💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › bob-black-justice-primitive-and-modern.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:54:55. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Justice, Primitive and Modern: Dispute Resolution in Anarchist and State Societies
Author: Bob Black
Language: en
Topics: justice, crime
Source: Source http://www.revoltlib.com/?id=3865, retrieved on December 2, 2020.
Notes: A much shorter, much different version of this article, under the title “Justice: Primitive and Modern,” was delivered as a speech at a B.A.S.T.A.R.D. Conference in Berkeley, California. Some years later, a closer version was delivered as a speech at the Pontifical and Royal University of Santo Tomas, under the auspices of its Philosophy Department, in Manila, Philippines on August 14, 2015. Among the others who have spoken at that site (the Thomas Aquinas Research Center) was then U.S. Secretary of State Hillary Rodham “Killary” Clinton. This version is thoroughly revised, greatly expanded, and referenced. The material on Restorative Justice is new.

Bob Black

Justice, Primitive and Modern: Dispute Resolution in Anarchist and

State Societies

I. INTRODUCTION

In all societies, there’s some trouble between people. Most societies

have processes for resolving disputes. These include negotiation,

mediation, arbitration and adjudication.[1] In their pure forms,

negotiation and mediation are voluntary. Arbitration and adjudication

are involuntary. The voluntary processes are typical of anarchist

societies, since anarchist societies are voluntary societies. The

involuntary processes are typical of state societies. In all societies

there are also self-help remedies.[2] These are often effective, but

they only provide justice when might and right happen to coincide. In

primitive societies, justice is not the highest priority.

The voluntary processes deal with a dispute as a problem to be solved.

They try to reach an agreement between the parties which restores social

harmony, or at least keeps the peace. The involuntary processes

implicate law and order, crime and punishment, torts, breaches of

contracts, and in general, rights and wrongs. The difference interests

me, among other reasons, because I’m an anarchist who lives in a statist

society. I’m also a former lawyer.

Most modern anarchists are ignorant of how disputes are resolved in

stateless primitive societies. And they rarely talk about how disputes

would be resolved in their own modern anarchist society. This is a major

reason why anarchists aren’t taken seriously. I have a lesson for the

anarchists. But I also have a lesson for modern legal reformers. Using

examples, I’ll discuss disputing in several primitive stateless

societies. Then I’ll discuss an attempt to reform the American legal

system which was supposedly inspired by the disputing process used in

one African tribal society. The idea was to insert mediation into the

bottom layer of the U.S. legal system at the discretion of judges and

prosecutors. It was a failure. I will come to the conclusion that you

can’t graft an essentially voluntary procedure onto an essentially

coercive legal system.

If I’m right, the case for anarchy is strengthened at its weakest point:

how to maintain a generally safe and peaceful society without a state.

Many anthropologists have remarked upon this achievement.[3] Few

anarchists have. The controversy over anarchist “primitivism” has been

almost entirely pointless, because it goes off on such issues as

technology, population, and the pros and cons of various cultural

consequences of civilization (religion, writing, money, the state, the

class system, high culture, etc.). The possibility that certain

structural features of primitive anarchy might be viable in – indeed,

may be constitutive of -- any anarchist society, primitive or modern,

has received no attention from any anarchist. Primitivists urge

anarchists to learn from the primitives[4] -- but learn what? How to

build a sweat lodge?

II. FORMS OF DISPUTE RESOLUTION

When a conflict arises between individuals – whether or not it later

draws in others – initially, and usually, it may be resolved privately

by discussion. Negotiation, a bilateral procedure, is undoubtedly a

universal practice[5]: “It is the primary mode of handling major

conflicts in many simple societies throughout the world.”[6] In the

terminology I adopt here,[7] where a conflict is resolved by

negotiation, there has been a conflict but not a dispute. There is first

a grievance: someone feels wronged. If she expresses her grievance to

the wrongdoer, she makes a claim. If she gets no satisfaction, she has

several alternatives. She may take unilateral action, actively or

passively. The active way, “self-help,” is to coerce or punish the

wrongdoer, but, sadly, that is often not feasible.[8] Nonetheless, where

real alternatives scarcely exist, as in the Inner City, some people

resort to violent unilateral retaliation.[9] The passive way is “lumping

it”: caving: doing nothing.[10] This is how many grievances, instead of

rising to the level of disputes, fall into oblivion: “You can’t fight

city hall” or various other too-powerful oppressors. Lumping it –

avoidance -- may also be universal, but it’s especially common in the

simplest and in the most complex societies: among hunter-gatherers and

in statist class societies with vast power disparities.[11]

As useful as negotiation can be, it doesn’t always work. It doesn’t

always produce agreement. Dyads may deadlock. Whereas in a triad, the

decision might be made by majority rule, or through mediation.[12] Or

feelings may run so high that the parties may refuse to talk to each

other, or if they do, the talk may turn violent.[13] And negotiation

isn’t always fair, because disputants are never exactly equal. If one

party has a more forceful personality, or a higher social status, or

more wealth, or more connections, if there is a settlement of the

dispute, it is likely to favor him unduly. Among the rationales for

involving a third party – whether a mediator, an arbitrator, or a judge

– is to equalize the process by bringing in a participant who is

impartial and independent. However, impartiality is the ideal but not

always the reality of mediation. [14] The third party may also serve as

a face-saving device for acquiescence in a settlement which, if

negotiated bilaterally, might appear to be (and might actually be) a

surrender to the other side.

If the victim (as he sees himself) voices her grievance to third

parties, now there is a dispute which implicates, if only in a minor

way, the interests of society. A dispute is an “activated complaint.”

[15] The appeal, whether explicit or implicit, depending on the

individual and the society, might mean calling the police, filing a

lawsuit, or just complaining to people you know. It might mean going to

court – the court of law or the court of public opinion. Mediation

(voluntary) and adjudication (compulsory) are distinguishable from

negotiation and self-help inasmuch as they necessarily involve a third

party who has no personal interest in the outcome of the dispute.[16]

Mediation could be considered assisted negotiation.[17]

Some primitive societies -- especially the smallest-scale societies, the

hunter-gatherers – have no customary dispute resolution processes. There

is not only no authority, there is no procedure for resolving disputes

or facilitating settlements: no mediator or arbitrator.[18] Thus, among

the Bushmen, interpersonal quarrels usually arise suddenly and publicly,

in camp. They range from arguments and mockery to fighting, which is

usually restrained by others who are present, but which occasionally

turns deadly. But if the dispute gives rise to ongoing enmity between

individuals (and their associates), often one of the disputants moves

away to join another band (this often happens anyway); or sometimes the

local band separates into two.[19] This is typical for hunter-gatherer

societies,[20] such as the Eskimos.[21] These might be considered active

forms of lumping it. In some other foraging societies, including some in

Australia, avoidance or exile are possible outcomes of formal disputing

processes.

In more complex class societies, avoidance (or, from organizations:

“exit”[22]) is also common. Thus American suburbia has been called an

“avoidance culture.”[23] But in modern urban society, avoidance can be

more difficult. Battered wives, for instance, are not always in a

position to move out. And avoidance, even where practicable, may be just

bowing to superior force. The absence of a formalized dispute resolution

process is arguably why the Kalahari Bushmen, when studied in the 1960s,

had an even higher homicide rate than the United States at that

time.[24] One ethnographer describes a New Guinea society where, in his

opinion, the absence of third-party dispute resolution processes is why

a dispute over a pig could escalate into a war.[25] Nonetheless, some

primitive societies which lack even these mechanisms are reasonably

orderly and peaceful.[26]

In arbitration, the parties (or the plaintiff) empower a third party to

hand down an authoritative decision, as a judge does.[27] It’s not

mediation: “Mediation and arbitration have conceptually nothing in

common. The one involves helping people to decide for themselves; the

other involves helping people by deciding for them.”[28]

But arbitration is not adjudication either, because of several

differences. In adjudication, the decision-maker is an official, an

officeholder who is not chosen by the parties. There, the third party

decides according to law – a law which is not of the parties’ own making

and which is not, for them, a matter of choice. In the United States,

some business contracts and many collective bargaining agreements

provide for arbitration. Arbitrators are usually drawn from a body of

trained experts, the American Arbitration Association, which is a

membership organization with codes of professional standards.[29] Often

the arbitrator has some expertise in the industry.[30] The arbitrator

interprets and enforces a law which the parties have previously made for

themselves.

Because arbitration is coercive in its result, and better for those with

more power than for those with less, from the1980s, many businesses have

incorporated mandatory arbitration clauses into consumer contracts so as

to restrict consumer remedies and keep consumers out of the courts.[31]

One Federal Circuit Court held that such contracts are unconscionable

and therefore illegal.[32] The problem became so serious that many

Congressional hearings were held.[33] Nothing resulted. In 2010, the

U.S. Supreme Court upheld consumer arbitration clauses which preclude

judicial review.[34] As a (predictable) result, “few plaintiffs pursue

low-value claims and super repeat-players perform particularly

well.”[35]

Sooner or later, Alternative Dispute Resolution (ADL) is always

co-opted: usually sooner.

However, in primitive societies, arbitration is rare,[36] so I will not

be discussing it any further. If anarchists ever bother to think about

such things, they might consider whether there’s a place for arbitration

in their blueprints for the future. The more complex, hierarchic and

coercive their societies may be, the better suited they would be to

compulsory arbitration: bringing the state back in, on the sly. I am

thinking, in particular, of anarcho-syndicalism .

In adjudication, a dispute – a “case” – is initiated by a complainant in

court. In criminal cases, the complainant is the state, not a private

party, but for present purposes, the difference from civil cases doesn’t

matter. The court is a previously constituted, standing tribunal. Court

proceedings are initiated voluntarily by a public official or a private

party, but after that, although the litigants still make some choices,

they are subject to pre-existing rules of procedure and the decisions of

the judge. They are always subject to the pre-existing laws of the

state.[37] Characteristic features of adjudication as an ideal stress

“the use of a third party with coercive power, the usually ‘win or lose’

nature of the decision, and the tendency of the decision to focus

narrowly on the immediate matter in issue as distinguished from a

concern with the underlying relationship between the parties.”[38] In

short: “Judges do not merely give opinions; they give orders.”[39]

In adjudication (litigation) the case is decided by a judge who doesn’t

know the parties. He doesn’t care about the background of the dispute.

He is not interested in repairing the relationship between the parties,

if they had one. He is not supposed to consider those matters. The judge

should be impartial and disinterested, deciding the cases on the basis

of the parties presenting “proofs and reasoned arguments.”[40] His

decision “must rest solely on the legal rules and evidence adduced at

the hearing.”[41] Rules of evidence, which are more numerous and complex

in the United States than in any other legal system, narrowly

circumscribe the admission of evidence, especially at trial. Resolutions

of cases arising from interpersonal disputes are “constrained in their

scope of inquiry by rules of evidence . . . “[42] U.S. courts are

designedly better, in the terminology of Donald L. Horowitz, at

identifying the “historical facts” of the particular case (whodunit)

than the “social facts” which might be illustrative of the general

circumstances which regularly give rise to cases like the one at

bar.[43]

That doesn’t mean that courts are very good at that either. Poverty is

never put on trial; poor people are put on trial. But the courts,

despite the title of a book by a reform-minded judge,[44] are never on

trial. It isn’t difficult to show that the ideal of the rule of law,

thus institutionalized, is a failure even on its own terms. Anarchists

and others have shown that repeatedly.

My main topic is mediation as practiced in more or less primitive

societies, and its implications for contemporary anarchism. I emphasize

that mediation is voluntary. The parties choose to submit their dispute

to a mediator, not for a ruling, but for help. They, or the complainant,

may select the mediator, or he might be “appointed by someone in

authority, [but] both principals must agree to his intervention.”[45]

Mediation is not primarily concerned with enforcing rules, although, the

parties may cite rules to support their positions. In mediation, unlike

adjudication, there is no such thing as irrelevant or inadmissible

evidence.[46] The purpose of mediation is not to identify who is to

blame, although the parties will do lots of blaming. The purpose of

mediation is not to enforce pre-existing rules, although the parties

will usually invoke rules. The purpose of mediation is rather to solve

an interpersonal problem which, unresolved, will probably become a

social problem.

These forms of dispute resolution I am describing are ideal types. One

legal philosopher, Lon L. Fuller, insists that they should be kept

distinct because each has its own “morality.” Often in reality they are

not so pure (such as the Ifugao example which follows, which Fuller was

accordingly unable to understand[47]). Even the distinction between

voluntary and involuntary processes, which I consider so important, is

often not a bright-line distinction. Power is insinuated into many

relationships which are not officially or overtly coercive.[48] If

consent can be a matter of degree, nonetheless, one may ask “what

proportion of nonconsensuality is implied in such a power relation, and

whether that degree of nonconsensuality is necessary or not, and then

one may question every power relation to that extent.”[49]

One inevitable consequence of involving a third party is that a third

party always has his own agenda.[50] That is not necessarily a bad

thing. American arbitrators of business/business and labor/management

disputes are chosen and paid by the disputants, and they might lose

their business if they are perceived to be biased or –so to speak –

arbitrary. Elsewhere, the third party facilitator might be a socially

prominent tribal mediator who strives to build a reputation as a

successful problem-solver (bringing in more mediation business -- for

which he, too, is paid[51]). Or he might be an American judge looking to

be re-elected, or aspiring to higher office.

Undoubtedly “every process, every institution has its characteristic

ways of operating; each is biased toward certain types of outcomes; each

leaves its distinctive imprint on the matters it touches.”[52]

Third-party dispute deciders or resolvers are usually of higher social

status than the disputants.[53] That may be essential to their

effectiveness: they have to be taken seriously. Obviously, mediation on

these terms may not be something to be imported, as-is and unthinkingly,

into a neo-anarchist society. But unless it can be imported thinkingly,

into an egalitarian society which not only tolerates, but encourages

excellence – and therefore a measure of inequality -- mediation will

never be as effective as it could be.

III. CASE STUDIES.

I’ll begin with examples from the ethnographic literature.

A. THE PLATEAU TONGA.I will usually not provide detailed page

citations to ethnographic sources. For the Plateau Tonga, my sources

are: E. Colson, “Social Control and Vengeance in Plateau Tonga Society”;

Elizabeth Colson, The Plateau Tonga of Northern Rhodesia: Social and

Religious Studies (Manchester, England: Manchester University Press,

1962) (the “Social Control” article is chapter 3, at 102-121); Elizabeth

Colson, “The Plateau Tonga of Northern Rhodesia,” in Seven Tribes of

British Central Africa , ed. Elizabeth Colson & Max Gluckman

(Manchester, England: Manchester University Press, 1951), 94-162.

I begin with a true story about a conflict which arose among the Plateau

Tonga of what is now Zambia. Traditionally they were shifting

cultivators and herdsmen. In 1948, they were a dispersed, partly

displaced, and rather demoralized population of farmers and herders.

Europeans had taken some of their best land. At a beer party, Mr. A, who

was drunk, slugged Mr. B. These men belonged to different clans and

lived in different villages. Unexpectedly, and unfortunately, after

several days, Mr. B died.

This was a stateless society. But there were social groups whose

interests were directly affected by this homicide. The Tonga are

matrilineal. For most purposes, a person’s most important affiliation is

with a limited number of matrilineal relatives. This is the group which

receives bridewealth when its women marry, and it’s the group which

inherits most of his property when a man dies. It’s also the group

that’s responsible for paying compensation for the person’s offences,

and for exacting vengeance.

The father’s matrilineal group (which, by definition, is different from

the son’s), is also an interested party. It is also liable for a

member’s offenses, but to a lesser extent, and it also inherits from

him, although it gets a smaller share than the matrilineal kin-group. By

killing Mr. B, Mr. A did an injury to Mr. B’s group. For several

reasons, Mr. B’s group didn’t take vengeance on Mr. A or, if they

couldn’t get at him, against one of his relatives. If it did, a blood

feud would result, with back and forth killings until everybody got sick

of it. Another reason for not taking vengeance is that the

British-imposed court system would have arrested the avenger. Mr. A

himself was in fact arrested, convicted of manslaughter, and sent to

prison.[54]

But that didn’t square things between the kin groups. Mr. B’s group had

lost a member and it demanded compensation.

The kin groups were intermarried. They also lived among one other. The

Tonga lived in very small villages of about 100 people. Most villagers

were not members of the same core kin group. But their fellow villagers

were some of their friends, and they were some of the people they worked

with. The villagers, as neighbors, also had an interest in a peaceful

resolution of the dispute.

Before Mr. B died, the A group had made apologetic and conciliatory

overtures to the B group. But after he died, all communication ceased.

The matter had become too serious. This caused a lot of trouble for many

people, especially if they had ties to both groups. Ordinary social life

was disrupted. Even husbands and wives might stop speaking to each

other, because they were often related to different, and now hostile,

kin groups. Something had to be done.

Mr. C, a prominent member of A’s group, found a go-between who was

related by marriage to both groups. All along, B’s group admitted that

Mr. B was obviously the wrongdoer. He had a reputation as a

troublemaker. Nobody was sorry when he went to prison. B’s group’s

concern was how much compensation it would have to pay. The case had to

end with payment of compensation. A feud was inconceivable, because so

many people in each group were related to people in the other group, and

the groups were intermarried. It was these cross-cutting ties that made

everybody want a generally acceptable settlement. In modern societies,

usually these ties don’t exist.

The anthropologist, Elizabeth Colson, doesn’t report the specifics of

the settlement. Because it doesn’t matter. She wrote an article about

this because she’d published a general account of Plateau Tonga society,

and some of her readers just couldn’t understand how there could be

anything but anarchy under a system of, well, anarchy.[55]

B. THE IFUGAO.Barton, Ifugao Law ; R.W. Barton, Autobiographies of

Three Pagans in the Philippines (New Hyde Park, NY: University Books,

1963) (originally 1938); R.W. Barton, The Half-Way Sun (New York: Brewer

& Warren, 1930); R.W. Barton, The Kalingas: Their Institutions and

Customary Law (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1949) (not

primarily about the Ifugao, but with frequent comparisons to them); E.

Adamson Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man: A Study in Comparative Legal

Dynamics (Cambridge & London: Harvard University Press, 2006), ch. 6

(originally 1954).

About 35 years earlier, the situation would have been dealt with in a

somewhat different way by the Ifugao of northern Luzon. They were

stateless, pagan wet-rice cultivators. And headhunters. They were

anarchists too, but their society was more stratified than Tonga

society. An American, Roy Barton, taught school there from 1906 to 1917.

His predecessor had been speared. He learned the language and wrote a

well-respected book on Ifugao law. I’ll be speaking in the present

tense, what anthropologists call “the ethnographic present.” But the

story is based on evidence of practices in the period before 1903,

before American authority became effective in the highlands. Spanish

authority had never been effective in the highlands.

Let’s assume the same situation as among the Tonga: an unintentional

killing by a drunken man. Drunken brawls among young men occurred among

the Ifugao too. If the killing had been intentional, the kin group of

the victim would have killed the wrongdoer.[56] If they couldn’t get at

the wrongdoer himself, they would kill one of his relatives. The result

is a blood feud. A death for a death, until the groups get sick of it.

But an unintentional killing by a drunk would usually be resolved by

mediation resulting in the payment of compensation by the one kin group

to the other.

The aggrieved party, or in this case one of his relatives, initiates the

process. The plaintiff would recruit a go-between, known as a mankulun.

The only restriction is that the mediator not be closely related to

either party. The mediator would be a relatively wealthy man, usually a

successful headhunter. He was preferably somebody with experience

mediating disputes. He could also recruit more support from relatives

and dependents than most people could do. If he arranges a settlement,

he is paid a fee by the defendant, and his prestige is enhanced. And

like everybody else, he wants the matter to be settled peacefully.

In theory, the defendant is free to reject mediation. In practice, the

mankulun makes him an offer he can’t refuse. If the defendant won’t

listen to him, “the monkalun waits until he ascends into his house,

follows him, and, war-knife in hand, sits in front of him and compels

him to listen.” The defendant is well aware that the mediator has used

knives -- maybe this very knife -- to cut off heads. He accepts

mediation.[57]

Once that happens, the parties and their relatives are forbidden to talk

to each other. Whatever they have to say to each other, has to go

through the mankulun, even if it has nothing to do with the dispute. I

think this is very ingenious. It keeps the parties from getting into

angry arguments and making matters worse. It makes it possible for the

mediator to manipulate everybody for their own good. The conflict

imposes a social cost on the village, because it disrupts the ordinary

social relations and the economic cooperation between members of the kin

groups, as it did among the Plateau Tonga. So it’s in the interest of a

lot of the local people to have the case resolved. However, separation

of the parties is not a typical feature of mediation in primitive

societies.[58]

One group of people who especially desire a settlement is people who are

related to both parties. The closest kin really have to side with their

kinsman, but they don’t have to like it. But those who aren’t so closely

related to one side will be severely criticized if they take sides in

the dispute. They want a settlement on almost any terms.

The mediator is a go-between. But he’s not just relaying messages. He

actively shapes the settlement as it eventually emerges. Mediators

almost always do that. I’ll quote from Barton again, because this

quotation often appears in books about the anthropology of law.

“To the end of peaceful settlement, he exhausts every art of Ifugao

diplomacy. He wheedles, coaxes, flatters, threatens, drives, scolds,

insinuates. He beats down the demands of the plaintiff or prosecution,

and bolsters up the proposals of the defendants until a point be reached

at which the two parties may compromise.” It’s part of the game that the

defendant initially refuses a settlement offer. These are proud people.

Even a defendant who’s obviously in the wrong is expected to be

truculent for awhile. He’s saving face. These are my kind of people. In

another society, “Even where a principal’s claim is very strong and the

balance of bargaining power lies with him, he commonly makes some effort

to show tolerance and good will by giving way to his opponent in at

least some small degree.”[59]

However, if the mediator thinks that the defendant is being unreasonable

for too long, he may formally withdraw from the case. For the next two

weeks, the parties and their kin can’t engage in hostilities. After the

truce expires, retaliation, which may include revenge killings,

commences. Nobody wants that. Usually the defendant backs down. But not

always. It’s possible to start over with a new mediator. But this won’t

go on endlessly. In another book, Ralph Barton mentions a case where the

defendant deserted his wife and refused to pay compensation to her

kinsmen. He rejected the settlements negotiated by four mediators. The

plaintiff’s kin then speared him. The defendant’s family didn’t do

anything about that.[60]

This is not the only way the Ifugaos cope with conflicts, or fail to. A

serious crime among family intimates (such as theft, or even homicide,

between brothers) is likely to go unpunished. Disputes are between, not

within groups. A group can’t punish itself or claim compensation from

itself. This is also the situation in some other primitive societies.

But it is also true that in legally ordered state societies, law is

least effective in regulating intimate relationships, those among people

with the least “relational difference.”[61]

The Ifugao mediation procedure which I’ve described is also increasingly

inactive as the relational difference among the disputants increases

beyond local, more or less face to face social networks so as to

implicate people who are more distant socially and geographically. Ralph

Barton described the Ifugaos – who were not an especially peaceable

people – as occupying concentric “war zones” radiating outwards. As

disputes crossed the borders of zones, they became more serious, and

more likely to be resolved by violence. In the outermost zone, the word

“dispute” hardly applies. There, anybody you don’t know is an enemy, to

be killed on sight. There is no doubt that primitive societies in

general have often failed to establish mechanisms for the resolution of

intergroup conflicts the more closely these approximate war.

But again, this is where states have also conspicuously failed, despite

the United Nations, “international law,” etc. They often lack the common

ground, the middle ground on which to base resolutions of disputes. We

are at our worst at solving our problems when we are either too close,

or too far apart. “The relationship between law and relational distance

is curvilinear”: “Law is inactive among intimates, increasing as the

distance between people increases but decreasing as this reaches a point

at which people live in entirely separate worlds.”[62] “This double

conception of morality,” wrote Kropotkin, in tranquil late Victorian

England, “passes through the whole evolution of mankind, and maintains

itself now.” He added that if Europeans had in some measure “extended

our ideas of solidarity – in theory at least – over the nation, and

partly over other nations as well -- we have lessened the bonds of

solidarity within our own nations, and even within our own

families.”[63] In 1914, like many other thoughtful people, he was

shocked to discover how tenuous international solidarity really was.

IV. MULTIPLEX RELATIONSHIPS.

Now I will get a bit theoretical. There’s something about these disputes

which makes them different from many disputes in modern societies. In a

modern urban society, in a dispute there’s usually only one social

relation between the parties. Each party plays a single role. Usually,

for instance, your landlord doesn’t also know you from church or at

work. Your employer isn’t your relative, except in the Philippines. Your

landlord is not your friend. The anthropologist Max Gluckman called

these relationships, simplex relationships.[64] American suburbanites,

for example, share few ties, and “even while they exist, most suburban

relationships encompass only a few strands of people’s lives.”[65]

But in primitive societies, which are anarchist societies, if you get

into a dispute with someone, he might be playing multiple roles in your

life. You have a multiplex relationship. Someone may be your brother in

law, your creditor, your workmate and your neighbor. This is someone you

probably encounter often in your everyday life. These multiple roles may

multiply occasions for conflict. But they also motivate both of you

resolve the conflict, because all these relationships taken together are

probably more important than whatever the dispute is about. And there

are typically a lot of other people who have an interest in a peaceful

settlement. This is what Gluckman calls a multiplex relationship. He

also argued that the more activities the disputants share, the more

likely is it for the dispute to be handled in a more conciliatory than

authoritative fashion.[66]

There’s a seeming paradox here. In complex societies, simplex

relationships predominate. In simpler societies, multiplex relationships

prevail. In Tonga and in Ifugao country, there were a lot of

cross-links. There were many people with ties to both sides. And there

was no state to impose law and order. Instead, the social organization

provided very powerful inducements to make peace.

V. FORMS OF DISPUTE RESOLUTION

What’s a dispute? I’ll adopt a definition used by some (not all) social

scientists. A dispute begins with a grievance. Someone feels she has

been wronged. She may complain to the wrongdoer. They might resolve the

matter. Up to this point, it’s been a completely private matter. But if

they don’t agree, and the victim goes public with the matter, then

there’s a dispute. Depending on the society, going public might mean

calling the police, filing a lawsuit, or just complaining to people you

know.

Negotiation is a two-party, bilateral form of dispute resolution. It

probably exists everywhere. But, it isn’t the solution to every problem.

A dyad can be deadlocked. Very often, as we saw, the involvement of a

third party is helpful. My main objective tonight is to contrast

mediation with adjudication. My focus is mediation. Mediation is

appropriate to anarchist societies. You find adjudication usually in

state societies.

I will define mediation as a disputing process which is, above all,

voluntary. It’s one where the parties choose to submit a dispute to a

mediator, not for a decision, but for help. It’s not primarily concerned

with enforcing rules, although, the parties may invoke rules. The

mediator’s purpose isn’t to identify somebody to blame, although the

parties will do lots of blaming. The purpose is to solve a problem. This

is an ideal type. Ifugao mediation isn’t quite pure, because it isn’t

commenced in a purely voluntary way. But it’s much purer than what was

later attempted in the United States.

I will define adjudication as when a dispute -- a case -- is initiated

by a grievant in a court. A court is a permanent, pre-existing tribunal.

It’s compulsory. Cases are decided by a judge who doesn’t know the

parties. He isn’t interested in repairing the relationship between the

parties, if they have one. He doesn’t care what the background of the

dispute might be. He’s not supposed to consider those things. He decides

the case according to the laws of the state. Usually, if the case goes

to trial, the judgment is that someone is “guilty” or not guilty of a

crime, or that someone is or is not “at fault” in a civil case. Usually,

one party wins and the other party loses. In mediation there aren’t

supposed to be any winners or losers.

That’s the ideal of adjudication. I could criticize it as a description

of the American legal system, and, I suspect, every legal system.

Adjudication doesn’t even live up to its own ideal. But I don’t even

like the ideal version. Instead, I want to discuss what can happen when

mediation is inserted into an adjudication system, supposedly as a legal

reform.

VI. THE POLITICS OF INFORMAL JUSTICE.

A. Solutions in Search of Problems

In the 1960s, there was a tremendous amount of social and political

conflict in the United States. Black people, women, poor people,

students, prisoners, radicals and other people made demands on American

society. By my definition, these were “disputes.” The courts were

recognizing many new rights. Alarmed lawyers spoke of a “rights

revolution.”

Now how did the legal establishment and the college professors react to

this? They decided that the courts had heavy caseloads. The way to

reduce their caseloads was by somehow preventing people from taking

their supposedly minor disputes to court. As a point of fact, there is

no evidence that most courts had heavy caseloads.[67] Many lawsuits are

filed, but few of them come to trial. Americans mostly go out of their

way not to initiate litigation.

So, just when the downtrodden started to claim rights through

adjudication, the legal establishment decided that we needed new,

informal, ways of rapidly processing the minor disputes of minor people.

There was nothing new about this ploy. 50 years before, “small claims

court” was created to decide cases which were too small for lawyers to

bother with. It was supposed to provide fast, inexpensive justice,

without a lot of legal technicalities, usually without the involvement

of lawyers. They called the small claims court the “people’s court.” The

plaintiffs were supposed to be the humble people. But small claims court

was really an eviction service for landlords and a collection agency for

ghetto businesses. The people who were supposed to be the plaintiffs

were usually the defendants.

So, in the 1980s, Richard Danzig, a scholar from the RAND

Corporation,[68] proposed a new conflict resolution mechanism. He called

for a “complementary, decentralized criminal justice system.” By

“complementary,” he meant that it was a supplement to the judicial

system, not a replacement for it. He said that the new structures

shouldn’t be subordinated to the judicial system. But how could the

systems co-exist unless one system was subordinated to the other? One or

the other has to decide which system has jurisdiction over which cases.

Obviously the courts would make that decision, because that’s where

cases start.

Danzig’s model was the system employed by the Kpelle in Liberia. [69] He

called it a moot. He got this from an anthropologist named James L.

Gibbs, Jr.[70] The word refers to Anglo-Saxon assemblies whose

composition is somewhat uncertain and whose procedures are totally

unknown.[71] Gibbs Jr. described a relatively informal proceeding which

was attended by the kinsmen and neighbors of the parties. The problem is

usually a domestic issue. The assembly is held at the home of the

complainant: home court advantage. Anybody can show up for it.

The complainant appoints the so-called mediator, who is a socially

important relative of his. That introduces bias right at the start.

Apparently the procedure is compulsory for the defendant. The parties

testify. They can cross-examine each other. They can cross-examine

witnesses. A party might have some respected or articulate supporter

speak for him. I’d call that person a lawyer.

Anybody can speak, but the mediator can impose a token fine on somebody

who, and I quote, “speaks out of turn.” (Meaning, standing for a round

of drinks.) The mediator also says what he thinks about the case. Then

he “expresses the consensus of the group.” But he doesn’t call for a

vote. The consensus is whatever he says it is. The party who is mainly

at fault is then required to formally apologize by providing token gifts

to the wronged person. Then he has to provide beer or rum for everyone

present. This isn’t mediation. It’s adjudication with a biased judge who

has more control over the temporary assembly than an American judge has

over a temporary jury. It’s court TV that isn’t filmed.

There is nothing resembling a moot in, for example, American

suburbia.[72] How do you approximate this institution in a modern city?

Here’s an example from Danzig himself. Suppose that there’s a juvenile

loitering around outside a store:

“If the complaint [to the police] were replaced by a moot discussion, to

which the teenager brought his friends, the shopkeeper and his

associates (including his family, other shopkeepers, his employees), and

the police officers working with juveniles, there would be a fair chance

for the kind of interchange which has proven valuable when staged as a

one-event ‘retreat’ in other communities.”[73]

If I were the teenager, I’d rather be arrested. Most of those other

people have absolutely no reason to waste their time on a trivial

problem that doesn’t concern them. Yet these ideas would inspire, or

justify anyway, the formation of Federally-funded Neighborhood Justice

Centers, which don’t even resemble Danzig’s idea of a moot, much less

Gibbs’ idea of a moot.

Their boosters proudly recounted: “Unlike small claims court and housing

court, these programs are not watered-down versions of real courts.

Their roots are not in Anglo-American jurisprudence, but in the African

moots, in socialist comrades courts, in psychotherapy and in labor

mediation.”[74] In point of fact, NJC mediation cases mostly originated

as criminal prosecutions in ordinary American criminal courts. The

reference to socialist (meaning: Communist) comrades’ courts is hardly

reassuring. They were coercive arms of authoritarian states. And

whatever else they accomplished in the way of dispute resolution, their

highest priority was always state security.[75] These courts have by new

been normalized, as the Russian, Chinese, and Cuban regimes have

reconciled with capitalism.

Originally, the establishment wanted alternatives to adjudication – for

other people. It wanted to limit access to the courts. The “litigation

explosion” quickly became a cliché. The courts were supposedly swamped,

mostly by the little people with their little problems. Surely alternate

dispute resolution (ADR) was the answer. The core ADR nostrum was

mediation.

A social science theory got into the picture. In the late 1960s, there

was a famous study, by the Vera Institute, of the processing of felony

cases in New York City. The politicians and the newspaper editors were

concerned about what they called the “deterioration” of these cases.[76]

This just means that very few cases went to trial. Look at what’s

happening! First the problem was supposed to be too many cases. Now the

problem was not enough cases. Somehow, it was concluded that these

problems had the same solution.

The study made the genuinely startling discovery that most felony

arrests involved people in some sort of prior relationship. Felonies are

the serious crimes in Anglo-American law, such as manslaughter, which is

what Mr. A was convicted of. For rape, 83% of arrests involved prior

relationships. For homicide, it was 50%. Felonious assault: 69%. Even

some property crimes fit the picture: 36% of robberies, and 39% of

burglaries. These are the cases that deteriorate. Often the complainant

and the defendant reconciled, because of their relationship. Or

witnesses didn’t show up for preliminary hearings. A complainant might

get somebody arrested, not to get him prosecuted, but just to harass him

for his bad behavior.

Now these continuing relationships weren’t usually multiplex

relationships. But they resemble them in one very important way. To the

disputants, their relationship is often more important than their

current dispute.

So, some academics therefore proposed that mediation was the best way to

deal with prior relationships cases. After all, in the anthropological

literature, offenses usually involved people in relationships, or at

least knew each other. So, let’s us mediate prior relationship cases

too. So said the U.S. Department of Justice, conservative judges,

several of the more intellectual members of the legal elite, and some

quasi-scholars at think tanks. All the new mediation agencies focused on

prior relationship cases.

B. Neighborhood Justice Centers

In the early 1970s, the call for ADL went out from no less than Warren

Burger, Chief Justice of the U.S. Supreme Court. Americans, he

declaimed, were too litigious, and so there was too much litigation.

They were wasting the precious time of judges (but, that’s what we pay

them for). The most powerful judge and lawyer in the United States – in

the world! -- repeatedly denounced judges and lawyers: but “[t]he

concerns were not with justice, but with harmonious relations, with

community, with removing ‘garbage cases’ from the courts. Nonjudicial

means were suggested as a means of dispute handling.”[77]

This was a neat trick. The rhetoric of the left – peace, love,

community, and harmony – was turned against it. And that worked, at

least to the extent that, although there was no popular demand or

support for ADL, neither was there any popular opposition to it. United

in support of the federal Dispute Resolution Act were, among others,

“the National Chambers of Commerce and Ralph Nader’s consumer advocates;

the Conference of Chief Justices and 1960s-style community activist

groups; and the American Bar Association and vociferous critics of

professionalism.”[78]

The U.S. Department of Justice financed three pilot programs in the late

1970s. These agencies were called Neighborhood Justice Centers, NJCs.

This was not in response to any grass-roots popular movement for court

reform. It was originated by the national government in response to

proposals by legal and judicial elites.[79] There was no concern for

rights or due process, only for smoothing over conflict.[80]

The claims on behalf of the as yet nonexistent NJCs were extravagant.

They were supposed to do all sorts of great things. Among other things:

They did none of these things.

1. They didn’t save any time or money. They didn’t save time, because

mediation involved lots of meetings, and it took longer than court

processing, whereas most cases deteriorate anyway before much time

passes. They didn’t save money either. Where there’s any evidence, as

for Dorchester, mediation was two or three times as expensive as

adjudication.[81] A later, multi-year, multi-million dollar study

concluded that there were no cost savings or time savings when

mediation, early neutral evaluation, and other devices were used after

legal proceedings commenced.[82] As late as 2005, there was no evidence

that mediation was cost-effective.[83]

2. They didn’t reduce judicial caseloads very much. Only a small number

of cases went to mediation. And many of them came back to court when

mediation failed. The vast majority of cases, civil and criminal, are

already resolved without trial or mediation. Anyway, if courts are such

a great idea, why is it so important to keep some people out of them? If

mediation is such a great idea, why not mediate almost everything, as is

done in many primitive societies?

3. Mediation didn’t promote community. Neighborhood Justice Centers

didn’t grow out of communities. They were inserted into them. Mediators

were mostly strangers from outside the community, of higher social

status and often of a different race (i.e., they were mostly white,

unlike most of the disputants).[84] Richard Danzig assumed a degree of

social solidarity which just doesn’t exist in impoverished urban slums,

or even in many other areas, such as suburbia.

In the Tonga, Ifugao and Kpelle examples, disputants came from villages

occupied by several hundred, mostly interrelated people. Everybody knew

everybody else, in person or by reputation. You rarely find that now in

urban (or suburban) areas of the United States: “In contemporary

mediation centers in the United States, few if any of these features of

mediation [as practiced in “small-scale societies”] will be found.”[85]

To approximate mediation in primitive societies, NJCs “must serve very

small populations rather than districts containing several thousand

residents who do not know one another nor expect to deal with one

another in the future.”[86] In Kansas City, the NJC was not located in a

neighborhood with a sense of solidarity and neighborliness. The “target

population” (a revealing phrase) was the inhabitants of a police patrol

area, approximately 53,000 people.[87]

The NJCs served so-called “neighborhoods” of tens of thousands of

people. Most of their residents knew very few of the other residents.

And most of the mediators weren’t from the neighborhood they worked

in.[88] A Kansas City prosecutor identified the targets: “poor white

trash,” not the deserving poor.[89] The parties didn’t choose the

mediator. That isn’t, strictly speaking, a requirement for mediation,

but it’s usually how it’s done in primitive societies where mediation is

more successful. Nor did the disputants have to approve the mediator,

who was simply assigned to their case. (Actually, it was usually several

mediators.) That is a requirement for mediation.

In a large, complex, socially differentiated society, where would

mediation work best? It would work best in stable, homogenous

communities of civic-minded people. In other words, rich white

neighborhoods or suburbs. A gated community would be ideal. In Boston,

they put the NJC in Dorchester, where people are working class or poor

or both. They should have put it in, for example, Brookline, which is a

wealthy Jewish suburb: a much more homogeneous community than

Dorchester. But for several reasons, they didn’t.

One reason is that the unstated purpose of the scheme was to pacify the

poor. The affluent don’t need to be pacified. A related reason is that

people in Brookline are satisfied with the regular court system. The law

functions to serve the interests of their kind of people. They are

mostly businessmen, landlords and professionals. In Brookline, mediation

would be a solution without a problem. In Dorchester, there’s a problem

without a solution.

This isn’t just speculation on my part. An NJC was set up in Suffolk

County, New York City suburbs which, like Brookline, are affluent,

white, and mostly Jewish. 40% of the cases were not resolved, usually

because the defendant wouldn’t participate. But that was a higher

success rate than in the other NJC’s.[90]

I’ll postpone Point Four, about how satisfying the experience was, for a

little later.

You will recall that Danzig wanted a “complementary” system. What

usually happened is that the courts used mediation to try to reduce

their caseloads. (Caseloads don’t have to be high for judges and

prosecutors to wish they were even lower and reduce their workload.)

Prosecutors had to agree each referral. Prosecutors often agreed to

reduce their caseloads by allowing what they consider “garbage cases” to

go to mediation. These were cases where they were not sure they would

win, or the cases weren’t worth their trouble. Most of these cases would

never have gone to trial.[91]

As one prosecutor explained: “Neighborhood justice is really handy

because it is like a garbage dump: they will take and deal with cases

which we simply are not set up to handle. I just like them because they

are handy. I wish I could get rid of more garbage that way.”[92]

So mediation was a way to widen the field of social control, which is

contrary to what some of its proponents expected.[93] NJC advocates

fancied that mediation would somehow facilitate de-legalization. But

systems of informal justice generally widen the net of social

control.[94]

Usually these programs made some provision for people to bring in their

own disputes for mediation, bypassing the court. But people didn’t do

that. In Dorchester, there were eight walk-ins in two years. In

court-ordered, prosecutor-approved mediation, mediators told the parties

that if mediation failed, the case would go back to court, and the judge

would be unhappy. The judge sent them to mediation because he never

wanted to see them again. If they came back, the defendant would be

viewed as uncooperative and unreasonable. The mediators were threatening

the defendant.[95] This is not a voluntary process.

NJCs were new, so, nobody had heard of them. The NJC in Los Angeles had

an aggressive outreach program. Over 50% of the cases were walk-ins.

Another one-third were referrals by courts or the police. The mediators

handled 50 cases a month, which is a very small number, in a city of

millions. I count it as success if the parties reach a mediated

agreement and comply with it. I consider it a failure if the case

doesn’t lead to a mediated agreement, or if that agreement isn’t

followed. Measured in this way, there were maybe 1,150 successes and

2,850 failures.[96]

I say “maybe” because the statistics are presented in misleading ways.

The investigators were advocates for NJCs. But they report that the

court-referred cases had an 82% success rate, where the genuinely

voluntary cases had a 14-36% success rate. Government coercion makes a

big difference.

What if an NJC accepted only walk-ins? I know of only one program like

that: the San Francisco Community Boards. It was also unusual in that

several of these Boards served somewhat smaller neighborhoods than is

usual. That’s where mediation works best, in theory. But their

populations ranged from 17, 117 to 105,592.[97] I lived in the biggest

neighborhood, Bernal Heights, for two years. I never heard of its

Community Board, although I had some neighbor conflicts, including one

lawsuit. All the Boards processed only 365 cases a year, in a city of

640,000 people. [98] The cost per referral was $750, as compared with

$350 in Dorchester.[99]

There were few cases, but many mediators: at any one time, 350-400

enthusiastic volunteers – usually more mediators than cases! They got a

lot of satisfaction out of mediation, which often served as “a vehicle

for personal growth” – for themselves.[100] That’s very California. Only

11% of their cases came from court referrals, possibly reducing court

caseloads by a few cases. But mediation was supposed to reduce caseloads

substantially. It had almost no effect on caseloads. It never does. In

Atlanta, for instance, the NJC received most of its cases from the

courts (nearly 50% were referred by court clerks, and almost 25% by

judges). But it processed, at most, 2% as many cases as the lower trial

courts.[101]

Community Boards are also exceptional in another, ironic way. They

rarely deal with prior-relationship cases.[102] That’s probably why they

are relatively successful.

The fundamental reason why studies claiming success for mediation can’t

be substantiated is that there is no control group. We know that judges

and prosecutors don’t randomly assign some cases to adjudication and

others to mediation. The garbage cases go to mediation. We’d like to

know what would happen if all cases remained in court. Everywhere, most

cases are dismissed before trial. One of my Berkeley professors studied

two lower trial courts in Connecticut. Those are the courts with

jurisdiction over misdemeanors, which are the less serious crimes. In a

2-month period, no cases went to trial. [103] Trials are rare, and

increasingly so, in state and Federal courts.[104]

The original three NJCs were financed by the U.S. Department of Justice.

Malcolm M. Feeley writes: “A proposal to treat these experimental

programs as true experiments and randomly assign would-be clients or

leave them to their own devices was explicitly and firmly rejected by

the Department of Justice.”[105] I have read only one study of a court

which did randomly assign some of the cases to the NJC. That was in

Brooklyn, New York – the study was privately funded by the Vera

Institute of Justice (the “continuing relationships” people) -- and it

dealt with felony cases, as had the Institute’s influential study of

arrest “deterioration,” Felony Arrests.

In the control group, 70% of cases were dismissed, or they were

adjourned in contemplation of dismissal. In the latter situation, the

case is postponed for 6 months, and if the defendant hasn’t gotten

arrested again, the case is dismissed.[106] That once happened to

me.[107] 3% of defendants were sentenced to jail terms, which means one

year or less, although they were arrested for felonies, which means

imprisonment for more than a year. Their charges were reduced. Only 1%

were referred to the grand jury, which decides whether there should be a

felony prosecution. Since the grand jury does not always indict

(although it usually does), that means that less than 1% of felony

arrests led to felony trials. Fewer still led to convictions, although I

assume that most trials resulted in convictions.

4. I return to Point Four (satisfaction). In the NJC group, only 56% of

the cases were mediated. In the other cases, the victim or the defendant

or both didn’t show up. Where mediation led to an agreement, the

participants reported higher satisfaction with the system than for the

court group, but the difference was not too great. These reports of high

satisfaction are worthless because they are based only on clients who

completed the mediation process. They ignore disputants who decided at

some point not to participate.[108] In Brooklyn, where there was random

assignment and a control group, mediation made some people feel better.

But “there was little evidence that mediation was more effective than

court adjudication in preventing recidivism during the four-month

follow-up period.”[109]

I have no objection to a process that makes people feel better, unless

they are being played. But there was little evidence that mediation had

fully or finally resolved the problems between the parties. This was

measured by how often new problems were reported by the plaintiff, by

the frequency of their calling the police again, and by arrests of

either party for a crime committed against the other party. There was no

significant difference between the mediation group and the court

group.[110] Although there are studies of how participants felt, I know

of only one study of whether they perceived the process as just or fair.

In Brooklyn, 88% thought that their mediation was fair, compared to 76%

who thought their adjudication was fair: not a big difference. And even

that is after more than 70% of the cases had been dismissed.[111]

Complainants are never asked if they feel the dismissal of their cases

was fair. The answer is obvious.

The final irony of the NJC debacle is this. Mediation was supposed to be

especially effective in prior-relationship cases. That was their main

selling point. But mediation is least effective in property disputes and

in disputes arising from longstanding relationships.[112]

C. The Prior History of Informal Justice in America

The NJC “movement” – if an elite-initiated, state-controlled phenomenon

can be called a movement – was not the first of its kind. It sought

alternatives to the regular court system. It sought procedural

informality. It sought to individualize justice. It sought non-punitive

dispositions which were conciliatory, rehabilitative, or even

therapeutic. It sought to get to the social “roots” of interpersonal

conflicts.

Most of these goals and methods were also among the goals and methods of

the Progressive-era juvenile-court movement, which was supposed to

humanize the official treatment of children who were causing trouble and

committing crimes. These troubled or troublesome children received a new

social identity: they were “juvenile delinquents.”[113] These youths

would be helped, and healed, by a fatherly juvenile court judge, by

social workers, and by “diversion” out of the regular criminal justice

system and prisons into custodial facilities tailored to their needs.

The juvenile justice system is now almost universally regarded as a

total failure.[114] And now, there are even proposals to combine these

failures! Mediation for juvenile delinquents![115] Actually, that would

be something like Richard Danzig’s absurd example, the loitering

juvenile.

Yet, the informal-justice reformers soldiered on. Their next reform was

small-claims courts:

The Small Claims Court movement has taken as its premise that small

cases are simple cases and that therefore a pared-down judicial

procedure is what is called for. Next to the juvenile court, there has

probably been no legal institution that was more ballyhooed as a great

legal innovation. Yet the evidence now seems overwhelming that that the

Small Claims Court has failed its original purpose; that the individuals

for whom it was designed have turned out to be its victims.[116]

One of the assumptions there was that “small” cases are simple cases

which do not require much judicial time or expertise. This assumption is

often false.[117] A seemingly simple case such as a landlord’s lawsuit

to evict a tenant for nonpayment of rent may implicate a complex body of

law – if the law were taken seriously. Small claims courts often have

jurisdiction over these summary eviction cases. But “the evidence now

seems overwhelming that the Small Claims Court has failed its original

purpose; that the individuals for whom it was designed have become its

victims.”[118] Small claims court is an eviction service for slumlords

and a collection agency for ghetto businesses. Nonetheless, small-claims

courts have been institutionalized everywhere. Once that happens, it no

longer matters whether the court serves its original purpose, or any

purpose. It always serves power and the servants of power.

A decade before the NJC movement, another court reform scheme, pre-trial

diversion, had some of the same goals as the NJC, with similar rhetoric

and rationale. But diversion programs rarely succeeded.[119] They were

optional for courts, and prosecutors had to consent to diversion. As

later with the NJCs, “many prosecutors came to regard diversion as an

alternative penalty for marginal offenders.”[120] What Feeley wrote in

1982 proved to be prophetic: “What pretrial diversion was to court

reform in the1970s, neighborhood justice or dispute settlement centers

are becoming in the 1980s. They are the new cure-all.”[121] Generally,

he writes, “criminal justice policy is often characterized by a

preoccupation with short-term outcomes and – all too often – with

gimmickry.”[122]

As far as I can tell, the NJC movement as such is extinct. Its “possible

demise” – and the reasons for it – were anticipated as early as

1982.[123] Something similar is now going on here and there, under other

names, such as “community mediation centers.” But in The Handbook of

Dispute Resolution, 546 pages, published in 2005, there is only one

sentence on neighborhood dispute resolution – in the article on “Roots

and Inspirations.”[124] NJCs are history.

I’ve come across self-congratulatory accounts of two mediation centers

which, as of 2013, were still in business.[125] One (the only one) in

Philadelphia, is operated by Roman Catholic nuns, and is described as a

“neighborhood justice center.” The other (also the only one there) is in

the Borough of Queens, New York City. Despite having “community” in

their names, these centers each service a catchment area of over three

million people. Both get most of their cases from court referrals or

other government referrals. The center in Queens annually receives 1,500

cases from courts and 500 walk-ins, which is the highest proportion of

walk-ins I know of anywhere, but 75% are still involuntary referrals.

Undoubtedly some people walk in to preempt prosecution or litigation.

Keeping even 2,000 cases out of the courts in Queens would have a very

small impact on court caseloads, even if we didn’t know what the author

doesn’t tell us: that many cases would not have gone to trial, and many

mediated cases return to court later. In Philadelphia, only 30% of

referrals were mediated at all, and surely these were not all success

stories. But the author of the article on the Philadelphia center is

right about one thing: “Conflict resolution is a growth industry.”[126]

Now there is a new cure-all: “Restorative Justice” (RJ). Not to keep you

in suspense, I will later conclude that, what pretrial diversion was to

court reform in the 1970s, and what neighborhood justice centers were to

court reform in the 1980s, restorative justice is since the 1990s. If a

new quack panacea has come along even more recently, I haven’t heard of

it yet.

VII. CONCLUSION FOR REFORMISTS

I conclude that in the short term, court-ordered mediation isn’t much

better, and maybe isn’t any better, than adjudication is in prior

relationship cases. It seems still more clear that, over a longer

period, it isn’t better at all. Mediation is probably keeping some cases

from going to court where the defendant might do better in adjudication.

In courts, you have some rights (although the rights of victims as such

are nonexistent or minimal, and rarely exercised[127]). In mediation,

you have no rights, and no lawyer. But you get a great big hug. And so

does the mediator.

The most common way to resolve chronic conflict in a relationship in an

urban society is to end the relationship, despite the costs and

hardships which may ensue.[128] Curiously, that’s also the most common

solution in the band societies of hunter-gatherers. Foragers don’t

remain for long in one place anyway. Individuals move away. Or, the

group splits and part of it moves away. But this isn’t always easy to do

in a modern urban society, where people are burdened with jobs, leases,

mortgages, etc.

I promised to provide two lessons. My lesson to legal reformers is:

disputing processes which work in primitive societies won’t usually work

in modern societies: “It may be difficult or impossible to transplant a

mode of conflict management between socially different settings.” [129]

The form -- mediation for instance – looks about the same. But the

social content and the social context are completely different. This is

equally true of the next reform to come along, Restorative Justice.

There are drastic differences between primitive and modern societies. In

primitive societies, individuals are imbedded in groups. Conflicts

between individuals almost always directly implicate the groups they

belong to.[130] There are usually some people with their own interests

at stake who actively involve themselves in resolving the problem. The

dispute is really between groups, and so is the mediation. In the NJCs,

a dispute was dealt with as a conflict between two individuals. The

Centers usually refused to bring in third parties. Probably that wasn’t

feasible. But that is only to say that NJC mediation wasn’t feasible.

Another drastic difference between primitive and modern societies is

that all primitive anarchist societies are more egalitarian than all

modern state societies. The very existence of the state establishes a

huge inequality. The criminal law treats certain disputes as between the

state and an individual accused of crime. No matter how many rights you

give the defendant, the state always has more power. And for many years,

American courts have been reducing the rights of those suspected or

accused of crime.[131] The state decides whether to respect those

rights, and the police, the prosecutor, and the judge are all part of

the state. I mentioned that the prosecutor had a veto on sending cases

to mediation. The prosecutor never participates in mediation.

These state societies are also class societies. The state always upholds

social hierarchy. The state is a social hierarchy. But some of the most

important personal and interpersonal problems are rooted in the economy

and the social structure. The parties are often unequal in wealth and

power. Tenants and landlords, husbands and wives, businesses and

consumers, bosses and workers -- they’re usually not equal. Pretending

that they’re equal doesn’t equalize them. People who are unequal before

they enter the legal system will still be unequal when they leave

it.[132] But maybe the weaker party got a warm fuzzy feeling from the

nice mediator listening to her problems. She might feel better for

awhile. It doesn’t mean that she received justice. At best, for awhile,

she may just think she did. But there is no evidence even of that.

Justice is not, for me, the highest social value. Mine is freedom. I am

all for justice, but the conditions required for freedom take priority.

No kind of Alternate Dispute Resolution even purports to enhance

freedom. And I doubt that ADR delivers justice any more than does

traditional adjudication, which itself is far from living up to the

promise of – these words are inscribed on the U.S. Supreme Court

building – equal justice under law.

VIII. THE INCOMPLETE ANARCHIST CRITIQUE OF CRIMINAL LAW.

Anarchists have a lot of excuses for their unpopularity. They’ve

suffered military and police repression. In the newspapers, as in the

history books, they’re either lied about or ignored. They get very

resentful about the stereotype of the bomb-throwing anarchist. Some

people are rude to them. Others mock them. It’s so unfair.

Bombing-throwing? We stopped doing that weeks ago. (Except in Athens.

I’ve seen videos.)

However, even if anarchists don’t throw bombs, some people do. Even

fair-minded people reasonably ask: if there’s no state, who will protect

us from aggressors and predators? The article I first discussed, about

the Plateau Tonga, was written for the express purpose of answering that

question.

The traditional anarchist answer is obviously inadequate. The anarchists

say that by abolishing private property, we eliminate almost all reasons

for people to quarrel. My examples -- the Plateau Tonga, the Ifugao, and

the Kpelle -- refute that argument. The vast majority of cases in the

Kpelle moot, for instance, involved conjugal disputes and rights over

women.[133] There are primitive anarchist societies, the

hunter-gatherers, which have even less property. The Bushmen, for

instance, were until recently, to put it bluntly, communists.[134] They

rarely quarreled over property, because they hardly had any. But they

did quarrel. Their homicide rate in the 1960s was even higher than the

American homicide rate in the 1960s.[135] Peter Kropotkin, in the 1890s,

praised the Bushmen as friendly, benevolent and generous: they “used to

hunt in common, and divided the spoil without quarreling; . . . “[136]

Food sharing is an aspect of the “generalized reciprocity” which is a

universal feature of hunter-gatherer society.[137] The Bushmen worked

cooperatively and shared food communally. But Kropotkin was mistaken to

assume that, consequently, they never quarreled. Work and food are not

the only things which people quarrel about. It is the same mistake

Kropotkin made about future communist anarchist society.

Kropotkin characterized the Papuans, also, as “primitive

communists.”[138] They are of course also anarchists. But in at least

one Papuan society, a dispute over a pig can escalate into a war.[139]

Communism + anarchy ≠ perpetual peace.

Among societies such as the Plateau Tonga and the Ifugaos, the

possibility of feud – interminable mutual retaliation – was recognized,

feared, but not always avoided. Some primitive societies made little

effort to avoid it. However, Kropotkin, as had Engels, was correct to

say that the spectre of eternal feud has been exaggerated. Eventually

feuds are composed,[140] or else they simply wane. But he was wrong to

blame feuds on “superstition,” specifically, witchcraft.[141] This is a

quaint 19^(th) century freethinker prejudice. Witchcraft furnished a

supposed means, not a motive for inflicting harm. Blaming witchcraft for

feuds is like blaming knives and spears for feuds. Among the Iroquois,

the kinfolk of a murder or witchcraft victim were expected usually to

accept compensation.[142]

“We already foresee a state of society,” wrote Peter Kropotkin in 1887,

“where the liberty of the individual will be limited by no laws, no

bonds – by nothing else but his own social habits and the necessity,

which everyone feels, of finding cooperation, support, and sympathy

among his neighbors.”[143] But social habits and felt necessities have

not eliminated disputes from anarchist primitive societies.

Someone with reasonable concerns about her personal safety, and the

protection of what little property he owns, will not be reassured by

airy nothings, such as this one from Nicolas Walter: “The biggest

criminals are not burglars but bosses, not gangsters but rulers, not

murderers but mass murderers.”[144] Or this one from Stuart Christie:

“Statist criminology treats of illegal crime, which is the least of

society’s serious problems and is treated as the greatest.” [145] Aside

from being erroneous by definition, because the law defines crimes and

the state imposes law,[146] this condescending piffle trivializes

popular fears of crime. People are afraid of the little criminals too,

who might rob, rape or murder them. Price-fixing and securities fraud

cause considerable harm, but they do not inspire fear.

An article by anarchist criminologist Larry F. Tifft, based on a 1983

address, sympathetically recounted Kropotkin’s contributions to what

Tifft then called “humanistic criminology.” Kropotkin believed that

universal sympathy, solidarity and economic equality, what Tifft calls

(these are not Kropotkin’s words) a “feelings-based” or “needs-based

criminology,” are a complete solution to the problem of crime.[147]

Tifft offers more quotations from Kropotkin than I do, but they add

nothing to mine. I am sure that between us, Tifft and I have identified

all of Kropotkin’s contributions to criminology. He confirms by silence

that I am right to conclude that Kropotkin had nothing serious to say

about ordinary everyday interpersonal conflicts, and that he had nothing

to say about dispute resolution processes.

In 2010, Professor Jeff Ferrell, after a 12 year sabbatical away from

anarchism, authored a brief entry for Kropotkin in Fifty Key Thinkers in

Criminology. It‘s mostly just a capsule biography, with a very short

summary of his critique of law and prisons.[148] It too reports nothing

in Kropotkin about anarchist dispute resolution.

It’s true that the fear of crime is way out of proportion to the

incidence of the kinds of crimes which people fear, thanks to

politicians and the media. Probably few people are aware that crime in

the United States has been declining for decades.[149] But there are

still many crimes committed directly against persons and personal

property. Outside of the 1%, most people have been victims of such

crimes, or they know someone who has. Crime and the fear of crime are,

like everything else in this society, unequally distributed. Women’s

fear of violence is justifiably high because the incidence of violence

against women is high, especially in intimate relationships.[150]

Anarchist rhetoric must ring more than usually hollow for rape victims

and battered wives. Tell them that Monsanto and Walmart are greater

criminals than their assailants.

Prince Kropotkin identified three categories of crimes: protection of

property, protection of government, and protection of persons.[151]

Obviously, if the state is abolished, so are crimes against the state.

“A good third of our laws,” Kropotkin maintains – taxes, the

organization of the military and the police, etc. – “have no other end

than to maintain, patch up, and develop the administrative

machine.”[152] The estimate is completely arbitrary. I know one legal

system – that of the United States -- far better than Kropotkin knew any

legal system, but I would not even try to make such an estimate. I think

his is much too high. But it is also beside the point, if the point is

the resolution of disputes in a modern anarchist society. When the

government apparatus occasions disputes, they are often disputes within

the governmental apparatus. People don’t think that these kinds of laws

are for their protection. They’re not.

The major classical anarchist argument is that the protection of

property is the major purpose of government (Kropotkin again):

Half our laws, -- the civil code in each country, -- serves no other

purpose than to maintain this appropriation [of the fruits of labor],

this monopoly for the benefit of certain individuals against the whole

of mankind. Three- fourths of the causes decided by the tribunal are

nothing but quarrels between monopolists – two robbers disputing over

their booty.[153]

Again the estimates are arbitrary. The description is ludicrously false

with respect to the criminal law. The defendants and their victims who

end up in court rarely fit the description of monopolists fighting over

the spoils of exploitation. Probably no case, civil or criminal, ever

addressed by a Neighborhood Justice Center fits the description. Some

plaintiffs in civil cases (such as evictions and collection of consumer

debts) might qualify as robbers and monopolists in some highly

hyperbolic sense, but not the defendants in those cases. Divorces? Drug

law prosecutions? Traffic violations? Antitrust prosecutions? Name

changes? The drafting of contracts, wills, powers of attorney and trust

agreements? Courts do many things.[154] As some of these examples show,

some of the law is facilitative, not directly restrictive or

repressive.[155]

Now it is old news that there is some correlation between poverty and

crime. There’s a link between crime rates and unemployment, and a

stronger link between crime rates and economic equality.[156] The

poorest communities have the highest crime rates.[157] There is “an

astonishingly linear relationship” between poverty and youth crime: “The

worse the deprivation, the worse the crime.”[158]

However, poverty does not, for instance, explain white-collar crime.

White-collar criminals are usually not poor and usually did not grow up

in poverty.[159] The motive is often simply greed (and the rich are

greedy too) -- although, some white collar workers embezzle as

retaliation against their bosses.[160] Presumably the anarchists would

say that, by abolishing the class system and private property in the

means of production – the more daring ones add: the abolition of money –

they would eliminate the motive and the opportunities for white collar

crime. Even that may not be completely true. For some people, crime is

work. And for some of them, as for some other workers, their work, when

well done, has intrinsic satisfaction: “some of the rewards of crime

have to do with the satisfaction inherent in craftsmanship, for

instance.”[161] The urge to rob banks and crack safes is also a creative

urge.

It is nonetheless possible in a society without private (or state)

ownership of the means of production for there to be disputes about

personal property, and for there to be disputes which, while basically

personal, take the form of stealing or destroying property. An anarchist

society would certainly have some property-related crimes if it retains,

as Noam Chomsky advocates, “central financial institutions.”[162]

Financial institutions move money around.[163] There is nothing better

for stealing than money.

The anarchist criminologists (who are few and far between) do complain a

lot about corporate crime and crimes of state.[164] These rarely

prosecuted crimes probably do more harm than do the street crimes which

so excite politicians, journalists, and almost all criminologists. But

the man on the street is afraid of street crime. Stronger enforcement of

anti-trust laws and environmental laws would do more for Josephine

Average than any possible crackdown on street crime. But that would do

nothing to reduce his fear of crimes against her person and property.

The anarchists, and the anarchist criminologists, sympathize with the

criminals, not the victims. Most people sympathize with the victims, not

the criminals. This is not just a public-relations problem for

anarchists. It’s a serious flaw in their doctrine.

Contemporary anarchist criminologists have added nothing to the

classical arguments except a little post-modernist punk posturing. In

1998, Will Farrell, now a tenured Professor of Sociology at Texas

Christian University, wrote: “In promoting fluid and uncertain social

relations, and attacking the sources of legal authority which stifle

them, anarchist criminology aims its disrespectable gaze both high and

low.” It does not “bother pretending to incorporate reasoned or

reasonable critiques of law and legal authority, either.” [165] Then he

does go on to bother to try to provide reasoned and reasonable critiques

of law and social order. They are mediocre, unpersuasive, and

derivative. The only novelty is the bad-boy braggadocio. Ferrell’s major

substantive publication – it was probably what academics call his

“tenure book” – is entitled Crimes of Style: Urban Graffiti and the

Politics of Criminality.[166] Ferrell has produced a criminology of

style – style without substance.

And so – I will inflict only one example on my patient readers – here is

what anarcho-criminologists Larry Tifft & Dennis Sullivan had to say in

1980: “Within an environment of such freedom and social organization

[i.e., anarchy], anti-person, anti-nature, and anti-social acts need not

be feared.”[167] No reasonable man or woman believes this drivel.

The anarchists continue: If some people are still anti-social after the

revolution, they must be crazy. We will cure them by gentle

treatment.[168] Most of the mentally ill are harmless -- Elliot Hughes

is an exception -- even if they do make us uneasy. But the violent,

acting-out kind of crazies aren’t all going to be pacified by a

revolution, or by being cuddled by sentimental saps. Violent people are

usually not crazy. Crimes of passion are not committed mainly by

maniacs. They are committed by ordinary men and women against other

ordinary men and women with whom, usually, they are already involved, as

the Vera Institute statistics showed (for instance, 50% for homicide,

83% for rape). The shocking fact about wife-beaters, who are numerous,

is not that they are numerous, but that they are ordinary . . . “the

attributes of men who batter women appear to be descriptive of men in

the United States generally, rather than of men who batter women or of

‘violent men’ specifically.”[169]

According to Colin Ward, “proper treatment of delinquency would be part

of the health and education system, and would not become an

institutionalized system of punishment.” [170] But it would be part of

an institutionalized system of health and education. Here’s the same

ploy as from Kropotkin: change the subject from social order to the

villainy of punishment. [171] The same from Alex Comfort, a Freudian

anarchist (I hope, the only one).[172]

As shown by my exemplary primitive societies, their dispute resolution

processes are directed toward reconciliation, not punishment. But at

least they have dispute resolution processes. Comfort does understand

this much: “No society, however utopian, is likely to remove altogether

the causes of delinquency. . . . The mechanism of restraint which

operates most effectively is one which centralized institutional

societies undermine – the interaction of public opinion and introjected

social standards.” He remarks – consistent with what I’ve said : “Our

lack of experience of this force of public opinion in city aggregates

makes us rather too ready to underestimate it. The ultimate sanctions of

such a community, ostracism and excommunication, are probably more

powerful than any institutional penalty.”[173] People in fear of crime

are supposed to accept this on faith? Because it is nothing but a

statement of faith, a credo, dressed up in a little Freudian jargon

(“introjected”).

For Dr. Comfort, there is nothing in between amorphous custom and

“public opinion,” on the one hand, and the “ultimate sanctions,” on the

other. He has no conception of dispute resolution processes. No

anarchist does, as far as I know. This even includes anarchist

anthropologists such as Brian Morris, Harold Barclay, Jeff Farrell, Neal

Keating, and David Graeber. They are all AWOL.

Well then, the anarchists go on, we will raise a new generation,

unwarped by capitalism and the state. One of them says that this may

take “a few generations.”[174] Obviously we, the living, will not

benefit from the paradise to be enjoyed by our remote descendants, if we

have any remote descendants. Our children (we are assured) will, after

anarchist tutelage, never exhibit aggression or hostility. With parents

like that, I think they will. Hippie parents may have punk children who

have hipster children. I doubt that Freud’s Oedipus complex really

exists, except occasionally. But someone might want to slay his father

even if he didn’t want to marry his mother. They might go on to be just

good friends.

The whole idea that interpersonal disputes are inherently anti-social or

pathological is literally reactionary. It assumes an organic, holistic

community which supposedly existed in the distant past. But there’s no

reason to think that it ever existed at any time anywhere. Societies

like the ones I’ve described are as close to organic and holistic as you

can get, yet they have disputes. Social conflict isn’t always a bad

thing. Even mainstream sociologists and anthropologists understand

that.[175] Revolutionaries ought to understand that!

I think that there’s some merit in the traditional arguments. Economic

inequality is certainly an important cause of crime. The state is itself

a source of social disorder.[176] But anarchists shouldn’t be thinking

in terms of crime. They should be explaining that anarchy, the

alternative to law and the state, is a voluntary form of society based

on equality and mutual aid. The law is a crude and ineffective way to

resolve conflicts between people.

More sophisticated than their economism and their moral indignation are

anarchist critiques of the nature of law as a force for order,

regardless of whose interests it serves and how badly it behaves. Law

operates categorically, but “every case is a rule to itself.” No two

acts (crimes, if you will) are exactly the same. No two criminals are

exactly the same. The consequences are never exactly the same. But the

laws are exactly the same. Law’s equal justice is inherently unequal,

and therefore inherently unjust. “As new cases occur, the law is

perpetually found deficient.” Then, either the judges distort the law to

fit the facts, or the legislature enlarges the body of law and makes it

more complicated. The result is that there is far more law than any

judge or lawyer could ever know, and “the consequences of the infinitude

of law is its uncertainty” – thereby, as William Godwin argued,

defeating its purpose of regulating conduct.[177]

Anarchists believe, correctly -- but only as an act of faith -- that law

does not provide much order, and that what order it does provide is

often the wrong kind of order. They are unaware that even many social

scientists acknowledge that most social order, such as it is, is even

today maintained by nonstate – by anarchist – social relations.[178]

That is also about as far as the more astute classical anarchists got in

analyzing the problem of interpersonal conflict.[179] Modern expositions

of anarchism go no further.[180]

Anarchists should stop pretending that their utopia will be one of

universal harmony. When they talk like that, people dismiss them as

naïve fools, and that’s exactly what they are. They should acknowledge

that there may always be disputes. But there are noncoercive,

conciliatory ways of resolving most disputes in decentralized,

egalitarian, anarchist societies. Anarchists won’t be able to explain

this to other people until they understand it themselves.

Disputes are universal. Third-party disputing processes are not

universal, but they are very common. The more complex the society, the

more likely it is to have processes of mediation or arbitration or

adjudication, singly or in combination. A major determinant of their

presence, and of which ones are present, is social scale and complexity.

Anarchists are not in agreement about how complex their anarchist

society should be. Like the classical anarchists, I am convinced that

modern anarchy would have to be, as primitive anarchy always was,

radically decentralized. This implies a limit on how much of existing

society it is possible or desirable to maintain. To me it’s obvious that

an anarchist society could not (and should not) preserve, and intensify,

as Noam Chomsky claims,[181] much of modern industrial society,

financial institutions, democracy, or the rule of law. Rather, it has to

approximate the Gemeinschaft, not the Gesellschaft ideal type.[182] Even

if a pure community of this type has never existed, we should try to

approximate it.

That society should, at its foundations, consist of face-to-face

communities, was understood by Fourier, Kropotkin, Malatesta, Goodman,

Perlman, Zerzan and many others. In such communities, negotiation and

mediation would be, according to my arguments, viable, effective, and

anarchist. I don’t give a damn about how primitive or how modern these

societies are, if they are really anarchist.

It is a little more difficult to envisage what form dispute resolution

would assume under anarcho-syndicalism. There, the formations at the

base consist of self-managed workplace workers’ councils, defined

functionally, along with communes defined geographically. Certainly

interpersonal disputes would arise in the workplace, as they often do

now, although, no syndicalist has acknowledged this. I don’t know if the

elected comrade managers/militants would adjudicate these disputes

themselves: that would not be very anarchist. They might instead add

these disputes to the agenda (probably already overburdened) of the

workplace assemblies, or a disputant might do that herself.

These meetings would be scheduled after work, if, under syndicalism,

there ever is any time after work. Most workers in assembly will

probably shun this obligation, because their relationship, if any, to

the disputants is simplex, except for a few pals and mates. A tribunal

consisting of partisans of the parties, plus the managers, plus whatever

militants like to go to meetings, seems to me to be inferior to any

known dispute resolution process, except maybe trial by ordeal.

What about mediation? Pure mediation requires a mediator accepted by

both parties, but where neither disputant has to accept the settlement

proposed by the mediator. Who might the mediator be? We have two

precedents. In primitive societies, the mediator is someone who knows

the disputants, in person or by reputation, or who at least has personal

ties to the kin of both disputants. He is usually a person of greater

wealth, or higher prestige, who can, if necessary, bring in his own kin

and clients, added to the supporters of the cooperative disputant,

against a recalcitrant party.

Under syndicalism, there might not be anybody with personal knowledge of

the parties, or anyone who has cross-cutting ties with them, or with

their friends or family. If there is somebody like that, he might not

want to be a mediator, or he might not be good at mediation. Of course,

under anarcho-syndicalism, there can be no differences in wealth. Might

there be differences in prestige? Spanish anarchism had its stars. I

imagine that there would be an anarchist egalitarian aversion to

differences in prestige, such that a more respected, more prestigious

person would be discouraged from conducting a mediation from which he

might emerge with even more prestige (this is the main motivation for

Ifugao mediators). Excellence and superiority are not syndicalist

values. Neither is honor.

The other precedent is modern ADL, conducted by trained, specialized

mediators – professionals – who have the power of the state behind them.

I’ve provided evidence what’s wrong with that. I hope that syndicalists

would reject that, but I am not at all sure that they would. They are

not, in principle, opposed to the division of labor in a complex

industrial society, but they are ignorant of, or indifferent to some of

its ramifications. If, as Cornelius Castoriadis and Noam Chomsky

contend, the formulation of national economic plans is just another

industry (the “plan factory”), with its own workers’ collectives and

council,[183] there might be no syndicalist objection to a

self-organized cadre (I mean, “industry”) of professional mediators. But

the anarcho-syndicalist fathers, like all other anarchists, have nothing

to say about interpersonal dispute resolution.[184]

The first book by avowed anarchist criminologists, Larry Tifft & Mark

Sullivan (published in 1980), only pauses briefly to endorse “direct

justice” which “means no institutionalization of the resolving of

conflict.” That would describe dueling and vigilantism. Despite having

social science Ph.Ds, Tifft & Sullivan are confused about what an

institution is. If an institution means a permanent organization, then

there could be no anarchist institutionalization of justice, for

institutionalized justice in that sense is necessarily part of the

state. But organization might mean ad hoc disputing processes which

people regularly resort to, like those I have described for several

primitive societies. Tifft & Sullivan were, at that time, apparently

unaware of the anthropological literature on disputing processes, which

is inexcusable. But they were dimly aware of disputing processes like

that, because they wrote: “These processes might include the airing of

conflicts among mutually selected friends. Perhaps the persons in

conflict could select a mediator.”[185]

Perhaps! You never know. These two don’t. Alas, we haven’t heard the

last from them. Read on.

IX. “RESTORATIVE JUSTICE.”

“Restorative Justice” (RJ) is the latest in informal justice. (Actually,

it was invented before NJCs, but it hasn’t faded.) Once again, the

leftist longing for peace, harmony and reconciliation has been turned

against the left. Once again, the left – the academic left: nobody else

has even heard of restorative justice – has been compromised, co-opted,

and duped.[186] Think of the criminal justice system as Lucy, the

credulous academics as Charlie Brown, and the football as, successively,

the juvenile court, small claims court, pretrial diversion, neighborhood

justice centers, and now restorative justice. Every time Charlie Brown

runs up to kick the football, Lucy pulls it away at the last moment, and

Charlie Brown ends up on his ass. And every time, he thinks that next

time will be different. It’s like voting.

The pioneer or, as he is often called, the “grandfather” of RJ is Howard

Zehr, the Distinguished Professor of Restorative Justice at Eastern

Mennonite University. From 1979 to 1996, he directed the Office on Crime

and Justice under the Mennonite Central Committee.[187] He describes

himself as “a white, middle-class male of European ancestry, a

Christian, a Mennonite.”[188] The Mennonite cult, whose background is

Anabaptist, is pacifist and, in principle, like the Quakers, antinomian.

[189] Obviously pacifists cannot collaborate with the state.[190] But

that has not kept the Mennonites (or the Quakers) from collaborating

with the state’s criminal justice system: “Mennonites and Quakers, for

example, often work with judges, lawyers, probation officers, and

bureaucrats to create reform, while protesting the institutions they are

working in.”[191] Mennonites, Quakers and Brethren (the “peace

churches”) invented RJ in the late 1970’s. It is a “faith-based”

process.[192]

Without trying to make too much of it, there is much more religious

influence and involvement in RJ than in the NCRs or other ADR programs.

The methods of RJ – reconciliation through confession, repentance and

forgiveness[193] – are overtly Christian. An Anglican bishop,

introducing a book on RJ, explains: “This speaks to me of New Testament

principles . . . “[194] Even secular RJ supporters mention the

“evangelical” zeal of some of its advocates,[195] and their

“self-righteousness.” [196] According to the Executive Director of a

South African RJ center: “Restorative justice is by its very nature

spiritual” – and by spiritual he means, experiencing and relating to the

supernatural.[197] But there is no such thing as the supernatural.

If RJ essentially involves recourse to the supernatural, it violates, in

the United States, the Constitutional separation of church and state, if

it is implemented by the state. Long before I knew that what I was

talking about was RJ, I wrote: “Obviously there are first amendment

limitations on implementing this Gospel philosophy governmentally.”[198]

Obvious to me, but not obvious to the inventors of the Florida Faith-

and Community-Based Delinquency Treatment Initiative in the state

Department of Juvenile Justice. Nor did the issue of the separation of

church and state occur to the keenly-treated minds of three college

professors who talked up the program at an annual meeting of the

Southern Sociology Society.[199]

RJ was invented by pacifists who were inspired by an ideology of

harmony. They were, and are, religious zealots who abhor conflict: “for

the Christian Mennonite movement it is the typically adversarial nature

of criminal justice which has aroused critique.”[200] RJ “practices

contain or sanitize conflict in the reconciliation discourse, regarding

it as an altogether destructive and unhealthy feature of human

conduct.”[201] But social conflict is inevitable, and not always

harmful, and it has some useful social functions. We don’t have enough

social conflict.[202] Conflict has always occurred in (and between)

anarchist societies. I’ve contended that probably it always will.

Nonetheless, as we will see, contemporary anarchist academics are

prominent exponents of RJ. They always get off at the wrong stop.

We saw that the NJCs made the tenuous and dubious claim to have been

inspired by primitive disputing processes, those of the Kpelle for

instance. We saw how false that was. RJ supporters also claim indigenous

inspiration, but they make a bigger deal about it. They take it for

granted that RJ is identical to indigenous procedures, which is an

untenable assumption.[203] In the teeth of the well-known history, they

say things like this: “Most analysts [?] trace the roots of RJ back to

aboriginal practices that predate colonization by the West.”[204] They

locate the “foundations” of RJ in Navajo peacemaking and the African

concept of ubuntu. [205] They also claim inspiration from the

Maoris.[206] It’s interesting that they don’t mention the Kpelle, whose

community moots are closer to RJ “circles” than to the NJCs supposedly

inspired by the Kpelle moot.

In much the same way that the Mormon Church retroactively converts the

dead, RJ devotees adopt indigenous ancestors. They do that because

indigenous peoples are chic, and also to legitimate themselves with an

origins myth,[207] something no religion can do without. But it’s a

pious fraud. We know very well that Mennonites invented RJ in the 1970s,

from religious motives.[208] To claim that a few white Mennonites in

remote Kitchener, Ontario – led by a Mennonite probation officer, Mark

Yantzi -- “developed RJ out of aboriginal and Native American practices

in North America and New Zealand,” [209] is preposterous. Whence came

their ethnographic savvy? Probably not college. Eastern Mennonite

University, where Howard Zehr is the grey eminence, doesn’t even have an

anthropology department. Christian theology cannot survive an encounter

with either history or the ethnographic record. It’s too bad that the

Mennonites don’t follow the example of their Amish cousins, who take

care of their own and leave the rest of the world alone.

I’ve referred to some of the claims made for the NJCs as extravagant.

But they were modest compared to the claims made for RJ. NJCs were

designed to deal with a specific range of disputes, especially those

arising out of prior relationships. There seemed to be some sort of

theoretical rationale for NJCs, in the Vera Institute’s Felony Arrests,

and – more tenuously – in the writings of scholars like Richard Danzig

and Frank Sander. But – with one conspicuous exception, to be discussed

-- RJ has no theoretical or, indeed, rational basis. But the believers,

the Arjays -- as I shall sometimes refer to them[210] -- promise the

moon, as lunatics are wont to do. Their rhetoric is often a bizarre

combination of solemnity and euphoria.

RJ has been advocated, and sometimes attempted, in “correctional

settings” and schools, and for sex offenders, elder abuse, business

conflicts, higher education disputes, teenage bullying, athletics, white

collar crime, disaster management – even (a Howard Zehr initiative) in

death penalty cases![211] RJ is a minor tweaking of alternative dispute

resolution, yet it has messianic ambitions. Do I exaggerate? According

to a Canadian law professor, RJ “is arguably the most significant

development in criminal justice since the emergence of the nation

state.”[212]

“Restorative justice,” as its grandfather (or godfather) explains, “is

an approach to achieving justice that involves, to the extent possible,

those who have a stake in a specific offence or harm to collectively

identify and address harms, needs, and obligations in order to heal and

put things as right as possible.”[213] Another definition, often quoted,

is by Tony Marshall, who sees it as “a process whereby all the parties

with a stake in a particular offence come together to resolve

collectively how to deal with the aftermath of the offence and its

implication for the future.”[214] But really there is no agreed-upon

definition of RJ.[215]

By “those who have a stake in a specific offence,” Zehr means primarily,

victims and criminals -- but he avoids those hard words: “A soft answer

turneth away wrath: but grievous words stir up anger.”[216] To “put

things right” means to get right with God. The therapeutic purpose,

which was present, but usually muted, in the NJCs is in the forefront

here. James Gibbs, Jr., viewed the Kpelle moot as therapeutic, and

Richard Danzig, whom he inspired, called for a radical change of

perspective, to “stop thinking of courts as adjudicators, and view them

instead as parts of a therapeutic process aimed at conciliation of

disputants or reintegration of deviants into society.”[217] Although NCR

advocates, in offering something for everybody, sometimes promised

therapeutic benefits, that was a minor theme. In RJ, as in the juvenile

court movement, it’s primary. RJ is “therapeutic jurisprudence.” [218]

At least the NJC pseudo-social movement was secular.

The medical model of interpersonal conflict has absolutely no validity.

In treating disputants as patients, RJ demeans them. The “sick role,”

with its “element of dependency,” is a subordinated role.[219] To speak

of RJ facilitators as “healers of conflicts”[220] is pernicious

nonsense, because conflicts are not injuries or diseases. This is the

Therapeutic State, referring to “the ascendency of the medical model as

the prevailing ideology of the modern welfare state [references

omitted].”[221] The therapeutic model is inherently conservative,

individualizing, isolating, and atomizing. So it’s not a way to

“collectively address” problems. It licenses deep intrusions into

personal life and the self.[222] Treating criminals as sick is at least

as ominous as treating them as sinners, a point made by no less than Max

Stirner:

Curative means or healing is only the reverse side of punishment, the

theory of cure runs parallel with the theory of punishment; if that

latter sees in an action a sin against right, the former takes it for a

sin of the man against himself, as a falling away from himself. [223]

This is an uncanny anticipation – and anticipatory repudiation – of

therapeutic justice. It strikes right to the heart of the RJ claim that

what Restorative Justice, at the end of the day, really restores, is

nothing real, but rather, coerced compliance with what is posited to be

the criminal’s innate human nature, his better self. The Therapeutic

State is a paternalistic and authoritarian state.[224]

To the limited extent that RJ may be popular, that reception owes a lot

to the conservative political climate: “The search for community and for

definitive moral responses to crime can be seen in the context of

neo-liberal demands for greater individual responsibility and

accountability.”[225] The most ambitious attempt to apply the criminal

law in a therapeutic way was the juvenile court. It was a failure. In

the 1960s, anti-institutional challenges shook the helping

bureaucracies: the social workers, psychiatrists and psychotherapists.

But they recovered their hegemony.[226] Restorative Justice is part of

that counter-revolution.[227]

But, by what benevolent “process” are parties reconciled and traumas

healed by RJ? By, among other devices, “victim/offender conferences,”

“family group conferences,” and “sentencing circles.” They are our old

friend, mediation, metastasized.[228] They may bring in a few more

participants than the victim and the criminal (the “microcommunity” or

“community of care”). Enthusiasts for RJ are, as were enthusiasts for

NJCs, academics and social control professionals – judges, elite

lawyers, social workers, etc. (now joined by religious activists). One

would therefore expect them to be mindful of the NJC experience, not to

mention the juvenile court experience.

But they are not. I have read only two RJ studies which referred to the

NJCs – curiously, without calling them that. One reported that they were

a great success,[229] citing none of the studies mentioned by Tomasic or

myself. The other acknowledged the finding of the Vera Institute’s

Brooklyn study, where there was a control group: the recidivism rates

were the same. The article referred to the Brooklyn mediation program as

“restorative justice,” although it was never called that at the

time.[230]

The NJCs, as we have seen, had the initial support of almost everyone

except the people of the communities where they were installed.

Similarly, RJ boosters include “police officers, judges, schoolteachers,

politicians, juvenile justice agencies, victim support groups,

aboriginal elders, and mums and dads.”[231] In other words, authorities.

RJ enthusiasts have made many grandiose claims -- but, that RJ is a

response to popular demand, is not one of them. The American Bar

Association, an early advocate of NJCs,[232] now publishes Dispute

Resolution Magazine, which regularly features -- alongside the

self-congratulatory stories about community mediation centers which I’ve

cited -- self-congratulatory stories about restorative justice.[233]

That RJ has critics[234] is rarely acknowledged by its real

“stakeholders”: law enforcement, the professors, and the

paraprofessional practitioners.

Although RJ is, I shall argue, even worse than the NJCs, it has been

around even longer, and it is still around. The NJCs were an American

phenomenon. RJ originated in Canada and it has spread to many parts of

the world. It may still be spreading. An RJ website maintained by the

Centre for Justice & Reconciliation, “operating within the Christian

tradition,” lists over 12,000 texts.[235] RJ is a – dare I say it? –

godsend to academics who have to publish or perish. RJ is a very easy

topic to write articles about. I’ve done it myself, although I didn’t

even know it at the time.[236] There are many, many books and articles:

but, after 40 years, not much research. Mostly, Arjays write articles

about each other’s articles. Many other academics do the same.

Some of the claims for RJ (there are many more) are the same claims as

were made for the NJCs. For each, I first cite to the corresponding NJC

claim.

1. RJ is a voluntary, non-state alternative to the criminal justice (CJ)

system.[237]

It is axiomatic for RJ that “participation by the one who has been

harmed is entirely voluntary.”[238] It is a non-state alternative to CJ.

Crime victims who don’t call the police or file complaints will rarely

be drawn into a criminal prosecution. Lumping it is a non-state

alternative to RJ only in the sense that it is no alternative at all.

But if participation by the offender has to be entirely voluntary, then

there exist almost no bona fide restorative justice programs.

For a subversive, non-state alternative to CJ – a new paradigm -- RJ is

strangely popular with the state. As early as 2001, “Virtually every

[American] State [was] implementing restorative justice at state,

regional, and local levels.”[239] It is practiced in hundreds of

prisons. [240] It is practiced in schools. It is endorsed by the United

Nations[241] and has been implemented, in name at least, in many

countries – including authoritarian states like Singapore, which allow

nothing to escape state control.[242] In New Zealand, the juvenile

justice system has been, since 1989, based on RJ principles.[243] In

California, “restorative justice and law enforcement personnel often

interpenetrate”: many probation officers are allowed to carry guns, they

exchange information with police, and they ride along with police.[244]

Worldwide, RJ is used far more for juveniles than for adults.[245] For

them, if for anyone, there might be a place for its paternalism. Perhaps

there is something infantilizing about RJ. Jesus taught that one must

become as a child to enter into the Kingdom of Heaven.

Arjays are in hopeless denial about this touchy matter. We see something

like this statement in most RJ books and articles: “Participation in

restorative justice was entirely voluntary for victims and offenders” –

and then, on the same page, we read: “In general, offenders proving

uncontactable were relatively rare -- not surprisingly, given that

offenders were still in the criminal justice process either pre- or

post-sentence.”[246]

Here, then, is the first common feature of RJ and CJ. They are both

court-annexed (in some countries, such as Australia,

police-annexed[247]) and, as such, they are statist and coercive. For

this, the Mennonites and Quakers are as sorry as the Walrus and the

Carpenter.[248] All the other claimed benefits of RJ founder on this

brute fact. State control of RJ is growing.[249] It is probably

complete.

2.[250] RJ is therapeutic for victims, offenders, and others.

RJ is above all about healing, according to the definitions by Howard

Zehr and many others.[251] RJ responds, not to crime per se, but to

“harm.” However, unless the harm is also a crime, state-annexed RJ can

have no jurisdiction. If RJ is healing, who does it heal? The

“stakeholders” always include the offender, the victim, and their

immediate families. In cases involving juveniles, the parents are

brought in – but the juvenile court has always done all of that.

By definition, because this is RJ – there has to be a harm -- the victim

has been harmed, physically, psychologically or financially. Restitution

is often ordered in case of property crimes, but, it would be perverse

to speak of “healing” the victim’s finances. Besides, most offenders are

unable to repair financial loss.[252] And there is nothing distinctively

RJ about restitution. It’s become a standard element in sentencing for

property crimes. Physical harm is redressed by medical care, not in an

encounter group. So RJ’s healing claims really boil down to the

provision of psychotherapy. However, “there are more effective means of

assisting the process of emotional catharsis and addressing mental

health issues than reliance on the criminal justice system.”[253] And I

have suggested: “For the justice system, doing justice is more important

than administering therapy.”[254]

The meaning of “harm” to a victim beyond violence to the person and

trespass to property, is highly problematic.

Psychiatric, psychological and social services are available to victims,

independently of RJ. Since the 1970s, there have been significant

support services available to the victims of crime. It’s always possible

to find that such programs are inadequate. Has there ever been a social

services program which didn’t want more money? RJ wants more money too:

“A common theme in the restorative justice community throughout the

world is the lack of resources for programs at all levels.”[255] Unlike

RJ, which is a one-shot fix, these programs at least offer services over

a long-term basis. There’s a “natural disconnect” between RJ and victim

services.[256]

The typical RJ process, such as victim-offender reconciliation programs

(VORP), after some behind-the-scenes manipulation of the parties by the

“facilitator” or “convenor,” culminates in a single meeting of

stakeholders.[257] This fact alone renders the strident claims for

success and satisfaction dubious. NJC mediation was a more protracted

process, but as we have seen, its claims for success were also dubious.

Successful mediation follows “essentially a model of overlapping phases

in which each phase opens the way to a succeeding one in a progression

toward settlement. The phases are distinguished by the nature and

content of the information exchanged and the concomitant learning and by

the degree of coordination involved.”[258] That was how mediation was

conducted in unhurried societies such as the Plateau Tonga and the

Infugao. But that’s not modern RJ. Modern societies are not unhurried.

RJ literature is loaded with moving anecdotes of “closure” for victims,

and of criminals seeing the light[259] -- the blinding light, such as

St. Paul saw on the Damascus road. In one infamous, oft-quoted anecdote,

it was the victim, who really was blinded, while in custody, by a South

African police officer, whose sight was (metaphorically) restored by the

opportunity to tell his story to a Truth and Reconciliation

Commission.[260] Jesus would have delivered more than closure. On at

least one occasion, he reportedly kicked ass.

I am so hard-hearted as to shed no tears of joy over these miracles,

possibly because I don’t believe in miracles. I am sure the Arjays shed

tears as sincerely as did the Walrus and the Carpenter.[261] But I have

not found a single case, documented by psychologists or psychiatrists or

psychiatric social workers, of RJ effecting personality changes in

anybody. RJ is much less like therapy than theatre – the theatre of the

absurd, or melodrama.

If victim healing is dubious, offender healing is scandalous. As we have

seen, the real focus of most RJ programs is on rehabilitating the

criminal, not the victim. The only certain “harm” to a convicted

criminal is criminal punishment. Naturally he would like to avoid that.

The lion would rather eat the lamb than lie down with him, but, he might

prefer lying down with the lamb to being caged. But why should the lamb

lie down with the lion? Nonetheless, that is the idyllic illustration on

the cover of Tifft and Sullivan’s Restorative Justice. A child is

petting the lamb. A dove of peace observes from a tree branch. I’m not

making this stuff up! [262]

Most people adhere, more or less consciously, to the “retribution”

theory of criminal punishment, which is also currently popular among

academics, who always bend with the winds, and bend over for the state.

Most people think that, in general, criminals should get their just

deserts, which will probably harm the criminals -- that’s the point. I

don’t endorse this point of view. I merely recognize its popularity. For

the pacifist founders of RJ, retribution is anathema (another religious

word), and RJ is the alternative. Criminals too, they say, need to be

healed. One reason RJ is less popular with victims than with offenders

is that victims may be offended when “the real criminals” are treated as

victims too. They might be outraged to hear an Arjay saying “that most

street criminals – the ‘bad guys’ in our justice system – are in fact

victims themselves.”[263] Any victim of crime knows better than the RJ

academic who babbled: “Crime does not exist.”[264] An ardent academic

Arjay admits:

Although the principles of restorative justice profess that it is for

both offenders and victims, the reality is that the majority of programs

are predominantly being used for offender rehabilitation. For the most

part, victims are still being neglected by most practitioners in the

countries where restorative justice is used.[265]

Victims are not merely neglected by RJ practitioners: they are being

used.

It’s a good thing for RJ that victims haven’t read the RJ academic

literature, where they might read that

victims are not necessarily the “good” in opposition to the offender’s

“bad.” . . . [T]his position serves to remind us that whilst crime does

impact upon [sic] people’s lives, victims of crime are people too. So by

implication, in this regard, it makes little sense to talk of people as

victims or offenders, or indeed victims or survivors. They are people,

and people need to feel OK about themselves and sometimes need some help

and support to achieve that.[266]

For victims, if not for sociology professors, it makes perfect sense to

talk of people as victims or offenders. Their common personhood did not

prevent offenders from victimizing them. Maybe some people should not

“feel OK about themselves,” because some people are not OK.

Criminals don’t usually need to be healed, because criminals, like

victims, aren’t usually sick. If they are, that has little to do with

their criminality. Possibly juvenile delinquents, who are still growing

up, should be treated therapeutically – at first, anyway. For the

Arjays, a crime is an opportunity for ministration. For them, in

accordance with their sickly Christian morality,[267] the criminal is a

sheep gone astray. They wallow in bathos. They rejoice in it. Arjays are

leper lickers.

In the parable of the Prodigal Son, the whoring, wastrel son leaves home

while the dutiful son remains to serve his father. When the Prodigal,

whose money has run out, drags his sorry ass back home, the patriarch

rejoices, and he sacrifices the fatted calf: “For this my son was dead,

and is alive again; he was lost, and is found. And they began to be

merry.”[268]

But not everybody began to be merry. The dutiful, obedient son “was

angry, and would not go in: therefore came his father out, and entreated

him.” The father told him, in effect: you I can take for granted. But

your brother needs to be (this is RJ jargon, not the Bible)

“reintegrated.”[269] Had they all been brought together in a “family

circle,” facilitated by a holy man -- that would be RJ. When

Christianity isn’t advocating rendering unto Caesar, and explaining that

the powers that be are ordained of God, it occasionally privileges the

wrongdoer. Where would Christianity be without sin?

Curiously, these Christians never discuss crime in terms of good and

evil, although that is historically their stock in trade. Like Father

Flanagan of Boys Town, they believe that there is no such thing as a bad

boy -- or girl, or man, or woman. Often, victims don’t share that

opinion. They often perceive RJ as favoring criminals over victims.[270]

They often consider offender apologies to be insincere.[271] In one

study which emphasized the apology ceremony, the juvenile delinquents,

when asked why they apologized, “27 per cent said they did not feel

sorry but thought they’d get off more easily, 39 per cent said to make

their family feel better, and a similar per cent said they were pushed

into it.”[272] In other words, what they were sorry about was getting

caught.

It’s all too likely, also, that “restorative justice projects might

report victim expression of forgiveness (as a performative action) that

may not equate with a change in sentiment for themselves as

individuals.”[273] Probably “that which is spoken in the mediation

session often is unwittingly scripted.”[274] Maybe not so unwittingly at

that. What makes excuses acceptable is not so much that they are true as

that they follow a culturally accepted script.[275] Where the criminal

has made a public show of his apology, the victim comes under pressure

to accept the apology -- or claim to – because she knows that’s what the

RJ paraprofessional gently, but firmly expects from her.[276] It’s what

the victim is there for.

I describe the victim as she and her deliberately. In the kinds of cases

relegated to RJ, more often than not the victim is female, and more

often than not, the perpetrator is male. Often these are crimes of

violence. Feminists have long criticized the unresponsiveness of the

criminal justice system to female victims of male violence. They

demanded that retributive justice be applied to these violent men.[277]

Just when the feminists were starting to get somewhere with

policymakers, along came the long lingering RJ policy fad whose

solicitude is more for the (usually) male criminal than for the

(usually) female victim. Obviously RJ demands much more from the victim

than from the criminal, although for almost anybody not ensorcelled by

RJ ideology,it should usually be the other way around. Apology is a lot

easier than forgiveness. And it’s a lot easier to fake. Calling this

“justice” does not pass the laugh test. In the unlikely event that I

were a feminist, I would be even more suspicious of Restorative Justice

than some feminists already are.

In a way, RJ could be passed off as feminist. If feminism is associated

with supposedly essential(ist) female attributes such as caring more

about relationships than rights, being more cooperative than

competitive, being a good listener, and being more conciliatory than

vindictive,[278] then there is something warm, nurturing, amniotic and

feminist about RJ. “It is the feminine, Native American and African

elements of our current [white male] leaders’ souls,” say some RJ women,

“and their unity with all of us that are being expressed in their

restorative justice work.”[279] There are feminist Arjays making this

argument.[280] There are many feminist Arjays in the academy. The ideal

or idealized woman, on this account, is also the ideal or idealized

victim. She’s a pushover. She is predisposed to play the victim role in

RJ dramas. She is the leading lady there.

But feminists -- regardless to what extent they endorse or reject this

unfortunate ideal type or stereotype -- have correctly foregrounded the

criminal justice system as a major site of the oppression of women, by

their relentless critique of the way it deals with violence against

women. For abused women they demand, of course, as a first priority,

protection, which nobody openly opposes. But they go on to criticize,

comprehensively, how women victims of crime are dealt with by the

criminal justice system. The brute fact is that “the demographics of

restorative justice on the question of who is required to learn love of

their victimizers will prove no exception to this rule: Women victims of

domestic violence, sexual assault, and other crime will be

overrepresented in the pool of victim participants in restorative

justice programs.”[281] Men will be overrepresented in the pool of

victimizers.

Do feminists want men (any men) who rape or batter women to be treated

like violent male criminals who are poor, young and black are treated?

I’m curious to hear an answer to that question. For now, I will confine

myself to noticing that RJ is vulnerable to the feminist critique. RJ is

better for male criminals than for female victims.[282] I, personally,

don’t want anybody to be mistreated, except my personal enemies, my

political enemies, my class enemies, my . . . – I’ll have to take that

back. I don’t necessarily sorrow if my enemies are mistreated that way,

if anybody is to be treated that way. Some feminists apparently feel as

I do. They are no exception to the widespread popularity of retributive

justice.

Academic advocates of RJ, many of them women, are very defensive when it

comes to RJ in sexual and domestic violence cases. There, its use is

“highly controversial.”[283] But about all they can say is, the

conventional criminal justice system is just as bad, if not worse.[284]

Actually, it might be better. There is no evidence that it’s not. A “new

paradigm,” or even a mere transformative reform, has to make a better

showing than that.

In fact, offender apologies often are insincere. Coerced apologies are

insincere.[285] What parent doesn’t know that? What former child doesn’t

remember that? That alone undermines claims that RJ is therapeutic for

victims. As one researcher put it: “A rather high level of satisfaction

was reported among participants, except victims.” 50% of victim

participants expressed satisfaction; 25% were indifferent; and 25% of

victims felt worse.[286] A number of studies find, not surprisingly,

that victims are the least satisfied participants in RJ.[287] The

evidence suggests scrapping RJ, which, of course, will not happen. The

RJ industry has too many stakeholders.

In return for the criminal’s show of remorse and repentance, which is

degrading, the victim is expected to put on a show of forgiveness and

conciliation.[288] The greatest beneficiaries of RJ are surely the jive

hustlers: the glib, fast-talking con-men. The inarticulate -- and they

will include many juveniles, and more generally the lower orders -- may

not be good at telling their stories or voicing remorse in a way the

victims recognize or which follow the RJ script. The Arjays – this shows

how, as Christians, how heretical they are – posit that human nature is

innately good. For them, “restorative” refers, not to restoring the

status quo, in relationships for example (where that may not be possible

or desirable) – it refers to “restoring” people to the best in

themselves, the best they can be.[289] It’s not the restoration of

anything that was ever real. “Restorative” is a misnomer and

“restorative justice” is a pretext. Self-realization, spiritual

transformation, the warm glow of fellow-feeling – all that, just by

attending a conference.[290] Who knew that it was that easy? Victims of

crime don’t know how lucky they are.

Crime victims have justifiably complained about their neglect by the

criminal justice system. Exploiting their resentment, designing

politicians legislated “rights” for them.[291] This began in the 1970s,

shortly before the ancient practice of Restorative Justice was invented.

Victims received the right to be informed of developments in the case.

They received the right to submit Victim Impact Statements to the court,

or sometimes to address the court in person, about the impact of the

crime on their lives. Conservatives loved victims’ rights because they

hate criminals. Liberals loved victims’ rights because they love

victims. Versions of victims’ rights bills were soon enacted in almost

all states.[292] But, as I’ve observed: “It is in reform movements which

seem to promise something for everybody that the apparent accord on a

program is likely to mask disagreement on objectives.”[293]

That lesson has direct application to RJ, the brave new paradigm, which

is of vast international scope, which is endorsed by left and right, by

police and criminals, by college professors and Christian pacifists, by

anarchists and the U.S. Department of Justice, and by the United Nations

and the American Bar Association. And by Noam Chomsky and Bishop Desmond

Tutu. Obviously there is something deeply wrong here. What’s wrong with

this picture?

What’s wrong is who isn’t in the picture: the victim. Victims’ Rights

(VR) made much more modest demands on the time and the emotions of

victims than does RJ. VR did not mandate a victim’s face to face public

confrontation with the criminal or her participation in a

repentance/forgiveness ritual. Surely this is an experience which many

victims will experience as an annoying waste of time, or which some will

experience as a second victimization, and which many will choose not to

go through.[294] Victims did not, in fact, often exercise their

Rights.[295] And yet, as of 2005, victims’ rights had been added to 32

state constitutions.[296] VR has been proposed as an amendment to the

U.S. Constitution.[297]

Dennis Sullivan &Larry Tifft decry victim participation in sentencing as

nothing but an opportunity for victims to vent their

vindictiveness.[298] They don’t like that kind of participatory justice.

They call for according victims an opportunity for “voice,” but only if

they say what they want to hear. What some victims want is revenge, but

what the Arjays want them to want is repentance, forgiveness and

redemption. What some victims want is compensation, but concentrating on

compensation is (they say) an “impediment to healing.”[299] It is clear

that for RJ, victims are merely means to extraneous moral ends. It is

not surprising that the major limitation on RJ aggrandizement is

chronically low victim participation rates.[300] There is no reason to

think that will ever change.[301]

3. RJ Involves the Community, Representing Its Values, and It

Reintegrates Offenders and Victims into the Community.[302]

Like the NJC advocates, the Arjays assert that one of the stakeholders

is “the community,” [303] and so, RJ will heal that too. But “community”

is here -- yet again -- a feel-good meaningless word. Although RJ

usually ropes in a few more participants than did the NGCs –usually just

the parents of juvenile delinquents – it’s a mockery to characterize the

few people who attend a conference as “the community,” or as the virtual

representatives of a community. And yet, many Arjays do that. In an

early RJ manifesto, Howard Zehr and Harry Mika used the word “community”

12 times in 5 ½ pages.[304] This is reprinted in the latest edition of

Zehr’s canonical best seller The Little Book of Restorative Justice,

which denies or qualifies almost every claim ever made for RJ.

Social scientists have used the word community in various ways, often

imprecisely. In Keywords, Raymond Williams identified five modern

meanings of the word.[305] But the general idea was usually to identify

a locality whose population participated in a relatively dense web of

social relations and whose residents identified with their community.

The assumption is that, typically, there is some continuity in time. Its

highest flowering is the “organic” community. We have seen that there

are few if any organic communities in contemporary American cities. Even

Tifft and Sullivan acknowledge the reality of “killed” communities.[306]

RJ conferences can hardly be considered communities, or even

representatives of communities in this sense. So, one RJ gambit is to

define the community as “anyone who ‘shows up’ for a community

sanctioning meeting.”[307] Community is a criminological cliché: “”’The

community’ has become the all-purpose solution to every criminal justice

problem.”[308] “Or, to paraphrase Jeremiah, our false prophets cry

‘Community, community,’ but we have no community!”[309] One fact about

this “warmly persuasive word” is a constant: “unlike all other terms of

social organization (state, nation, society, etc.) it seems never to be

used unfavourably, and never to be given any positive opposing or

distinguishing term.”[310]

A related gambit is to keep the word but change the subject. RJ

addresses community problems by redefining whatever it does supposedly

do as addressing community problems. Never mind if only a handful of

persons are concerned in the matter, and maybe not very concerned. Never

mind if it’s a minor matter. Now, the community is the

“microcommunity”[311] of victim, offender, and “the families of each,

and any other members of their respective communities who may be

affected, or who may be able to contribute to prevention of a recurrence

[citation omitted].”[312] In the “Wagga Wagga” model (Australia), the

conference takes place at the police station: “The ‘community’ is a

panel of police sergeants.”[313]

The “respective communities” – is this an infinite regress? Defining a

community by reference to members of other, equally suppositious

communities? The families of victim and offender, who will usually be

strangers to one another – even if victim and offender are not -- may

not be neighbors, and may not share any social networks, and may not

share the same values. And yet, this accidental temporary aggregate,

this handful of individuals is taken to be the vox populi, the voice of

community morality: “The role of the community in restorative justice .

. . is to establish the boundaries of the community, to set the moral

norms. The community provides the forum in which justice can

occur.”[314] What does “establish the boundaries of the community” mean?

Nothing.

And so “the concept of restoring the community remains a mystery, as

indeed does the identification of the relevant ‘community.’”[315] How do

you heal a community if you don’t even know if there is one? Or what it

is? And who says the community needs healing, just because somebody

committed a crime there, which happens every day, everywhere? How do you

heal an abstraction? Nonetheless, the cant of community persists in an

evidentiary void and as an open affront to common knowledge.

In primitive societies, as I have related, individual conflicts concern

the community because the disputants have ties to kin groups, and

sometimes also other groups, which are implicated because they are

responsible for the wrongs of their members. They don’t need healing.

They just need to prevent intergroup conflict. That’s not true of a

modern urban society. There, often there exist no such groups, kin-based

or anything-based. Only a few crimes have community-wide ramifications,

by any definition of community. Modern society is largely a society of

strangers. For most city dwellers and suburbanites, even your next door

neighbors – or the tenants in the adjacent apartment – don’t know you

very well. They feel no responsibility for helping you solve your

personal problems. In a society as alienated as ours is, why should

they? They don’t expect you to solve their problems either. Most

Americans live in “killed neighborhoods.”[316]

The criminal law has always recognized, as a stakeholder, an actor more

encompassing than the criminal, the victim, and others immediately

involved: the state. In a statist society, the state is the only

organized organ of the entire community. It establishes its own

boundaries, by war if necessary. Indeed, the only meaningful definition

of “community” is “the population which the state governs.” The

community is shadowy, but the state is solid. The state expropriates

many conflicts, and also appropriates the means of their

resolution.[317] It creates a civil law system for private disputes in

which it has (usually) no direct interest, beyond keeping the peace and

sustaining property relations. It creates a criminal law system for

disputes to which it deems itself to be a party. The state claims to be

hurt by any crime, even if it harms no one else. Anti-statists have

always objected to this, but we at least recognize the state as a

deplorable reality. Claims of harm to unidentifiable, phantom

communities are meaningless. Injuries to imagined communities[318]

cannot be repaired any more than can injuries to Oz, or Never-Never

Land, or Middle Earth, or the Abbey of Theleme, or Walden Two, because

they do not exist.

RJ does not object to this reification, since RJ advances the less

credible claim that, in the words of Howard Zehr, “the problem of crime

– and wrongdoing in general – is that it represents a wound in the

community, a tear in the web of relationships.”[319] By “wrongdoing in

general” he means, of course, not crime, but sin. Sullivan & Tifft:

“Part of the restorative process entails healing the original harm or

sin . . . “[320] Since most sins are not crimes,[321] except in Iran and

Saudi Arabia, it is against the best interests of us sinners for the

distinction to be blurred. The result will usually be, not to treat

crimes as sins, but to treat sins as crimes, as the Puritans did and as

the mullahs do. It never occurs to Sullivan, Tifft, Zehr & Co. that law

might represent a wound in the community, and a tear in the web of

relationships.

Tifft &Sullivan, with their social science Ph.Ds, can say – this is so

grotesque, they must actually believe it: “No one of us can be harmed or

traumatized without all of us suffering and no one of us can prosper

without all of us gaining in our common identity and well-being.”[322]

If they, like former President Bill Clinton, feel our pain, they must be

in a lot of pain. But you don’t understand the first thing about modern

society if you don’t understand that it is precisely there that an

injury to one is not an injury to all. If it were, nobody would injure

anybody. And the wealthy few, the 1%, have prospered at the expense of

the majority for the last 40 years, “without all of us gaining in our

common identity and well-being.”

4. RJ Reduces Recidivism.[323] There was no evidence that NJCs reduce

recidivism. I’ve cited some of the studies. Does RJ? The Arjays often

take the high ground here (a Mount is a good place from which to preach

a Sermon). While vaguely claiming some success here too – as, indeed,

everywhere -- Howard Zehr writes: “Nevertheless, reduced recidivism is

not the primary reason for operating restorative justice programs.

Reduced recidivism is a byproduct, but restorative justice is done first

of all because it is the right thing to do.”[324] If, for adjudication,

often the process is the punishment, for RJ, the process is its own

reward. It is intrinsically good. It is even, some say, “a way of

life”![325] That is reminiscent of the San Francisco Boards whose best

documented accomplishment was the personal growth of the mediators.

However, the heavens are where manna falls from, and good manna is hard

to find. Governments don’t fund RJ, and courts don’t compel criminals to

submit to its loving embrace, because that is the right thing to do.

Governments are not in the right-thing-to do business, although they

have no objection if what they do, for their own reasons, happens to

coincide with the right thing to do. Where governments invent or

incorporate RJ programs, that is partly for public relations, to take

credit for RJ’s dubious utility for crime control. RJ has always

depended on the state for both its funding and its referrals. The trend

is for that dependence to continue and to increase.

Unlike the NJCs, RJ has apparently not claimed to be faster and cheaper

than adjudication, although I may have overlooked something. It couldn’t

very well do that. Certainly that was no part of its original rationale.

Like the NJCs, maybe more so, RJ is labor-intensive. Its facilitators

and convenors are supposed to be graduates of training programs. There

is no pretense this time that they are just volunteer public-spirited

neighborhood people. They are paraprofessionals. They and their support

staffs, have to be paid. The adjudication, except for sentencing, is

usually complete when RJ is called in. RJ can be used for pre-trial or

pre-sentencing diversion;[326] that is its main use in Europe.[327] RJ

diversion programs are apparently less common here.

With noticeable reluctance, the Arjays are making claims that RJ reduces

recidivism (reoffending). That’s because they know which side their

bread is buttered on. They need bread in order to put on their circuses.

An early study by Mark S. Umbreit, whose devotion to RJ is fanatical,

found that RJ reduced recidivism, but the difference was not

statistically significant.[328] Arjays made more of this claim in the

early days when there was little evidence. But now, as another RJ

ideologue ruefully remarks: “They claimed, for example, that restorative

justice would dramatically cut reoffending rates. When it began to be

apparent that it did not, it was easy for politicians, police officers

and others juggling tight budgets to disregard its other possible

benefits.”[329] Actually, often they did discern “other possible

benefits” – to themselves. Discernment is often most acute when

motivated by self-interest.

One major “meta-study” – a study of studies – on the issue of recidivism

was published in 2005. The article makes the point that studies

asserting statistically significant reductions in recidivism “can be

misleading, especially when sample size is small.”[330] They are usually

small: RJ is a boutique version of criminal justice. There are further

pertinent and interesting methodological reservations, which I will

mostly pass over.

To study recidivism, you have to follow up on the offender. Often, these

studies are conducted by the RJ paraprofessionals themselves, who lack

methodological sophistication and who are inclined to follow up on

offenders only as long as it takes to document a happy ending. A few

studies have carried on further. The authors identified 39 studies,

mostly from the United States, whose methodology was, in their view, up

to professional standards.[331] The average interval before a follow-up

study was 17.7 months.[332] That’s not very long. Of almost all

reoffending studies it may be said, as was said of one of them, “the

evaluation did not including contacting respondents again a considerable

time into the future.”[333]

The meta-study concluded:

reductions in recidivism in these minor cases of white male juvenile

delinquency.

recidivism.”

with high-risk offenders. In other words: offenders who were less likely

to reoffend, reoffended less often than offenders who were more likely

to reoffend. That’s brilliant. Just like the conventional court

system.[334]

The authors also report that RJ appears to be becoming more effective

(but that is merely an impression as of 2005). Even if that’s true, the

improvement is offset by the fact that court-ordered RJ programs have no

effect on recidivism. Virtually all RJ programs in the United States,

and probably elsewhere (Australia, New Zealand, Britain) are by now

court-annexed. The best evidence available indicates that these programs

“have no effect on recidivism.”

The main reason why RJ cannot do very much to reduce recidivism is that

RJ cannot do very much of anything, for the same reason the NJCs could

not. The caseloads are too small. Even high rates of success, however

defined, could not have much effect on crime rates. RJ for juvenile

offenders has been in place in New South Wales (where it is administered

by the police) since the 1990s. It claims “modest benefits in reduction

of re-offending compared to court.” But only “between 2 and 4 percent of

police interventions involving young people result in referral to a

youth justice conference.”[335]

The most comprehensive study in Europe of RJ effectiveness, especially

with respect to recidivism, was published in April 2010. It concluded

that evaluations of RJ effectiveness, especially as to recidivism, are

“weak,” often methodologically unsound, “and largely relate impressions

rather than statistical proof.”[336]

As with the NJCs, measurements of success are easy to rig. Cases where

offenders decline RJ – if they have a choice – are not scored as

failures. Cases where victims decline to participate in the charade

(these are much more frequent) are not scored as failures. Cases where

offenders reoffend, but not within the relatively short periods in which

they are followed up on, are not scored as failures. Sample sizes are

small and there is usually not a control group by which to determine if

offenders would not have reoffended anyway if they went through the

conventional court system.[337] There are deeply moving anecdotes, like

the story of the Prodigal Son. But that was not even an anecdote: it was

a parable.

X. “REINTEGRATIVE SHAMING”

Unlike the NJCs, where theory preceded practice, for Restorative

Justice, practice preceded theory. It accumulated various ad hoc

rationales as time went by. But there is a theory, invented by an author

who was then unacquainted with RJ, which some Arjays have pressed into

service: “reintegrative shaming.” In a book published in 1989,[338]

Australian criminologist John Braithwaite argued that “the theory of

reintegrative shaming explains compliance with the law by the moralizing

qualities of social control rather than by its repressive qualities.”

Everywhere, he claims, there is an overwhelming moral consensus in favor

of the criminal law. He thinks that’s a (morally) good thing too. He

further asserts – and this is false – that most people know most of what

the criminal law forbids. Not even most judges and lawyers know that,

not even the specialists. There are, for example, over 175,000 pages in

the Code of Federal Regulations, which is not even complete. Recently, a

court held found that the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services

does not even understand its own regulations.[339] If people knew more

about the law, they would respect it even less than they do.[340]

Braithwaite was unaware of RJ in 1989, but, they were made for each

other. By 2002 he was a major RJ theorist.[341] It is the closest thing

to a theory which RJ has. Not everybody is happy about that. Howard Zehr

writes: “The topic is highly controversial, however, and the best

research [which is not cited] suggests that shame is indeed a factor in

both victimization and offending, but it has to be handled very

carefully. In most situations, the focus needs to be on managing or

transforming shame rather than imposing it.”[342]

Repression is never defined. It approximates the punitive approach

deplored by RJs. It is ineffective (Braithwaite argues) to control

crime. Instead of bringing the offender back into the community, it may

drive him into criminal subcultures which are largely outside the moral

consensus. Instead of being punished in the usual fashion, the criminal

must be made to feel shame, express contrition, and be reconciled to the

community: “A shaming ceremony followed later by a forgiveness and

repentance ceremony[343] more potently builds commitment to the law than

one-sided moralizing.” Braithwaite identifies few such ceremonies, but,

RJ was already performing such ceremonies.

If criminals believe so staunchly in the criminal law, they should not

need a ceremony to remind them to be ashamed of themselves. The criminal

justice process, which is a sequence of degradation ceremonies beginning

with arrest, will provide painful reminders. Braithwaite admits this.

But his way of shaming is different, and better:

The distinction is between shaming that leads to stigmatization – to

outcasting, to confirmation of a deviant master status – versus shaming

that is reintegrative, that shames while maintaining bonds of respect or

love, that sharply terminates disapproval with forgiveness, instead of

amplifying social deviance by progressively casting the deviant out.

Reintegrative shaming controls crime; stigmatization pushes offenders

toward criminal subcultures.

But what if, as is often the case, the offender is already a member of a

criminal subculture? What if there are no “bonds of respect or love”?

Bonds with whom? The victim? Braithwaite isn’t interested in victims.

Thus far this is not a “theory,” merely a hypothesis, because it doesn’t

explain anything, although (as Braithwaite claims) it may not be

inconsistent with the criminological research available in 1989. He

needs some sociological underpinning. It’s the usual: “Individuals are

more susceptible to shaming when they enmeshed in multiple relationships

of interdependency; societies shame more effectively when they are

communitarian.” In other words, multiplex relationships, cross-cutting

ties, and roots in a stable community. Braithwaite is even more evasive

about what a community is than his future allies the Arjays. He appears

to consider Japan – the poster child for reintegrative shaming – to be a

community. The word he should have fumbled for was “culture.”

Braithwaite proposes a “family model of the criminal process:

reintegrative shaming.” It is nothing of the sort. Japan is not a

family. American cities, and their neighborhoods, are mostly nothing

like families. Even some of their families are nothing like families on

the traditional model. So, like some Arjays, he speaks of “communities

of interest” – this one goes all the way back to Richard Danzig’s

get-together of the juvenile loiterer, the nervous store owner, and

anybody else he could think of. If reintegrative shaming works – just as

for RJ -- it only works in exceptional circumstances. It’s not a new

paradigm for criminal justice. It’s another peripheral state-controlled

practice. If operationalized, it would have a negligible effect on crime

rates. Some RJ processes do operationalize the theory, more or less. We

have seen that the results are unimpressive.

The “family model” is appropriate – if even then – to only one

institution: the family itself. And the modern nuclear family has many

cogent critics, including feminists and anarchists.

RJ processes, such victim-offender conferences, are mostly futile, but

mostly harmless -- although it bears remembering that in one study, 25%

of the victims felt worse afterwards. Reintegrative shaming is

potentially dangerous, as even Braithwaite admits: “However, for all

types of crime, shaming runs the risk of counterproductivity when it

shades into stigmatization.” The social engineering for shaming to be

reliably reintegrative rather than stigmatizing does not exist and it

never will. In Japan, they have a long history of shaming. It can be

reintegrative. But Japanese who have been shamed may commit suicide.

Braithwaite has next to nothing to say about how to institutionalize

reintegrative shaming in a (as he sees it) extremely individualistic

society such as the United States. He can only express hope that this

country is (as he thought it might be) moving slowly in a communitarian

direction. It wasn’t. He wrote this book while Ronald Reagan was

President! And the United States is still not, in any sense of the word,

communitarian. That would require a social revolution. A social

revolution would require that many people reject the supposed moral

consensus in support of the criminal law.

If the word “community” is vague to the point of often being

meaningless, “communitarian” is worse. It appears, often more than once,

on 28 of Braithwaite’s 186 pages. His definition of “communitarianism”:

“(1) densely intermeshed dependency, where the interdependency is

characterized by (2) mutual obligation and trust, and (3) are

interpreted as a matter of group loyalty rather than individual

convenience. Communitarianism is therefore the antithesis of

individualism.” Another word for the antithesis of individualism is

“authoritarianism.”

If any modern industrial country approximates communitarianism, the

author does not say so. Japan does not. Even Singapore does not. His (1)

characterizes any society with a complex division of labor. His (2) does

not characterize any state. His (3), a vulgarization of the Greek,

Roman, and colonial American ideologies of public virtue, in modern

societies characterizes only fascist states . No admittedly fascist

state now exists, although North Korea and possibly Singapore are good

for (3). Even Braithwaite admits that he would not want to live in

Japan. It never occurs to him that some of these three characteristics

may be in tension with some of the others. That would explain why they

are never all found together. Why, in other words, communitarian

societies are nonexistent. Modern state societies cannot be

communitarian. Their legal systems cannot be communitarian.

Braithwaite understands that social control is almost completely based

on informal sanctioning. I often make this point. But the criminal

justice system, by definition, cannot engage in informal sanctioning. It

is, by definition, formal. My thesis throughout this essay is that

formal state justice is incompatible with informal justice. Supporters

of the NJCs back in the day, and supporters of RJ today, have tried and

failed to squirm out of this dilemma. In this book anyway, Braithwaite

has not even tried.

Braithwaite occasionally nods at primitive societies, but he may know

even less about them than the early Arjays did. Consider my examples of

primitive societies. Ifugao disputing is, to borrow a word from

Braithwaite, the antithesis of reintegrative shaming. Its purpose is to

achieve reconciliation, or at least forbearance, without shaming

anybody. The Ifugaos are proud individualists. Nobody apologizes for

anything. Among the Plateau Tonga, likewise, shaming plays no role. The

Kpelle “moot” is the only example which is even superficially similar to

reintegrative shaming. It involves a group process or ceremony,

culminating in a public, pro forma apology by the wrongdoer. What

follows is not absolution, but rather a beer party on the defendant’s

dime. Nobody has to be reintegrated because nobody was deintegrated in

the first place. There was merely a dispute. When, in a primitive

society, an intolerable person is finally deintegrated – outlawed – that

is irreversible. Then he is dead meat.

One of Braithwaite’s many shortcomings is that he does not, as he

admits, really understand the difference, in practice, between guilt and

shame. In this respect he resembles the Puritans, perhaps not as they

really were, but as they are portrayed in The Scarlet Letter. For him,

shaming just is making someone feel guilty. No doubt shame and guilt are

often both involved in particular cases. That may be a reason to avoid

both of them.

Although the subject is too large to develop here, guilt corresponds to

a felt sense of sin, whereas shame corresponds to a felt sense of

dishonor. Dishonor can result, not only from what you do, but from what

someone does to you, where that is publicly known. Absolution from sin

results from contrition and forgiveness. Shame is dispelled by erasing

the dishonor by revenge or by – if accepted – an equivalent, by

compensation. Guilt and shame, although they can be confused by the

confused, are fundamentally different.

The difference between guilt cultures (like ours) and shame cultures

(such as Japan, Homeric Greece, other Mediterranean societies, and

Muslim societies) has been discussed by various scholars, and

Braithwaite is somewhat acquainted with the literature,[344] although he

has trouble understanding it. Very likely, the distinction is also lost

on most other Australians, Americans and Westerners. In shaking off our

aristocracies, we also shook off their values, instead of generalizing

them. Nietzsche deplored this. So do I. Raoul Vaneigem, in a wonderful

phrase, called for “masters without slaves,”[345] but the masses are a

conglomeration of slaves, either with, or -- more or less -- without

masters. Their servitude is voluntary.[346] Where no master is

available, people enslave themselves. They have, as Stirner reproached

them, wheels in their heads.[347]

Shame culture is not extinct in Western societies. But there, the sense

of honor is either a personal value, or else a value for what

Braithwaite calls criminal subcultures (of which he disapproves).[348]

It’s not a value for leftists. It’s not a value for feminists. It’s not

a value for most radicals. It’s not even a value for anarchists who

suppose that they are avant garde. In fact, among them, I’ve found less

of a sense of honor, and less of a sense of solidarity, than among any

kind of people I have ever associated with. There is more honor on

elementary school playgrounds. And on ghetto streets. The notion that an

injury to one is an injury to all elicits only laughter in the Bay Area

anarchist scene. That is something to put on the masthead of an IWW

newspaper, not to put into practice.

However, the main problem with reintegrative shaming is that -- as a

matter of social psychology -- it is, as a crime-control policy, totally

wrong. Shaming is not the main solution to crime. Shaming is the main

cause of crime. At least, it’s the main cause of the violent crimes

which inspire so much fear. James Gilligan, a psychiatrist who worked

for many years with the most violent criminals in Massachusetts prisons,

has written about this. Violent criminals are people (mostly men) who

have been shamed: “the basic psychological motive, or cause, of violent

behavior is to ward off or eliminate the feeling of shame or humiliation

– a feeling that is painful, and that can be intolerable and

overwhelming – and replace it with its opposite, a feeling of

pride.”[349] One implication, which is consistent with such as there is

of anarchist criminology, is that “punishment is the most violent

stimulus to violent behavior that we have discovered. . . . Punishment

does not prevent crime, it causes it.”[350] Kropotkin and Berkman would

have agreed. Where respect is not spontaneously forthcoming, the direct

and certain way to gain respect is by instilling fear.[351] This is also

how police, who are despised by everybody, coerce respect.

Who’s right, Braithwaite or Gilligan? Usually much more Gilligan than

Braithwaite, in my opinion. More important, why should either opinion be

institutionalized by the state? Because these theories are irrelevant

unless they are, as they both obviously are, policy prescriptions. They

have written advice books for rulers, like the medieval and Renaissance

books which were often titled A Mirror for Princes. Erasmus wrote one,

under another title. Machiavelli’s The Prince is another example,

although not a typical example. The state has usually ignored the advice

of criminologists, even when it was good advice. May that continue.

XI. THE ANARCHIST ACADEMICS: A SORRY STORY

The anarchist academics are by now almost as welcome in academia as the

Marxist academics are, and for the same reason. They’re harmless, but

they add a touch of the picturesque. Their inclusion is all the easier

because they are almost indistinguishable from the Marxists, who by now

have tenure. What, then, does an anarchist criminologist espouse? Not

anarchy! He espouses “restorative justice.”

I’ve already scorned Larry Tifft & Dennis Sullivan, who are apparently

the first avowed anarchist criminologists. They are bleeding-heart

radicals with a conventional leftist critique of law and the state as

tools of the powerful -- only their version is sentimental and mystical.

Despite their opportunity to be more up- to- date and well-informed than

the classical anarchists, these two, in their 1980 book, added nothing

to the stale old leftist critique except a few hippie grace notes. I

thought they would drop out of the academy. Given their ideology, they

could no more make research contributions to criminology (necessary for

tenure) than a creation scientist could make research contributions to

biology (necessary for tenure).

Instead, they found a way to have it both ways: Restorative Justice. A

review comparing their 1980 and 2001 books recognized that the second is

to some degree an attempt to redress the shortcomings of the first, but

“it is still the case that specific details as to how alternative

systems would deal with acts such as theft, assault, rape, or murder are

sorely lacking here.”[352]

A 1998 article by one Jeff Ferrell, now Professor of Sociology at Texas

Christian University -- which has been reprinted in at least five

anthologies which I have no intention of looking at -- is just an

epitome of Tifft & Sullivan (1980), adding nothing except a few

post-modernist grace notes.[353] But by then, Tifft & Sullivan had

discovered Restorative Justice. Today, these anarchists are among the

foremost expositors and advocates of RJ. Ferrell has apparently not

dabbled in Restorative Justice. It’s not edgy enough.

I’ve come across several brief online articles linking anarchism to RJ

without showing any critical understanding of either.[354] I came along

another one by Brian Gumm – yet another guy whose name is not yet a

household word in anarchist households – “The Anarchist Genius of

Restorative Justice?” He is a “lay theologian,” a former student of

Howard Zehr, and, like Zehr, a Mennonite.[355] If Howard Zehr is an

anarchist, which he has never claimed, he has fooled everybody,

including himself, for forty years. The only thing anarchism and

Restorative Justice have in common is that they are currently

fashionable. For both, their vogue may be waning.

Throughout my relatively long life, there have been fads and fashions.

That time includes my several involvements with academia. My impression

is that the pace is increasingly speeded up, and the turnover is faster

(is this “future shock”?). The mini-skirt fashion of the 1960s, despite

the bitter resistance of gay fashion designers, stubbornly persisted for

longer than did the NJC fad of the 1980s. Of course there still exists

the occasional NJC, just as one occasionally sees a jeune fille in a

mini-skirt. More often, actually.

RJ may still be expanding, here and around the world. It may never go

away, as the NJCs (however labeled) will never go away, because RJ has

been institutionalized in court systems, universities, consulting firms,

NGOs, and in demi-academic journals like the Dispute Resolution Magazine

(published , I repeat, by the American Bar Association) and the

International Journal of Dispute Resolution. And also in court-annexed

reconciliation processes, benevolently operated by state-paid

paraprofessionals. There are many conferences. There are many training

programs for practitioners in many countries, and at least one graduate

degree program. There are grants. All this replicates, and indeed

outdoes, the NJC history.

And yet, for the anarcho-liberals Tifft & Sullivan, RJ will always be

“at its core a form of insurgency and subversive in nature.”[356] Tifft

& Sullivan still pretend to be outsiders. I don’t doubt their commitment

and sincerity. But it’s not unusual to find in the same person a pure

heart and an empty head. Tifft & Sullivan are obviously not outsiders.

Outsiders would not have been invited to edit the Handbook of

Restorative Justice. The nondynamic duo would be the Prodigal Sons of

academia, except that they have never been prodigal. They didn’t have to

go home again. They never left.

Not only Tifft & Sullivan, but lots of other Arjays of the writing kind,

have repeated, long after it became monotonous, that RJ is really great:

it’s the conquering new “paradigm.” Poor Thomas Kuhn! We just have to

expand RJ -- somehow – to tackle the structural sources, the economic

and social sources of interpersonal crime.[357] Never repudiate RJ:

always expand it. But that would mean, not resolving individual

conflicts, but rather fomenting social conflicts. There are no

individualized answers to what used to be called the Social Question. “A

criminology which remains fixed at the level of individualism,” writes

John Braithwaite, “is the criminology of a bygone era.”[358] Any

criminology is fixed at the level of individualism, and largely fails to

fix anything.

For Arjays, and not just the Mennonites, social conflict is bad!

Violence is especially bad! (except when it is state violence to

implement Restorative Justice). Sullivan & Tifft like to invoke

Kropotkin, but Kropotkin was unequivocally a class-struggle

revolutionary anarchist. They have written approvingly of workplace

arrangements, with “restorative structures and practices,” under which

workers are treated a little better than usual, their ideas are listened

to, they are allowed a measure of self-managed servitude, and they

receive a stable income. Never mind that these enlightened businesses

are all but nonexistent. These pacifists of course commend a program for

worker pacification -- another of their lion-and-lamb scenarios: “When

this level of well-being exists in a workplace, feelings of envy and

resentment toward [higher-paid] co-workers and coordinators are

significantly reduced. People feel restored.”[359] And work harder!

They’re suckers. Or rather, they would be suckers, if they existed. This

never happens.

“Coordinators” is a euphemism for bosses. The class-collaboration

ideology which Tifft & Sullivan witlessly endorse is nothing less (well,

maybe even less) than the old “Progressive human resource management

(HRM)” perspective in industrial relations studies, which is almost

forgotten today.[360] During their many tranquil years in the academy,

the American workplace has become a harsher place of longer hours and

more dangerous conditions over which workers, whose levels of

unionization have fallen sharply, have less influence than ever.[361]

And yet Tifft & Sullivan intuit an “increased sensitivity” of bosses to

the personal needs of workers![362] It’s obvious that in all their

lives, neither of these guys has ever had a real job.

Anarchists should actively combat Restorativist influences everywhere.

We want a new world. We don’t want to “restore” anything. Let’s be

lions, not lambs.

The expansion and entrenchment of RJ are directly proportionate to its

institutionalization by the state. If some of the earliest RJ programs

maintained some autonomy from the state – I haven’t come across any

examples – they are all now nothing but minor, auxiliary parts of the

criminal justice system. They are on as long or as short a leash as

courts, prosecutors and police allow them under the local arrangements.

The solution has, as usual, become part of the problem. By its

voluntarist and humanist pretenses, RJ in a small way legitimates the

criminal justice system, and maybe it opiates a few people, as religion

sometimes does.

It may be that Restorative Justice is becoming passé. An imposing

Handbook of Criminological Theory published in 2016 does not mention

it.[363]

The trouble with criminal justice reforms is that nothing ever goes

away. Penitentiaries (the very name – evoking “penitence” -- reveals an

affinity with RJ), insane asylums, probation, parole, pre-trial

diversion, compulsory schooling, indeterminate sentencing, determinate

sentencing, juvenile courts, small claims courts, drug courts, community

justice centers, community policing, RJ, reintegrative shaming – we

still have all of them somewhere, and we have most of them everywhere.

Their coexistence is proof that the system is incoherent. But coherence

is not a requirement for social control. In Germany, the Nazi Party, the

Gestapo, the S.S., military courts, state police, local police and local

courts had overlapping, often vaguely defined jurisdictions. There were

jails, prisons, mental hospitals, labor camps and concentration camps

operated by various authorities – something for everybody who fell afoul

of a Kafkaesque system: “The confusion of powers liberated policy-makers

from the constraints of morality and law.” [364] Redundancy is

functional for systems.

Anarchist criminologists can probably do little to de-legitimate the

state. But they can do at least as much as I’ve done here. Instead, they

legitimate the state by indirection, by pretending that there isn’t

always an iron fist inside the velvet glove. Unlike me, they get paid to

write books and articles. They are writing the wrong books and articles.

Aside from Ferrell’s 1998 article in Social Anarchism, the

anarcho-criminologists have hitherto not, to my knowledge, addressed

their fellow anarchists. And Ferrell said nothing about RJ, with which

by then he must have been familiar. RJ programs originated around the

time the NJCs did, and they have long outlived them, regrettably. But,

like the NJCs, they have never involved large numbers of participants

from the general public (or “the community”). Most people generally,

like most anarchists, and like most students of criminal justice, have

heard little or nothing of RJ, as Sullivan & Tifft admit.[365] This is

one reason why RJ programs persist undisturbed, off in a corner of the

criminal justice system.[366] Nobody cares if they work or not. They

work for those who work in them.

Restorative justice, even as idealized by Tifft & Sullivan, is

incompatible even with their own pacifism. Their statism, pacifism and

mysticism are mutually incoherent, as well as incompatible with any type

of anarchism. It is just as well that the anarchists are ignorant of RJ.

But it is not so well that they have not advanced beyond their

traditional, somewhat outdated, and incomplete critique of law to

envisage anarchist societies with disputing processes which are as

voluntary as life in society allows for.

To my regret, the criminologists are finally trying to make some inroads

among anarchists. On March 26-27, 2016, there was held the “1^(st)

Annual Anarchism, Crime, and Justice Conference at Fort Lewis College in

Durango, Colorado, USA.” According to the announcement: “This conference

is structured around challenging and abolishing punitive justice, while

promoting community-based alternatives such as restorative justice,

transformative justice and Hip Hop battling. . . . “ There follows a

long list of the standard leftist Social Justice Warrior issues: 27

“topics of interest.” One of them is “green anarchism”; another is

“anarchism.” [367] Two workshops on anarchism out of 27. At this

anarchist conference, as at some earlier ones, the anarchism is an

afterthought. The organizer was Anthony Nocella II, whom I have

previously abused here.

There is no suspicion that possibly “justice” itself has become, for

modern anarchists, a problematic goal or value. The anarchist correct

line on criminal justice, has – unknown to the vast majority of

anarchists – been authoritatively settled. Anarchists are to be for

restorative justice, transformative justice, and Hip Hop battling

(whatever that is). I’m sure some anarchists have heard of Hip Hop

battling (I haven’t, but, I am an elderly white man), but probably not

the other stuff. If it resembles the “song duels” among the Eskimos, who

were anarchists – where disputants, face to face, sing insulting songs

about each other, and the audience reacts – well, that might be one

anarchist dispute resolution mechanism.[368] It seems inappropriate,

however, in cases of securities fraud, armed robbery, identity theft,

homicide and rape.

Neighborhood Justice Centers were, I’ve argued, not a solution to any

social problem. But I agree with their focus on disputes, not on crimes

as such. Some crimes are unilateral predation, not bilateral disputes.

But most crimes, including most of the most feared crimes, arise from

disputes. Restorative Justice and reintegrative shaming, although they

purport to reject repressive, punitive justice, in fact fundamentally

agree with its conservative, individualist, right-and-wrong,

law-and-order, crime-and-punishment conception of interpersonal

conflict. Beware Mennonite probation officers and armed humanists.

Shaming, officially administered, is obviously punishment. That

conception, I’ve argued,[369] is incompatible with anarchism. And,

anarchism aside (where it is likely always to remain), that approach is

costly, cruel, oppressive, and even on its own terms a disastrous

failure. The only within-the-system reform which would represent a

substantial improvement would be substantial de-criminalization.[370]

But less of more of the same is not enough.

In a modern anarchist society, as in primitive anarchist societies, the

emphasis would be on dispute resolution, not on sin, guilt, shame,

crime, and punishment. There would be no law, especially no moralizing

law such as Braithwaite and other conservatives endorse. Moralizing law

is the major source of mass incarceration, police brutality, and most

violent crime. But it generates business for politicians, police, the

private prison industry, Fox News commentators, organized crime, and

criminology professors. Including the criminology professors who

organize conferences on anarchism, criminology and justice. Unless the

anarchists offer a radical alternative, they will continue to be

scorned, and rightly so.

[1] Donald Black with M.P. Baumgartner, “Toward a Theory of the Third

Party,” in Donald Black, The Social Structure of Right and Wrong (San

Diego, CA: Academic Press, 1993), 110-115 (originally 1983).

[2] Laura Nader & Harry F. Todd, Jr., “Introduction: The Disputing

Process,” in The Disputing Process – Law in Ten Societies, ed. Laura

Nader & Harry F. Todd, Jr. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1978),

9-10. Despite the title of their book, they profess neutrality as to

“the question whether these procedures are law or social control or

‘merely’ custom. “ Ibid., 8. Many people, including myself, draw a stark

distinction between law (regarded as statist) and custom (regarded as

anarchist). E.g., Donald Black, The Behavior of Law (New York: Academic

Press, 1976), 2 (defining law as “governmental social control”); Stanley

Diamond, “The Rule of Law versus the Order of Custom,” in The Rule of

Law, ed. Robert Paul Wolff (New York: Simon & Schuster, Touchstone

Books, 1971), 116-17.

[3] E.g., E. Colson, “Social Control and Vengeance in Plateau Tonga

Society,” Africa 23(3) (July 1953), 199-200, reprinted as chapter 3 of

Elizabeth Colson, The Plateau Tonga of Northern Rhodesia: Social and

Religious Studies (Manchester, England: Manchester University Press,

1962); Diamond, “The Rule of Law versus the Order of Custom,” 135; R.F.

Barton, Ifugao Law (Berkeley & Los Angeles, CA: University of California

Press, 1969), “Preface” (n.p.) & 3 (originally1919).

[4] E.g., A. Morfus, “Beyond Utopian Visions,” in Uncivilized: The Best

of Green Anarchy (n.p.; Green Anarchy Press, 2012).

[5] P.H. Gulliver, “Case Studies of Law in Non-Western Societies:

Introduction,” in Law and Culture in Society, ed. Laura Nader (Berkeley,

CA: University of California Press, 1997), 21 (originally 1969).

[6] Donald Black, “The Elementary Forms of Conflict Management,” Social

Structure of Right and Wrong, 83.

[7] Ibid., 14; Frank E.A. Sander, “Varieties of Dispute Processing,” in

Roman M. Tomasic & Malcolm M. Feeley, eds., Neighborhood Justice:

Assessment of an Emerging Idea (New York & London: Longman, 1982), 38 n.

4 (originally1976); Richard E. Miller & Austin Sarat, “Grievances,

Claims, and Disputes: Assessing the Adversary Culture,” Law & Society

Rev. 15(3, 4) (1980-1981): 525-566.

[8] But it is more common than is generally believed. Donald Black,

“Crime as Social Control,” in Towards a General Theory of Social

Control, ed. Donald Black (Orlando, FL: Academic Press, 1984), 2: 1-27,

reprinted in Social Structure of Right and Wrong, 27-46; Bob Black,

“’Wild Justice’: Crime as an Anarchist Source of Social Order,” Defacing

the Currency: Selected Writings, 1992-2012 (Berkeley, CA: LBC Books,

2012), 233-267.

[9] Elijah Anderson, Code of the Street: Decency, Violence, and the

Moral Life of the Inner City (New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 1999); Black,

“Crime as Social Control.”

[10] William L.F. Felsteiner, “Influences of Social Organization on

Dispute Processing,” in Neighborhood Justice, 54.

[11] M.P. Baumgartner, The Moral Order of a Suburb (New York & Oxford:

Oxford University Press, 1988), 11.

[12] “Mediation – Its Forms and Functions,” in The Principles of Social

Order: Selected Essays of Lon L. Fuller, ed. Kenneth I. Winston (Durham,

NC: Duke University Press, 1981), 133; see also The Sociology of Georg

Simmel, ed. Kurt Wolff (New York: The Free Press, 1950), 118-169.

[13] Simon Roberts, Order and Dispute: An Introduction to Legal

Anthropology (Oxford, England: Martin Robertson, 1979), 72.

[14] Gulliver, “On Mediators,” 16, 46.

[15] W.L.F. Felstiner, Richard Abel, & Austin Sarat, “The Emergence and

Transformation of Disputes: Naming, Blaming, Claiming . . . ,” Law &

Society Rev. 15 (1980-1981), 635-37.

[16] Felsteiner, “Influences of Social Organization on Dispute

Processing,” 48.

[17] Social Workers and Alternative Dispute Resolution (Washington, DC:

National Association of Social Workers, 2014), 7.

[18] Roberts, Order and Dispute, 97.

[19] Richard Borshay Lee, The !Kung San: Men, Women, and Work in a

Foraging Society (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 370-398;

Roberts, Order and Dispute, 84.

[20] Black, “Elementary Forms of Conflict Management,” 80.

[21] Asen Balici, The Netsilik Eskimo (Garden City, NY: Natural History

Press, 1970), 192-93.

[22] Black, “The Elementary Forms of Conflict Management,” 80; Albert O.

Hirschman, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms,

Organizations, and States (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1970),

ch. 3 & passim.

[23] Baumgartner, Moral Order of a Suburb, ch. 3.

[24] Lee, The !Kung San, 398.

[25] Klaus-Friedrich Koch, “Pigs and Politics in the New Guinea

Highlands,” in Nader & Todd, Disputing Process, 41-58. The article is

adapted from Klaus-Friedrich Koch, War and Peace in Jalémó: The

Management of Conflict in Highland New Guinea (Cambridge: Harvard

University Press, 1974). Curiously, the famous McHoy/Hatfield feud also

originated in a dispute over a pig. Black, “’Wild Justice,’” 252 & n.

45; Alina L. Walker, Feud: Hatfields, McCoys, and Social Change in

Appalachia, 1860-1900 (London & Chapel Hill, NC: University of North

Carolina Press, 1988), 2-3.

[26] Roberts, Order and Dispute, 158.

[27] Sarah Rudolph Cole & Kristen M. Blankley, “Arbitration,” in The

Handbook of Dispute Resolution , ed. Michael L. Moffitt & Robert C.

Bordone (San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass, 2005), 318-19; Roberts, Order

and Dispute, 70-71, 135.

[28] A.S. Meyer, “Functions of the Mediator in Collective Bargaining,”

Industrial & Labor Relations Rev. 13 (1960), 164. “However the two

processes have a way of shading into each other.” Ibid.

[29] Social Workers and Alternative Dispute Resolution, 4-5; American

Arbitration Association, “The Code of Ethics for Arbitration in

Commercial Disputes,” May 1, 2004, & idem; “Code of Professional

Responsibility for Arbitrators of Labor Management Disputes,” Sept.

2007, at htpps://www.adr.org.

[30] Carrie Menkel-Meadow, “Roots and Inspirations: A Brief History of

the Foundations of Dispute Resolution,” in Handbook of Dispute

Resolution, 318.

[31] Social Workers and Alternative Dispute Resolution, 5; Michael L.

Moffitt & Robert C. Bordone, ”Perspectives on Dispute Resolution: An

Introduction,” Handbook of Dispute Resolution, 21.

[32] In re American Express Merchants’ Litigation v. American Express,

634 F.2d 182 (2d Cir. 2011).

[33] Mandatory Binding Arbitration Agreements: Are They Fair for

Consumers? hearing before the Subcommittee on Commercial and

Administrative Law of the Committee on the Judiciary, House of

Representatives, 110^(th) Cong., 1^(st) sess., June 12, 2007; Federal

Arbitration Act: Is the Credit Card Industry Using It to Quash Legal

Claims? hearing before the Subcommittee on Commercial and Administrative

Law of the Committee on the Judiciary, House of Representatives,

111^(th) Cong., 1^(st) sess., May 5, 2009; Arbitration or Arbitrary: The

Misuse of Mandatory Arbitration to Collect Consumer Debts: hearing

before the Subcommittee on Domestic Policy of the Committee on Oversight

and Governmental Reform, House of Representatives, 111^(th) Cong.,

1^(st) sess., July 22, 2009; Mandatory Binding Arbitration: Is It Fair

and Voluntary? hearing before the Subcommittee on Commercial and

Administrative Law of the Committee on the Judiciary, House of

Representatives, 111^(th) Cong., 1^(st) sess., Sept. 15, 2009;

Arbitration: Is it Fair When Forced? hearing before the Committee on the

Judiciary, U.S. Senate, 112^(th) Cong., 1^(st) sess., Oct. 13, 2011.

[34] Rent-a-Center West, Inc. v. Jackson, 561 U.S. 63, 72 (2010).

“Rent-to-own” is one of the worst rackets for exploiting low-income

consumers.

[35] David Horton & Andrea Camm Chandrasekher, “After the Revolution: An

Empirical Study of Consumer Arbitration,” Georgetown L.J. 104(1) (Nov.

2015), 124.

[36] Roberts, Order and Dispute, 163-64.

[37] Felsteiner, “Influences of Social Organization on Dispute

Processing,” 48; Kenneth I. Winston, “Introduction,” The Principles of

Social Order, 28-29.

[38] Sander, “Varieties of Dispute Processing,” 28.

[39] Black, “Toward a Theory of the Third Party,” Social Organization of

Right and Wrong, 114.

[40] Fuller, “The Forms and Limits of Adjudication,” Principles of

Social Order, 93-94.

[41] Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254, 271 (1969).

[42] Robert C. Davis, “Mediation: The Brooklyn Experiment,” Neighborhood

Justice, 156.

[43] Donald L. Horowitz, The Courts and Social Policy (Washington, DC:

The Brookings Institution, 1977), 45, 48.

[44] Jerome Frank, Courts on Trial: Myth and Reality in American Justice

(New York: Atheneum, 1963) (originally 1949).

[45] Nader & Todd, “Introduction,” 10.

[46] E.g., James L. Gibbs, Jr., “The Kpelle Moot,” in Paul Bohannan,

ed., Law and Warfare: Studies in the Anthropology of Conflict (Garden

City, NY: The American Museum of Natural History, 1967), 282-83.

[47] “What appear to us [sic] as hopelessly confusing ambiguities of

role were probably not perceived as such either by the occupant of the

role [the mediator, the monkulun] or by those subject to his

ministrations.” [Fuller,] “Mediation – Its Forms and Functions,” 156. Of

course Fuller is hopelessly confused when he looks for his Platonic

Forms and finds only reality. Laura Nader’s work in a Mexican town

“illustrates how a single person, the president, may be mediator,

adjudicator, and arbitrator all in one day.” Nader & Todd,

“Introduction,” 10. The “style” of adjudication may be penal,

compensatory, therapeutic, or conciliatory. Donald Black, The Behavior

of Law (New York: Academic Press, 1976), 4-5.

[48] Michel Foucault, “Truth and Power,” The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul

Rabinow (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), 61.

[49] Foucault, “Politics and Ethics: An Interview,” in ibid., 379.

[50] Gullivers, “On Mediators,” 16.

[51] Barton . Ifugao Law, 87, 88-89.

[52] Horowitz, The Courts and Social Policy, 24.

[53] “Friendly peacemakers tend to be about equal to the adversaries,

whereas mediators, arbitrators, and adjudicators tend to be (in the same

order) increasingly elevated above the adversaries.” Black, “Elementary

Forms of Conflict Management,” 86. This issue came up after I delivered,

as a speech, a version of this article in Manila. One of the formal

responders gave his own speech in praise of the Katarungang Pambarangay

(or Barangay Justice System) in the Philippines. It provides, on a

neighborhood or village basis, for compulsory mediation of certain kinds

of disputes between residents of the same barangay (the smallest unit of

government). The mediators consist of a barangay “captain,” an elected

official, in association with conciliation committees of local

residents. The system remotely resembles some earlier indigenous dispute

resolution institutions, such as that of the Ifugao. From the little I

know of them, they may not have some of the defects which vitiated our

Neighborhood Justice Centers (infra). The barangays are much smaller,

and probably more homogeneous than the catchment areas of the NJCs. This

system probably moves faster than the regular courts, and lawyers are

not necessary – in fact, they are banned. It has reliable permanent

financing from the national government. In the United States, parties to

lawsuits, or involved in criminal prosecutions, may feel like the

proceedings are conducted in a foreign language. In the Philippines,

they actually are. In the regular courts, proceedings are conducted in

English, and the English language proficiency of Filipinos, as I learned

during a 17 day visit, varies widely. In the barangay courts, the local

language is used.

The system was initiated in 1975, by Presidential Decree No. 1508 – by

President Ferdinand Marcos, who had assumed dictatorial power and

imposed martial law. He had political reasons for doing that.

Nonetheless, in three villages in Cebu Province, the rural population in

the 1970’s accepted the system as useful for them. G. Sidney Silliman,

“A Political Analysis of the Philippines’ Katarungang Pambarangay System

of Informal Justice Through Mediation,” Law & Soc’y Rev. 19(2) (1985):

279-302. Obviously I lack up-to-date sources. But it is at least clear

that this system of informal justice is not, as it has been called, a

non-state justice system. S. Golub, ‘Non-State Justice Systems in

Bangadesh and the Phillipines” (2003), Department for International

Development (London),

http://www.gsdrc.org/go/display/document/

legacyid/825.

[54] This example, and all the others I discuss, are based on

observations of peoples subject to Western colonialism. Elizabeth Colson

was an employee of the British colonial regime. The dispute processing

institutions all existed by the recognition or sufferance of the

colonial powers, which created formal court systems for what they

considered serious crimes and claims. The indigenous disputing processes

were, therefore, subordinate parts of what are now called “dual” legal

systems. However, their subordinate position did not detract from the

fact that, within the jurisdiction allowed to them, they generally

worked. As Colson writes, “These [traditional forms] still work to reach

a settlement over and above that which can be obtained through the

courts. They are interested, not in the punishment of the offenders, but

in the re-establishment of good relations between the groups involved.”

Colson, “Social Control and Vengeance,” 204.

[55] Colson, “Social Control,” 199-200, 210-211.

[56] Barton states as the general rule that unintentional homicides are

compensable, but, that is at the option of the victim’s kin. One of his

informants insisted that if a hunter through carelessness in handling

his spear caused a death, that would not be compensable. Barton,

Autobiography, 182. That may reflect a local variation in the law, or,

it occurs to me, a distinction between an innocent and a negligent

homicide. Ifugaos consider a drunk not to be blameworthy. In U.S. law,

voluntary intoxication mitigates but does not excuse a homicide.

[57] “The word monkalun comes from the root kalun, meaning advise. The

Ifugao word has the double sense, too, of our word advise, as used in

the following sentences, ‘I have the honor to advise you of your

appointment!’ and ‘I advise you not to do that.’” Barton, Ifugao Law, 87

n. 19.

[58] P.H. Gulliver, “On Mediators,” in Social Anthropology and Law, ed.

Ian Hamnett (London: Academic Press, 1977), 33.

[59] P.H. Gulliver, “Dispute Settlement Without Courts: The Ndeneuli of

Southern Tanzania,” in Law in Culture and Society, ed. Laura Nadar

(Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1997), 67 (originally

1969).

[60] Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man, 110-111.

[61] Black, Behavior of Law, 40-41.

[62] Black, Behavior of Law, 41 (emphasis deleted).

[63] Peter Kropotkin, Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution (Boston, MA:

Extending Horizons Books, 1960), 113 (emphasis added) (originally

published 1902). I would like to thank Michael Disnevic (letter to Bob

Black, March 3, 2016) for reminding me to re-view this book. Kropotkin

held the curious belief that international law, because it is customary

law (which is not entirely true), embodies values of mutual aid and

equality. Idem, “A New Work on International Law,” The Speaker (April 1,

1905, 7-8).

[64] Max Gluckman, The Ideas in Barotse Jurisprudence (2d ed.; New

Haven, CT & London: Yale University Press, 1967), 19-20; Max Gluckman,

The Judicial Process Among the Barotse of Northern Rhodesia (Manchester,

England, UK: Manchester University Press, 1965), 5-6.

[65] “Such ties usually arise from residential proximity or common

membership in an organization, and they are only rarely buttressed by

shared employment, joint ownership of possessions, participation in a

closed social network, or economic interdependence.” Baumgartner, Moral

Order of a Suburb, 9.

[66] Gluckman, Judicial Process Among the Barotse of Northern Rhodesia,

20-21.

[67] Malcolm M. Feeley, The Process Is the Punishment: Handling Cases in

a Lower Criminal Court (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 1979), ch. 8.

[68] He later became U.S. Secretary of the Navy – this was under

President Bill Clinton. The U.S. military prefers unilateral, coercive

dispute resolution. Danzig’s wife is a psychotherapist.

[69] The Kpelle made a previous appearance in my writings, for the way

they organize and carry out work (they do not like hard work) in a

relatively ludic way. Bob Black, “Primitive Affluence: A Postscript to

Sahlins.” Friendly Fire (Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia, 1992), 30-31; Bob

Black, Instead of Work (Berkeley, CA: LBC Books, 2015), 49-50. The

former military dictator of Guinea, Moïse Dadis Camara, is a Kpelle.

According to DNA testing, Oprah Winfrey is of Kpelle ancestry. She

thought her ancestors were Zulus. DNA evidence yields important clues to

individual identity. According to my test, I am 1% Finnish.

[70] Gibbs, “The Kpelle Moot,” 277-289.

[71] The documentary sources “do not give any clue whatever to the

nature and form” – or the functions and procedures – “of the assembly.”

George Laurence Gomme, Primitive Folk-Moots; or, Open-Air Assemblies in

Britain (London: Sampson Low, Marston, Searle & Rivington, 1880), 50.

[72] Baumgartner, Moral Order of a Suburb, 41.

[73] Richard Danzig, “Towards a Complementary, Decentralized System of

Criminal Justice,” in Neighborhood Justice: An Emerging Idea, ed. Roman

Tomasic & Malcolm Feeley (New York: Longman, 1982), 17. These “retreats”

are for corporate executives, company-organized. They are for

morale-building, not dispute resolution. A classic send-up of these

bizarre rituals is in the first novel by Kurt Vonnegut, Jr., Player

Piano (New York: Delacorte Press, 1952). When he wrote the book,

Vonnegut was a public relations officer for General Electric. He

resigned before it was published. Richard Danzig can’t tell the

difference between a tribal moot and the Bohemian Grove. He has never

attended a tribal moot, but he is elite enough that he may have attended

the Bohemian Grove.

[74] William L.F. Felstiner & Lynne A. Williams, “Mediation as an

Alternative to Criminal Prosecution,” Law & Human Behavior 2(3) (1980),

233.

[75] Harold J. Berman & James W. Spindler, “Soviet Comrades’ Courts,” U.

of Chicago L. Rev. 45 (1978): 842-910; Jesse Berman, “The Cuban Popular

Tribunals,” Columbia L. Rev. 69(8) (Dec. 1969): 1317-1354; Sally Engle

Merry, ”Defining ‘Success’ in the Neighborhood Justice Movement,” in

Neighborhood Justice, 174.

[76] A study of homicides in Houston, covering about the same time

period, found that these cases deteriorated at all stages, beginning

even before they were cases: police made many fewer arrests. In a

category of cases in most of which the grand jury returned a “no bill,”

i.e., refused to indict, terminating the prosecution, that was the

determination in 40.26% where victim and killer were relatives, in

36.77% where they were friends or associates, and in only 23.64% of

cases where they were strangers to each other. This indicates that it is

not merely because of decisions by prosecutors and judges – by system

professionals – that cases deteriorate. Henry P. Lundsgaarde, “Murder in

Space City,” in The Social Organization of Law, 133-156. Grand juries

are ad hoc panels of lay persons.

[77] Laura Nader, “When Is Popular Justice Popular?” in The Possibility

of Popular Justice: A Case Study of Community Mediation in the United

States, ed. Sally Engle Merry & Neal Milner (Ann Arbor, MI: University

of Michigan Press, 1993), 441. Nader, an anthropologist – the sister of

lawyer-activist Ralph Nader – believes that Burger was prompted by his

chief aide Mark Cannon, “a man of Mormon background, whose philosophy

reflects the Mormon idea of community and consensus and the Mormon

dislike of courts and lawyers [citations omitted].” Id.; cf. Mark

Cannon, “Contentious and Burdensome Litigation,” Phi Kappa Phi Journal

(1986): 10-12. Fringe religious types also pioneered a later form of

ADL, “Restorative Justice” (infra).

[78] Daniel McGillis, “Minor Dispute Processing: A Review of Recent

Developments,” in Neighborhood Justice, 63.

[79] Roman Tomasic & Malcolm M. Feeley, “Introduction,” Neighborhood

Justice, xi; Nader, “When Is Popular Justice Popular?” 441-42, 447.

[80] E.g., Sander, “Varieties of Dispute Processing,” 37.

[81] William L.F. Felsteiner & Lynne Williams, Community Mediation in

Dorchester, Massachusetts (Washington DC: U.S. Department of Justice,

1980), 42.

[82]

J. Kakalik et al., An Evaluation of Early Mediation and Neutral

Evaluation Under the Civil Justice Reform Act (Santa Monica, CA:

RAND Institute of Justice, 1996); Menkel-Meadow, “Roots and

Inspirations,” 25. Thus the RAND Corporation’s own research

discredited their former employee Richard Danzig’s absurd, but

absurdly influential reveries about complementary, decentralized

justice.

[83] Moffitt & Bordone, “Perspectives on Dispute Resolution,” 25.

[84] Felsteiner & Williams, “Community Mediation,” 150; Merry, “Sorting

Out Popular Justice,” 59; Yngvesson, “Local People, Local Problems,”

395.

[85] Roman Tomasic, “Mediation as an Alternative to Adjudication,” 231;

Merry, “Defining ‘Success,’” 176-77.

[86] Sally E. Merry, “A Plea for Thinking How Dispute Resolution Works,”

The Mooter 2(4) (1979), 39.

[87] Christine B. Harrington, Shadow Justice: The Ideology and

Institutionalization of Alternatives to Court (Westport, CT & London:

Greenwood Press, 1985), 109-110.

[88] In Cambridge, Massachusetts, an investigator found a “pattern of

relatively young, highly educated, predominantly white mediators serving

a predominantly poor, racially mixed population of litigants.” This was

also true of San Francisco. Sally Engle Merry, “Sorting Out Popular

Justice,” The Possibility of Popular Justice, 59. Another description:

the volunteers were “predominantly female, predominantly white,

relatively young, well-educated, aspiring professionals . . . “

Yngvesson, “Local People, Local Problems,” 395. They were yuppies. Today

they would be called hipsters.

[89] Harrington, Shadow Justice, 149.

[90] Merry, “Defining ‘Success,’” 176.

[91] Harrington, Shadow Justice, 122-23

[92] Quoted in Harrington, Shadow Justice, 147.

[93] Harrington, Shadow Justice, 170-71.

[94] Richard L. Abel, “The Contradictions of Informal Justice,” in The

Politics of Informal Justice, ed. Richard L. Abel ( New York: Academic

Press, 1980), 1: 267-301. “Informalism expands the capacity of the

justice system to manage minor conflicts and legitimates the extension

of state intervention on functionalist grounds.” Harrington, Shadow

Justice, 170. This is why the Philippine dictator Marcos instituted the

Barangay courts.

[95] Harrington, Shadow Justice, 122-23; Merry, “Defining ‘Success,’”

178-79.

[96] Janice A. Roehl & Royer F. Cook, “The Neighborhood Justice Centers

Field Test,” in Neighborhood Justice, 91-110.

[97] Frederic L. DuBow & Craig McEwen, “Community Boards: An Analytic

Profile,” The Possibility of Popular Justice, 130.

[98] Ibid., 127.

[99] Ibid., 148.

[100] Barbara Yngvesson, “Local People, Local Problems, and Neighborhood

Justice: The Discourse of ‘Community’ in San Francisco Community

Boards,” The Possibility of Popular Justice, 295.

[101] Roehl & Cook, “The Neighborhood Justice Centers Field Test,” 95,

96.

[102] Royer F. Cook, Janice A. Roehl, & David I. Sheppard, Neighborhood

Justice Centers Field Test – Final Evaluation Report (Washington, DC:

American Bar Association, 1980), 6.

[103] Feeley, The Process Is the Punishment, 251.

[104] Marc Galanter, “The Vanishing Trial: An Examination of Trials and

Related Matters in Federal and State Courts,” J. of Empirical and Legal

Studies (1) (2004): 459- 570.

[105] Feeley, Court Reform on Trial, 112.

[106] Davis, “Mediation: The Brooklyn Experiment,” 170 n. 5.

[107] I once went through this! I was not rearrested. The system works.

[108] Harrington, Shadow Justice, 142-43.

[109] Davis, “Mediation: The Brooklyn Experiment,” 163.

[110] Harrington, Shadow Justice, 143-44. Proponents of mediation have

quietly dropped this claim: “The language of resolution implies a level

of finality that is only occasionally a realistic condition.” Moffitt &

Bordone, “Perspectives on Dispute Resolution,” 4. This is true of

mediation generally, not just in NJCs. Gulliver, “On Mediators,” 20 n.

8.

[111] Robert C. Davis, Martha Tichane, & Deborah Grayson, Mediation and

Arbitration as Alternatives to Prosecution in Felony Arrest Cases – An

Evaluation of the Brooklyn Dispute Resolution Center (New York: Vera

Institute of Justice, 1979), 50, 52.

[112] Dispute Resolution Alternatives Committee, The Citizen Dispute

Settlement Process in Florida – A Study of Five Programs (n.p.; Office

of the State Court Administrator, Florida Supreme Court, 1979), 55;

Felsteiner & Williams, “Mediation as an Alternative to Criminal

Prosecution,” 66-68; Tomasic, “Mediation as an Alternative to

Adjudication,” 236.

[113] Anthony M. Platt, The Child Savers: The Invention of Delinquency

(2d, enl. ed.; Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1977); Robert

M. Mannel, Thorns & Thistles: Juvenile Delinquents in the United States,

1825-1940 (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England, 1973).

[114] A New Juvenile Justice System: Total Reform of a Broken System,

ed. Nancy E. Dowd (New York & London: New York University Press, 2015).

[115] Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and

Circles, ed. Allison Morris & Gabrielle Maxwell (Oxford, England &

Portland, OR: Hart Publishing, 2001).

[116] Sander,“Varieties of Dispute Processing,” 33. This article is

considered to be “the ‘Big Bang’ of modern dispute resolution and

practice.” Moffitt & Bordone, “Perspectives on Dispute Resolution,” 19.

If it all began with a bang it has ended, in the words of T.S. Eliot, in

a whimper. But in an institutionalized, well-funded whimper, which will

echo on.

[117] Barbara B. Yngvesson & P. Hennessey, “Small Claims, Complex

Disputes: A Review of the Small Claims Literature,” Law & Soc’y Rev. 9

(1975): 219- 274.

[118] Sander, “Varieties of Dispute Processing,” 33.

[119] Feeley, Court Reform on Trial, 108.

[120] Feeley, Court Reform on Trial, 105; Sally Baker & Susan Sadd,

Court Employment Project Evaluation Final Report (New York: Vera

Institute of Justice, 1979).

[121] Feeley, Court Reform on Trial, 109. These programs never learn the

lessons of their predecessors: “Crisis thinking lacks historical

perspective.” Ibid., 192.

[122] Brian Williams, Victims of Crime and Community Justice (London &

Philadelphia, PA: Jessica Kingsley Publishers, 2005), 127 (note the

ambiguity of the title).

[123] Merry, “Defining ‘Success,’” 172.

[124] Menkel-Meadow, “Roots and Inspirations,” 19-20.

[125] Cheryl Catrona, “Fitting the Fuss to the Community Mediation

Center Forum,” Dispute Resolution Mag. (Winter 2013): 11-15

(Philadelphia); Mark Kleiman, “Mending the Fabric of Community,” Dispute

Resolution Mag. (Winter 2013): 16- ---- (Queens). Pope John Paul II

spoke of “mending the Christian fabric of society.” Quoted in Petros

Willey, “Editor’s Note: Mending the Fabric,” The Sower 33(4), available

at

https://catechetics.com/editors-note-mending-the-fabric

. Not all societies are made out of Christian fabrics.

[126] Cutrona, “Fitting the Fuss,”11.

[127] Robert C. Black, “Forgotten Penological Purposes: A Critique of

Victim Participation in Sentencing,” American J. of Jurisprudence

(1994): 225-240, available online at

http://scholarship.lawnd.edu/ajj/vol39/issI/9.

[128] And as Lon L. Fuller wrote, “mediation can be directed, not toward

cementing a relationship, but toward terminating it.” “Mediation – Its

Forms and Functions,” 129. So can adjudication – divorce, for instance.

[129] Black, “Elementary Forms of Conflict Management,” 94 n. 32.

[130] Roberts, Order and Dispute, 49.

[131] Leonard W. Levy, Against the Law: The Supreme Court and Criminal

Justice (New York: Harper & Row, 1974); Yale Kamisar, “The ‘Police

Practices’ Phases of the Criminal Process and Three Phases of the Burger

Court,” in The Burger Years: Right and Wrong in the Burger Court,

1969-1986, ed. Herman Schwartz (New York: Viking, Elisabeth Sifton

Books, 1987), 143-168.

[132] Merry, “Defining ‘Success’ in the Neighborhood Justice Movement,”

182.

[133] James L. Gibbs, Jr., “Law and Personality: Suggestions for a New

Direction,” in Law in Culture and Society, 188 (Table 1).

[134] Richard B. Lee, “Reflections on Primitive Communism,” in Hunters

and Gatherers, ed. Tim Ingold, David Riches, & James Woodburn (London:

Berg Publishers, 1990), 1: 252-268; idem, “Primitive Communism and the

Origin of Social Equality,” in The Evolution of Political Systems:

Socio-Politics in Small-Scale Sedentary Societies, ed. Steadman Upham

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 225-246.

[135] Lee, The !Kung San, ch. 13.

[136] Kropotkin, Mutual Aid, 89.

[137] Lee, The !Kung San, 437.

[138] Kropotkin, Mutual Aid, 95.

[139] Koch, War and Peace in Jalémó.

[140] Kropotkin, Mutual Aid, 108-109; Frederick Engels, “Origin of the

Family, Private Property and the State,” Karl Marx & Frederick Engels,

Selected Works in One Volume (Moscow, USSR: Progress Publishers & New

York: International Publishers, 1968), 520, 528. Engels’ source is Lewis

Henry Morgan, League of the Iroquois (Secaucus, NJ: Citadel Press,

1969), 330-33.

[141] Kropotkin, Mutual Aid, 94-95. The feud (more like a war) recounted

by Koch had nothing to do with “superstition.” It was provoked by the

theft (or recovery) of a pig, not by witchcraft accusations. Koch, “Pigs

and Politics in the New Guinea Highlands.”

[142] Anthony F.C. Wallace, The Death and Rebirth of the Seneca (New

York: Vintage Books, 1969), 25-26, 30.

[143] “Anarchist Communism: Its Basis and Principles,” in Kropotkin’s

Revolutionary Pamphlets, ed. Roger N. Baldwin (New York: Dover

Publications, 1970), 63.

[144] Nicolas Walter, About Anarchism (updated ed.; London: Freedom

Press, 2002), 76 (originally1969).

[145] Stuart Christie, “Publisher’s Foreword,” Larry Tifft & Dennis

Sullivan, The Struggle to Be Human: Crime, Criminology, and Anarchism

(Over the Water, Sanday, Orkney, UK: Cienfuegos Press, 1980), vii.

[146] Bob Black, “An Anarchist Response to ‘The Anarchist Response to

Crime,’” Defacing the Currency, 195.

[147] Larry L. Tifft & Lois E. Stevenson,”Humanistic Criminology: Roots

from Peter Kropotkin,” J. of Sociology & Social Welfare 12(3) (Sept.

2015): 488-520 (based on a lecture delivered in 1983, and not updated)..

[148] Jeff Ferrell, “Peter Kropotkin (1842-1921),” in Fifty Key Thinkers

in Criminology, ed. Keith Hayward, Shadd Maruna & Jayne Mooner (London &

New York: Routledge, 2010), 30-36.

[149] John G. Perry, “Challenging the Assumptions,” in Restorative

Justice: Repairing Communities Through Restorative Justice (Lanham, MD:

American Correctional Association, 2002), 1. Even prison guards like

Restorative Justice! But I am getting ahead of myself .

[150] Larry L. Tifft, Battering of Women: The Failure of Intervention

and the Case for Prevention (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993), 171 n.

1; Jodi Lane et al., Fear of Crime in the United States: Causes,

Consequences, and Contradictions (Durham, NC: Carolina Academic Press,

2014), ch. 4 (“Gender: The Most Consistent Predictor of Fear of Crime”).

[151] “Law and Authority,” in Kropotkin’s Revolutionary Pamphlets, 212.

[152] Ibid., 214. Or as Kropotkin describes them: “It again is a

complete arsenal of laws, decrees, ordinances, orders in council, and

what not, all serving to protect the diverse forms of representative

government, delegated or usurped, beneath which humanity is writhing.”

[153] Ibid., 213.

[154] Murray L. Schwartz, “The Other Things That Courts Do,” UCLA Law

Rev. 28 (1980-81): 438- ----.

[155] H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: at the Clarendon Press,

1961), 27-28; Malcolm Feeley, “The Concept of Laws in Social Science: A

Critique and Notes on an Expanded View,” Law & Society Rev. 10 (1976),

505-513; Marc Galanter, “Justice in Many Rooms: Courts, Private

Ordering, and Indigenous Law,” J. Legal Pluralism 19 (1981), 19.

[156] Steven Jones, Criminology (3d ed.; Oxford: Oxford University

Press, 2006), 154-56.

[157] Todd R. Clear & David R. Karp, The Community Justice Ideal:

Preventing Crime and Achieving Justice (Boulder, CO: Westview Press,

1999), 113.

[158] Elliott Currie, Confronting Crime: An American Challenge (New

York: Pantheon Books, 1985), 146 (quoted), 148-51 (citing statistics

from the United States, England and Denmark).

[159] Edwin H. Sutherland, “White Collar Criminality,” Am. Sociolog.

Rev. 5 (1940): 1-12.

[160] Donald R. Cressey, Other People’s Money: A Study in the Social

Psychology of Embezzlement (Glencoe, IL: The Free Press, 1953), 57-66;

M.P. Baumgartner, “Social Control from Below,” in Towards a General

Theory of Social Social Control, 1: 309-11; Black, “’Wild Justice,’”

247.

[161] Peter Letkemann, Crime as Work (Englewood Cliffs, NJ:

Prentice-Hall, 1973), 159. This little-known but very interesting book

is based on research on property crime career criminals, especially

safecrackers and bank robbers.

[162] Chomsky on Anarchism, ed. Barry Pateman (Edinburgh, Scotland &

Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2005), 65; cf. Bob Black, “Chomsky on the Nod,”

132.

[163] Black, “Chomsky on the Nod,” Defacing the Currency, 137.

[164] E.g., Tifft & Sullivan, The Struggle to Be Human.

[165] Will Farrell, “Against the Law: Anarchist Criminology,” Social

Anarchism 25 (1998) (unpaginated), available at

www.socialanarchism.org

& library.nothingness.org.

[166] Boston, MA: Northeastern University Press, 1996.

[167] Tifft & Sullivan, The Struggle to Be Human, 179.

[168] E.g., Walter, About Anarchism, 76.

[169] Tifft, Battering of Women,12 (emphasis in the original).

[170] Walter, About Anarchism, 77.

[171] Kropotkin, “Law and Authority,” 215-16.

[172] Alex Comfort, Authority and Delinquency in the Modern State: A

Criminological Approach to the Problem of Power (London: Routledge &

Kegan Paul, 1950), 99-104.

[173] Ibid., 101. Except that few “city aggregates” now approximate

communities.

[174] Scott W., “The Anarchist Response to Crime,” which may still be

available at libcom.org, a little gang of maladorous anarcho-leftists in

London. My rejoinder (suppressed by lib.com) is Bob Black, “An Anarchist

Response to ‘The Anarchist Response to Crime,‘” Defacing the Currency,

193-216.

[175] Lewis Coser, The Functions of Social Conflict (New York: The Free

Press, 1956); Georg Simmel, “Conflict,” in Conflict and the Web of

Group-Affiliations (New York: The Free Press, 1955), 11-123; Paul

Bohannan, “Introduction,” Law and Warfare, xi. As anthropologist Simon

Roberts writes, “it should be clear that whatever the shared assumptions

against which everyday life in a particular society may go on, we should

not start out with the idea that peace and harmony necessarily represent

a ‘natural’ state of things, disrupted only by occasional, pathological

instances of trouble.” Order and Dispute, 33-34.

[176] Black, “’Wild Justice,’” 233.

[177] William Godwin, An Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, ed. Mark

Philp (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 403-05 (originally1793).

“The rules of justice would be more clearly and effectually taught by an

actual intercourse with human society unrestrained by the fetters of

prepossession, than they can be by catechisms and codes.” Ibid., 403.

[178] Black, “An Anarchist Response,” 235-36; Bob Black, “’Wild

Justice,’”235. Donald Black writes that “the more we study law, indeed,

the more we realize how little people really use it to handle their

conflicts . . . “ “Social Control as a Dependent Variable,” in Towards a

General Theory of Social Control, ed. Donald Black (Orlando, FL:

Academic Press, 1984), 1:3, reprinted in Black, Social Structure of

Right and Wrong, 1-26.

[179] Alexander Berkman, What Is Communist Anarchism? (New York: Dover

Publications, 1972), 186 (originally 1929); Rudolph Rocker,

Anarcho-Syndicalism (London: Pluto Press, 1999), 19 (originally 1938).

[180] E.g., Bob Black, “Anarchy 101,” Defacing the Currency, 37-51;

Nicolas Walter, About Anarchism; Ruth Kinnah, Anarchism: A Beginner’s

Guide (Oxford: Oneworld Publications, 2005); Colin Ward, Anarchism: A

Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).

[181] “The Relevance of Anarcho-Syndicalism (1976),” in Chomsky on

Anarchism, ed. Barry Pateman (Oakland, CA & Edinburgh, Scotland: AK

Press, 2005), 133, 136-37; Black, “Chomsky on the Nod,” 128, 132-153 &

passim.

[182] Ferdinand Tönnies, Community and Society, trans. C.P. Loomis (East

Lansing, MI: Michigan State University Press, 1957), 84-112.

[183] Black, “Chomsky on the Nod,” 138-40.

[184] There is nothing, for instance, in Rocker, Anarcho-Syndicalism or

in Emile Pataud & Emile Pouget, How We Shall Bring About the Revolution:

Syndicalism and the Cooperative Commonwealth, trans. Charlotte & Fredric

Charles (London & Winchester, MA: Pluto Press, 1990) (originally1909).

[185] Tifft & Sullivan, The Struggle to Be Human, 74.

[186] Sharon Levrant, Francis T. Cullen, Betsy Fulton, & John F.

Wozniak, “Reconsidering Restorative Justice: The Corruption of

Benevolence Revisited?” Crime & Delinquency 45(1) (Jan. 1999): 3-27.

[187] Curriculum vita of Howard Zehr, available online at

emu.edu/cjp/restorative-justice/howard-zehr-cv/CV.pdf.

[188] Howard Zehr, The Little Book of Restorative Justice (rev., updated

ed.; New York: Good Books, 2015), 10. Since 2002, this book has sold

over 110,000 copies. Ibid., 11.

[189] Lawrence M. Sherman, “Two Protestant Ethics and the Spirit of

Restoration,” in Restorative Justice and Civil Society, ed. Heather

Strang & John Braithwaite (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001),

35-51.

[190] Gary Chartier, Anarchy and Legal Order: Law and Politics for a

Stateless Society (New York & Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

2013), 243.

[191] Anthony J. Nocella II, “An Overview of the History and Theory of

Transformative Justice,” Peace & Conflict Rev. 6(1) (2011), 3.

[192] Ibid., 3, 2; Zehr, Little Book, 18. Nocella’s claim that

“peacemaking criminology, rooted in a faith-based and holistic approach

to crime and justice,” was influenced by, among other “peace activists,”

Fred Hampton and Malcolm X, is dishonest and offensive. They had pride.

[193] John Braithwaite, “Survey Article: Repentance Rituals and

Restorative Justice,” J. of Political Philosophy 8(1) (2000): 115-131;

idem, Shame, Crime, and Reintegration (Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 1989), 80-83. This isn’t punishment? Cruel and unusual

punishment, at that.

[194] Stanley Booth-Clibborn, “Foreward to the First Edition,” in Martin

Wright, Justice for Victims and Offenders: A Restorative Response to

Crime (2d ed.; Winchester, England: Waterside Press, 1996), viii; see

also Christopher D. Marshall, Beyond Retribution: A New Testament Vision

for Crime, Justice and Punishment (Grand Rapids, MI & Cambridge, UK:

William B. Erdmans Pub., 2001); Michael L. Hadley, “Spiritual

Foundations of Restorative Justice,” in Handbook of Restorative Justice,

ed. Dennis Sullivan & Larry Tifft (New York & London: Routledge, 2006),

174-187; Jack B. Hamlin, “Restorative Justice: An Answer to the Call of

the Gospel of St. Mark for Service and Restoration,” International J. of

Humanities & Social Sciences 1(19) (2011): 277-285; Mark M. Umbreit,

Crime and Reconciliation: Creative Options for Victims and Offenders

(Nashville, TN: Abingdon Press, 1985), ch. 5 (“Biblical Justice”).

[195] E.g., Carolyn Hoyle, “The Case for Restorative Justice,” in Chris

Cuneen & Carolyn Hoyle, Debating Restorative Justice (Oxford & Portland,

OR: Hart Publishing, 2010), 3; Williams, Victims of Crime and Community

Justice, 65.

[196] Todd R. Clear, “Community Justice versus Restorative Justice:

Contrasts in Family of Value,” in Handbook of Restorative Justice, 471.

[197] Michael Batley, “What Is the Appropriate Role of Spirituality in

Restorative Justice?” in Critical Issues in Restorative Justice, ed.

Howard Zehr & Barb Toews (Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press &

Cullompton, Devon, UK: Willan Publishing, 2004), 371, 366. This idiot

also asserts: “The supernatural always played a part in the indigenous

understanding of justice.” Ibid., 370. My accounts of the Plateau Tonga,

Ifugao and Kpelle made no reference to the supernatural because it does

not play any part in their disputing processes, nor does it in many

other primitive societies. Ifugao religion, which is typically animist,

consists of myths, rituals and magical techniques. It has no ethical

content. The Ifugao rarely fear and never revere their many gods. R.W.

Barton, The Religion of the Ifugaos ([Manasha, WI]: American

Anthropological Ass’n [Memoirs of the American Anthropological Ass’n,

no. 65], 1946).

[198] Black, “Forgotten Penological Purposes,” 234 n. 42.

[199] Ronald L. Akers, Jodi Lane & Lonn Lanza-Kaduce, “Faith-Based

Mentoring and Restorative Justice: Overlapping Theoretical, Empirical

and Philosophical Background,” in Restorative Justice: From Theory to

Practice, ed. Holly Ventura Miller (London: JAI Press, 2008), 139-165.

[200] Joanna Shapland, Gwen Robinson & Angela Sorsby, Restorative

Justice in Practice: Evaluating What Works for Victims and Offenders

(London & New York: Routledge, 2011), 7.

[201] Bruce A. Arrigo, “Postmodernism’s Challenges to Restorative

Justice,” in Handbook of Restorative Justice, 479. “Thus, fundamental to

restorative justice is a commitment to order, homeostasis, and

equilibrium.” Ibid., 478.

[202] Nils Christie, “Conflicts as Property,” British J. of Criminology

17(1) (Jan. 1977), 1. Ironically, RJ boosters often cite this article.

[203] Chris Cunneen, “What are the Implications of RJ’s Use of

Indigenous Traditions?” in Critical Issues in Restorative Justice, 346.

There is the little matter of the state, for one thing. RJ is about as

indigenous as chop suey is Chinese. Many indigenous disputing processes,

such as among the Ifugao and Plateau Tonga, bear little resemblance to

any variety of RJ.

[204] Clear, “Community Justice versus Restorative Justice: Contrasts in

Family of Value,” 463.

[205] James W. Zion & Robert Yazzi, “Navajo Peacemaking: Original

Dispute Resolution and a Life Way,” Handbook of Restorative Justice,

151-160; Dirk J. Louw, “The African Concept of Ubuntu and Restorative

Justice,” Handbook of Restorative Justice, 161-173.

[206] Zehr, Little Book, 18-19.

[207] Kathleen Daly, “Restorative Justice: The Real Story,” Punishment &

Society 4(1) (Jan. 2002): 55-79; Douglas J. Sylvester, “Myth in

Restorative Justice History,” Utah L. Rev. (2003), 501-522; Chris

Cunneen, “The Limits of Restorative Justice,” in Debating Restorative

Justice, 109-112.

[208] “In Kitchener, Ontario, the first known restorative case involving

two teenagers on a vandalism rampage in 1974 was responded to by a

volunteer probation officer from the Mennonite Central Committee, Mark

Yantzi.” John P.J. Dussich, “Recovery and Restoration in Victim

Assistance,” in The Promise of Restorative Justice, 68. Dussich, after

“twenty-nine years in the US Army’s Military Police Corps, retir[ed] at

the rank of colonel in 1993. For the past thirty-four years [as of 2010]

he has been working mostly in the field of criminology, specializing in

victim services.” “The Contributors,” ibid., 258. The incident

anticipates many of RJ’s problematic features. The probation officer

presented his plan to the court, which approved it ex parte (without

notice to, and in the absence of the defendants and their counsel, if

they had any). He then took the vandals to the houses of their many

victims, where he forced them to apologize, and forced them to listen to

the victims describe their losses and how they felt about them. (This

was not their only punishment: they were compelled to pay restitution.)

John Smith, “Righting the Relational Wrong,” a speech delivered to the

Canadian Parliament, May 6, 2014, available at www.arpacanada.com. Dr.

Smith is a Professor of the Old Testament at the Canadian Reformed

Theological Seminary. He then expiated upon RJ’s “Biblical Roots.”

[209] Nocella, “An Overview,” 3 (quoted); Zehr, Little Book, 18.

[210] No disrespect to the doo-wop band of that name, although, it was a

lousy band (e.g., “Good Night Sweetheart,” on YouTube).

[211] The Promise of Restorative Justice: New Approaches for Criminal

Justice and Beyond, ed. John P.J. Dussich & Jill Schellenberg (Boulder,

CO & London: Lynne Rienner Publishers, 2010). It was also pushed by

neo-liberal Tony Blair’s “New Labour”: “Tough on crime, tough on the

causes of crime,” but he was only tough on crime (or rather, criminals).

James Gilligan, Preventing Violence (New York: Thames & Hudson, 2001),

9-10.

[212] Bruce Archibald, “Why Restorative Justice Is Not Compulsory

Compassion: Annalise Acorn’s Labour of Love Lost,” Alberta L. Rev. 42(3)

(2005), 941.

[213] Zehr, Little Book, 48.

[214] Tony Marshall, “The Evolution of Restorative Justice in Britain,”

European J. on Criminal Policy Research, 4(4) (1996), 37.

[215] Kathleen Daly, “The Limits of Restorative Justice,” in Handbook of

Restorative Justice, 135. The index to this anthology has 12 listings

under “definitions of RJ.”

[216] Proverbs 15:1 (KJV).

[217] Danzig, “Towards the Creation of a Complementary, Decentralized

System,” 14-15.

[218] Ruth Ana Strickland, Restorative Justice (New York: Peter Lang,

2004), 7-8.

[219] Talcott Parsons, The Social System (new ed.; London: Routledge,

1991), 436-38 (originally 1951).

[220] Marty Price, “Personalizing Crime: Mediation Produces Restorative

Justice for Victims and Offenders,” Dispute Resolution Magazine (Fall

2001) (unpaginated).

[221] James J. Chriss, “Introduction,” Counseling and the Therapeutic

State, ed. James J. Chriss, “New York: Aldine de Gruyter, 1999), 5-6;

see also Thomas Szasz, The Therapeutic State: Psychiatry in the Mirror

of Current Events (Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 1984).

[222] “By bringing about profound changes at the most intimate levels of

human experience, the state aims to integrate marginal citizens into the

social mainstream. Further, resistance on their part will not be

tolerated.” Andrew J. Polsky, The Rise of the Therapeutic State

(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1991), 4.

[223] Max Stirner, The Ego and Its Own, ed. David Leopold (Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 1995), 213. “But the correct thing is that I

regard it either as an action that suits me, that I treat it as my

property, which I cherish or demolish. . . . ‘Crime’ is treated

inexorably, ‘disease’ with ‘loving gentleness, compassion,’ and the

like.” Ibid., 213-14

[224] Thomas Szasz, The Medicalization of Everyday Life: Selected Essays

(Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press, 2007).

[225] Cunneen, “Limits of Restorative Justice,” 119.

[226] James L. Nolan, Jr., Justifying the Welfare State at Century’s End

(New York: New York University Press, 1998).

[227] Annalise E. Acorn, Compulsory Compassion: A Critique of

Restorative Justice (Vancouver, BC, Canada: UBC Press, 2004).

[228] Paul McCold, “The Recent History of Restorative Justice:

Mediation, Circles, and Conferencing.” Handbook of Restorative Justice,

24-27; Mark S. Umbreit, Robert B. Coates, & Betty Vos, “Victim Offender

Mediation: An Evolving Evidence-Based Practice,” Handbook of Restorative

Justice, 52-62; Christa Pelikan & Thomas Trenczek, “Victim Offender

Mediation and Restorative Justice: The European Landscape,” in Handbook

of Restorative Justice, 82; Dennis Sullivan & Larry Tifft, Restorative

Justice: Healing the Foundations of Our Everyday Lives (Monsey, NY:

Willow Tree Press, 2001), 74.

[229] McCold, “Recent History of Restorative Justice,” 24-25.

[230] Shapland, Robinson & Sorsby, Restorative Justice in Practice,

16-17.

[231] Larry Johnstone & Daniel W. Van Ness, Handbook of Restorative

Justice (Devon, UK: Willan Publishing, 2007), 76-77.

[232] American Bar Association, Report of the Pound Conference Follow-up

Task Force (Chicago, IL: American Bar Foundation, 1976).

[233] E.g., Marty Price, “Personalizing Crime: Mediation Produces

Restorative Justice for Victims and Offenders,” Dispute Resolution

Magazine (Fall 2001) (unpaginated), available online at

http://www.vorp.com

.

[234] E.g., Daly, “Restorative Justice: The Real Story”; Acorn,

Compulsory Compassion; Bruce A. Arrigo & Robert C. Schwehr, “Restoring

Justice for Juveniles: A Critical Analysis of Victimoffender [sic]

Mediation,” Justice Quarterly 15(4) (1998): 629-666; Cunneen, “The

Limitations of Restorative Justice,” 101-187; Takagi & Shank, “Critique

of Restorative Justice”; George Pavlich, Governing Paradoxes of

Restorative Justice (London: Glasshouse Press, 2005).

[235]

http://restorativejustice.org

; Cunneen, “The Limitations of Restorative Justice,” 101. The Centre is

a project of the Prison Fellowship International, which was founded by

Watergate criminal Charles Colson after he got religion.

[236] Black, “Forgotten Penological Purposes.”

[237] Tomasic, “Mediation as an Alternative to Adjudication,” 225-28.

[238] Zehr, Little Book, 57 (quoted) ; Tifft & Sullivan, “Introduction:

The Healing Dimension of Restorative Justice: A One-World Body,” in

Handbook of Restorative Justice, 2.

[239] Price, “Personalizing Crime,” n.p.

[240] Nocella, “Overview,” 4.

[241] United Nations (July 27, 2000), Basic Principles on the Use of

Restorative Justice Programmes in Criminal Matters (ESCO Res. 2000/14

U.N.Doc. E/2000.

[242] Wing-Cheong Chan, “Family Conferencing for Juvenile Offenders: A

Singaporean Case Study in Restorative Justice,” Asian J. of Criminology

8(1) (March 2013): 1-23.

[243] Gabrielle Maxwell, Allison Morris & Hennessey Hayes, “Conferencing

and Restorative Justice,” in Handbook of Restorative Justice, 91-106.

[244] Paul Takagi & Gregory Shank, “Critique of Restorative Justice,”

Social Justice 31(3) (2004), 161.

[245] Thom Brooks, Punishment (London & New York: Routledge, 2013), 82;

Mario Thomas Gaboury & Duane Ruth-Heffelbower, “Ínnovations in

Correctional Settings,” in The Promise of Restorative Justice, 16.

[246] Shapland, Robinson & Sorsby, Restorative Justice in Practice, 53.

[247] Ibid., 6 (this is the “Wagga Wagga model”). Also used in New

Jersey. Margarita Zernova, Restorative Justice: Ideals and Realities

(Aldershot, Hampshire, UK & Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing, 2007),

10-12.

[248] “I weep for you,” the Walrus said: “I deeply sympathize.”

With sobs and tears he sorted out

Those of the largest size,

Holding his pocket-handkerchief

Before his streaming eyes.

“O Oysters,” said the Carpenter,

You’ve had a pleasant run!

Shall we be trotting home again?”

But answer there came none –

And this was scarcely odd, because

They’d eaten every one.

Lewis Carroll, “Through the Looking-Glass,” The Annotated Alice: The

Definitive Version (New York & London: W.W. Norton & Company, 2000),

187-88

[249] “Carolyn Boyes-Watson, “What Are the Implications of the Growing

State Involvement in Restorative Justice?” in Critical Issues in

Restorative Justice, 215-24.

[250] Danzig, “Towards the Creation of a Complementary, Decentralized

System,” 14-15 (NJCs).

[251] E.g., Zehr, Little Book, 48 & passim; Susan Sharpe, Restorative

Justice: A Vision for Healing and Change (Edmonton, Alberta, Canada:

Mediation and Restorative Justice Centre, 1998).

[252] Martin Wright, Justice for Victims and Offenders: A Restorative

Response to Crime (2d ed.; Winchester, UK: Waterside Press, 1996), 151;

Black, “An Anarchist Response to ‘The Anarchist Response to Crime,’”

206.

[253] Jonathan Doak, “Honing the Stone: Refining Restorative Justice as

a Vehicle for Emotional Redress,” Contemporary Justice Rev. 14(4)

(2011), 439.

[254] Black, “Forgotten Penological Purposes,” 230.

[255] Vernon E. Yantzi, “What is the Role of the State in Restorative

Justice?” in Critical Issues in Restorative Justice, 193. Dr. Yantzi, a

professor at Eastern Mennonite University, is almost certainly related

to Mark Yantzi, the Mennonite who originated victim/offender mediation

in Canada. The Mennonites are very inbred.

[256] Dussich, “Recovery and Restoration,” 69-70 (quoted); Herman, “Is

Restorative Justice Possible Without a Parallel System for Victims?”

77-78.

[257] SINGLE

[258] Gulliver, “On Mediators,” 22. Here is yet another reason why the

Kpelle moot is not mediation.

[259] E.g., Howard Zehr, Transcending: Reflections of Crime Victims:

Portraits and Interviews (Intercourse, PA: Good Books, 2001).

[260] Acorn, Compulsory Compassion, 71. I will not burden my overlong

discourse with the story about how RJ is the ideology behind truth and

reconciliation commissions in various countries coming to terms with the

legacy of their previous repressive regimes. That may have been

politically expedient, even necessary, but the rationale is even feebler

than for RJ in ordinary criminal cases. Stuart Wilson, “The Myth of

Restorative Justice: Truth, Reconciliation and the Ethics of Amnesty,”

South African J. of Human Rights 17 (2001): 531-562.

[261] “’I like the Walrus best,” said Alice: “because he was a little

sorry for the poor oysters’.” “’He ate more than the Carpenter, though,’

said Tweedledee.” Carroll, “Through the Looking-Glass,” 187-88.

[262] The Bible quotation is actually a little more elaborate than is

commonly assumed: “The wolf shall also dwell with the lamb, and the

leopard shall lie down with the kid; and the calf and the young lion and

the fatling together; and a little child shall lead them.” Isaiah 11:6

(KJV). Not all of this menagerie is in the illustration. I don’t know if

Tifft & Sullivan are Protestants, but many of their RJ colleagues are,

and they might have done fact checking. Protestants are the Bible-beater

Christians. That’s not all they beat.

[263] Bonnie Price Lofton, “Does Restorative Justice Challenge System

Injustices?” in Critical Issues in Restorative Justice, 384.

[264] Nils Christie, A Suitable Amount of Crime (Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 2001), 123.

[265] Dussich, “Recovery and Restoration ,” 68; see also Susan Herman,

“Is Restorative Justice Possible Without a Parallel System for Victims?”

in Critical Issues in Restorative Justice, 77.

[266] Sandra Walklate, “Changing Boundaries of the ‘Victim,’” Handbook

of Restorative Justice, 283-84.

[267] “From the start, the Christian faith is a sacrifice: a sacrifice

of all freedom, all pride, all self-confidence of the spirit; at the

same time, enslavement and self-mockery, self-mutilation.” Friedrich

Nietzsche, “Beyond Good and Evil,” Basic Writings of Nietzsche, trans. &

ed. Walter Kauffman (New York: The Modern Library, 1968), 250. For

Nietzsche, “man’s ‘sinfulness’ is not a fact, but merely the

interpretation of a fact, namely of physiological depression – the

latter viewed in a religio-moral perspective that is no longer binding

on us.” “On the Genealogy of Morals,” in ibid., 565.

[268] Luke 15: 11-27 (quotation at 11: 24) (KJV).

[269] Luke 15: 28-32.

[270] There’s a detail in the story which the preachers never mention:

“Son, thou art ever with me, and all that I have is thine.” Luke 15: 31.

[271] Zernova, Restorative Justice, 11; Daly, “Limits of Restorative

Justice,” 139-40; Brooks , Punishment, 82. In one study, most victims

accepted the offender’s apology – but barely one third of offenders

offered apologies. Mandeek K. Dhami, “Offer and Acceptance of Apology in

Victim-Offender Mediation,” Critical Criminology 20 (2012): 45-60.

[272] Daly, “Limits of Restorative Justice,” 140.

[273] Ross McGarry & Sandra Walklake, Victims: Trauma, Testimony and

Justice (London & New York: Routledge, 2015), 137-38. I will not explain

why the philosophical term “performative,” introduced by J.L. Austin, is

meaningless here. Cf. J.L. Austin, “Performative Utterances,”

Philosophical Papers, ed. J.O. Urmson & G.J. Warnock (3d ed.; Oxford:

Oxford University Press, 1979), 233-252 (originally1956).

[274] Arrigo,“Postmodernism’s Challenges to Restorative Justice,” 478.

[275] Ken-ichi Ohbuchi, “A Social Psychological Analysis of Accounts:

Toward a Universal Model of Giving and Receiving Accounts,” Japanese

Apology Across Disciplines, ed. Naomi Sugimoto (Commack, NY: Commack

Science Publishers, 1999), 28-29.

[276] “While restorative justice insists that the victim’s participation

be wholly voluntary (it would of course be unconscionable if it were

coerced), its insistence on consent does not let restorative justice off

the hook of having to answer for the ethics of the tactics it uses to

secure the victim’s participation.” Acorn, Compulsory Compassion, 70.

“[R]estorative justice uses talk of healing as a means of enticing

victims to participate.” Ibid., 71.

[277] Acorn, Compulsory Compassion, 3.

[278] Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and

Women’s Development (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)

(originally published 1982).

[279] Barbara E. Reye, “How Do Culture, Class and Gender Affect the

Practice of Restorative Justice? (Part 2),” in Critical Issues in

Restorative Justice, 336.

[280] E.g., ibid,; Emily Gaardner & Lois Presser, “A Feminist Vision of

Justice? The Problems and Possibilities of Restorative Justice for Girls

and Women,” in Handbook of Restorative Justice, 483-494.

[281] Acorn, Compulsory Compassion, 44.

[282] Cunneen, “Limitations of Restorative Justice,” 148-154.

[283] Nicole Westmarland, Violence Against Women: Criminological

Perspectives on Male Violences (London: Routledge, 2015), 100-101.

[284] Hoyle, “The Case for Restorative Justice,” 77-78.

[285] Thom Brooks, Punishment (London & New York: Routledge, 2013), 82.

[286] Zernova, Restorative Justice, 11 (emphasis added).

[287] Acorn, Compulsory Compassion, 70.

[288] “Against Remorse. --- . . . After all, what is the good of it! No

deed can be undone by being regretted; no more than by being ‘forgiven’

or ‘atoned for.’ One would have to be a theologian to believe in a power

that annuls guilt: we immoralists prefer not to believe in ‘guilt.’”

Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, ed. Walter Kaufmann, trans.

Walter Kaufmann & R.J. Hollingdale (New York: Vintage Books, 1968), 136.

[289] Human nature -- the biggest lie in theology, moral philosophy, and

libero-conservative ideology -- I have debunked elsewhere. Black,

“Chomsky on the Nod,” 103-117 & passim; Black, Nightmares of Reason, ch.

9, available online at www.theanarchylibrary.org.

[290] “It may be unreasonable to expect that an hour-and-a-half

restorative encounter would turn around what are quite often life-time

problems.” Zernova, Restorative Justice, 33. “’Seems,’ madam? Nay, it

is. I know not ‘seems.’” William Shakespeare, “Hamlet,” Tragedies (New

York & Toronto, Canada: Everyman’s Library, 1992), 1: 13 (1.2.77).

[291] Robert Elias, The Politics of Victimization: Victims, Victimology,

and Human Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986).

[292] David L. Roland, “Progress in the Victims’ Rights Movement: No

Longer the ‘Forgotten Victim,’” Pepperdine Law Rev. 17 (1988), 51 n. 87;

Black, “Forgotten Penological Purposes,” 226.

[293] Black, “Forgotten Penological Purposes,” 226.

[294] Cunneen, “Limitations of Restorative Justice,” 134-35.

[295] Anne Heinz & Wayne Korstetter, “Victim Participation in Plea

Bargaining: A Field Experiment,” in Plea-Bargaining, ed. William F.

MacDonald & James A. Kramer (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1980),

67-77; Edwin Villmoare & Virginia U. Neto, Victim Appearances at

Sentencing Under the California Victims’ Bill of Rights (Washington, DC:

U.S. Department of Justice, National Institute of Justice, 1982), 42-44;

Black, “Forgotten Penological Purposes,” 231.

[296] Mary Achilles & Lorraine Stutzman-Amstutz, “Responding to the

Needs of Victims: What Was Promised, What Was Delivered,” in Handbook of

Restorative Justice, 212-13. Stutzman-Amstutz is another Mennonite.

Achilles was the appointed Victim Advocate for the Commonwealth of

Pennsylvania.

[297] Ibid., 213. The sponsors were Senators Dianne Feinstein (D-Cal.)

and John Kyl (R-Ariz.). Both have well-earned reputations as

arch-enemies of civil liberties and the rights of criminal defendants.

[298] Sullivan & Tifft, Restorative Justice, 17.

[299] Ibid., 18-19.

[300] Williams, Victims of Crime and Community Justice, 69; Zernova,

Restorative Justice, 21 (13% victim attendance at community boards), 118

n. 2 (citing four studies finding low victim attendance).

[301] Incidentally, this tenet of RJ ideology refutes the claim that RJ

is a return to age-old forms of reconciliation. For societies like the

Plateau Tonga and the Ifugaos, either revenge or compensation, depending

on the case, is not only taken for granted, it is encouraged. See, e.g.,

William Ian Miller, Bloodtaking and Peacemaking: Feud, Law, and Society

in Saga Iceland (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1990). A man

who refused to exact revenge or demand compensation would be dishonored.

In these societies, where honor is important, he who turns the other

cheek is not only despised, he can expect some more slaps on that side

too. In our society, especially among anarchists, honor is an almost

forgotten value. Also: “I have no belief in the theory that

non-resistance has, as a rule, a mollifying effect upon the aggressor. I

do not wish people to turn me the other cheek when I smite them,

because, in most cases, that has a bad effect upon me. I am soon used to

submission and may come to think no more of the unresisting sufferer

than I do of the sheep whose flesh I eat at dinner.” Charles Horton

Cooley, Human Nature (rev. ed.; New York, Schocken Books, 1964), 276

(originally 1902).

[302] Tomasic, “Mediation as an Alternative to Adjudication,” 230-32.

[303] Zehr, Little Book, 21, 26, 84 & passim.

[304] Howard Zehr & Harry Mika, “Fundamental Principles of Restorative

Justice,” in Zehr, Little Book, 83-89.

[305] Raymond Williams, Keywords (new ed.; Oxford: Oxford University

Press, 2015), 39.

[306] “Transformative Justice and Structural Change,” Handbook of

Restorative Justice, 495.

[307] George Bazemore & David R. Karp, “Community Justice Sanctioning

Models: Assessing Program Integrity,” in Restorative Justice: Repairing

Communities, 192.

[308] David Garland, The Culture of Control: Crime and Social Order in

Contemporary Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011). Or if not

“community,” “family.”

[309] Gilligan, Preventing Violence, 11.

[310] Williams, Keywords, 40.

[311] Paul McCold & Benjamin Wachtel, “Community Is Not a Place: A New

Look at Criminal Justice Initiatives,” in Restorative Justice: Repairing

Communities through Restorative Justice, 46.

[312] Tony Marshall, quoted in ibid., 46.

[313] Takagi & Shenk, “Critique of Restorative Justice,” 156.

[314] John G. Perry, “Challenging the Assumptions,” in Restorative

Justice: Repairing Communities, 11.

[315] Andrew Ashworth, Sentencing and Criminal Justice (5^(th) ed.;

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 94.

[316] Sullivan & Tifft, “Introduction,” Restorative Justice, 6. The

phrase “killed communities” is from Nils Christie, “Conflicts as

Property,” 12.

[317] Christie, “Conflicts as Property.”

[318] I borrow the phrase from Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities:

Reflections on the Origins and Spread of Nationalism (rev. ed.; London &

New York: Verso, 1991).

[319] Zehr, Little Book, 29.

[320] Sullivan & Tifft, Restorative Justice, 164 (emphasis added).

[321] Lysander Spooner, Vices Are Not Crimes: A Vindication of Moral

Liberty (originally 1875), available at

oll.thelibertyfund.org/titles/2292. Unlike Sullivan and Tifft, Spooner

was an anarchist.

[322] Sullivan & Tifft, “Introduction,” 14.

[323] Tomasic, “Mediation as an Alternative to Adjudication,” 242.

[324] Zehr, Little Book, 16.

[325] Zehr, Little Book, 11; see also Fred Boehrer, “The Good Samaritan

or the Person in the Ditch? An Attempt to Live a Restorative Justice

Lifestyle,” in Handbook of Restorative Justice, 546-554 (a history of

Emmaus House, a “Catholic Worker house” in Albany, New York, inspired by

the Catholic anarchist Dorothy Day). I live in Albany. I know about

Emmaus House. It offers short-term room and board for a few homeless

people. What this has to do with RJ, I have no idea.

[326] Shapland, Robinson & Sorsby, Restorative Justice in Practice, 7;

Zehr, The Little Book, 66-67.

[327] Pelikan & Trenczek, “Victim Offender Mediation and Restorative

Justice,” 82.

[328] Mark S. Umbreit, “Restorative Justice Through Victim-Offender

Mediation: A Multi-Site Assessment,” Western Criminology Rev. 1(1) (June

1998) (unpaginated), available online at

http://www.westerncriminology.org/documents/WCR/v01n1/Umbreit/umbreit.html

. This is the same guy whose first RJ book had a chapter on “Biblical

Justice.” If you consider the Old Testament to be the Bible, as Jews do,

or as part of the Bible, as Christians do, you do not want Biblical

justice. The New Testament only looks better by comparison. In another

of his innumerable RJ articles, Umbreit mentions the statistics from his

own study – but not the fact that the difference in recidivism rates was

not statistically significant. George Bazemore & Marc Umbreit, “A

Comparison of Four Restorative Conferencing Models by the Office of

Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention,” in Restorative Justice:

Repairing Communities, 71. I’m pretty sure that Umbreit is another

Mennonite, but I haven’t found the smoking gun, since Mennonites are

nonviolent. They leave violence to the police, and preserve their

personal purity. Some positive evaluations of RJ are blatantly

worthless. One 1994 study found that jurisdictions with RJ have slightly

lower recidivism rates than jurisdictions which do not. Strickland,

Restorative Justice, 26. This is known as the Ecological Fallacy.

[329] Hoyle, “The Case for Restorative Justice,” 94.

[330] James Bonta, Rececca Jesseman, Tanya Rugge & Robert Cormier,

“Restorative Justice and Recidivism: Promises Made, Promises Kept?” in

Handbook of Restorative Justice, 110.

[331] Ibid., 113.

[332] Ibid., 114. The authors report that “most of the offenders in the

restorative justice programs were low-risk, male, Caucasian youth. Very

few programs targeted serious cases such as violent offenders or those

who committed crimes against the person. “ For some reason, I am not

surprised that these whiteboys “displayed very high rates of

satisfaction with restorative justice.” Ibid.

[333] Shapland, Robinson & Sorsby, Restorative Justice in Practice, 166.

Here is an astounding admission from a seven-year study of three English

programs: “In talking about reducing or ceasing offending, it is also

important to recognise that this is only a relevant question if the

perpetrator has a previous history of offending.” Ibid., 176. What! Only

academics are interested in recidivism per se. Everybody else wants to

know if a criminal will offend again, whether or not he has offended

before.

[334] Bonta et al., “Restorative Justice and Recidivism,” 117.

[335] Chris Cunneen, “The Limits of Restorative Justice,” in Debating

Restorative Justice, 184.

[336] Restorative Justice and Crime Prevention: Presenting a Theoretical

Exploration, an Empirical Analysis and the Policy Perspective (April

2010), 173.

[337] Zernova, Restorative Justice, 32.

[338] John Braithwaite, Crime, Shame and Reintegration (previously

cited). I will not be providing specific page citations. The book,

though short, is repetitious. You don’t have to look very long to find

anything.

[339] Caring Hearts Personal Services, Inc. v. Burwell, No. 14-3243

(10^(th) Cir., May 31, 2016).

[340] E.g., Dick Hyman, The Trenton Pickle Ordinance and Other Bonehead

Legislation (Baltimore, MD: Penguin Books, 1984) (originally1976).

[341] John Braithwaite, Restorative Justice and Responsible Regulation

(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).

[342] Zehr, Little Book of Restorative Justice, 101 n. 3. What social

engineers have the expertise to do that?

[343] Shouldn’t that be, “a repentance and [then a] forgiveness

ceremony”? Braithwaite admits Christian precedents, and also mentions

Alcoholics Anonymous, which claims to be self-help but whose members are

mostly ordered into it by the legal system, or occasionally by

employers. A.A. is a thinly (very thinly) disguised Protestant cult.

“Such role models do exist in Christian cultures of the West, though the

Prodigal Son is hardly one of our leading folk heroes.” Besides, parable

addresses only forgiveness. Whether the Son repented, or just ran out of

money, is not indicated. And there was a party, not a forgiveness

ceremony. The loyal son did not forgive. As Braithwaite remarks, “the

Prodigal Son is hardly one of our leading folk heroes.”

[344] E.g., Ruth Benedict, The Crysanthemum and the Sword: Patterns of

Japanese Culture (Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin , 1946); Honour and

Shame: The Values of Mediterranean Society, ed. J.G. Peristiany

(Chicago, IL: Universityof Chicago Press, 1966).

[345] Raoul Vaneigem, The Revolution of Everyday Life, trans. Donald

Nicolson-Smith (Oakland, CA: PM Press, 2012), ch. 21.

[346] Étienne de la Boétie, The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse of

Voluntary Servitude (Auburn, AL: Mises Institute, 2015).

[347] Stirner, The Ego and Its Own, 43. Is it inconsistent for an amoral

egoist to talk like this? Not at all. We are not precluded from having

values or preferring that more people shared them. We want a world of

masters without slaves. We want a world which is rational without being

regulated. The fewer the dupes of morality and ideology, the better for

all concerned. Egoists prefer to deal with other egoists.

[348] Anderson, Code of the Street.

[349] Gilligan, Preventing Violence , 29. The argument is more fully

worked out in James Gilligan, Violence: Reflections on Our Deadliest

Epidemic (London & Philadelphia, PA: Jessica Kingsley Publishers, 2000)

(originally1996).

[350] Ibid., 18 (emphasis omitted). Why did Cain slay Abel? Because

(Genesis 4:5 (KJV) the “Lord had respect unto Abel and his offering: But

unto Abel . . . he had not respect.’” “And Cain was very wroth, and his

countenance fell.” Cain slew Abel because “God ‘dis’d’ Cain. Or rather,

Cain was ‘dis’d’ because of Abel – and he acted out his anger over this

insult in exactly the same way as the murderers with whom I was

working.” Gilligan, Preventing Violence, 31.

[351] Gilligan, Preventing Violence, 53.

[352] Randall Amster, “Breaking the Law: Anti-Authoritarian Visions of

Crime and Justice,” New Formulation 2(2) (Winter-Spring 2004)

(unpaginated), available at http://newformulation.org/4Amster.htm.

[353] Jeff Ferrell, “Against the Law: Anarchist Criminology,” available

online at www.socialanarchism.org.

[354] Coy McKinney, “An Anarchist Theory of Criminal Justice,” May 2012,

available at

www.theanarchylibrary.org

, is based entirely on one article and one book about RJ. The book is –

what else? -- Howard Zehr, The Little Book of Restorative Justice (2002

edition, published in Intercourse, PA). Megan Petrucelli, “Beyond

Absolutes: Justice for All,” available at

http://anarchiststudies.org/2016/01/27/beyond-absolutes-justice-for-all-by-megan-petrucelli,

after espousing anarchism in its first paragraph, goes off on a long

autobiographical soliloquy about the author’s victimization, and

concludes with a brief, idealized summary of RJ ideology. For someone

who is beyond absolutes, she is absolutely sold on RJ. Duane

Ruth-Heffelbower, “Anarchist Criminology: A New Way to Understand a Set

of Proven Practices” (2011), available at

http://ruth-heffelbower.us/docs/Anarchist_Criminology.pdf

, does not understand that RJ is not a proven practice, as we have seen.

And it is difficult to see how state-coerced practices are compatible

with anarchism. These writers don’t know enough about RJ or anarchism to

notice these difficulties. Ruth-Heffelbower is an attorney and a

professional mediator and arbitrator. He also has a Masters in Divinity

degree from – what else? -- a Mennonite seminary. He is the author of

After We’re Gone: A Christian Perspective on Estate Planning for

Families That Include a Dependent Member with a Disability (3d ed.;

Goshen, IN: Mennonite Publishing Network, 2011).

[355] July 10, 2013. Available at

restorativetheology.blogspot.com/2013/the-anarchist-genius-of-restorative/html.

[356] Sullivan & Tifft, “Introduction: The Healing Dimension of

Restorative Justice,” 2.

[357] E.g., David G. Gil, “Toward a ‘Radical’ Paradigm of Restorative

Justice,” Handbook of Restorative Justice, 499-511 – who has no idea how

to do that. Nobody does. Five more citations to the “paradigm shift”

claim appear in Anne-Marie McAlinden, “Are There Limits to Restorative

Justice?” Handbook of Restorative Justice, 306. “Buddy, can youse

paradigm?” Bob Black, “Let Us Prey!” The Abolition of Work and Other

Essays (Port Townsend, WA: Loompanics Unlimited, [1986]); idem,

“Afterthoughts on the Abolition of Work,” Instead of Work (Berkeley, CA:

LBC Press, 2015), 151. Cf. Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific

Revolutions (2d ed., enl.; Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press,

1970). No academic text is complete which fails to cite this book.

[358] Braithwaite, Crime, Shame and Reintegrative Shaming, 148.

[359] Dennis Sullivan & Larry Tifft, “What Are the Implications of

Restorative Justice for Society and Our Lives?” in Critical Issues in

Restorative Justice, 398-99 (emphasis added).

[360] John Godard, Industrial Relations: The Economy and Society

(Toronto, Canada: McGraw-Hill Ryerson Ltd., 1994), 146-152, 157; Black,

“Afterthoughts on the Abolition of Work,” 204-205.

[361] Black, “Reflections on the Abolition of Work,” 209-215, 255-267 &

passim.

[362] Tifft & Sullivan, Restorative Justice, 184-85.

[363] The Handbook of Criminological Theory, ed. Alex R. Piquero

(Chichester, Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell, 2016).

[364] Kevin Passmore, Fascism: A Very Short Introduction (2d ed.;

Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 65.

[365] Dennis Sullivan & Larry Tifft, “Introduction: The Healing

Dimension of Restorative Justice: A One-World Body,” Handbook of

Restorative Justice, 6-7. Of course, they imagine (in 2006) that RJ is

coming to be known, and coming into its own. Ibid., 7. As their bizarre

subtitle indicates, Sullivan & Tifft have fully embraced the mysticism

of the faith-based RJ advocates (with, to make matters worse, Marshall

McLuhan thrown in). There were premonitions of this in The Struggle to

Be Human, at 150, where they announced that “a spiritual awakening is

necessary” – following this with a long quotation from Tolstoy.

[366] “RJ remains on the periphery, exciting the intellects of academics

and some practitioners, while the CJ system continues largely with

business as usual, processing individuals through routine institutional

practices and a set repertoire of responses.” Cunneen, “Limitations of

Restorative Justice,” 122.

[367] “Embarrassments to the Milieu,” Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed

No. 77 (2016), 68.

[368] Hoebel, The Law of Primitive Man.

[369] Black, “An Anarchist Response to ‘The Anarchist Response to

Crime.’”

[370] Edwin M. Schur, Radical Non-Intervention (Englewood Cliffs, NJ:

Prentice-Hall, 1973). Braithwaite dislikes this book. He supports the

drug laws. He writes: “The theory of reintegrative shaming implies that,

rather than be tolerant and understanding, we should be intolerant and

understanding.” Crime, Shame and Reintegration, 166.