💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › wayne-price-anarchism-as-extreme-democracy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:48:01. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchism as Extreme Democracy
Author: Wayne Price
Date: 2000
Language: en
Topics: democracy, introductory
Source: Retrieved on 2017-02-08 from https://web.archive.org/web/20170208133932/http://www.utopianmag.com/files/in/1000000006/anarchism_extreme.pdf
Notes: Published in The Utopian, Volume 1.

Wayne Price

Anarchism as Extreme Democracy

As Marxism, and state-socialism in general, have increasingly been

discredited, there has been a tendency for leftists to turn to another

tradition, that of the democratic revolution.Democracy can be seen as a

ground for opposition to the authoritarianisms of capitalist society

(Morrison, 1995; Mouffe, 1992; Trend, 1996; Wood, 1995). One influential

work concludes, “The task of the Left, therefore, cannot be to renounce

liberal democratic ideology, but, on the contrary, to deepen and expand

it in the direction of a radical and plural democracy.... [S]ocialism is

one of the components of a project for radical democracy, not vice

versa” (Laclau and Mouffe, 1985, pp. 176, 178).

“Democracy” has two contradictory meanings today: the justification of

the existing state versus a tradition of revolutionary popular

liberation. It is the ideological support of the existing “democratic”

states of the West and elsewhere—precisely because democratic ideals are

so attractive. Periodical elections and (relative) freedom of expression

and association are used to justify a society where a few really rule

over the majority. Capitalist democracy is used by competing factions of

rulers to settle their disputes without (much) bloodshed. It serves to

coopt rebellious popular forces.

But democracy is also the cry of the oppressed against ruling elites—the

idea that ordinary people should participate in, and control, the

institutions which make up their society. This idea of democracy goes

back to tribal councils, to classical Athens,to the great bourgeois

revolutions of England, the U.S., and France, to the U.S. abolitionists,

and, today, to ideals loved by millions. It is rights torn from rulers

by the struggle and blood of the people. It is the standard for judging

the state—and for condemning it. As such, it may not yet have lost its

revolutionary potential.

This theoretical development is interesting to those of us who see

socialist-anarchism as nothing but the most extreme, consistent, and

thorough-going democracy. Writers such as Paul Goodman (1965) and Noam

Chomsky(1994), have claimed their versions of anarchism as extensions of

the democratic tradition from Jefferson to John Dewey. Benjamin Tucker,

the nineteenth century U.S.anarchist, wrote, “The anarchists are simply

unterrified Jeffersonian democrats” (1888; p. 11). The contemporary

anarchist Murray Bookchin writes, “...A free society will either be

democratic or it will not be achieved at all” (1995; p. 17).

Yet the historical relation between anarchism and democracy is highly

ambiguous. This should not be surprising, considering how vague and

open-ended have been both terms. Like “socialism” or “freedom,” they

have meant many different things to many different people.

In What is Property?, the first work to claim the term “anarchist,”

Pierre Joseph Proudhon explicitly counterposed it to “democrat”: “I hear

some of my readers reply: ...‘You are a democrat.’ No... ‘Then what are

you? ’‘I am an anarchist’” (quoted in Woodcock, 1962,p. 12). But years

later, Proudhon advocated the replacement of the state by a democracy of

voluntary producers’ associations, “a vast federation of associations

and groups united in the common bond of the democratic and social

republic” (quoted in Guerin, 1970; p. 45).

Anarchism may offer a unique perspective on democracy’s two meanings.

Liberals and social democrats believe in democracy and may call

themselves “democratic socialists.”But while highly critical of aspects

of the system, ultimately they succumb to the mystifying aspect of

democratic theory. They accept the existing state as undemocratic, but

hope to modify it, to make it “even more democratic.” On the other hand,

authoritarian revolutionaries—Stalinists,radical nationalists, etc.—do

not fall for the democratic obfuscations of U.S. imperialism. But they

intend to replace this state with a new state, one in which they are the

new rulers. They reject the ideal of popular self-management.

Anarchists, however, can reject the claim that existing states should be

supported because they are democratic, while continuing to hold up

democracy as a liberating vision. But to do this, anarchism and

democracy must be accepted as compatible. To clarify this issue, I will

first discuss a criticism of anarchism from the standpoint of democracy,

and then a criticism of democracy from the standpoint of anarchism.

Democratic Anti-Anarchism

Robert Dahl’s Democracy and Its Critics (1989) is a major statement of

the case for democracy, clearly written and thoughtful. Before plunging

into his argument, Dahl discusses two fundamental “objections” to

democracy, namely anarchism and “guardianship.” He defines anarchism,

fairly enough, as “a society consisting only of purely voluntary

associations, a society without the state” (p. 37). He quickly adds,

“Because democracy might well be the most desirable process for

governing these associations, it might also be the prevalent form of

government in an anarchist society” (p. 37). This makes clear that

anarchism is not opposed to democracy but to the “democratic state.”

Unfortunately, he does not go on to explain what he means by “the

state.”“I do not pro-pose to define the term ‘state’ rigorously” (p.

359). He uses it, apparently, to mean “the major means of organized

coercion” (p. 43, see also p. 359).

Dahl goes on to make an argument that some coercion is necessary and

that anarchists are wrong to absolutely oppose all social coercion. The

goal should be to “...minimize coercion and maximize consent” (p. 51).

Essentially I agree with his argument. Whatever may be the case after

centuries of anarchist freedom, a newly-anarchist society will need some

way to control individual psychopathic killers or violent organized

counterrevolutionaries.However, Dahl seems to assume that coercion means

a state. He admits that preliterate peoples, such as the Inuit (Eskimo),

lived satisfactorily for centuries or millennia without states,but he

does not consider how they dealt with the social need for coercion. They

had coercion, whether by public opinion or organized violence—every

male, at least, was armed and organized by the tribal council. What they

did not have was a state.

Kropotkin defined the state: “The State idea...includes the existence of

a power situated above society...the concentration in the hands of a few

of many functions in the life of society.... A whole mechanism of

legislation and of policing has to be developed in order to subject some

classes to the domination of others” (1993; p. 160). Comparable ideas

were expressed by Engels: “...[T]his power, arisen out of society but

placing itself above it, and alienating itself more and more from it, is

the state....[I]t consists not merely of armed men but also of material

adjuncts, prisons, and institutions of coercion of all kinds...” (quoted

by Lenin, 1970; pp. 290, 292).

The argument of anarchists is not that it is possible to immediately

abolish all coercion (although some may have posed it that way). It is

that it is possible to abolish the bureaucratic, socially-alienated

institution of the state. The “democratic state” is to be condemned, not

because it is still coercive, but because it cannot be truly democratic.

By its very nature,this instrument of coercion which stands above and

against society must serve a ruling minority against an oppressed

majority.

Dahl does not deal with this issue directly, but it relates to a major

point of his book. Modern society, he says, is too large and complex to

be based on the face-to-face, direct democracy of the preliterate tribes

or later city-states. For democracy to exist on a large scale, it needed

the “invention” of representation. Only representative government (by

implication, a state) could have brought democracy to the modern world,

he claims.

But this has two sides. Representation made a sort-of-democracy possible

on the large scale of modern nations,but that large scale made it

possible to create a form of elite rule which could still be called

democracy. Instead of direct,participatory democracy, we have a layer of

elected politicians and government bureaucrats who stand between the

people and the actual making of decisions. From time to time, the

passive citizens elect these “representatives” to be political for them.

Wood (1995) cites the views of leading figures among the U.S. Founding

Fathers, “Their argument was not that representation is necessary in a

large republic,but, on the contrary, that a large republic is desirable

so that representation is unavoidable.... Representation...is intend-ed

to act as a filter” (p. 216).

Undoubtedly, some degree of representation or delegation,from lower to

higher bodies, is necessary. As federalists,anarchists have generally

agreed with this. But the meaning of representation, and all other

aspects of democracy, would change drastically in a different social

context. The anarchists’ proposed changes in society might be summarized

in two concepts:

First, the creation of an egalitarian society in which separate groups

of oppressors and oppressed either do not exist any longer (capitalists

and workers) or have redefined their relationships as equals (men and

women, European-Americans and African-Americans, North Americans and

Latin Americans). Where wealth is evenly distributed and no oppression

exists, society is no longer pulled in different directions by competing

and hostile forces. It does not need a state to hold things together; it

is easier to maximize con-sent and minimize coercion.

Second (and here most Marxists disagree), anarchists want a society

based in direct democracy through popular assemblies—at the workplace,

in the community, and in many voluntary associations. The more decisions

are made locally,then the fewer are made centrally. The more people

experience face-to-face democracy as a vibrant, daily way of life, the

more they will really control any representatives sent to delegated

assemblies. The police and army would be replaced by a militia—the

people armed. “If the entire people were truly sovereign, there would no

longer be either government or governed...the State...would be identical

to society and disappear into industrial [and other—WP]organization”

(Guerin, 1970; p. 17).

Dahl is aware of these arguments and agrees with them to a point. He

seeks to decrease social and political inequalities. He advocates

greatly increasing participation and decision-making at the local

community level. He supports a democratic socialism where the economy is

socially owned and regulated but firms compete with each other. Unlike

most sup-porters of “market socialism,” he advocates that the firms be

democratically managed by their employees, like producer cooperatives or

the previous Yugoslavian system. “...[I]t would be a mistake to

underestimate the importance of authoritarian institutions in the daily

lives of working people and the consequences of introducing a more

democratic system in the governing of economic enterprises” (p. 332).

Yet he does underestimate the consequences of such decentralized

democratization on the more centralized, national and international,

institutions of society. He dismisses the idea of a drastic

transformation of society raised by either Marxists or anarchists.

“Market socialism” itself suggests that, even under “socialism,” the

economy will not be run overall by democratic decision-making but by the

market. While agreeing that our society is highly unequal, he denies

that there is minority rule (because there are competing elites). This

society—which he calls “polyarchy”—is imperfect, but he argues that it

is still democratic and worthy of support. In practice, if not in

intention, he is one of those who accept the role of democracy as

justifying the existing patriarchal capitalist state.

Part of the problem is that, whenever Dahl backs up theory by referring

to practice, he always turns to existing democratic capitalist states.

Using these as models produces a rather limited view of what democracy

is capable of being. Anarchists, in contrast, focus on the historical

revolutions (for example, Dolgoff, 1974; Kropotkin, 1986; Voline, 1974).

The lessons which anarchists draw from these revolutions are summarized

by Bookchin(1996): “From the largely medieval peasant wars of the

sixteenth century Reformation to the modern uprisings of industrial

workers and peasants, oppressed people have created their own popular

forms of community association...to replace the oppressive states....

[T]hese associations took the institutional form of local

assemblies...or representative councils of mandated recallable deputies”

(p. 4). These historical examples cannot “prove” the validity of a

radically democratic society, but they provide ample evidence of its

possibility.

Anarchist Anti-Democracy

The relation of anarchism and democracy has been raised from the other

side, by Errico Malatesta, the great Italian anarchist (active from the

1870s to the 1930s). Unlike the individualist, anti-organizational

tendency within anarchism, Malatesta advocated that anarchists organize

themselves and promote the self-organization of working people. In

the1920s, he wrote two brief pieces on our topic, with the theme

summarized in the title of one,“Neither Democrats nor Dictators:

Anarchists” (Malatesta, 1995; pp. 73–76 and 76–79).

He believed that the capitalist democratic state was preferable to a

dictatorship, if only because anarchists could use its ideology against

it. “...[T]he worst of democracies is always preferable, if only from

the educational point of view, than [sic] the best of

dictatorships....Democracy is a lie, it...is, in reality, oligarchy,

that is, government by the few to the advantage of a privileged class.

But we can still fight it in the name of freedom and equality...”(p.

77).

As can be seen from this, much of Malatesta’s opposition to democracy is

really directed against democratic ideology as a rationalization for

capitalism and the state. But he mixes this up with a denunciation of

the very concept of majority rule. “...[W]e are neither for a majority

nor for a minority government; neither for democracy nor for

dictatorship.... We are...for free agreement.... We are for anarchy” (p.

76).

The democratic concept is “the rule of the majority, with respect for

the rights of the minority.” Under patriarchal capitalism, “majority

rule” has meant the rule of the dominant minority which shapes majority

public opinion through the control of media and in other ways. “Minority

rights” have often been called on against any attempt by the majority to

take any of the wealth of the rich. But “majority rule” and “minority

rights” have also been rallying cries against ruling minorities and the

prejudiced mass which follows them.

Malatesta points out that the majority is often wrong, compared to the

most enlightened minority. If the majority rules, he argues, it must

dictate to the minority, forcing its will on the minority. This is just

as bad as minority rule. How can the majority be trusted to respect

minority rights if the majority rules over the minority? For these

reasons, Malatesta rejects majority rule in principle. Such views must

be responded to.

Civil libertarians have long argued that there are many areas of life

where collective decision-making is not necessary. In these areas, such

as sexual orientation, the majority have no right to dictate to the

minority. Large numbers of people today would respect the rights of

“consenting adults” to engage in minority sexual practices. As Thomas

Jefferson argued for religious freedom, “...[I]t does me no injury for

my neighbor to say there are twenty gods or no God. It neither picks my

pocket nor breaks my leg” (Dewey, 1957; p. 111). Anarchists seek to

vastly expand the range of voluntary association for such self-chosen

activities,activities outside the realm of majority rule.

However, there will still be areas which require collective

decision-making. For example, a community may need to decide whether to

build a new road. Consensus would be best, but people often disagree. A

majority and a minority may polarize about this issue. This can-not be

treated as a matter of voluntary association (although dissidents are

always free to pick up and go elsewhere—but other communities also must

decide whether to build roads). Either the road is built or it is not.

If a majority forms for road-building, then the anti-builder minority

may be asked to participate, to give their share of the labor or social

wealth.In any case, they will have to live in the community with a new

road, unwanted by them.

This is not coercion by the police but by reality. A decision had to be

made collectively. If not determined by majority vote, then how? A

community may decide that such decisions must be unanimous. But what if

everyone cannot agree? Perhaps the minority gets to veto the proposal,

since it is not unanimous. Then it is the minority which rules,

preventing the majority from getting its road. Alternately, the minority

agrees to keep quiet, so as to “not block consensus.” This denies them

the right to be openly counted as disagreeing. I am not denying the

right of any community or association to decide to rely on consensus,

just arguing that majority rule is not authoritarian in principle.

Malatesta asks what rights the minority has under majority rule. People

with minority views have the right to participate in all decision

making. They have the right to try to win a majority to their views. If

they lose one vote, they may continue to participate and to seek to

become the new majority. Perhaps in the future they will persuade enough

community members that the new road was a mistake and to tear it down,

or, at least, not tobuild new ones. They may be in the majority on other

issues.

Minority rights is an essential part of majority rule. If the members of

a community do not have the chance to hear all opinions, including

minority ones, then they cannot be said to really decide the issues. The

suppression of minority views in capitalist democracy (by force or just

by lack of money or lack of coverage in the media) is one way the ruling

minority creates the illusion that the majority is governing.

At the same time, minority rights are safest when the majority rules, as

opposed to any minority dictatorship. Majority rule and minority rights

are not opposites but require each other.

To democracy, Malatesta counterposes “free agreement.” But there is no

such opposition.People may freely agree to form voluntary

associations—whether to trade stamps or to produce shoes. But then how

will they run the associations? Presumably people will not agree

completely on everything. There must be some process other than

dissolving the associations each time everyone fails to agree. That

process is democracy. Anarchists are not fora democratic state but can

be for a democratic society, for democracy as a “way of life.” Anarchism

is democracy without the state.

Anarchism’s Importance For Democracy

Why is this important? We can see what happens when radicals try to

develop democratic theory without incorporating anarchism. Often it is

little more than “democratic socialism” restated, that is, reformist

state socialism. For example, David Trend’s Radical Democracy (1996) is

mostly articles by members of Democratic Socialists of America. They are

somewhat embarrassed by the identification of their socialism with

statism, but they still have no alternative to using the existing state

to intervene in the economy.

A democratic theory which is really radical would strongly deny that the

existing patriarchal/racist capitalist state is truly democratic, would

oppose the whole socially-alienated, bureaucratic-military state

machine, and would propose instead a democratic federation of assemblies

and associations. Anything less will gloss over the

undemocratic—anti-democratic—nature of our society and its state.

A significant attempt to develop a radical democratic theory which

includes socialism has been made by Chantal Mouffe and those associated

with her. She is quite clear that her “radical democracy” is not an

alternative to the existing state but an extension of it. “What we

advocate is a kind of ‘radical liberal democracy’—we do not present it

as a rejection of the liberal democratic regime or the institution of a

new political form of society” (1996; p.20). Her aim is “...extending

democracy within the framework of a liberal-democratic regime” (1992; p.

3). She is critical of direct democracy or community as goals.

In fact the only time she seems to directly deal with the state is in a

discussion of those who oppose “civil society” to “the state” (in Laclau

and Mouffe, 1985). It is not hard to show that “civil society”—the realm

of capitalism, patriarchy, and racism—is not the ground for salvation

from the state. But “civil society” is internally antagonistic, based on

the tensions between oppressed and oppressors, including the struggles

of classes, genders, and races,among others. This pressure from below

for freedom is the source of all social progress.

Mouffe claims that the state also has internal antagonisms, therefore

implying that it is wrong to reject the state as such. She notes, for

example, that the state may pass legislation against gender

discrimination or in defense of peasants against landlords in poor

countries. This is true, but these are like raises which the management

of a business may offer its workers. It may do this because the workers

force it to or because it is far-sighted and provides benefits before

the workers form a union—but whatever the reason, management remains

capitalist and the enemy of the workers. There are divisions within

management,as within the state, but they are over how best to suppress

and/or coopt the oppressed.Neither management nor the state is the

friend of workers or women or peasants.

Laclau and Mouffe add that there are times when the state is opposed to

“civil society.”“...[T]his is what happens when the state has been

transformed into a bureaucratic excrescence imposed by force upon the

rest of society, as in Eastern Europe, or in the Nicaragua of the

Somozas...” (p. 180). That is, in countries, such as the U.S., where the

majority do support the regime, the state is not, they claim, a

bureaucratic-military excrescence upon society. This is an opinion held

by many people, including that U.S. majority. It can be argued for, but

I do not see how it can be called “radical.”

Democracy’s Importance For Anarchism

If democratic theory needs anarchism, so anarchism needs democracy.

There is an authoritarian trend within the history of anarchism. It

begins with Proudhon, who was racist,anti-Semitic, patriarchal, and who

imagined himself ruling France as dictator over his federation of

associations (Draper, 1970). Bakunin, the second “father of anarchism,”

kept on trying to organize secret societies which would manipulate mass

organizations from behind the scenes (Guerin, 1970; Woodcock, 1962).

Anarchist terrorists and bomb throwers(including the Unabomber) acted as

elite heroes without (or against) the people.

From then until now, anarchists have often capitulated either to

reformism (support of the current state) or to revolutionary

dictatorships. Proudhon ended up getting elected to the French

parliament. Kropotkin, the third “father of anarchism,” became an

enthusiastic supporter of the Western imperialist states in World War I.

Goodman (1965) and Chomsky (1994) could fairly be called reformists.

This anarchist support for reformism became a serious matter when the

Spanish anarchists of the 1930s, faced with a revolutionary situation,

became ministers in the liberal capitalist government. On the other

side, many anarchists joined with the Bolsheviks after the Russian

Revolution. In the 1960s, the anarchist-pacifists of Liberation magazine

became apologists for Castro and Ho Chi Minh. Further examples are

easily found.

The Marxist Hal Draper has argued that the basic problem with anarchism

is its supposed rejection of democracy. “...[A]narchist

‘libertarianism’...is not concerned with the winning of democratic

control-from-below, but with the destruction of ‘authority’ over the

individual ego, even the most extremely democratic version of authority

imaginable” (1969; p. 93). He quotes Proudhon, “Any man who cannot do

what he wants and anything he wants has the right to revolt, even alone,

against the government, even if the government were everybody else”

(same). Draper comments, “The only man who can enjoy this ‘freedom’

unlimited by society is a despot” (same).

While there is an authoritarian side of the anarchist tradition, it

would be ridiculous to deny that there is also a libertarian-democratic

side, in both theory and practice. Whether or not they used the word

“democracy,” socialist-anarchists have long advocated replacing

bureaucratic institutions by self-governing associations, that is, by

democracy (and, as I have argued, a strong defense of individual and

minority rights does not necessarily contradict democracy or majority

rule). Anarchists have organized mass democratic, labor unions, popular

armies,and self-managed peasant collectives and worker cooperatives.

Marxism too has both democratic and authoritarian sides, but the

dominant tendency of its main wings,social democracy and Stalinism, has

been authoritarian statism (as Draper would agree). Between Marxism and

anarchism, it is anarchism which has the more democratic and

freedom-loving theory and tradition.

Also, anarchists have a different relation to their theoreticians.

Unlike Marxism and Leninism, anarchism is not named after its historic

figures. It has no sacred writings comparable to Capital or State and

Revolution. It has no problem rejecting the errors of its founders.

However, Draper has a major point. Anarchism, if not inherently hostile

to democracy, has had a contradictory relationship with it. The

individualist tendencies are the worst in that regard, as has been

recognized by socialist-anarchists. What is needed is for anarchists to

identify anarchism as extreme, revolutionary democracy. The weaknesses

of anarchism are real,but they can be corrected from within the

anarchist tradition.

The program of anarchism is to replace the bureaucratic-military state

machine with a federation of popular assemblies and associations, as

decentralized as is practically possible. This is democracy without the

state. Any other program, such as staying within the limits of the

existing state but making it “more democratic” (“democratic socialism”

or “radical-liberal democracy”) falls for “democracy” as an ideological

cover of the rule of a minority—of patriarchal/racist capitalism and its

bureaucratic state.

References

Bookchin, Murray (1995). Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An

Unbridgeable Chasm. London: AK Press.

Bookchin, Murray (1996). The Third Revolution: Popular Movements in the

Revolutionary Era. Vol. 1. New York: Cassell.

Chomsky, Noam (1994). Secrets, Lies and Democracy. Tucson, AZ: Odonian

Press.

Dahl, Robert (1989). Democracy and Its Critics. New Haven: Yale

University Press.

Dewey, John (ed.) (1957). The Living Thoughts of Thomas Jefferson. New

York: Fawcett.

Dolgoff, Sam (ed.) (1974). The Anarchist Collectives: Workers’

Self-Management in the Spanish Revolution 1936–1939. New York: Free Life

Editions.

Draper, Hal (1969). “A Note on the Father of Anarchism.”New Politics.

Vol. VIII, no. 1. Pp. 79–93.

Goodman, Paul (1965). People or Personnel: Decentralizing and the Mixed

System. New York: Random House.

Guerin, Daniel (1970). Anarchism: From Theory to Practice. (M. Klopper,

trans.) NewYork: Monthly Review Press.

Kropotkin, Peter (1986). The Great French Revolution: 1789–1793. (N. F.

Dryhurst,trans.) London: Elephant.

Kropotkin, Peter (1993). “The State: Its Historic Role.” Kropotkin’s

Fugitive Writings. (G. Woodcock, ed.) Montreal: Black Rose Books. (Pp.

159–201.)

Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal (1985). Hegemony and Socialist

Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics. New York: Verso.

Lenin, V.I. (1976). Selected Works. Moscow: Progress Publishers.

Malatesta, Errico (1995). The Anarchist Revolution: Polemical Articles

1924–1931. (V. Richards, ed.) London: Freedom Press.

Mouffe, Chantal (Ed.) (1992). Dimensions of Radical Democracy:

Pluralism, Citizenship, Community. New York: Verso.

Mouffe, Chantal (1996). “Radical Democracy or Liberal Democracy?” In D.

Trend (Ed.), Radical Democracy. New York: Routledge. (Pp. 19–26.)

Morrison, Roy (1995). Ecological Democracy. Boston: South End Press.

Trend, David (Ed.) (1996). Radical Democracy: Identity, Citizenship, and

the State. NewYork: Routledge.

Tucker, Benjamin R. (1888). State Socialism and Anarchism: How Far They

Agree and Wherein They Differ. Alpine, MI: Charles W. Bergman.

Voline (1974). The Unknown Revolution: 1917–1921. Montreal: Black Rose

Books.

Wood, Ellen Meiksins (1995). Democracy Against Capitalism: Renewing

Historical Materialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Woodcock, George (1962). Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and

Movements.New York: World Publishing.