💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › alexei-borovoy-anarchism-and-law.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 06:27:42. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchism and Law
Author: Alexei Borovoy
Language: en
Topics: law, Russia, the State
Source: Retrieved on 15 January 2011 from http://quod.lib.umich.edu/cgi/t/text/text-idx?c=labadie;cc=labadie;view=toc;idno=2917084.0001.001
Notes: published by:  Friends of Malatesta  Box 72, Bidwell Station  Buffalo, NY 14222

Alexei Borovoy

Anarchism and Law

Biographical Note: Alexei Borovoy. Brilliant Russian Anarchist

theoretician, writer and orator. Professor of Political Economy at

Moscow University, prior to and after the Revolution, until ousted by

the Bolsheviks. Known and respected throughout Russia, where he had

great influence among workers, students and intellectuals. In 1920 the

students of Sverdlov petitioned the university administration to permit

a series of debates on “Anarchism versus Marxism,” Borovoy representing

the Anarchist viewpoint. The local Communist Party, designated the

famous Bolsheviks, Bukarin and Lunacharsky, to defend Marxism. The

Central Committee of the CP of Russia at the last minute overruled the

local CP and forced cancellation of the debates.

Because of his great popularity, the Bolsheviks postponed the silencing

of Borovoy until 1929 when he was arrested and deported to Viatka,

Siberia, where he died in 1936, the victim of persecution, cold and

hunger.

In literature concerning anarchism there is a general opinion that

anarchism, which negates existing society and existing legal codes, has

an equally negative position concerning social codes in general. This

opinion is absolutely false.

The reasons for this error are:

and the State in the writings of anarchists themselves;

both of anarchists and of their critics;

sociological naivete, are sincerely convinced that anarchy is the

absence of any sort of regulation;

but do not bother to learn even the essential elements of anarchist

thought;

“scientific socialism.”

The Problem of Law and the State

The problem in which we are interested can be presented as follows: Can

a society exist in which nothing limits the individual, where all

regulation is an affair of the individual and not of the collective

will?

Anarchism favors the establishment of a society

“of brothers, each of whom contributes his share, living harmoniously,

not because of a legal system which severely punishes those who disobey,

but because of the force of interpersonal relations, the inevitable

force of natural laws.” — Reclus

How restrictive are these natural laws? Do they permit of a society in

which each individual is free to do as he pleases, or on the other hand,

do they require the existence of a State for the preservation of an

orderly society?

Impartial sociologists have found that the State (the authoritarian

society with an established power) is not the first form of human

society. The State appeared as the result of complex phenomena: of a

particular material and intellectual culture, of the progressive

differentiation of society, of conquest and at the same time of a

progressive consciousness of the advantages of solidarity among large

groups. The same sociologists have pointed out the parallel growth of

the institution of power, which progressively engulfs functions which

previously belonged to local and autonomous social organisms. If some of

these functions have been better executed by the new power, others have

been executed badly and with a constant disregard for the fundamental

rights of the individual.

The process of governmental hypertrophy is well described by Durkheim:

“The governmental power tends to pre-empt all forms of social activity.

Among them it is obliged to take upon itself a considerable number of

functions for which it is unsuited and which it executes in an

insufficient manner. Its passion for bringing everything under its

jurisdiction is matched only by its inability to regulate human life. It

expends enormous amounts of energy which are totally out of proportion

to the obtained results.

“On the other hand, men obey no other collectivity before the State,

because the State proclaims itself the only collective organism. They

acquire the habit of looking upon society as having a perpetual

dependence on the State. And meanwhile, the State is situated very far

from them, it remains an abstract entity which cannot exercise an

immediate influence, so that in a great part of their lives they move in

a void.”

It is on this terrain — the tendency of the State to engulf all things,

the human person, his social needs, to paralyze his will with threats

and sanctions, that the anarchist revolt is born.

Anarchists seek to abolish the State and in general to replace it, not

with chaos, but with anew form of organization. They seek to organize

society not on the principle of class power, but on the principle of

mutual aid.

Imposed and Spontaneous Codes

There has not been a single society, even prior to the birth of the

State, that has not made certain demands upon its members. While

specific regulations may vary from society, some form of regulation is

always necessary.

Aside from legal codes, there exist in all societies what can be called

codes of convention. Shtamler points to these:

“In rules of ethical conduct, in interpersonal relationships.., in

collective norms such as the chivalric codes of the Middle Ages or the

codes of the guilds.”

The force of these codes is perhaps greater than the force of laws. The

fundamental difference is that these codes are based on a collective

accord:

“Men consent to a collective agreement, perhaps an unconscious one, like

the majority of social phenomena, but an agreement nevertheless.”

Meanwhile, legal codes are created by a specialized body, detached from

society, having as its primary aim the preservation of the established

order, which imposes its “sovereignty” without regard to the needs of

individual human beings. Genuinely collective codes, based on the free

agreement of human beings, can be correctly called anarchist codes. This

is recognized by the foremost representatives of anarchist thought, and

follows necessarily from the fact that neither social organization nor

social progress are consistent with unlimited individual liberty.

After this brief theoretical exposition, we would do well to see what

the more important anarchist thinkers have to say about the role of

collective codes in future society.

1. Godwin

According to Eltzbacher, Godwin opposes all forms of social regulation.

However, while he opposes government in all its forms, he speaks of

communes as organizations for the collective benefit of all, and points

out the necessity of accepting such organizations. Considering the

possibility of anti-social acts on the part of particular members of a

commune, he speaks of a committee of wise men which would have the power

to punish these people or expel them from the group. Furthermore, he

envisages regional conferences for the discussion of conflicts betwen

communes and for the necessities of defense against the attacks of

common enemies. He feels that such institutions would be much more

effective than existing ones. Thus he favors the replacement of existing

legal codes with the regulation of society by communal organizations.

2. Proudhon

There are many seeming contradictions in the work of Proudhon concerning

centralization and the State. One can call the institutions advocated by

Proudhon “anarchist” and “federalist,” but these institutions carry with

them certain governmental characteristics. Even the word “anarchism” is

used by Proudhon in two senses: one is the ideal, the vision of a

society totally without coercion; the other is simply a form of

organization characterized by a preponderance of individual liberty.

Proudhon compromises the ideal of anarchism even further. He envisions a

society built largely on the principle of centralization, and his

federalism follows largely from the overt recognition that anarchy is

impossible. In realizing that a realistic solution of social problems

must start with a principle of federalism, he makes a realistic

compromise between anarchy and democracy.

3. Bakunin

No one has written such passionate criticisms of the State as Bakunin.

For him the State is an absolute evil:

“The State is an immense cemetery, the scene of the suicide, death and

burial of all manifestations of individual life or collective life —

briefly, of life. It is the altar for the sacrifice of liberty and

wellbeing, and the more complete this sacrifice is, the more perfect is

the State. The State is an abstraction which destroys the life of the

people.”

But the State, he insists, is a “historically necessary” evil, in the

same way that the bestiality of the first humans or the theological

imagination of men is necessary. But the State must disappear. It must

be replaced by a free society built on the basis of total autonomy;

starting with the small commune and building toward a worldwide union

joining all men. The relation between different organizations will no

longer be violent — it will be imposed not by law but by the free

consent of all. The voluntary commune — that is the source of Bakunin’s

social norms.

4. Kropotkin

Kropotkin, like his predecessors, accepts social norms in relations

between men, for example, the obligation to fulfill a freely accepted

contract. In “The Conquest of Bread,” for example, he deals extensively

with the objections to and false notion of anarchist communism. In his

answers he shows himself to be above all a humanist, believing more in

human nature than in logic. He correctly insists that the most effective

way to deal with antisocial behaviour is to find and remove the reasons

for its existence. Meanwhile, such problems as the refusal of some men

to work or the refusal to submit to a collective decision can appear

even in the most perfect society. In this case, the recalcitrant can

always be banished. But in a communist society this can be a terrible

punishment, even for the perpetrator of a despicable crime. Unless, of

course, the banished criminal simply finds another commune. We must find

other solutions.

5. Tucker and the Individualists

In his philosophical constructions, Tucker follows the reasoning of

Stirner and Proudhon. From Stirner he takes the principle of the

absolute sovereignty of the individual; from Proudhon he takes his

methods for achieving a free society constructed on the principle of

individual agreement.

Like all extreme individualists, Tucker rejects all imposed

organization. From there he launches a violent attack on the State:

“The State is the greatest criminal of our time. It acts not for the

defense of its most important unit, that is, the individual, but on the

contrary, to limit him, to oppress him, to attack him.”

Tucker vehemently criticizes all monopolies: government, the classes it

protects, money, laws. Against monopolies he opposes the principle of

unlimited competition:

“General and unlimited competition leads to absolute peace and true

cooperation.”

From there begins the battle of the anarchist individualists against

state socialism — they reproach it as being the victory of the mob over

the individual. Under state socialism power arrives at its culminating

point, monopolies wield their greatest power. At the same time, the

anarchist individualists fail to distinguish between state socialism and

anarchist commuism. For them, the latter is a phase in the development

of state socialist doctrine.

The characteristic trait of anarchist individualists is their acceptance

of private property. The problem they face is the following: can they

accept the monopoly of the individual over the product of his labor? If

they reply negatively, they give society the right to infringe upon the

individual. They have therefore chosen the other response and therefore

reintroduce the private ownership of land and the means of production.

From the principle of egoism as the sole motive force of men, Tucker

derives the law of equal liberty for all. The limit of the power of each

is found precisely in this egoism. The source of social norms based on

the will of all is the necessity to accept and honor the liberty of

each. Thus the anarchist individualists not only accept certain social

norms, but they tend to defend them.

Therefore, in anarchist individualism, as in anarchist communism, we are

faced with the tragic impossibility of resolving the incompatibility of

the individual and society, the choice between absolute individual

liberty or the necessity of a harmonious society.

If anarchism accepts this incompatibility, it turns to the principle

which is the proper basis of its theories: the principle of the equality

of all members within a free organization. If anarchism does not accept

this, it must then accept other social norms.

Conclusion

This article follows from the fact that anarchism is not an imaginary

dream, but a reality which gives logic and a realistic sense to the

revolt of the human spirit against violence. To be anarchist one does

not have to speak of fictions such as “absolute, unlimited liberty” and

the negation of duty and responsibility. The eternal contradiction, the

incompatibility of the individual and society, is insoluable, because it

is rooted in the nature of man himself, in his need for independence and

his need for society.

Let us openly admit that anarchism admits social norms. The norms of a

free society resemble neither in spirit nor in form the laws of

contemporary society, the bourgeois society, the capitalist society.

Neither do they resemble the decrees of a socialist dictatorship.

These norms will not seek the detachment of the individual from the

collectivity, neither will they serve such abstractions as a “common

good” to which the individual must sacrifice himself. Anarchist norms

will not be a torrent of decrees from a higher authority. They will1

come organically from the restlessness of the spirit which feels in

itself the force of creation, the thirst for the creative act, for the

realization of its desires in forms accessible to men.

The guarantee of this order of things will be the responsibility for our

own liberty and for the liberty of others. Like all social orders, it

will have to be defended. The concrete forms of this defense cannot be

indicated in advance. They will correspond to the concrete needs of the

society at the given moment.