đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș the-age-old-question.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:14:51. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Age-Old Question Author: Eric Fleischmann Date: May 17th, 2022 Language: en Topics: anarcho-capitalism, conservatism, libertarianism, left-libertarianism, anarchism, Benjamin Tucker, liberalism, C4SS Source: Retrieved on 5/17/22 from https://c4ss.org/content/56712.
Is anarcho-capitalism a form of anarchism? The resounding cry from
anarchists of all stripesâincluding myselfâis NO! The debate rages on,
but two questions are raised by this claim: why isnât it anarchism and
if it isnât anarchism then what is it? I believe the answers are:
because it fails to meet the deeper commitments of anarchism and is
actually a form of radical libertarianism. And this brings up the
further question: what then is the relationship between libertarianism
and anarchism? I will attempt to substantially elaborate on the former
response in order to lead to an open ended exploration of the latter.
First though, it bears mentioning that, for much of the world,
libertarian and anarchist are used more or less interchangeably.
âLibertarianâ was first used in a political sense by anarcho-communist
Joseph DĂ©jacque and remains in use as an inherently leftist idea in much
of the world outside of the United States. However, in 1955, Dean
Russell proposed that classical liberals abandon the public title of
liberal and advanced that âthose of us who love liberty trade-mark and
reserve for our own . . . the good and honorable word âlibertarian.ââ So
libertarian in its common usage in the U.S. really just means, at least
at its core, liberal. And the meaning of liberalism can be found in its
etymological root, with Bettina Bien Greaves writing in the preface to
Ludwig von Misesâs Liberalism: In The Classical Tradition that â[t]he
term âliberalism,â from the Latin âliberâ meaning âfreeâ referred
originally to the philosophy of freedomâ and summing up its real-world
applications as represented by âthe free market economy, limited
government and individual freedom.â Essentially: liberalism takes the
form of a belief in the essential liberty of the individual, the
real-world practice of which is the greatest possible minimization of
the state and the greatest possible maximization of the market. These
are therefore the basics of libertarianism.
Of course, liberalism now dominates the world in its corrupted,
hegemonic form of neoliberalism, but at its inception, as Kevin Carson
writes, â[t]he liberalism of Adam Smith, David Ricardo and the other
classical political economists was very much a left-wing assault on the
entrenched economic privilege of the great Whig landed oligarchy and the
mercantilism of the moneyed classesâ before primarily taking âon the
character of an apologetic doctrine in defense of the entrenched
interests of industrial capital.â[1] So while libertarianism has a
common origin with neoliberalism, it is certainly not the status quo and
can therefore be identified as this original radical essence of
liberalism brought to bear in the 20th and 21st century. Admittedly,
this is giving a lot more credit than is due to vulgar libertarians who,
as Carson accounts, âuse the term âfree marketâ in an equivocal sense,â
seeming âto have trouble remembering, from one moment to the next,
whether theyâre defending actually existing capitalism or free market
principlesâ and consequently become apologists for the status quo and
ruling elite, but Jason Lee Byas argues that libertarianismâdespite its
misusesâis still fundamentally a radical form of liberalism and further
that â[t]o say that libertarians are radical liberals is to say more
than just that we are more extreme.â It means âtaking an idea to its
roots, and applying that idea consistently.â Radical liberalism leads to
the conclusion that âalthough our interests are naturally aligned, they
are wildly at odds in the world around us. This unnatural disharmony
comes from the imposition of power and the way aggression feeds upon
aggressionâ and that though â[t]here is little adrenaline behind the
legislatorâs vote, the bureaucratâs checklist, or the policemanâs casual
stroll, . . . they are acts of war all the same. Throughout that
monotonous charge, the unknowing infantryâs supreme objective is always
the protection of political authority.â In turn, radical
libertarianismâradical radical liberalismâtakes these observations
regarding power and violence and the aforementioned aspects of
individual freedom, limited government, and the free-market economy to
the conclusion of absolute individual sovereignty, zero government, and
everything being provided by a market. This is the vision of
anarcho-capitalism as described by thinkers like Murray Rothbard and
David Friedman, and it may sound like anarchism in the colloquial sense,
but the abolition of the state and voluntary association of a genuinely
free market is not enough to qualify as anarchism.
This may seem like an odd statement to make, as many definitions of
anarchism center on free association and zero government. Emma Goldman
explains anarchism from an anti-government standpoint as being â[t]he
philosophy of a new social order based on liberty unrestricted by
man-made law; the theory that all forms of government rest on violence,
and are therefore wrong and harmful, as well as unnecessary.â David
Graeber, from a âvoluntary orderâ perspective, concludes that â[t]he
easiest way to explain anarchism . . . is to say that it is a political
movement that aims to bring about a genuinely free society â and that
defines a âfree societyâ as one where humans only enter those kinds of
relations with one another that would not have to be enforced by the
constant threat of violence.â And Pyotr Kropotkin combines both types of
views in the definition of anarchism as âthe name given to a principle
or theory of life and conduct under which society is conceived without
government â harmony in such a society being obtained, not by submission
to law, or by obedience to any authority, but by free agreements
concluded between the various groups, territorial and professional,
freely constituted for the sake of production and consumption, as also
for the satisfaction of the infinite variety of needs and aspirations of
a civilized being.â And if one chose not to read further than these
cherry-picked quotes, it would seem that these definitions would seem to
point to anarcho-capitalism, being, at least in its basic principles of
voluntary exchange and individual property ownership, a form of
anarchism.
However, a deeper question arises: are these descriptions of what
anarchism is or rather a description of an end goal reached through
rigorous meeting of deeper commitments? The latter is believed by Byas,
who maintains that âanarchism . . . [is not] simply synonymous with
voluntary association and nothing more. Voluntary association is
necessary and non-negotiable, but the anarchistâs work is not over if
non-violent forms of domination persist.â As John Clark argues, the
âessence of anarchismâ is not simply âthe theoretical opposition to the
state, but the practical and theoretical struggle against domination,â
which âdoes not stop with a criticism of political organizationâ but
goes to the root of the thing in condemning âthe authoritarian nature of
economic inequality and private property, hierarchical economic
structures, traditional education, the patriarchal family, class and
racial discrimination, and rigid sex-and age-roles."[2] Another, more
concise explanation might be found in the famous line by Noam Chomsky
thatâŠ
â[t]he core of the anarchist tradition, as I understand it, is that
power is always illegitimate, unless it proves itself to be legitimate.
So the burden of proof is always on those who claim that some
authoritarian hierarchic relation is legitimate. If they canât prove it,
then it should be dismantled.â
And Byas explains that ancaps âoften [forget] to emphasize . . . [this]
centrality of non-domination in the anarchist ethos.â In advocating for
an economy centered around private ownership of the means of
productionâa socio-economic order that not only reproduces hierarchy but
came into existence through primitive accumulation and other forms of
violence like settler-colonialism and imperialismâfail to meet the
deeper commitments of seeking to abolish hierarchy and domination beyond
just that off the state, and so, while qualifying as radical
libertarianism, anarcho-capitalism is not anarchism.
This thesis is contested by Roderick Long in his contribution on
libertarianism and anarchism to Brillâs Companion to Anarchism and
Philosophy, where heâthough not an ancap himselfâholds that
anarcho-capitalism does qualify as anarchism even if it considers âthe
forms of domination in Clarkâs list as legitimate, either in the weaker
sense of not being rights-violations and so not permissible targets of
forcible interference, or in the stronger sense of not being problematic
even in terms of private morality.â He presentsâas I see itâtwo major
arguments: 1) North American individualist anarchism like that of
Benjamin Tucker, Josiah Warren, Voltraine De Cleyre, and Lysander
Spooner is considered a legitimate form of anarchism, and
âanarcho-capitalism is best understood [as] a subset of individualist
anarchism.âAnd furthermore, â[m]any of the features of
anarcho-capitalism to which social anarchists point as grounds for
exclusion from the anarchist ranks appear to be shared by individualist
anarchistsââin particular private defense agencies. 2) The system that
ancaps describe as âcapitalismâ is not the existing statist economy but
rather an actually free market. And not only then does such a system
allow for non-capitalist projects such as mutual aid, cooperatives, and
communes but massive inequalities, parasitism, and monopolism are
âlargely the product of state intervention rather than free markets, and
so should not be expected to feature in any realistic implementation of
anarcho-capitalistsâ ideals, whatever the anarcho-capitalists themselves
expect.â Long only loosely addresses the issue of deeper commitments to
anti-hierarchy and non-domination, writing it off as a âstrategy of
exclusion-by-definition.â I think this is a serious error, as it opens
the door to allowing reactionary values into the anarchist movement. Is
there nothing inherent in anarchism that rejects racism, misogyny,
homophobia, and other forms of bigotry? Long points to Pierre-Joseph
âProudhonâs misogyny, anti-Semitism, and homophobiaâ but continued place
in anarchist canon as essentially proof that there is notâeven if such a
rejection is good. But are we to view them as compatible or as errors in
the early development of the ideology? I believe the latter, and
Proudhon himself once said, ââI dream of a society where I will be
guillotined for being a conservative.â[3]
But moving on to the arguments that Long makes more substantially, I
actually agree that anarcho-capitalism is in some way descendent from
individualist anarchism but not because the former is a form of
anarchism but because the latter is a form of proto-libertarianism.
Individualist anarchism shares a âcontinuity with classical liberalismâ
just as anarcho-capitalism does and they both advocate for the complete
reduction of the state and the expansion of the market into
everythingâincluding law and defense. However, the 19th century
individualist anarchists went further to champion progressive social
values like, as Long outlines, âfeminism, free love, antimilitarism, and
labor empowerment.â And their free market ideology is best understood
not simply as institutions like private defense agencies being
âconceived as . . . implementedâ not in a âcapitalistic contextâ but âan
anti-capitalistic one,â but further that an expansion of the free market
in all spheres will generate results favorable to those aforementioned
values and destructive to capitalism in general. Long contests this
belief, arguing that not only were some 19th century individualists (in
particular Spooner) not wholly opposed to interest, rent, and wage labor
per se but âjust as Tucker expected and predicted that genuinely free
markets would undermine capitalist institutions, but did not make his
support for laissez-faire conditional on the accuracy of this
predictionâ and âhe saw the connection between [anarchism and the
undermining of capitalist exploitation] as causal rather than
definitional, and acknowledged that if he had to choose between
individual liberty and a more equitable distribution of wealth, he would
choose liberty.â Long cites two points in particular to back up this
assertion:
[Tuckerâs] more succinct phrasing elsewhere: âEquality if we can get it,
but Liberty at any rate!â [And how,] [w]hile opposing interest, Tucker
noted that he had âno other case against interest than that it cannot
appear (except sporadically) under free conditions,â and that he would
cease to oppose interest if he could be convinced âthat interest can
persist where free competition prevails.â
Setting aside what I believe to be the anomalous views of Spooner, I
think using these as reasons to say Tucker (particularly as the
fountainhead of free market anti-capitalism) did not see the undermining
of exploitation as an essential part of his politics is a
misunderstanding of both of these sentiments.
The latter of these points can be best understood as a continuation of a
sentiment presented by Proudhon, who writes that he does not intendâŠ
to forbid or suppress, by sovereign degree, ground rent and interest on
capital. I think that all these manifestations of human activity should
remain free and voluntary for all: I ask for them no modifications,
restrictions or suppressions, other than those which result naturally
and of necessity from the universalization of the principle of
reciprocity which I propose.
Here Proudhon is not defending interest or rent but rather acknowledging
that anarchism does not function in a prohibitory manner like statist
ideologies but rather creates a situation in which interest could exist
but probably would not. As Carson writes, drawing from Tuckerâs own
analysis of the money monopoly, it is âthe stateâs licensing of banks,
capitalization requirements, and other market entry barriers enable
banks to charge a monopoly price for loans in the form of usurious
interest rates.â The admiration of liberty over equality in the former
part of Longâs above quote can, in turn, be best viewed not as an
endorsement of any system as long as it does not have a state but rather
as a sentiment found in the context of his opposition to state
socialism. Despite self-describing as a socialist, Tucker was vehemently
opposed to its statist form, writing, âthere is no half-way house
between State Socialism and Anarchismâ and describing the former as âthe
doctrine that all the affairs of men should be managed by the
government, regardless of individual choice.â It is in this opposition
that Tucker calls for liberty over equality, believing that ultimately
the first would lead to the second but opposing any ideologyâlike state
socialismâthat held its priorities the other way around as it would
never truly establish freedom or equality. This is how we should
understand James J. Martinâs account of Tucker writing in his old age
that âCapitalism is at least tolerable, which cannot be said of
Socialism or Communism;â not as an endorsement of capitalism that, as
Susan L. Brown rationalizes, provides âthe shift further illuminated in
the 1970s by anarcho-capitalistsâ but the bitter words of a committed
anarchist who watched the rise of the authoritarian-statist USSR in the
last 15 or so years of his life.[4] So while certainly the 19th century
individualist anarchists were not willing to give up their entire
ideology because some of the outcomes might not create as much equality
and liberation as they thought, this does not mean that one can do away
with these egalitarian and and liberatory end goalsâa necessary process
if anarcho-capitalism is to be brought into the anarchist canon.
And even admitting a libertarian (as opposed to anarchist) continuity
between individualist anarchism and anarcho-capitalism, I would also
like to make a strategic argument about to whom the heritage of
individualist anarchism belongs. Charles Johnson accounts how the debate
between ancaps and social anarchists over the ownership of this heritage
can be deeply disingenuous, with ancaps obscuring and neglecting âthe
socialistic bite of the individualist understanding of class, privilege,
and exploitationâ and social anarchists cutting âa lot of corners in
explaining the individualistsâ positionsâ in order âto make them seem
significantly less propertarian, and more friendly towards
collectivistic and communistic socialism, than they actually were.â And
furthermore, he points out that individualist anarchists âare still
about and hardly need a bunch of anarcho-capitalists and social
anarchists to do the talking for us.â Johnson says he doesnât âhave much
of a dog in the fight, except insofar as it gets a bit tiresome watching
the two bicker over the individualist tendency within the movement as if
they were arguing over the contents of their dead grandmotherâs will,â
but I think we as contemporary individualist anarchists still fighting
for both free markets and an end to capitalist exploitation need to
assert that said inheritance as our birthright. Right-wingers have
attempted to claim our tradition before; the French proto-fascist group
Cerele Proudhon attempted to selectively draw from Proudhonâs critique
of statist democracy to justify vicious nationalism. Tucker writes thatâŠ
[o]ne of the methods of propagandism practised by these agitators is the
attempt to enroll among their apostles all the great dead who, if
living, would look with scorn upon their ways and works. Every great
writer who has criticised democracy and who, being in his grave, cannot
enter protest, is listed as a royalist, a nationalist, and an
anti-Dreyfusard. Chief among these helpless victims is the foremost of
all Anarchists, to whom these impudent young rascals constantly refer as
notre grand Proudhon. Indeed, they have formed a Cerele Proudhon, which
publishes a bi-monthly review under the title, Cahiers du Cerele
Proudhon.
We should take heed from this historical anti-reactionary stance by
Tucker and, instead of becoming awkward apologists for
anarcho-capitalism, should take on the legacy of 19th century
individualist anarchism ourselves. As I said at the start, this is more
of a strategic claim than a purely factual one, but I do not think that
detracts from its importance when so many ancaps and other
right-libertarians are falling prey to the allure of fascism,
monarchism, white nationalism, and other forms of reactionary
authoritarianism.
This final point is what leads me to critique the idea that ancaps
should be accepted as anarchists on the basis that what they call
capitalism is not the existing system but a truly free market and that
consistent application of free market principles would lead to a world
very dissimilar to the present day economy. Anna Morgenstern believes
that if ancaps âgenuinely wish to eliminate the state, they are
anarchists, but they arenât really capitalists, no matter how much they
want to claim they are.â This is because in the absence of the state
âthe cost of protecting property rises dramatically as the amount of
property owned increases;â âwithout a state-protected banking/financial
system, accumulating endless high profits is well nigh impossible;â and
âunder anarchism, such a thing as âintellectual propertyâ wouldnât
exist, so any business model that relies on patents and copyrights to
make money would not exist either.â This would in turn make âmass
accumulation and concentration of capital . . . impossible;â â[w]ithout
concentration of capital, wage slavery is impossible;â and â[w]ithout
wage slavery, thereâs nothing most people would recognize as
âcapitalism.ââ And there are certainly ancaps that advocate for a
genuinely free marketâthey often choose to describe themselves as
voluntaryistsâeven as it clashes against traditional capitalist
principles; in particular, Karl Hess and Rothbard during his time allied
with the New Left come to mind. The former admits (and is echoed at
least at one point by the latter) thatâŠ
much of that property [which now is called private] is stolen. Much is
of dubious title. All of it is deeply intertwined with an immoral,
coercive state system which has condoned, built on, and profited from
slavery; has expanded through and exploited a brutal and aggressive
imperial and colonial foreign policy, and continues to hold the people
in a roughly serf-master relationship to political-economic power
concentrations.
But the aforementioned vulgar libertarianism rears its ugly head again
and again with manyancaps defending the existing system (minus the most
obvious elements of statism) without looking into its violent framework
of white supremacy, patriarchy, settler-colonialism, imperialism, etc.
(that, it should be noted, do rely fundamentally on the state to be
perpetuated). And because this backdrop of horrific violence is required
for the existing features of capitalismâlike wage labor, large-scale
private property, and immense wealth inequalityâto continue, said
structure is assumed by vulgar ancaps to be essentially what a free
market would look like; and they therefore find themselves defending
these monstrous systems.
Long admits that ancaps âare likelier to endorse hierarchical features
of existing economies,â but the problem is much more severe than that.
This reasoningâalongside a desire to appeal to the white middle-class in
the United Statesâled Rothbard and Lew Rockwell to conceptualize the
ideology of paleoconservatism. This backward ideology follows Rockwellâs
agreement with conservatives thatâŠ
political freedom is a necessary but not sufficient condition for the
good society. . . . Neither is it sufficient for the free society. We
also need social institutions and standards that encourage public
virtue, and protect the individual from the State.
This leads to him to a number of principles like:
VII. The egalitarian ethic is morally reprehensible and destructive of
private property and social authority.
VIII. Social authority, as embodied in the family, church, community,
and other intermediating institutions, as helping protect the individual
from the State and as necessary for a free and virtuous society.
IX. Western culture as eminently worthy of preservation and defense.
X. Objective standards of morality, especially as found in the
Judeo-Christian tradition, as essential to the free and civilized social
order.
And so ultimately, as Tom Bagwell explains, paleolibertarians place
âheavy emphasis on nationalism and closed borders keeping their Austrian
economic system contained within their nation-state. They also place
heavy emphasis on racial and cultural identity particularly . . .
arguing that right-libertarian economics only works among whites of
European descent and that European and North American states should be
kept largely or exclusively [white] (European).â And it is exactly this
colonial, racialized, chauvinistic, logic that has led Hans-Herman Hoppe
to argueâby taking Rockwellâs above ideas to the absolute extremeâthat
âcontemporary libertarianism can be characterized . . . as theory and
theorists without psychology and sociology, much or even most of the
Alt-Right can be described, in contrast, as psychology and sociology
without theoryâ and that therefore these two movements should unify on
some level in opposition to egalitarianism, social justice, and other
âcultural Marxistâ ideas and institutions in favor of an
ultraconservative, ethnocentric society based on Eurocentric ideas of
hierarchical social order. This type of thinking is a marked trend in
hubs of anarcho-capitalist thought. Look at the article âDo White People
Have A Future?âfrom lewrockwell.com that calls for white people to arm
themselves against âimmigrant invadersâ and warns that âwhite societies
will disappear in the emerging barbarism;â or the piece âFor a New
Libertarianâ from the head of the Mises Instituteâwhere Hoppe is a
senior fellowâthat lauds âblood and soil and God and nationâ and âelite
families;â or the mods of the subreddit r/anarcho_capitalism admitting
to embracing âmonarchism, conservatism, AuthCapism, Christian
Capitalism, National Socialismâ because âitâs inevitableâ and they are
no longer âlarping as anarchists;â or Liberty Hangout publicly promoting
Catholic theocracy and Holocaust denialism. And even as well meaning
right-libertarians struggle to maintain the false neutrality of
thinness, former ancaps like Stefan Molyneux and Christopher Cantwell
have turned toward explicit white nationalism. These are all natural
outcomes of defending the horrifying âpackage dealâ of capitalism and
almost all other present systems of oppressionâfrom white supremacy to
patriarchy and beyond.
So what does this conclusion mean for someone (like myself) who
identifies as both an anarchist and a left-libertarian? Since
libertarianism has been identified as an ideology based fundamentally
not on anti-hierarchy and non-domination but on the minimization of
government and maximization of market and therefore distinct from
anarchism, can there ever be principled overlap between the two? To
answer this, one should observe that a characteristic difference between
left-libertarians and right- to far-right libertarians is the latterâs
commitment to a progressive and liberatory thickness. Thickness is, as
defined by Nathan Goodman, âany broadening of libertarian concerns
beyond overt aggression and state power to concern about what cultural
and social conditions are most conducive to liberty.â While many
right-libertarians like Walter Block try to avoid the problem by
claiming a false neutrality or âthinnessâ and far-right libertarians
like the aforementioned Rockwell and Hoppe see this as an opening for
their reactionary social order, it leads left-libertarians to being
committed to not only limited-to-zero government, individual
sovereignty, and absolutely free markets but alsoâjust like the 19th
century individualist anarchistsâvalues and ideologies, as outlined by
Johnson, like âfeminism, anti-racism, gay liberation,
counterculturalism, labor organizing, mutual aid, and environmentalism.â
And these are not just personal values tacked onto an anarcho-capitalist
framework but rather necessary for and entailed by its principled
application. Johnson argues, for example, that ârejecting these ideas,
practices, or projects would be logically compatible with
libertarianism, [but] their success might be important or even causally
necessary for libertarianism to get much purchase in an existing statist
society, or for a future free society to emerge from statism without
widespread poverty or social conflict, or for a future free society to
sustain itself against aggressive statist neighbors, the threat of civil
war, or an internal collapse back into statism.â He holds in particular
that wealth inequality needs to be addressed âwith voluntary
anti-poverty measuresâ because â[e]ven a totally free society in which a
small class of tycoons own the overwhelming majority of the wealth, and
the vast majority of the population own almost nothing is unlikely to
remain free for long.â Or take Cathy Reisenwitz, who asserts that
libertarians should incorporate sex-positive feminism into their
thinking because it âseeks to destroy the judgment and shame which keep
people from being able to fully enjoy sex, or a lack of sex, or anything
in betweenâ and â[l]ibertarianism should seek to destroy the judgment
and shame which keep people from being able to fully enjoy any kind of
peaceful, voluntary exchange. In this way, it will fully engage in
creating a world which allows the greatest amount of peaceful, voluntary
exchange possible.â And furthermore, left-libertarians, according to
Carson, seek to âdemonstrate the relevance and usefulness of free market
thought for addressing the concerns of todayâs Leftâ such as racism,
wealth inequality, landlordism, and ultimately capitalism in its
entirety. Look at the points made by Morgenstern above about the
impossibility of wealth accumulation and consequently wage labor in a
genuinely free market, or consider Carsonâs argument that the âoutcomes
of free market competition in socializing progress would result in a
society resembling not the anarcho-capitalist vision of a world owned by
the Koch brothers and Halliburton, so much as Marxâs vision of a
communist society.â Ultimately, left-libertarianismâwhen it is taken to
the extreme of total government abolition and totalizing free(d)
marketsâmeets the criteria for radical libertarianism but also holds the
same anti-domination and anti-hierarchy commitments of anarchism. This
means that left-libertarian anarchists can be properly described as
anarchists (and even draw upon ancap thinkers like David Friedman,
Rothbard, etc. as radical libertarians) without requiring
anarcho-capitalism to be included under the ideological umbrella as well
[1] The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy accounts that â[t]hough not
all scholars agree on the meaning of the term, âneoliberalismâ is now
generally thought to label the philosophical view that a societyâs
political and economic institutions should be robustly liberal and
capitalist, but supplemented by a constitutionally limited democracy and
a modest welfare state.â However, Carson espouses that in reality a
âstructural model of farming out government functions to private
capital, at public expense and with guaranteed private profit, and
within a web of state-enforced monopolies and legal protections, is at
the heart of whatâs called âfree market reformâ under neoliberalism.â
Not to mention the use of the welfare state in the U.S. as a form of
human regulation which, as suggested by Frances Fox Piven and Richard A.
Cloward, expands during times of civil disorder and retracting when the
danger to the status quo has passed; and how all of this is tied in a
nice package of imposing U.S. interests on the rest of the world through
imperialism and neocolonialism as well economic globalization that
Carson effectively argues is also the product of state intervention.
[2] This quote is taken from its reproduction in Roderick Longâs article
on libertarianism and anarchism.
[3] Itâs unclear where this quote comes from originally but it is cited
often.
[4] See Brownâs âThe Free Market as Salvation from Government: The
Anarcho-Capitalist Viewâ in Meanings of the Market in Western Culture.