💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › noam-chomsky-what-is-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:01:23. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: What is Anarchism?
Author: Noam Chomsky
Date: November 18 2013
Language: en
Topics: introductory
Source: Transcript of [[https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=oB9rp_SAp2U]]
Notes: This is a transcript of the talk that Noam Chomsky gave at MIT Wong Auditorium on November 18, 2013. The event was sponsored by the Boston Review and based on the topic of Chomsky’s new volume, On Anarchism.

Noam Chomsky

What is Anarchism?

It’s hardly a secret that the terms of political discourse are not

exactly models of precision. And considering the way terms are used,

it’s next to impossible to try to get a meaningful answer to such

questions as what is socialism or what is capitalism or what are free

markets and many others in common usage. That’s even more true of the

term “anarchism.” It’s been not only subject to varied use but also

quite extreme abuse, sometimes by bitter enemies, sometimes,

unfortunately, by people who hold its banner high. So much is the

variation and abuse that it resists any simple characterization. In

fact, the only way I can see to address the question that’s posed this

evening, “What is anarchism?” is to try to identify some leading ideas

that animate at least major currents of the rich and complex and often

contradictory traditions of anarchist thought and, crucially, anarchist

action.

I think a sensible approach can start with remarks by the perceptive,

important anarchist intellectual and also activist, Rudolf Rocker. I’ll

quote him. He saw anarchism not as “a fixed, self-enclosed social

system,” with a fixed answer to all the multifarious questions and

problems of human life, but rather as “a definite trend in the historic

development of mankind,” which strives for “the free, unhindered

unfolding of all the individual and social forces in life.” That’s from

the 1930s.

These concepts are not really original. They derive from the

Enlightenment and the early Romantic period. In rather similar words

Wilhelm von Humboldt, one of the founders of classical liberalism, among

many other achievements, described the leading principle of his thought

as “the absolute and essential importance of human development in its

richest diversity.” That’s a phrase that John Stuart Mill took as the

epigraph to his On Liberty.

It follows from that that institutions that constrain such human

development are illegitimate, unless, of course, they can somehow

justify themselves. You find a similar conception widely in

Enlightenment thought, so, for example, in Adam Smith. Everyone has read

the opening paragraphs of The Wealth of Nations, where he extols the

wonders of division of labor, but not many people have gotten farther

inside to read his bitter condemnation of division of labor and his

insistence that in any civilized society the government will have to

intervene to prevent it because it will destroy personal integrity and

essential human rights, will turn people, he said, into creatures as

“stupid and ignorant” as a human can be. It’s not too easy to find that

passage, whatever the reason may be. If you look in the standard

scholarly edition, the University of Chicago Press bicentennial edition,

it’s not even listed in the index, but it’s one of the most important

passages in the book.

Looked at in these terms, anarchism is a tendency in human development

that seeks to identify structures of hierarchy, domination, authority,

and others that constrain human development. And then it seeks to

subject them to a very reasonable challenge: Justify yourself,

demonstrate that you’re legitimate, and maybe in some special

circumstances or conceivably in principle. And if you can’t meet that

challenge, which is the usual case, the structures should be dismantled,

not just dismantled but reconstructed from below.

The ideals that found expression during the Enlightenment and the

Romantic era foundered on the shoals of rising industrial capitalism,

which is completely antithetical to them. But Rocker argues, I think

quite plausibly, that they remain alive in the libertarian socialist

traditions. These range pretty widely. They range from left

anti-Bolshevik Marxism, people like Anton Pannekoek, Karl Korsch, Paul

Mattick, and others, including the anarchosyndicalism that reached its

peak of achievement in the revolutionary period in Spain in 1936. And

it’s well to remember that despite its substantial achievements and

successes, it was crushed by the combined force of fascism, communism,

and Western democracy. They had differences, but they agreed that this

had to be crushed. The effort of free people to control their own lives,

that had to be crushed before they turned to their petty differences,

which we call the Spanish Civil War.

The same tendencies reach further, to worker- controlled enterprises.

They’re springing up in large parts of the old Rust Belt in the United

States, in northern Mexico. They’ve reached their greatest development

in the Basque country in Spain. Mondragon is partly a reflection of the

achievements of the long, complex, rich Spanish tradition of anarchism,

and partly it comes out of Christian anarchist sources. Also included in

this general tendency are the quite substantial and cooperative

movements that exist in many parts of the world, and I think it also

encompasses at least a good part of feminist and human rights activism.

In part, all of this sounds like truism. So why should anyone defend

illegitimate structures? No reason, of course. And I think that

perception is correct. It really is truism, I think. Anarchism basically

ought to be called truism. But truisms have some merit. One of them is

the merit of being true, unlike most political discourse. This

particular truism belongs to an interesting category of principles,

principles that are not only universal but doubly universal: they’re

universal in that they’re almost universally accepted and universal in

that they’re almost universally rejected in practice. There are many of

these.

For example, the general principle that we should apply to ourselves the

same standards we do to others, if not harsher ones. Few would object,

few would practice it. Or more specific policy proposals, like democracy

promotion or humanitarian intervention. Professed generally, rejected in

practice almost universally. All doubly universal. This truism is the

same—the truism that we should challenge coercive institutions of all

kinds, demand that they justify themselves, dismantle and reconstruct

them if they do not. Easy to say, but not so easy to act on in practice.

Proceeding with similar thoughts, I will quote Rocker again. “Anarchism

seeks to free labor from economic exploitation and to free society from

ecclesiastical or political guardianship, and by doing that opening the

way to an alliance of free groups of men and women based on cooperative

labor and a planned administration of things in the interest of the

community.” Rocker was an anarchist activist as well as political

thinker, and he goes on to call on the workers’ organizations, other

popular organizations to create “not only the ideas but also the facts

of the future itself” within the current society. That’s an injunction

that goes back to Bakunin.

One traditional anarchist slogan is “Ni Dieu, ni Maître,” “No God, no

Master.” It’s a phrase that Daniel Guérin took as the title of his very

valuable collection of anarchist classics. I think it’s fair to

understand the phrase “No God” in the terms that I just quoted from

Rocker — opposition to ecclesiastical guardianship. Individual beliefs

are a different matter. That’s no matter of concern to a person

concerned with free development of thought and action. That leaves the

door open to the lively and impressive tradition of religious anarchism,

for example, Dorothy Day’s very impressive Catholic Worker Movement. But

the phrase “no master” is different. That refers not to individual

belief but to a social relation, a relation of subordination and

dominance, a relation that anarchism, if taken seriously, seeks to

dismantle and rebuild from below, unless it can somehow meet the harsh

burden of establishing its legitimacy.

By now we’ve departed from truism and, in fact, to ample controversy. In

particular, right at this point the rather peculiar American brand of

what’s called libertarianism departs very sharply from the libertarian

tradition. It accepts and indeed strongly advocates the subordination of

working people to the masters of the economy and, furthermore, the

subjection of everyone to the restrictive discipline and destructive the

features of markets. These are topics worth pursuing. I’ll take them up

later, if you would like, but I’ll put them aside here, though also

recommending to you about bringing together in some way the energies of

the young libertarian left and right, as indeed sometimes is done. For

example, it’s done in the quite important and valuable theoretical and

practical work of economist David Ellerman and some others.

Anarchism, of course, is famously opposed to the state while at the same

time advocating “planned administration of things in the interests of

the community,” Rocker’s phrase again, and beyond that, broader

federations of self-governing communities at workplaces. In the real

world of today, the same dedicated anarchists who are opposed to the

state often support state power to protect people and society and the

Earth itself from the ravages of concentrated private capital. Take,

say, a venerable anarchist journal like Freedom. It goes back to 1886,

formed as a journal of socialist anarchism by supporters of Kropotkin.

If you open its pages, you will find that much of it is devoted to

defending rights of people, the environment, society, often by invoking

state power, like regulation of the environment or safety and health

regulations in the workplace.

There’s no contradiction here, as sometimes thought. People live and

suffer and endure in this world and not some world that we imagine. And

all the means available should be used to safeguard and benefit them,

even if the long-term goal is to displace these devices and construct

preferable alternatives. In discussing this, I’ve sometimes used an

image that comes from the Brazilian workers’ movement. It’s discussed in

an interesting work by Biorn Maybury-Lewis. They use the image of

widening the floors of the cage. The cage is existing coercive

institutions that can be widened by committed popular struggle. It

happened effectively over many years. And you can extend the image

beyond. Think of the cage of coercive state institutions as a kind of

protection from savage beasts that are roaming outside, namely, the

predatory, state-supported, capitalist institutions that are dedicated

to the principle of private gain, power, domination, with the interest

of the community at most a footnote. Maybe revered in rhetoric, but

dismissed in practice and, in fact, even in Anglo-American law.

It’s also worth remembering that anarchists condemned really existing

states, not visions of unrealized democratic dreams, such as government

of, by, and for the people. They bitterly opposed the rule of what

Bakunin had called “the red bureaucracy,” which he predicted 50 years in

advance would be among the most savage of human creations. They also

opposed parliamentary systems that are instruments of class rule. The

contemporary United States, for example, which is not a democracy, it’s

a plutocracy. That’s very easy to demonstrate. The majority of the

population has no influence over policy. As you move up the

income/wealth scale, you get more and more influence. The very top

people get what they want. Well established by academic political

science but familiar to everyone who looks at the way the world works. A

truly democratic system would be quite different. It would have the

character of “an alliance of free groups of men and women based on

cooperative labor and a planned administration of things in the

interests of the community.”

In fact, that’s not too remote from one version of the mainstream

democratic ideal. Actually, one version. I’ll stress that. I’ll return

to others. Take, for example, the leading American social philosopher of

the 20^(th) century, John Dewey. His major concerns were democracy and

education. No one took Dewey to be an anarchist. But pay attention to

his ideas. In his conception of democracy, illegitimate structures of

coercion must be dismantled, and that includes domination “by business

for private profit through private control of banking, land, industry,

reinforced by command of the press, press agents, other means of

publicity and propaganda.” He recognized that “power today resides in

control of the means of production, exchange, publicity, transportation,

and communication. Whoever owns them rules the life of the country,”

even if democratic forms remain. And until these institutions are in the

hands of the public, politics will remain “the shadow cast by big

business on society.” Very much what we see around us, in fact.

It’s important that Dewey went beyond calling for some form of public

control. That could take many forms. He went beyond. In a free and

democratic society, he wrote, the workers should be “the masters of

their own industrial fate,” not tools rented by employers, not directed

by state authorities.” That position goes right back to the leading

ideas of classical liberalism articulated by von Humboldt, Smith,

others, and extended in the anarchist tradition.

Turning to education, Dewey held that it is “illiberal and immoral” to

train children to work “not freely and intelligently but for the sake of

the work earned,” to achieve test scores, for example, in which case

their activity is “not free because it’s not freely participated in” and

it’s quickly forgotten too, as all of us know from our experience. So he

proceeded to conclude that industry must be changed “from a feudalistic

to a democratic social order” and educational practice should be

designed to encourage creativity, exploration, independence, cooperative

work — exactly the opposite of what’s happening today.

These ideas lead to a vision of society based on workers’ control of

productive institutions, the links to community control within the

framework of free association and federal organization. In the general

style of thought that includes, of course, along with many anarchists,

others too, say G.D.H. Cole’s guild socialism in England, left

anti-Bolshevik Marxism, a current development, such as, for example, the

participatory economics and politics of Michael Albert, Robin Hahnel,

Stephen Shalom, and others, along with important work in theory and

practice by the late Seymour Melman, his associates, and many others,

notably Gar Alperovitz’s very valuable recent contributions on

worker-owned enterprise and cooperatives. Not just talk but actual

taking place.

Going back to Dewey, he was as American as apple pie, to borrow the old

cliché, right in the mainstream of American history and culture. In

fact, all of these ideas and developments are very deeply rooted in the

American tradition and in American history, a fact which is kind of

suppressed but is very obvious when you look into it. When you pursue

these questions, you enter into an important terrain of inspiring, often

bitter struggle. That’s ever since the dawn of the Industrial

Revolution, which was right around here, Lowell, Lawrence, eastern

Massachusetts, mid-19^(th) century.

The first serious scholarly study of the industrial worker in those

years was 90 years ago. It’s by Norman Ware. It’s still very much worth

reading. He reviews the hideous working conditions that were imposed on

formerly independent craftsman and immigrants and farmers, as well as

the so-called “factory girls,” young women brought from the farms to

work in the textile mills around Boston. He mentions that, he reviews

it. But he focuses attention on something else—what he calls “the

degradation suffered by the industrial worker,” the loss “of status and

independence,” which could not be cancelled, even where there

occasionally was some material improvement. And he focuses on the

radical capitalist “social revolution, in which sovereignty and economic

affairs passed from the community as a whole into the keeping of a

special class of masters,” often remote from production, a group “alien

to the producers.” Ware shows, I think pretty convincingly, that “for

every protest against machine industry and privation there can be found

100 protests against the new power of capitalist production and its

discipline.” In other words, workers were struggling and striking not

just for bread but also for roses, in the traditional slogan of the

workers’ communities and organizations. They were struggling for dignity

and independence and for their rights as free men and women.

Their journals are very interesting. There’s a rich and lively labor

press written by working people, artisans from Boston, factory girls

from the farms. In these journals they condemned what they called the

“blasting influence of monarchical principles on democratic soil, which

will not be overcome until “they who work in the mills will own them,”

the slogan of the massive Knights of Labor, “and sovereignty will return

to free and independent producers.” Then they will no longer be “menials

or the humble subjects of a foreign despot, the absentee owner, slaves

in the strictest sense of the word, who toil for their masters.” Rather,

they will regain their status as “free American citizens.”

The capitalist revolution instituted a crucial change from price to

wage. It’s very important. When a producer sold his product for a price,

Ware writes, “he retained his person. But when he came to sell his

labor, he sold himself.” I’m quoting from the press. That’s a big

difference. He lost his dignity as a person as he became a slave, a wage

slave, to use the common term of the period. One hundred sixty years

ago, a group of skilled workers repeated the common view that a daily

wage was equivalent to slavery, and they weren’t warned, perceptively,

that a day might come when “wage slaves will so far forget what is due

to manhood as to glory in a system forced on them by their necessity and

in opposition to their feelings of independence and self-respect,” a day

that they hoped would be far distant. These were very popular notions in

the mid-19^(th) century, in fact, so popular that they were a slogan of

the Republican Party. You could read them in editorials of The New York

Times. That’s then, not now. But that day may come back. Let’s hope.

Labor activists of the time warned, bitterly often, of what they called

“the new spirit of the age: Gain wealth, forgetting all but self.” That

was the new spirit of the age 150 years ago. In sharp reaction to this

demeaning spirit, there were quite enormous and active rising movements

of working people and radical farmers. Radical farmers actually began in

Texas and spread through the Midwest and much of the country. It was, of

course, an agricultural country then. These are the most significant

democratic popular movements in American history. They were dedicated to

solidarity, mutual aid. They were crushed by force. We have a very

violent labor history as compared to other countries. But it’s a battle

that’s not over, far from over, despite setbacks, often violent

repression.

There are familiar apologists for the radical revolution of wage

slavery, and they have an argument. They argue that the workers should

indeed glory in a system of free contracts voluntarily undertaken. There

was an answer to that 200 years ago by Shelley in his great poem “The

Masque of Anarchy.” This was written right after the Peterloo massacre

in Manchester, England, when the British cavalry brutally attacked a

peaceful gathering of tens of thousands of people—the first major

example of huge, nonviolent protest and the reaction of the state

authorities to it. They were calling for parliamentary reform. Shelley

wrote that we know what slavery is. “Tis to work and have such pay/As

just keeps life from day to day/In your limbs, as in a cell/For the

tyrants’ use to dwell. … Tis to be slave in soul/And to hold no strong

control/Over your own wills, but be/All that others make of ye.”

That’s slavery. That’s what working people and independent farmers were

struggling against. The artisans and factory girls who struggled for

dignity and independence and freedom might very well have known

Shelley’s words. Observers at the time noted that they were highly

literate. They had good libraries. They were acquainted with the

standard works of English literature. This is before mechanism and wage

slavery. The wage system ended, or at least curtailed, the days of

independence, high culture, and security. Before that, Ware points out,

a workshop might be what he called a lyceum. A journeyman would hire

boys to read to them while they worked. These were social businesses,

with many opportunities for reading, discussion, mutual improvement.

Along with the factory girls, the journeyman, the artisans bitterly

condemned the attack on their culture.

The same was true in England, incidentally, where conditions were much

harsher. There’s actually a great book about this by Jonathan Rose

called The Intellectual Life of the British Working Classes. It’s a

monumental study of the reading habits of the working class of what we

think of as Dickensian England. He contrasts what he calls “the

passionate pursuit of knowledge by proletarian autodidacts” with the

“pervasive philistinism of the British aristocracy.” Actually, I’m old

enough to remember residues that remained among working people in New

York in the 1930s, who were deeply immersed in the high culture of the

day. It’s another battle that may have receded, but I don’t think it’s

lost.

I mentioned that Dewey and American workers and farmers held one version

of democracy with very strong libertarian elements. But the dominant

version has been radically different. Its most instructive expression is

at the progressive end of the mainstream spectrum. That is among people

who are good Woodrow Wilson, FDR, Kennedy liberals. Here are a few

representative quotes from icons of the liberal intellectual

establishment on democratic theory.

The public are “ignorant and meddlesome outsiders.” They have to “be put

in their place.” Decisions must be in the hands of an “intelligent

minority” of “responsible men,” namely, us, and we have to be protected

“from the trampling and roar of the bewildered herd” out there. The herd

does have a function in a democratic society. They are supposed to lend

their weight every few years to a choice among the responsible men. But

apart from that, their function is to be “spectators, not participants

in action.” And all of this is for their own good. We should not succumb

to “democratic dogmatisms about men being the best judges of their own

interests.” They are not. They are like young children. You have to take

care of them. We are the best judges of their own interests. So their

attitudes and opinions have to be controlled for their own benefit. We

have to “regiment the minds of men the way an army regiments their

bodies, ” and we have to discipline the institutions responsible for

what they called “the indoctrination of the young”: schools,

universities, churches. If we can do this, we can get back to the good

old days — this is complaints about the 1960s — when “Truman had been

able to govern the country with the cooperation of a relatively small

number of Wall Street lawyers and bankers,” then we will have true

democracy.

These are quotes from icons of the liberal establishment: Walter

Lippmann, Edward Bernays, Harold Laswell, the founder of modern

political science, Samuel Huntington, Trilateral Commission, which

largely staffed the Carter administration. The conflict between these

conceptions of democracy goes far back. It goes back to the earliest

modern democratic revolution in 17^(th) century England. At that time,

there was a war raging between supporters of the king and supporters of

parliament. That’s the civil war that we read about. But there was more.

The gentry, the men who called themselves “the men of best quality,”

were appalled by the rabble, who didn’t want to be ruled by either king

or parliament, like the Spanish workers in 1936, neither side. They had

their own pamphlet literature, and they said they wanted to be ruled by

“countrymen like ourselves that know our wants. It will never be a good

world while knights and gentlemen make us laws that are chosen for fear

and do but oppress us and do not know the people’s source.” That’s

17^(th) century England.

The essential nature of this conflict, which is far from ended, was

captured nicely by Thomas Jefferson in his later years. He had serious

concerns about both the quality and the fate of the democratic

experiment. He made a distinction between what he called aristocrats and

democrats. The aristocrats are “those who fear and distrust the people

and wish to draw all powers from them into the hands of the higher

classes.” The democrats, in contrast, “identify with the people, have

confidence in them, cherish and consider them as the honest and safe,

although not the most wise, depository of the public interest.”

The modern progressive intellectuals—the Wilson, Roosevelt, Kennedy

intellectual left, those who seek to put the public in their place and

are free from democratic dogmatisms about the capacity of the ignorant

and meddlesome outsiders to enter the political arena—they’re

Jefferson’s aristocrats. These basic views are very widely held, though

there are some disputes, namely, who should play the guiding role.

Should it be what the liberal intellectuals call the technocratic and

policy-oriented intellectuals, the ones we celebrate as the Camelot

intellectuals, who run the progressive knowledge society, or should it

be bankers or corporate executives? In other versions, should it be the

central committee or the guardian council of clerics? They are all

pretty similar ideas.

And they’re all the examples of the ecclesiastical and political

guardianship that the genuine libertarian tradition seeks to dismantle

and reconstruct from below, while also changing industry from a

feudalistic to a democratic social order, one that’s based on workers’

control, community control, respects the dignity of the producer as a

genuine person, not a tool in the hands of others, in accordance with a

libertarian tradition that has deep roots and, like Marx’s old mole, is

always burrowing quite close to the surface and ready to spring forth.