as it

appeared on the surface of Soviet society was not profit in a Marxian

sense was that developed by Raya Dunayevskaya. In pioneering work in the

late 1930s early ‘40s, she undertook a functional analysis of the cycle

of capital accumulation as it actually took place in the USSR. She saw

that the role of the ‘turnover tax’ on consumer goods gave an entirely

‘fictitious profit’ to light industries, but this was “merely the medium

through which the state, not the industry siphons off anything ‘extra’

it gave the worker by means of wages.” And this is “why this ‘profit’

attracts neither capital nor the individual agents of capital.” However,

as she points out, even in classical capitalism, “the individual agent

of capital has at no time realised directly the surplus value extracted

in his particular factory. He has participated in the distribution of

national surplus value, to the extent that his individual capital was

able to exert pressure on this aggregate capital. This pressure in

Russia is exerted, not through competition, but state planning.”

(Dunayevskaya, ‘The Nature of the Russian Economy’ in The

Marxist-Humanist Theory of State-Capitalism (Chicago: News & Letters,

1992)). However, despite this recognition that in terms of ‘profit’ one

had to see through the discourse of the Russian economists to the

reality, she took their admission in 1943 that the ‘law of value’ did

operate in the USSR at face value as, for her, an admission that it was

state capitalist. She thus saw no reason to take theoretical analysis of

the situation any further.

[101] Of course, the USSR was having a different kind of crisis based on

difficulties, in the absence of unemployment, in imposing

labour-discipline which led to more and more use of terror against both

the working class and even managers. See the Ticktin-influenced history

of this period by D. Filtzer, Soviet Workers and Stalinist

Industrialisation: The Formation of the Modern System of Soviet

Production Relations 1928–1941 (London: Pluto, 1986).

[102] At the height of tripartite corporatism in the 1960s attempts were

made by governments in Western Europe to co-ordinate investment plans of

the major companies that dominated the national economy along with state

investments and wage demands in order to maximise capital accumulation,

This was known as indicative planning.

[103] One possible exception is Chattopadhyay’s The Marxian Concept of

Capital and the Soviet Experience (Westport CT: Praeger, 1994). In his

analysis the specific capitalist development in the USSR (which he does

not label state capitalist) was unable to effectively make the shift

from extensive accumulation based on absolute surplus value to intensive

accumulation based on relative surplus value and the real subordination

of labour. To expand, it thus relied on drawing ever more workers and

raw materials into production on the existing basis; it could not make

the shift to the constant revolutionising of the relations and forces of

production that intensive accumulation demanded.

[104] An important issue for previous theories has been whether the USSR

should be seen as ‘state capitalist’ or, as with Bordiga for example,

simply as ‘capitalist’. We shall argue below for a reconsideration of

the meaning of ‘state capitalism’ that makes this issue redundant.

[105] In the case of the NICs, this success has been relative. As

recently seen with the Asian crisis, their development is still

subsidiary to that of the more advanced capitalist countries.

[106] Penguin edition, p. 84.

[107] Geoffrey Kay, Development and Underdevelopment: A Marxist Analysis

(London: Macmillan, 1975), p. 99.

[108]

G. Kay, op. cit., p. 100.

[109]

G. Kay, op. cit., p. 103.

[110] One of the most striking features of capitalist society is the

prevalence of atomization. Of course this atomization of society arises

directly from the predominance of the commodity-form and the reification

of social relations that this gives rise to. As Ticktin notes, such

atomization was characteristic of the USSR. However, because he denies

the existence of the commodity-form in the USSR Ticktin has to go

through all sorts of contortions to explain it.

[111] Grundrisse, pp. 196–197, Penguin edition.

[112] For this reason we cannot agree with Neal Fernandez’s assertion

that ‘blat’ was itself a form of capitalist money. While an individual

could be said to have ‘more’ or ‘less’ ‘blat’, it is not quantifiable

and calculable in the discrete units necessary for it to play the role

of money. Other attributes it lacks include universality and

transferability. ‘Blat’ cannot play the impersonal dominating role which

money as a ‘real abstraction’ is able to do. However, Fernandez has

drawn attention to the role of this phenomenon, which expressed the

constrained role of money in the USSR, part of the deformation of value.

Blat played the role it did because proper money did not fully function.

[113] Of course, such reproduction may involve other social relations

like those around gender, age and so on.