💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › shawn-p-wilbur-legal-order.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:08:27. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Legal Order Author: Shawn P. Wilbur Date: November 28, 2021 Language: en Topics: Legal Order, law, criticism and critique, critique Source: Retrieved August 28, 2022 from https://www.libertarian-labyrinth.org/glossary/legal-order-2/
There is a kind of slogan or maxim that circulates in anarchist spaces:
Anarchy means “no rulers,” but not “no rules.” It is most often
presented as a kind of common-sense answer to portrayals of anarchy as
some kind of “Mad Max” scenario, where all parties engage in a constant
struggle to ward off the depredations of lawless others. It is
generally, I think, presented in good faith — as are similar attempts to
distinguish between government and governance, the various appeals to
“legitimate authority” and “justified hierarchy,” etc. — but it forces
us to distinguish between at least two very different currents in modern
anarchistic thought.
The ultimate source of the slogan is not clear, but in One Life at a
Time, Please (1988), Edward Abbey presents a version of it:
Ten thousand years of human history demonstrate that our freedoms cannot
be entrusted to those ambitious few who are drawn to power; we must
learn — again — to govern ourselves. Anarchism does not mean “no rule”;
it means “no rulers.” Difficult, but not utopian, anarchy means and
requires self-rule, self-discipline, probity, character.
In the same text, of course, he also claims that:
Anarchy is democracy taken seriously, as in Switzerland, where issues of
national importance are decided by direct vote of all citizens. Where
each citizen, after his period of military training, takes his weapon
home with him, to keep for life. Anarchy is democracy taken all the way,
in every major sector of social life.
So it feels safe to say that the “anarchy” invoked there is a sort of
“good government” or “self-government,” rather different from the “
” anarchy that is at the center of the theory being elaborated in
“Constructing Anarchisms.”
There would probably be some utility in tracing the development — or at
least the persistence — of this approach, from pre-1840 conceptions of
“natural government,” through texts like Emile Digeon’s 1882
Rights and Duties in Rational Anarchy
and on to tendencies like modern anarchist constitutionalism, if only to
clarify its differences from the sort of an-arche-centered approach that
seems to me to be a more consistent development of the indications given
by figures like Proudhon after 1840. For now, however, I want to focus
on the consistent definition and rejection of legal order and the
problem of licit harm.
⁂
In the anarchist context, it is common to approach the question of legal
order by asking whether anarchists truly desire a society in which
nothing is prohibited. This is, it seems to me, only half of the
question that needs to be asked, as an anarchic society would also be
one in which nothing is permitted. And it is probably this second aspect
that is most helpful in evaluating the antinomian character of anarchy.
Legal order exists when society is guided by laws, rules or principles
that are considered binding and enforceable. Legal order inevitably
depends on some assertion of
and is part of the apparatus of a governmental hierarchy. The range of
presumed authorities can, of course, be great, but whether the basis is
divinity, democracy, sanctified might or nature, the basic quality of
legal order changes very little. If we understand the anarchist critique
as at least in part a rejection of the hierarchical pretense of
elevating some elements of society above others (either directly or as
proxies for some reigning abstraction) and endowing those elements with
a “right” to command, then the specific pretext for that elevation is a
matter of only secondary concern.
It is important to recognize that legal order is pervasive — and
arguably becomes so as soon as a single binding precept is established.
Where law is in force, it tends to divide all actions into the
categories of legal and illegal, licit and illicit, permitted and
prohibited. So, while there are lots of obvious differences between
Leviticus, the penal code of a given government, papal bulls, the
non-aggression principle, “natural law,” etc., the systems that they
represent all presume to pass judgment on essentially the whole of
future human activity, with necessarily limited attention to contexts.
In anarchist circles, the defense of some form of law usually depends on
the recognition that some small number of acts seem unjustifiable to
almost anyone under any circumstances, but this is hardly a compelling
argument for imposing a necessarily pervasive legal order, with all the
recourse to authority and hierarchy that seems inseparable from it.
After all, what the experience of legal order appears to teach us is
that a certain number of absolutely intolerable acts are likely to occur
despite all the laws that can be proposed and all the punishments that
can be applied. These worst cases are not so much a final justification
for the imposition of legal order, but instead an example of its limits.
There is no question that, even under the most promising conditions, the
power of law is limited. We are often asked how we will “prevent crime”
— and it is obviously not quite enough to observe that crime is itself a
construction of legal order. So some clarity regarding the limits of law
and legal enforcement is necessary.
We know that laws do not prevent crime. They create crime — in the sense
of identifying certain acts as criminal — and, in the process, they also
identify those acts that can be considered legal, licit, permitted. They
may perhaps deter crime in those most likely to conform to social
expectations — but I think experience indicates that most people are
fairly comfortable breaking laws that are unpopular, unenforced or
unenforceable. That leaves the threat of enforcement as the primary
deterrent. And, again, what we observe is that the “best” laws — those
precepts about which there is presumably the least controversy — are
still regularly broken, whether by criminals who remain undeterred or by
agents of the governmental apparatus who are rendered exempt from the
laws and immune to prosecution under them.
It would be trivial to note that laws don’t “prevent crime” — except
that crime-prevention is so consistently the excuse, sometimes even
among anarchists, for defending them.
Meanwhile, the problem of licit harm — acts that injure or endanger
others, but against which those others have at best limited recourse,
thanks to the “legal system” — arguably remains to key to most of our
most intractable social and environmental crises.
⁂
The practical mechanics of an anarchic, alegal social order remain
relatively unexplored by anarchists — in part because some of us have
not yet decided we really need to go there. And the difficulties of
establishing practices that minimize social conflict, without, in the
process, reestablishing some form of legal order, will be considerable.
But there are at least useful indications going all the way back to
figures like Proudhon and Bakunin.
Consider the problem of the appropriation of resources. While we may not
know how to arrange systems of property without recourse to some sort of
legal framework, we know that appropriation will go on regardless.
Living beings will consume and transform resources — if they are to
continue living. So, whatever the social or economic framework we
develop for addressing potential conflicts over resources, we aren’t
going to be free of the fact of appropriation, which lurks behind all of
our discussions of the alternatives to familiar property-forms and
property “rights.” The question is how best to break free of archic
assumptions enough to really distinguish our an-arche-centered anarchism
from the various attempts at “good government.”
When we return to the “classical” sources, we often find theoretical
advances couched in the language of government and authority. Proudhon
and Bakunin agreed on necessity as the sole “law” applicable to
anarchistic relations. Proudhon presented balance as “justice” and
necessity as “right” — providing a kind of bridge or translation
mechanism between anarchic and archic conceptions. As indications,
understood in the general context of early anarchist thought, we have to
consider these maneuvers at least potentially helpful — but we know how
easily a notion like “the authority of the bootmaker” slips free of that
all-important context. The “classics” provide first steps in processes
that we must presumably continue — moving forward into unmapped
territory — if we are to propose real alternatives. All too often,
however, anarchists seem content to treat their half-transformed
governmentalism as something familiar to cling to.
We can probably say similar things about the specific strategy of
reimagining governmental relations in terms of “contract” — as proposed
in works like Proudhon’s General Idea of the Revolution in the
Nineteenth Century and much of the individualist “market anarchist”
literature. Perhaps contract is a useful transitional notion, but it is
hard to rid of fundamentally legal connotations. If contracts are
binding and enforceable, then we still seem to be under the sway of
legal order. If they are not, well, it’s not entirely clear what the
word means.
There is a strange sense in which the attempts to begin to conceptualize
anarchistic relations by hijacking various concepts associated with
governmentalism commit — or tempt us to commit — the same sorts of
category errors we find in anti-anarchist texts like Engels’ “On
Authority.” The “rights” in Proudhon’s War and Peace mark demands made
on the world by various organisms, not permissions granted to fulfill
the various needs expressed. They are the elements that we would have to
take into account if we wanted to elaborate some alternative to what we
call “rights.” Perhaps, in the context of the serial dialectic adopted
by Proudhon, maintaining the name makes sense, despite the changes in
the institutions and relations described — but, at least for now, that
framework is, almost without exception, not our own, so it is very easy
for the language to lead us astray.
We can, perhaps, turn the rather clumsy critique of Engels to some good
use here. If we, presumably acting as anarchists, do, in fact, attempt
to justify our rebellion against authority, subordination, exploitation,
etc. in terms of “our rights” — including the “right of self-defense” —
then we arguably surrender much of the “high ground” that we so often
claim in our conflicts with statists and authoritarians. If we don’t —
dispensing with justification as itself part of the apparatus we are
trying to abandon — then I think it is entirely fair to observe that we
have a hard time articulating our rationales. Our appropriations from
Stirner and some kindred spirits are a start, but arguably not much more
than that.
Perhaps, for the moment, our best tools are simply an insistence on
anarchy, in the “full force of the term,” and an understanding that
those early anarchist indications and provocations do indeed come
complete with contexts that might help us to first carefully trace the
explorations and experiments made by their authors — and then make
genuine advances of our own.
One of the passages in Proudhon that I cling to when I am trying to
think about genuinely non-governmental alternatives is the one in
“Organization of Credit and Circulation,” where, in the context of
discussing “
the fundamental laws of the universe
,” he defined reciprocity — “the second law of creation and humanity” —
as “the mutual penetration of antagonistic elements.” There is a
tendency to treat reciprocity and mutuality as states to be achieved —
through “fair trade” or “equal exchange” in some anarchistic market, or
perhaps through the abandonment of market relations — but what Proudhon
seems to suggest is that reciprocity is, in fact, a preexisting
condition and a problem to be solved. This first “law of the universe”
is “Contradiction” or “Universal Antagonism.” The second, which seems to
be a bit of a corollary to the first, is that the antagonism takes place
among elements that are not simply distinct. They are at least, as
Stirner put it, one another’s “food” — but it probably takes a special
point of view to move very directly to any kind of social harmony from
that starting point, so perhaps we should just acknowledge some degree
of mutual interdependence. We have an experience of the world, thanks to
the structure of our consciousness and bodily organism, that is not
always well-adapted to thinking in those terms. We instead imagine
ourselves more separate, more solitary, more unique in various senses.
Hence our inability to entirely shake the question of property. But
perhaps beginning — or at least attempting to begin again — with the
fact of reciprocity (in this particular sense) and the necessity of
appropriation (whatever we make of social property-forms) has some
advantages when we are trying to escape the logic of legal order.