💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › matt-bruenig-violence-vouchers.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:37:21. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Violence Vouchers
Author: Matt Bruenig
Date: March 28, 2014
Language: en
Topics: property, law, coercion, Structural Violence, legal system
Source: https://mattbruenig.com/2014/03/28/violence-vouchers-a-descriptive-account-of-property/

Matt Bruenig

Violence Vouchers

Introduction

I’ve argued here and elsewhere that property is an institution of

involuntary, violent, coercive aggression. These arguments are clearly

correct, but they are lacking in one important respect: they don’t

constitute a full descriptive account of the institution of property.

They describe certain characteristics of property — that it is violent,

that it is coercive, that it is involuntary. But they don’t fully

describe what is going on when someone holds property, transfers

property, rents property, and so on. Here, I attempt to provide a more

robust description of the institution of property using a concept I have

dubbed Violence Vouchers.

Holdings

Saying someone owns a piece of the world obscures what is actually going

on. Ownership is not a relationship between a person and a piece of the

world. It is a relationship between a person and all other persons. It

is a relationship that consists of the following threat: should someone

else act upon this piece of the world, violence will be brought against

them in order to cause them to desist.

The person who we call the owner is the person who has the power to

direct violence against others who try to act upon the piece of the

world. In our society, that person directs violence against other people

by calling upon the state, which then mobilizes its police forces to

carry out the violence. Thus, what makes someone an “owner” is that they

possess a violence voucher that they can redeem with the state under

certain circumstances. The circumstances in which the owner can redeem

their violence voucher depends upon the laws. It is the laws that create

violence vouchers and construct their terms and conditions.

When a state (or state-like entity) establishes a system of private

property, all it really does is hand out violence vouchers to people who

we call owners. This can be done through direct grants to individuals or

by establishing some set of rules, the following of which entitles the

follower to a violence voucher. The Homestead Acts are a good example of

the latter: individuals that followed a specific set of rules were given

violence vouchers that they could redeem with the state should someone

else act in a proscribed manner towards some piece of the world they

“homesteaded.”

Thus, when we say someone holds property, all we mean is that someone

has a violence voucher that they can redeem with respect to the specific

piece of the world we call their property. The exact terms of the

violence voucher can differ depending on the laws of the state that has

issued it, but generally it entitles the holder to, at minimum, direct

the state’s violence against others who try to act on the piece of the

world that the violence voucher covers.

Trading

People do not trade pieces of the world. They trade violence vouchers.

When a trade has occurred, the pieces of the world have not changed.

There are no metaphysical switches in pieces of the world that register

a new owner. All that has happened is that violence vouchers have

changed hands.

In fact, the existence of violence vouchers is the only reason the

“trading of property” happens in the first place.

Suppose I wanted to act upon a house I have spotted, by which I mean

live in it. This seems easy enough: walk on in and start living in it.

If I could do that, I would never trade something for the house. I would

never “buy” the house. But it turns out that I am prevented from doing

that. The person who currently lives in the house has a violence voucher

that they will surely redeem if I try to live in the house. It is

because I know that the violence voucher will be redeemed that, if I

want to live in the house, I have to trade for it.

When I trade for the house, I don’t actually trade for the house of

course. I trade for the house’s violence voucher. The house has no value

at all to me. Only the violence voucher does. It’s quite obvious why

this is so. If I come into ownership of the house (whatever that might

mean) without coming into ownership of the violence voucher, I could not

keep anyone out of the house. The prior owner and anyone else could live

in the house and I would be powerless to exclude them. This would be of

no value to me. I buy the house specifically so I can exclude people and

maintain it as a place just for me. Which is to say: I buy the house’s

violence voucher.

This violence voucher swap works both ways of course. No person would

ever sell me their house’s violence voucher for some property I had.

They would only sell it to me for some violence voucher I had. Giving me

their violence voucher in exchange for something that they cannot

exclude from others via the redemption of a violence voucher would be a

total loss for them. Additionally, giving me their house’s violence

voucher for some piece of the world I do not have a violence voucher for

would also be a total waste for them because, if I do not have a

violence voucher for it, they would not need to trade me anything in

order to gain the ability to access it.

One important insight that springs from these observations is that there

is no such thing as a non-coercive trade. All trades rely upon violent

coercion. I only trade with someone because they have a violence voucher

that they will redeem if I decide to act upon the piece of the world

without doing so. They only trade with me for the same reason. If you

got rid of the coercion, which is to say you got rid of violence

vouchers, no trading would occur. You would not need to trade in a world

without violence vouchers. Indeed, it’s not at all clear what a trade

even is in such a world because after the “trade” has happened, everyone

would be in the exact same position as they were before the trade, i.e.

everyone would still be able to act freely upon all the pieces of the

world involved in the trade just as they were before the trade.

Rents

People do not rent property from other people. They trade their violence

voucher over some piece of the world in exchange for the person they are

renting from agreeing to waive their right to redeem their violence

voucher over some other piece of the world for some period of time.

To be concrete about this, suppose someone (landlord) has a violence

voucher with respect to an apartment unit. Suppose someone else (tenant)

has a violence voucher with respect to $1000. The tenant would like to

live in the apartment unit, but if they try to do so, the landlord

redeems their violence voucher and the state boots them out. Due to this

violent coercion, the tenant is forced to strike a deal with the

landlord, a deal we might call a rental agreement. In the rental

agreement, violence vouchers are not swapped (as in the trade explained

in the prior example). Instead, the landlord agrees to waive their right

to redeem their violence voucher for a period of time if the tenant

gives up to the landlord the violence voucher the tenant has with

respect to the $1000.

As with the trade, this is not a voluntary agreement. It is an agreement

coerced through violence. It is more pernicious than the trade though.

With the trade, violence vouchers are swapped such that each party to

the trade maintains their wealth level (by wealth I mean the value of

the portfolio of their violence vouchers). But in the rental agreement,

the landlord has held on to their violence voucher with respect to the

apartment unit and received an additional violence voucher with respect

to the $1000. The landlord’s portfolio of violence vouchers has grown

larger while the tenant’s portfolio of violence vouchers has shrunk.

A rent can thus be described as the acquisition of a violence voucher in

exchange for temporarily waiving a right to redeem a violence voucher. A

rent is when you leverage threats to redeem your violence vouchers in

order to acquire violence vouchers from others without giving any

violence vouchers in return.

This definition of rent is not constrained to renting buildings of

course: it can ultimately capture all capital income including interest

and dividends. What a capitalist does is leverage their portfolio of

violence vouchers in order to get others to give them violence vouchers

without the capitalist having to give up any violence vouchers in

return. Or, to put it in Marxist terms, a capitalist leverages their

control of the means of production in order to coerce others to pay them

for nothing.

Some will reply that the capitalist has given more than nothing. They

have given access to pieces of the world that can be used productively.

But to say this obscures the reality. Nobody needs the capitalist to

give them access. Access is available so long as nobody acts (violently)

to shut it down. It is only the prospect of a violence voucher

redemption that precludes access.

What the capitalist has actually done is agreed to not redeem their

violence voucher for some period of time against those who are using

those pieces of the world. They have held a gun to the head of those who

wish (or in fact need) to use those pieces of the world and demanded

that violence vouchers be forked over to them in exchange for not

shooting. It’s extortion plain and simple. If the state did not issue

violence vouchers or refused efforts to redeem them, it couldn’t happen.

Closing Remarks

The last section is the one that will probably rankle the most people,

so I’d like to clarify its implications. Rents are certainly suspicious

on their face, but that suspicious nature is not necessarily dispositive

of their justness.

Rents cannot be justified on just deserts grounds because they involve

the distribution of resources to those who merely leverage violence

vouchers to capture an income, which, unlike working, is not actually

contributory. Rents cannot be justified on just processes grounds (i.e.

on voluntarism grounds) because they are acquired solely through threats

to redeem violence vouchers. Thus, the two most favored right-wing

frameworks of economic justice cannot justify rents.

But you may attempt to justify the rents on other grounds, e.g.

utilitarian grounds. You may argue that the payment of these rents

creates a market in capital allocation, which generates price signals

that directs resources to their most productive uses. Sure we pay a

hefty fee for that — around one-third of national income flows to

capital each year, the vast majority of which is held by a tiny fraction

of Americans — but maybe that hefty fee is worth it for the broad-based

welfare gains it supposedly generates. Of course, for this to pass

utilitarian muster, it must be the case that there is no better

welfare-maximizing way to allocate capital, which I suspect isn’t true,

especially compared to what we have now.

There are also institution-agnostic egalitarian grounds that might

justify a system featuring these rents. If one-third of the national

income flowed to these rents, that may not be a problem if the

distribution of the rents was relatively equal, i.e. everyone got a

pretty even chunk of passive income each year. Maybe such a thing is

possible, but it is not the world we currently find ourselves in. In

2007, 47 percent of capital income went to the top 1 percent of

households. Seventy-two percent went to the top 10 percent of

households. In the same year, 75 percent of capital gains went to the

top 1 percent of households. Ninety-two percent went to the top 10

percent of households.

So while it is possible to imagine a world in which those rents are

justifiable on utilitarian and egalitarian grounds, it seems very

unlikely that there is not some other constellation of institutions — at

minimum market socialist ones — that would deliver more utilitarian and

egalitarian outcomes.

Regardless of how this all shakes out within the realm of political

justice, I think violence vouchers are worthwhile as a descriptive

matter. A private property economy is not built upon the trading of

pieces of the world really. It is built upon a market of

government-issued violence vouchers. These violence vouchers are what

really establish what we call “ownership.” These violence vouchers are

what coerce people to trade. These violence vouchers are what make

“ownership” over pieces of the world at all valuable. It is these

well-placed threats of violence that actually animate the so-called

“voluntary” capitalist economy, and descriptions of the institution of

property that fail to capture this core reality are inadequate.