💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › wayne-price-the-anarchist-method.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:50:11. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Anarchist Method
Author: Wayne Price
Date: September 1, 2012
Language: en
Topics: introductory, scientific method, counter-economics
Source: Retrieved on 2013-12-08 from https://web.archive.org/web/20131208054104/http://utopianmag.com/articles/the-anarchist-method
Notes: Originally appeared as a chapter in The Accumulation of Freedom: Writings on Anarchist Economics. (D. Shannon, A. J. Nocella II, & J. Asimakopoulos, eds.). 2012. Oakland CA: AK Press.

Wayne Price

The Anarchist Method

There are various opinions on the question of what a libertarian

socialist economy would look like. By “libertarian socialism,” I include

anarchism and libertarian Marxism, as well as related tendencies such as

guild socialism and parecon—views that advocate a free, cooperative,

self-managed, non-statist economy once capitalism has been overthrown.

Before directly discussing these programs, alternate visions of communal

commonwealths, it is important to decide on the appropriate method.

Historically, two methods have predominated, which I will call the

utopian-moral approach and the Marxist-determinist approach (neither of

these terms is meant to be pejorative). I will propose a third approach,

which has been called the “method of anarchism” (or “of anarchy”).

The utopian-moral method goes back to the earliest development of

socialism, before either Marxism or Bakuninist anarchism developed. It

was the method of Saint-Simon, Robert Owen, Fourier, Cabet, and later of

Proudhon. A thinker starts with a set of moral values by which the

present society may be condemned. Then the author moves on to envision

social institutions which could embody these values. (These writers,

pioneers of socialism, communism, and anarchism, did not call themselves

“utopians,” but saw themselves as “scientific”thinkers.)

A current example of utopian-moral methods is the pro-gram of “parecon”

(short for “participatory economics”),originally developed by Michael

Albert and Robin Hahnel.[1] Typically, in the first section of Albert’s

book, Parecon, he poses the key question, “What are our preferred values

regarding economic outcomes and how do particular economic institutions

further or inhibit them?”[2] He works out a set of desirable values and

then considers how an economy could be organized to carry them out.

The advantages of this method should be apparent. What Albert wants and

why he wants it is transparent. It may be fairly argued for or against.

Pareconists offer a yardstick by which to judge potential economies, as

well as real ones, so that radicals do not claim to be for freedom but

accept some totalitarian monstrosity.

However, there are also problems with the utopian-moral method. Various

thinkers start with more-or-less the same values(e.g., freedom,

cooperation, equality, democracy/ self-management, and the development

of each person’s potentialities). Yet they pro-pose quite different

models of a new economy.How to decide among these models?

Also it could be argued that it is authoritarian for radicals today to

make decisions about how other people will organize their lives in the

future. The more precise and concrete the model, the more this is a

problem. Not surprisingly, quite a number of historic utopian models

were very undemocratic in structure (speaking of Owen, Fourier, Cabet,

and Saint-Simon). This is not true of the parecon model, but a modern

version is in B.F. Skinner’s Walden Two (1976), an imagined socialist

commune with a dictatorship by behavioral psychologists (!).

Finally there is a problem in that the utopian approach starts from

values rather than from an analysis of how capitalist society functions.

There is really no necessary connection between any particular model and

the dynamics of capitalism (besides the moral critique). The visions of

the possible futures do not point to any strategies for getting to these

futures.Since they propose a drastic change in society, they maybe seen

as implying a social revolution. But it is certainly possible to adopt

some utopian model and believe that it can be reached by gradual

changes, such as building various alternative institutions until

capitalism can be peace-fully replaced—that is, by following a gradual,

pacifistic,and reformist strategy. A program that does not say whether

to be revolutionary or reformist is not much of a guide to action.

The main alternate method has been that of Marxist-determinism. Marx and

Engels valued the preceding “utopian socialists”for various things, such

as their criticism of capitalism and some of their proposals. But the

original Marxists claimed that another method was needed. It was, they

thought, necessary to analyze how capitalism was developing, including

its main drive mechanism: the capital-labor relationship in

production.This provided the basis of a strategy: the working class

revolution. It indicated the emergence of a new society out of that

revolution. This relationship was their main interest. Marx and Engels

only mentioned the nature of the new society in passing remarks,

scattered throughout their writings—such as a few paragraphs in Marx’s

Critique of the Gotha Program.[3]

In this work, Marx discussed the nature of communism, including at first

paying workers with labor credits and later providing goods freely upon

need. Yet such ideas were not advocated nor made as speculation, but

stated as factual predictions. This is what would happen, he was saying;

human choice seemed to be irrelevant. The goal of Marx and Engels was

not to implement a new social system. It was to see that the working

class overthrew the capitalist class and took power for itself. Once

this happened, the historical process would take care of further social

development.

In The State and Revolution, Lenin regarded himself as praising Marx

when he wrote, “Marx treated the question of communism in the same way

as a naturalist would treat the question of the development of, say, a

new biological variety, once he knew that it had originated in such and

such a way and was changing in such and such a definite direction... It

has never entered the head of any socialist to ‘promise’ that the higher

phase of the development of communism will arrive; ...[it is a] forecast

that it will arrive...”[4]

The Marxist-determinist method also has distinct advantages. It is tied

to an economic theory. It has an analysis of what forces are moving in

the direction of a new society and what are blocking them. It leads to a

strategy that identifies a specific change agent (the working class,

leading other oppressed groups). There are strands of autonomist Marxism

which interpret Marxism in a libertarian, anti-statist fashion which

overlaps with class struggle anarchism.

On the other hand, like a naturalist’s study of an organism’s

development, there is no moral standard, just a “forecast” (even though,

in fact, Marx’s work is saturated with moral passion; but this is not

the system). So when Marxist-led revolutions produce state-capitalist

totalitarianisms that murder tens of millions of workers and peasants,

very many Marxists support this as the result of the historical process

which has created “actually existing socialism.” Marx and Engels would

undoubtedly have been horrified by what developed in the Soviet Union

and other so-called Communist countries. But a method without a moral

standard made it difficult for Marxists to not support these states.

Both the utopian-moral and Marxist-determinist methods have advantages

and weaknesses. Let me suggest an alternate approach to post-capitalist,

post-revolutionary economic models. This has been raised by anarchistsin

the past. It starts from the doubt that every region and national

culture will choose the same version of libertarian socialist society.

It is unlikely that every industry, from the production of steel to the

education of children, could be managed in precisely the same manner.

Kropotkin proposed a flexible society based on voluntary associations.

These would create “an interwoven network,composed of an infinite

variety of groups and federations of all sizes and degrees, local,

regional, national, and international—temporary or more or less

permanent—for all possible purposes: production, consumption and

exchange, communications, sanitary arrangements...and so on...”[5]

Perhaps the clearest statement of this flexible and experimental

anarchist method was made by Errico Malatesta, the great Italian

anarchist (1853–1932). To Malatesta, after a revolution,“probably every

possible form of possession and utilization of the means of production

and all ways of distribution of produce will be tried out at the same

time in one or many regions,and they will combine and be modified in

various ways until experience will indicate which form, or forms, is or

are, the most suitable... So long as one prevents the constitution and

consolidation of new privilege, there will be time to find the best

solutions.”[6] Malatesta continued, “For my part, I do not believe there

is ‘one solution’ to the social problems, but a thou-sand different and

changing solutions in the same way as social existence is different and

varied in time and space.”[7]

We cannot assume, he argued, that, even when the workers have agreed to

overthrow capitalism, they would agree to create immediately a fully

anarchist-communist society. What if small farmers insist on being paid

for their crops in money?They may give up this opinion once it is

obvious that industry will provide them with goods, but first they must

not be coerced into giving up their crops under conditions they reject.

In any case a compulsory libertarian communism is a contradiction in

terms, as he pointed out.

“After the revolution, that is, after the defeat of the existing powers

and the overwhelming victory of the forces of insurrection, what then?

It is then that gradualism really comes into operation. We shall have to

study all the practical problems of life: production, exchange, the

means of communication, relations between anarchist groupings and those

living under some kind of authority... And in every problem

[anarchists]should prefer the solutions which not only are economically

superior but which satisfy the need for justice and freedom and leave

the way open for future improvements...”[8]

Whatever solutions are tried, he is saying, they must be

non-exploitative and non-oppressive. They must “prevent the constitution

and consolidation of new privilege” and “leave the way open for future

improvements.” It is precisely this flexibility, pluralism, and

experimentalism which characterizes anarchism in Malatesta’s view and

makes it a superior approach to the problems of life after capitalism.

“Only anarchy points the way along which they can find, by trial and

error, that solution which best satisfies the dictates of science as

well as the needs and wishes of everybody. How will children be

educated? We don’t know. So what will happen? Parents, pedagogues and

all who are concerned with the future of the young generation will come

together, will discuss, will agree or divide according to the views they

hold, and will put into practice the methods which they think are the

best. And with practice that method which in fact is the best will in

the end be adopted. And similarly with all problems which present

themselves.”[9]

Others have pointed to the experimental approach as central to the

anarchist program. For example, Paul Goodman, the most prominent

anarchist of the 60s, wrote: “I am not proposing a system... It is

improbable that there could be a single appropriate style of

organization or economy to fit all the functions of society...”[10] Or,

as Kropotkin put it, an anarchist “society would rep-resent nothing

immutable... Harmony would... result from an ever-changing adjustment

and readjustment of equilibrium between the multitudes of forces and

influences, and this adjustment would be the easier to obtain as none of

the forces would enjoy a special protection from the state.”[11]

Issues Raised by Differing Models of Post-Capitalism

There are a number of problems that post-capitalist visions have to

address and the ways that they address these issues are what

differentiate them. The approach I have raised does not insist on any

one answer to each issue, but suggests that different answers may be

tried in different regions at different times. However, the answers

proposed by different models provide us with ideas of possible responses

to these problems.That is, the utopian-moral and Marxist-determinist

models may be treated as “thought experiments,” providing suggestions

that may be experimented with.

A key problem is the method of coordination in the post-capitalist

economy. Three answers have been proposed: a market,central planning,

and some sort of non-centralized planning. First, there has been

proposed what might be called “decentralized market socialism.” It would

be for an economy of democratically managed producer (worker-run)

cooperatives,consumer cooperatives, family farms, municipal

enterprises,and very small businesses that would compete in a

market.Such a model has been advocated by various reform socialists who

are concerned with the failures of state-managed economies.[12] It has

been advocated by Right Greens, Catholic distributionists, non-socialist

decentralists, and others.[13] The Yugoslavian economy under Tito had

something like this (under the overall dictatorship of the Communist

Party).

In theory such a system would not be capitalist, because there is no

capitalist class that owns the means of production and there is no

proletariat that sells its ability to work to a separate capitalist

class. But, however democratic each enterprise, the population cannot be

said to actually manage the overall economy in a democratic way. It

would really be run by the uncontrollable forces of the market. There

are bound to be business cycles, unemployment, and a distinction between

more prosperous and poorer enterprises and regions (effects which were

seen in “Communist” Yugoslavia).

An alternative would be some degree of central planning, as Marx seems

to have assumed. In a non-statist society, the central authority would

be answerable to an association of popular councils and assemblies.[14]

Castoriadis imagined that there could be a central “plan factory,” which

would create an over-all plan.[15] Somehow, he believed, this could be

consistent with libertarian socialism of self-managing workers’

councils. Anarcho-syndicalists and guild socialists have also tended

toward a centralized economy, managed by democratic unions. All sorts of

representative institutions can be pro-posed for democratic central

planning, although they all have the difficulty of important decisions

being made outside of the direct control of the working population.

The third suggestion is that of a democratically planned, but not

centralized, cooperative economy, “the idea that production could be

directly coupled to individual and social need through democratic

assemblies (or cybernetic networks) of workers and consumers...”[16]

Parecon is a model of such a non-market, non-centralized system.

Planning would be carried out through cycles of back-and-forth

negotiations among producer and consumer councils using the internet.

In a pluralist, experimental, post-capitalist world, different regions

might experiment with different types of economic coordination. Regions

might try out mixtures of different models. For example, even in the

parecon model there is an element of central planning in the

“facilitation boards,” which help to smooth along the planning process.

Even in decentralized market socialism, presumably there would be some

sort of overall regulation, as there is under capitalism, if not by a

state then by some communal agency. Takis Fotopoulis proposes “a

stateless,moneyless, and marketless economy” but one which includes“an

artificial market” for a “non-basic needs sector...that balances demand

and supply...”[17]

A related issue is the size of the economic unit. While economic

planning by capitalist states is on a national basis, revolutionary

socialist-anarchists generally regard this as inappropriate to a

post-capitalist economy. As internationalists, we are aware that the

world is being knit together by imperialist globalization. At the same

time we know that much of this worldwide centralization is not due to

technical needs but to the need of capitalists to control natural

resources, to dominate world markets, and to exploit the poorest workers

in order to make the biggest profits.To end the rule of states and

bureaucracies, anarchists want as much as possible of local,

face-to-face democracy. This requires a degree of economic

decentralization. Indeed, any sort of economic planning would be easier,

and easier to make democratic, the smaller the units. Finally it would

also be easier to keep production and consumption in balance with

nature, the small-er the units are.[18]

Traditionally anarchists have sought to balance national and

international association with the need for local community by

advocating federations and networks. There can be no hard and fast rule

about how centralized or decentralized an economy has to be. As Paul

Goodman put it, “We are in a period of excessive centralization... In

many functions this style is economically inefficient, technologically

unnecessary, and humanly damaging. Therefore we might adopt a political

maxim: to decentralize where, how, and how much [as] is expedient. But

where, how, and how much are empirical questions. They require research

and experiment.”[19]

Murray Bookchin advocated an economy based on communist communes similar

to the Israeli kibbutzim . This was part of his “libertarian

municipalist” model.[20] Another version is raised by Fotopoulis[21] and

it is also discussed as “Scheme II”in Goodman & Goodman.[22] The

community as a whole would be an enterprise and, through its town

meetings, would make decisions about economic planning. This would not

prevent communities from forming federations on a regional,national, and

international level. They could coordinate their plans and exchange

goods, services, and ideas.

Parecon has its own twist on this issue. Workplaces would be managed by

workers’ councils. Consumption would be organized through consumers’

community councils. These are relatively small, face-to-face groupings.

But the unit which is covered by the final plan is primarily the

nation(which, in the case of the United States, if it still existed,

would be much of a continent). In fact, Albert specifically rejects

“green bioregionalism” and any notion of prioritizing small institutions

or local “self-sufficiency.”[23] (Actually decentralists do not advocate

complete community self-sufficiency, but enough dependence on local and

regional resources to be relatively self-reliant, within broader

federations and networks).

The issue of size is directly related to that of technology. Just as is

true of economic institutions, so productive technology would have to be

flexible, pluralistic, and experimental. Machinery and the methodology

of production have been organized by the processes of capitalism (and

militarism) to serve its interests.Technology would have to be

completely reorganized and redeveloped over time to meet the needs of a

new society.Immediately after a revolution, the workers will need to

begin to rework the process of production (machinery included) to do

away with the distinction between order-givers and order-takers, to

produce useful goods, to be in balance with the ecology, and to make a

decentralized but productive economy possible.[24]

Just how these will be done would require a great deal of rethinking and

trial-and-error.[25]

The parecon model does not include any reconsideration of technology,

but does call for the reorganization of work to create “balanced job

complexes.” Occupations would be broken down and reconfigured so that

individual jobs would include both interesting and boring tasks, both

decision-making and tedious aspects. (This has been described by

Marxists and anarchists as the abolition of the division of labor

between mental and manual labor).

This approach is distinct from either the technophobes, who want to

reject all technology beyond that of hunter-gatherer society, and those

who accept modern technology as capital-ism has created it. Both these

views overlook how flexible technology might be in a totally different

society.

Another key question facing a post-capitalist economic economy is that

of reward for work. There have been proposals for paying workers for

their work in some sort of money or credit,which is used to acquire

goods and services. Pareconists propose paying workers for the

“intensity” and “duration” of their labor,that is, how hard and how long

they work, as judged by co-workers. In Walden Two, the ruling

psychologists were able to increase or decrease the amount of credits

earned for any particular job to motivate members to do unpleasant

tasks.[26]

By contrast, in a fully communist economy, work would be done only for

the pleasure of doing it, or because people feel a duty, or because of

social pressure (people do not want their neighbors to call them “lazy

bums”). Consumption will be aright, based only on human need and

unrelated to effort.Kropotkin is usually understood as advocating such a

communist system after a revolution. Bookchin also proposed going

straight to a free communist economy.

Various thinkers have proposed a split system. Almost every socialist

system, including parecon, provides free goods for children, the ill,

and retired older adults. Fotopolous advocates a basic needs sector and

a non-basic needs sector, the first to be treated as free communism and

the second as having goods to be earned through work.[27] Similarly Paul

and Percival Goodman propose dividing the economy into a basic economy,

which provides a guaranteed minimum subsistence(food, clothing, shelter,

medical care, and transportation), and a separate economy to take care

of everything else.[28] Even if the non-basic needs sector was

market-like, there would be no reserve army of the unemployed, since

everyone would have at least the guaranteed minimum to live on.

This too is an area where different regions might try out different

methods.

This leads to the question of whether to plan for a transitional

economy, whether to expect two or more stages of post-capitalist

economic development. In his Critique of the Gotha Program, Marx wrote,

“We are dealing here with a communist society, not as it has developed

on its own foundations, but as it emerges from capitalist society...

still stamped with the birthmarks of the old society...”[29] He

distinguished between this “first phase of communist society” and “a

more advanced phase of communist society.”[30] These are both communism,

to Marx, because even the first phase is a “cooperative society based on

common ownership of the means of production.”[31] (For some reason,

Lenin renamed the first phase “socialism”and only the final phase

“communism”).

In Marx’s first phase, people would be rewarded for the number of hours

worked with labor-time certificates which they can exchange for goods

according to how many hours went into making each good. While vastly

more just and equal than capitalism, this still has bourgeois

limitations since workers have unequal capacities and unequal needs.

When productivity has vastly expanded and human abilities are further

developed, it will be possible to advance to the higher stage of

communism,which will function according to the standard, “From each

according to their abilities, to each according to their needs.”

We can add that in poorer, less-industrialized nations, a

post-revolutionary society would not be able to even reach the lower

phase of communism (socialism) by itself. It would,however, be able to

take steps toward socialism by such means as replacing the state with a

council system and replacing corporations with self-managed

cooperatives. Yet it might be unable to abolish money or it may have to

make other com-promises with capitalism. Meanwhile it would do all it

could to help the revolution to spread internationally, especially to

the industrialized, richer nations, in order to get economic aid for

industrializing in its own way. (This concept was raised by Lenin[32]

and Trotsky[33]; I have “translated” it into libertarian socialism, so

to speak).

While Marx’s views are well-known, less well-known are the similar views

of Bakunin. According to his close comrade,James Guillame, Bakunin

believed, “We should, to the greatest extent possible, institute and be

guided by the principle, From each according to his [sic] ability, to

each according to his need. When thanks to the progress of scientific

industry and agriculture, production comes to outstrip consumption...

everyone will draw what he needs from the abundant social reserve of

commodities... In the meantime each community will decide for itself

during the transition period the method they deem best for the

distribution of the products of associated labor.”[34]

Even Kropotkin, author of anarchist-communism, believed that right after

a revolution goods would not be free to all able-bodied adults but would

only be guaranteed to those who were willing to work for a set amount of

time. Only as productivity increased would it be possible to make goods

available to all regardless of labor.[35]

The realism of a transitional approach should be obvious given that we

would indeed be going into a cooperative, non-profit economy straight

from capitalism. Modern technology is potentially more productive than

either Marx or Bakunin could have imagined. Yet a post-revolutionary

generation would still have to develop the poorer majority of the world

in a humane and ecological fashion. Also, they would have to rebuild the

technology and cities of the industrialized countries in a self-managed

and sustainable way. Therefore, I doubt that there could be an immediate

leap into full communism.

However, the “transitional stage” concept has been used by Marxists to

justify all sorts of horrors, making excuses for Stalinist

totalitarianism. This is not what Bakunin, or even Marx, had in mind. It

shows the need for a vision with moral values to judge a new society.

Neither Marx nor Bakunin/Guillame proposed a mechanism for going from a

transitional phase to full communism. One possibility might be to use

the idea of a split economy (a basic communism and a non-basic needs

sector). As productivity grows, the free communist sector might be

deliberately expand-ed, until it gradually includes all (or most) of the

economy.

Rather than a series of transitional periods, it may be most productive

to think in terms of an experimental, pluralist, and decentralized

society, in which different parts face the problems caused by the

transition out of capitalism and deal with them in differing ways. A

libertarian socialist society would always be “transitional” in that it

would always be changing, always in transition to a more harmonious,

freer, and more egalitarian society. It would never reach perfection,

since that is not a human goal, but it would continually be changing,

refining itself, re-adapting to new circumstances in a never-ending

spiral of experimental improvement.

[1] See Michael Albert, Moving Forward: Program for a Participatory

Economy (Edinburgh/San Francisco: AK Press, 2000); Michael Albert,

Parecon: Life after Capitalism (London/NY: Verso Books, 2003); and Robin

Hahnel, Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation

(New York: Routledge, 2005).

[2] Albert, Parecon, 28.

[3] Karl Marx, “Critique of the Gotha Program,” in The First

International and After: Political Writings, vol. 3, ed. David Fernbach

(London: Penguin Books, 1974), 339–359.

[4]

V. I. Lenin, Selected Works in Three Volumes, vol. 2, (Moscow:Progress

Publishers, 1970), 348, 357–8. Lenin’s emphasis.

[5] Peter Kropotkin, The Essential Kropotkin, ed. E. Capouya andK.

Tompkins (New York: Liveright, 1975), 108.

[6] Errico Malatesta, Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas, ed. Vernon

Richards (London: Freedom Press, 1984), 104. My emphasis.

[7] Ibid., 151–152.

[8] Ibid., 173.

[9] Errico Malatesta, Anarchy (London: Freedom Press, 1974), 47.

[10] Paul Goodman, People or Personnel: Decentralizing and the Mixed

System (New York: Random House, 1965), 27.

[11] Kropotkin, The Essential Kropotkin, 108.

[12] See Frank Roosevelt and David Belkin, ed., Why Market Socialism?

Voices from Dissent (Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1994).

[13] For example, see Robert A. Dahl, A Preface to Economic Democracy

(Berkely CA: University of California Press, 1985).

[14] See Wayne Price, The Abolition of the State; Anarchist and Marxist

Perspectives (Bloomington IN: AuthorHouse, 2007).

[15] See Cornelius Castoriadis, Political and Social Writings: Vol 2,

1955–1960, ed. and trans. D. A. Curtis (Minneapolis:University of

Minnesota, 1988).

[16] David Belkin, “Why Market Socialism? From the Critique of Political

Economy to Positive Political Economy,” in Why Market Socialism?, ed. F.

Roosevelt and D. Belkin (Armonk NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1994), 8.

[17] Takis Fotopoulous, Towards an Inclusive Democracy (London/NY:

Cassell, 1997), 256–257.

[18] For a compendium of decentralist arguments, see Kirkpatrick Sale,

Human Scale (New York: Coward, McCann& Geoghegan, 1980).

[19] Goodman, People or Personnel, 27.

[20] See Janet Biehl with Murray Bookchin, The Politics of Social

Ecology: Libertarian Municipalism (Montreal/NY: Black Rose Books, 1998).

[21] See Fotopoulous, Towards an Inclusive Democracy.

[22] See Paul Goodman and Percival Goodman, Communitas: Means of

Livelihood and Ways of Life (New York: Columbia University Press/A

Morningside Book: 1960).

[23] Albert, Parecon, 80–83.

[24] See Castoriadis, Political and Social Writings.

[25] For ideas, see Goodman and Goodman, Communitas; George McRobie,

Small is Possible (New York: Harper & Row,1981); and E. F. Schumacher,

Small is Beautiful: Economics as if People Mattered (New York: Harper &

Row/PerennialLibrary Schumacher, 1973).

[26] See B.F. Skinner, Walden Two (New York: Macmillan, 1976).

[27] See Fotopoulous, Towards an Inclusive Democracy.

[28] See Goodman and Goodman, Communitas.

[29] Marx, “Critique,” 346.

[30] Ibid., 347.

[31] Ibid., 345.

[32] See V. I. Lenin, “The Impending Catastrophe and How toCombat It,”

in Selected Works in Three Volumes, vol. 2(Moscow; Progress Publishers,

1970).

[33] See Leon Trotsky, The Permanent Revolution & Results and Prospects

(New York: Pathfinder Press, 1970).

[34] James Guillaume, “On Building the New Social Order”, in Bakunin on

Anarchism, ed. Sam Dolgoff (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1980), 362.

[35] See Kropotkin, The Essential Kropotkin.