💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › david-wieck-the-negativity-of-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:25:42. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Negativity of Anarchism
Author: David Wieck
Date: 1975
Language: en
Topics: authority, ethics, feminism, ideology, individualism, introductory, marxism
Source: Retrieved on 16 August 2011 from http://quadrant4.org/anarchism.html
Notes: From Interrogations: Revue Internationale de Recherche Anarchiste, Paris, France, No. 5 (December 1975)

David Wieck

The Negativity of Anarchism

Anarchism is notoriously pluralistic in the sense that there are many

philosophers and many schools with no obvious common ground except the

rejection of political sovereignty implicit in an-archia. Not

unreasonably, anarchism is frequently taken to be a family of minimally

related ideas that deny the legitimacy of the state and (usually)

propose its abolition. This view, although texts in support of it could

be cited, is narrow; for anarchism is not merely anti-state, somehow it

is an idea or theory of freedom. But this not merely, this freedom, are

indefinite and much in need of elucidation.

I offer here a view of anarchism, a way of understanding it in terms of

a common basis, that I hope will make evident its importance and its

meaning. This is a problematical undertaking, quite different from a

study of the thought of an individual anarchist writer. It calls for

decisions about what is essential in the various anarchist traditions,

and there is high risk that the result be more revelatory of one’s own

bias or predilections than of anarchism past or present. More exactly,

then, the present article is an expression of my intuition, based

chiefly on my personal experience of anarchism, of what is central to

anarchism and what most worthwhile in the sense of statement about human

society and human being. In the course of the reflective effort to

express my intuition as precisely as I can, I have come to see a number

of fundamental issues in a way that is new and illuminating to me.

My discourse is objective in mode and intended for philosophical

scrutiny. I wish to make it quite clear, however, especially because I

believe that what one thinks and claims to know in the objective mode is

inseparable from one’s convictions (where one is coming from, as the apt

phrase had it), that I share the broad attitude or orientation that I

identify as anarchist.

As I say later on, the perspective of anarchism, as a living idea rather

than as an intellectual possibility, is a perspective of oppressed

people to whose anger at their oppression and the oppression of their

comrades anarchism gives voice; the purpose of anarchism is to serve as

a means for putting end to those oppressions. Just how far one can grasp

the meaning of life-conditions that are not one’s own — a question

raised vigorously by blacks and by women — I am not sure. (I have

experienced oppressions but not as a permanent condition to which

society and circumstance have condemned me; in the family of mankind I

have been a middle-privileged person at least.) However that may be, I

am convinced that anarchism can become meaningful only if one has a

concrete sense of the social reality — I am afraid I do not know a

better term out of which it arises, and I hope that I have kept this

reality, namely the human meaning of oppression, in constant view.

The Anarchist Idea

To a preliminary conception of anarchism and of what I mean by a common

basis, comparison and contrast of the role of ideas and ideology in the

history of socialism and anarchism will provide a way of approach, less

circuitous than may at first appear.

Anarchism is usually called an ideology, and in some senses of a term

that everyone defines at will, this characterization would be correct if

not very informative. I prefer to define ideology, in the spirit of Marx

and Mannheim, as an aprioristic and rationalized belief system that

serves to justify, and to mystify on behalf of, the dominance and power

of some social group or some institutional complex. (This definition is

meant to comprehend trascendental ideologies, ie., theologies, as well

as social ideologies.) Although I believe it to have broader theoretical

utility, the reader is free to regard this definition, which will have a

thematic function in my discussion, as a means of making distinctions

useful in clarifying the status of anarchism.

Socialism before Marx expressed an incompletely determinate but by no

means abstract ideal, roughly describable as abolition of bourgeois

property, economic exploitation, and class division, vindication of the

dignity of labor, and institution of production for use. Philosophically

and by social science, Marx tried to create for socialism a theory of

method and a justification for its goals. Subsequently, in the

historically important variants of socialism, Marxist theory, or perhaps

more exactly the philosophy and methodology of Engels, suitably glossed,

became doctrinal truth: first of all in the German Social Democracy and

American DeLeonism and then in Leninism and its derivatives.

‘Orthodoxy,’ ‘deviation,’ ‘revisionism,’ and the remainder of a

vocabulary of rigidified theology-like system, enforced by a centralized

party, signal the transition. This last stage of Marxism, these systems

of truth, are fully ideological in the sense of the definition above.

(That the Marxisms which have a share of the world historical scene are

aprioristic belief-systems resting on definitive foundations is widely

recognized for the Leninist Instances. If it is less usual to regard

Leninism as justifying and mystifying on behalf of a dominant social

group, this is in part because, from a bourgeois standpoint, itself

ideological, it seems like a proseletyzing faith. I see its primary

function as justification of the rule of the leadership of a party over

its members, of the rule, present or future, of a party over society;

and as mystification of the people. Leninist Marxism turns out therefore

to be an ideology of state-dominion that merges with — appropriates or

perhaps is appropriated by — ideologies of nationalism. Social

democracy, of course, has found accommodation with capitalist ideology.)

Anarchism, by contrast, while not free of ideological tendency, has

never been dominated or delimited by the theories of its philosophical

and scientific proponents. Those anarchists who have advocated doctrinal

unification have usually affiliated eventually with Marxist parties, as

have advocates (the same persons most often) of party-like organizations

intended to lead and direct popular movements of social revolution. The

anarchist belief is fundamental that no person, no theory, no historical

process, stands higher than oneself, and that life does not yield

primacy to thought abstracted from it. The most significant legacy from

the past therefore is certain values and (especially) principles, the

lives, and often the deaths, of exemplary and heroic persons, and

cautionary experiences. Resolve and action, knowledge of one’s desires

and goals, is what matters: which is to say that Marxist accusations of

voluntarism do not malign anarchism.

Mannheim’s classification of anarchism as utopian rather than

ideological — because it seeks to sunder and not to sustain the social

present — has much to recommend it but is still not accurate and is

prejudicial moreover in that ‘utopian’ (as much as ‘ideological’) was

for Mannheim a term of contrast to the realistic methods of liberal

social-scientific meliorism. Anarchism, non-ideological and prior to

philosophy and to science, we may best, if with slight semantical

awkwardness, speak of as an Idea: a mode of speech familiar to at least

some anarchists, certainly to those in the Spanish and Italian

traditions.

Characterization as an Idea situates anarchism in that constellation or

cosmos of Ideas, kindred in spirit one to another although wholly

concordant by no means, that assumed major significance in the

eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries in Europe and the Americas:

Ideas of socialism, reason, liberty, equality, democracy, mankind,

progress, history, the nation. Certain of these, such as anarchism and

socialism, expressed social ideals directly; certain, among them

socialism, and the idea of the nation equally fatefully, became the

source of later ideologies. We lack an unambiguous name for that

pre-ideological mode of thought; idealistic may be best but in a sense

that is pre-philosophical and discontinuous with philosophic Idealism.

(The sense of Idea here is not Hegel’s but that of a recently emerged

mode of thought that he sought to understand and appropriate. He blamed

the abstract. Ideas for the course of the French Revolution, not

realizing, or preferring not to see that although they were undoubtedly

used as manipulative abstractions, i.e., ideologically, by the wielders

of new power, they had meaning enough, and concretely, for the poor and

oppressed.)

An Idea like anarchism, as I conceive it, is a thought, a thinking, a

conviction, a desire, an aim, a vision of life, whose nature is an

insistence that it be realized and whose full meaning is to become

manifest only in its realization. It expresses a potentiality of human

being, recognizable by human beings and embraceable as a goal that

together they endeavor to consummate. It exists in (and as) social

movements, in (and as) movements of mind, in (and as) the lives,

actions, and experiences of persons. It has ground in the social present

and objectivity and potential reality as a shared and social aim.

Although capable of articulation, it is not essentially conceptual,

certainly not rationalistic. At its core, as its matter, as its material

source, is feeling — feelings about relations among human beings, about

personal identity and worth, about human being.

In terming anarchism an Idea, I mean to convey specifically that it is

non-doctrinal; that it has always been understood rather than defined;

that it gives shared meaning to deep-felt longings; that it indicates an

ideal aim for which a social movement, of everyday human beings who in

practice will often enough contradict their ideals, is called forth;

that it expresses an ought that is an anticipation of its object of

striving; that it serves as object of faith, as ground of solidarity and

mutual aid; that it has been enriched but not transformed essentially by

supporting speculations. and reasoned argument; and that it has remained

continuously and intensely in touch with its originating ideals.

By no means does this anarchism signify mindlessness, irrationalism or

an anti-intellectual attitude — a misinterpretation common in the

youth-radical movements of the 1960’s, possibly reflecting confusion

between (in my terminology) ideas and ideology. On the contrary,

self-education, thinking through and discussing exhaustively the meaning

and consequences of one’s basic beliefs, being their master and not

their servant, these are implicit in the anarchist Idea and were the

norm, and frequently the practice, of traditional anarchist movements.

To say that this Idea is a thought seeking its realization is to say

that it demands a maximum of social inventiveness and practical

imagination, that it demands (again) that one know what one wants. It is

opposite to obedience to ideas abstracted from life and to action

uninformed by thought. This, rather than the anarchism of one or another

theorist, is the anarchism whose meaning I shall try to bring forth.

The fact that the anarchism in question remained essentially an Idea

grounded in feeling does not mean that this Idea has no history or

evolution, but I shall not attempt to deal with that evolution here.

Anarchism

With the foregoing formal conception of anarchism in mind, I now offer a

statement of its content.

The theme of political sovereignty will be the point of departure, with

proviso that we adopt the wide sense of ‘politics’ employed by

contemporary feminists who by speaking of sexual politics have drawn

notice to a veritable host of politics.

(“The term ‘politics’ shall refer to power-structured relationships,

arrangements whereby one group of persons is controlled by another. By

way of parenthesis one might add that although an ideal politics might

simply be conceived of as the arrangement of human life on agreeable and

rational principles from whence the entire notion of power over others

should be banished, one must confess that this is not what constitutes

the political as we know it, and it is to this that we must address

ourselves.” Kate Millett, Sexual Politics, N. Y.: Doubleday, 1970, pp.

23–24.)

On this model (the political as we know it) we may conceive of the

politics of production and consumption, the politics of education, the

politics of race, the politics of religion, the politics of art, the

politics of age — and the politics of every social sphere, the

conventionally political included, in which a group or class or caste

dominates others, or some institutional complex rules the lives of

people. In many of these spheres, exchangeable slogans of freedom and

liberation, and more problematic slogans of power as well, have been

raised.

As might be expected, there is also a politics of liberation — a

politics of overt or covert power-structures that control particular

movements of liberation.

We shall have in mind, then, a panoply of political relationships, among

them, masters and slaves, governors and governed, propertied and

propertyless, employers and employees, male and female, teachers and

students, old and young (and young and old), dominant and subjugated

races, party leaders and party members, bureaucrats and clients, labor

leaders and rank and file, commanders and troops, priests and their

flocks (and on some views: God and human being), imperial nations and

subject-peoples, liberators and those whom they propose to liberate.

With respect to each of the power-relationships one can identify a

‘distinctive ideology, sometimes formally articulated, although rarely

with the thoroughness of orthodox Leninism, sometimes primitive or

parasitic on other ideologies.

Anarchism can be understood as the generic social and political Idea

that expresses negation of all power, sovereignty, domination, and

hierarchical division, and a will to their dissolution; and expresses

rejection of all the dichotomizing concepts that on ground of Nature,

Reason, History, God or other, divide people into those dominant and

those justly subordinated. Anarchism is therefore far more than

anti-statism, but government (the state), as claimant to ultimate

sovereignty and hence to the right to outlaw or legitimate particular

sovereignties, and because sustained from self-interest by those who

guard particular fiefs and turfs, stands at the center of the web of

social dominion and is appropriately the focus of anarchist critique.

Anarchism is anti-political, therefore, in a comprehensive sense for

which electoral and parliamentary abstentionism is a fitting symbol.

The relationship between the anarchist idea and my definition of

ideology is by now obvious: a relationship justified by the aptness of

the anarchist perspective for assessment of the exploitation of ideas by

power and the ideologizing of ideas, a project to which Marxism

contributes mightily but which its own commitment to power betrays. For

the state itself, traditional political philosophy, above all in the

epoch of the nation-state, has provided consistent ideological support.

Anarchism then is the social and political philosophy that proposes the

eradicating of all divisions between (political) haves and have-nots,

the dissolving rather than the redistributing of power; and the

abolishing of identities of ruler and subject, leader and led, learned

and ignorant, superior and inferior, master and servant, human and

inhuman. If the anarchist ideal were realized, all persons in their

unique individuality would be related to each other in multiple

nonstratified societies of voluntary (freely chosen) association.

Today, individuality signifies, almost invariably, membership in an

elite class or caste, opposite a mass, and depends on (is given

definition by) that membership; such individuality is not authentic

because not properly individual. What is presently thought of as

socialization is a stabilized, preferably frictionless politics to which

the subordinate assent. The aim of anarchism is universal and genuine

individuality and complete socialization, their antithesis overcome by,

precisely, the elimination of constraining and distorting contexts of

power. Then ail persons would be political equals, not in the sense of

equality of power (for anarchism negates social power) or necessarily of

goods but in the sense that no one, no group, and no institution would

rule, control, decide for or dominate another. There would be society,

but no polity.

Individuality (uniqueness) and the socialization of human existence, so

reconceived, can be identified as basic values of anarchism, values in

turn describable as social freedom. Justice will no longer be defined in

terms of distribution, or of rights that presuppose sovereignty,

certainly not by lawfulness. If slavery be taken as metaphor for

domination, applicable literally or nearly so to many of its forms,

justice and injustice of institutions can be defined in terms of slavery

so that an Institution is unjust if and insofar as persons implicated in

it are the slaves of others. However benign and altruistically

intentioned, slaveries violate human being systematically and

essentially, and this cannot be made-good. The master of course thinks

otherwise, and otherwise say his ideologies.

Plainly, to strive for the total abolition of slaveries is not the only

possible mode of response to their recognition: if it were, there would

be no liberalisms or Marxisms and anarchists would be everywhere. If

convinced that abolition is Impossible, one may choose to mitigate,

reform or exchange systems of power; without devaluing freedom, one

might not hope for more than marginal and sporadic realization of it.

Except for incidental remarks, I shall avoid discussion of practicality

and the philosophical problems concerning judgment of it, problems that

are particularly difficult because the generalization of anarchist

attitudes toward institutions might have significant results, in keeping

with anarchist values, even if the ideal aim were never approximated. I

limit myself to trying to exhibit the meaning of the anarchist Idea, a

project prior to, even though not fully distinguishable from, judgments

of practicality, and necessary (I believe) because the degree to which

an anarchist perspective restructures perception and anticipation of

human being, of society, and of history, is rarely appreciated

sufficiently.

(Sometimes the characteristics of anarchism discussed here are

expressed, by anarchists and others, as anti-authoritarianism. This is

an unhappy mode of expression, first because anti-authoritarianism is

professed by numerous and diverse political groups; second because there

are forms of authority that do not entail power over persons; third

because authority is that to which power pretends and which its ideology

claims for it; and for other reasons. Authority that is specifically and

voluntarily delegated is not power-over-persons, although it may be

converted to such power. Recognition of the authority of technical

competence is not submission to power, unless the technically competent

are permitted to determine ends as well as means, or to determine means

in a fashion that determines ends. The authority of each in his or her

own sphere of activity is a way of enunciating the freedom of each.

Analysis of authority, to distinguish the genuine from the spurious, has

been lacking in anarchist literature; the problem is met squarely by

Giovanni Baldelli’s Social Anarchism, N. Y.: Atherton Press, 1971. from

which I have learned much.)

Anarchism and Marxism

Persons familiar with early Marx might suggest that I have just

described uncorrupted Marxism. The matter is worth pursuit both for its

own sake — since I believe Marxism and anarchism to represent truly

basic alternatives — and in order to bring out other important

dimensions of the anarchist Idea, especially its temporality.

Marx might be called a philosophical anarchist in the sense of the

phrase that signifies affirmation of anarchy as an ideal without present

relevance. The conflict between Marx and the anarchists in the First

International makes it clear that Marx did not in organizational

practice or revolutionary program share the anarchists’ negativity

toward power. He demanded control by the central organization over the

sections; he insisted on programmatic unity, in effect the enforcement

of agreement to truths of a leadership-elite; he destroyed the

International rather than permit it to be an association of solidarity

in diversity; he emphatically rejected the anarchist thesis that the

abolition of the state was a present concern. Anarchist criticism of

Marxism, in addition to unjustly Identifying Marx with later dialectical

materialism, sometimes overstresses the historical personage Karl Marx

but, besides foreshadowing the political and ideological practice of

future socialism, including the Leninist monoliths, his behavior

reflects his conception of power and freedom.

The ideals sometimes (not so very frequently) affirmed in Marxism may

not be significantly opposed to those of anarchism; but for all the time

between the present and, in Marxism, the eventual realization of the

ideal there is systematic variance. For Marx as for Marxism, no-power,

to the extent acknowledged, is beyond History, while for anarchists it

is within History, within the present, immanent as potentiality in the

present.

Anarchism provides, as I have indicated, a critique of the politics of

liberation itself — a critique that only a few Marxists have attempted.

Basic to Marxism is the view that economic power is the key to a

liberation of which the power of a party, the power of government, and

the power of a specific class are (or are to be) instruments. Basic to

anarchism is the opposing view that the abolition of dominion and

tyranny depends upon their negation, in thought and when possible

action, in every form and at every step, from now on, progressively, by

every individual and group, in movements of liberation as well as

elsewhere, no matter the state of consciousness of entire social

classes. Thus, anarchists see in Marxism an illusion of liberation and

the creation of new structures of power that forever defer it and that

nullify spontaneous liberations briefly tolerated. Correlatively, in the

anarchist view the choices and actions of individuals are important for

those persons, for their milieu, and for all of us; in the view of

Marxists, collectivities and their actions alone have significance, are

alone objectively real (this has turned out to be the operational

meaning of Marx’s famous Feuerbach-thesis on the individual).

Congruently with theory, the strategies of Marxist movements have been

strategies for conquest and use of power, strategies of affirmation of

politics. In every country ruled by Marxists the basic politics, i.e.

the basic structures of state, have been perpetuated, or if in collapse

reinstituted and revivified, a fact that lends support to the claim that

anarchism is the only social philosophy that asserts an alternative to

the politics of power. (Of the various liberalisms, the anarchist

critique need not be spelled out.)

In the light of the preceding, certain familiar Marxist polemics against

anarchism can be subjected to inversion: the result is polemical also

but perhaps not unfair. Rather than anarchism, it may be Marxism, with

its vision of post-historical transcendence, that is apocalyptic and

utopian. Anarchism rather than Marxism may be capable of sustaining a

conception of genuine social dialectic, for Marx’s theory of

superstructure and the primacy of impersonal economic forces inhibits,

if it does not entirely rule out, an apprehension of continuous

interplay among the many arenas of politics and liberation. It may be

anarchism that implies the more complete view of anthropos because it

does not by abstraction obscure and ignore the psychology and the now so

important sociology of power. And it may be not anarchism but Marxism,

with its econocentrism, its controlling dialectic of technology and

property, that is simplistic and naive.

In the section that follows, part of the meaning of the above theses

will be developed.

The New Relevance of Anarchism

Recent revival of interest in anarchism, and the tendency of some North

American and Western European Marxists to revise Marxism in libertarian

directions, allow explanation in terms of the present discussion.

First, anarchism is the natural generic expression for the many

particular movements of liberation, including a number that have emerged

in force only recently. As such a generic Idea, anarchism implies these

liberations, and most lines of argument against particular

power-and-dominance relations tend conversely to generalize to the

anarchist position. Not merely awareness of twentieth century extensions

of state-power, therefore, has given anarchism contemporary relevance

both for radical youth and for various intellectuals and social

philosophers.

Anarchism does more than unify the many themes of liberation. For those

who suspect that power rather than wealth may be the root of oppression,

and that power may be the more comprehensive concept, anarchism offers a

framework of explanation. Marxist have generally derived racism from the

interest of the wealthy classes in dividing the mass of the people

against one another; one does not have to deny this interpretation all

validity to see that the psychology of social or ethnic domination, for

the sake of domination, may be a deeper theme. It has been difficult, in

view of the imperialist actions of the Russian state, to attribute

imperialism and wars to economic and profit considerations primarily. In

many other spheres, the sphere of liberation included, we see power

sought after from motives deeper than a theory centered upon economics

accounts for; while a theory centering upon power is capable of

explaining also the seemingly irrational intensity of acquisitive

behavior.

Third, it is becoming Increasingly apparent that to speak about a ruling

class in the present era is totally inadequate. Nationally and

internationally, the economics of capitalist distribution retains its

disproportionality of wealth and poverty but now power is corporate and

bureaucratic. Even that statement falls short, and phrases like

‘military-industrial complex’ seem ineluctably apt. Individuals and

groups face elaborate structures of power, national and transnational,

and their self-sense, even at relatively high levels of privilege, is

likely to be one of powerlessness, helplessness, insecurity. The class

that rules is not exactly a class of persons but more like an

institutional complex whose administrative and managerial technicians

work, one may say with only slight exaggeration, to job-description.

Even if we define this personnel, together with the major beneficiary

individuals and families, as the ruling class, it remains nonetheless,

in the U.S.A. as in the U.S.S.R., an impersonal power with replaceable

figureheads. The power demands of the American ‘60’s expressed a sense

of contemporary society’s, not America’s alone, central problematic: the

abstraction of power from persons in the form of bureaucratic society,

managerial society, etc. Anarchism becomes more plainly relevant when

power itself, not this group or that class of persons, reveals itself as

the truth of the nation-state and of international capitalism and

nationalistic socialism, and when power rather than wealth is the prime

image of success, the one model presented for emulation.

Fourth, from many sources have come reasons to believe that any theory

that finds the secret of human liberation in something so specific as

the politics of property neglects the interdependence of the many

liberations. Each species of dominance and power re-enforces other

species, directly in ways that can be mapped sociologically, indirectly

by requiring and engendering habits of rule and/or submission. Children

who have undergone hierarchically structured families and schools will

be most fortunate if enabled by countervailing experiences to affirm

themselves thereafter in non-power-structured situations, or to relate

freely and responsibly as persons with persons, or to resist power

rationally rather than by brief rebellion. Solidarity among, professedly

antagonistic groups against challenge from below — the solidarity of

union officials and corporate managers, to name a familiar type — is in

striking contrast to the normal and self-defeating non-solidarity, most

often mutual hostility, of oppressed groups from different categories.

As we proceed more deeply into a world of Institutional management of

human existence, and in that evolution might be approaching, if we have

not already passed, a point of no return, questions of liberation

increasingly reveal themselves as a single issue of manifold human

liberation.

Fifth, the interdependence of the many liberations suggests that human

liberation must be a continuous process and that the anarchist method of

seeking to transform qualitatively the scene of one’s life, of trying to

create spheres of freedom, even when one cannot affect large social

institutions of property and government directly, may be a meaningful

and necessary part of a multidimensional process of liberation in which

many are active in varied and particular ways. This can be expressed by

saying that anarchism proposes the continuous realization of freedom in

the lives of each and ail, both for its intrinsic, immediate values and

for its more remote effects, the latter unpredictable because they

depend on the unpredictable behaviors of persons not known and of

nonpersonal historical processes.

Nevertheless, anarchism remains extraordinarily difficult to adopt other

than philosophically, i.e., intellectually, for it makes a severe

dialectical demand: that persons envision and find ways to overcome a

condition of objective and subjective powerlessness and futility, not by

seeking power or planning its seizure, or by pleading with power, and so

on, which are the ways of politics and the ways also by which people

attempt to cope with everyday oppressions, frustrations, and

resentments, but by negating power absolutely and choosing

powerlessness. (Choice of powerlessness does not, however, imply

passivity or lack of militancy. Anarchism and Taoism have much in common

— but anarchism is not a way of merely personal salvation.) The demand

is severe, given, in the U.S.A. for specific example, a society that is

barren of public ideas other than the power-oriented; given a prevailing

ethics that allows one to do whatever one wants so long as no one is

hurt very directly; given that authentic models of liberty,

individuality, and free cooperation are scarce; given a superficial but

malignant pessimism about human being; given a complex of overlapping

hierarchies such that all but a few people are relatively superb r to

others who are institutionally inferior; given a communications

technology that provides a year-round circus of politics for the

entertainment and mystification of the citizenry; given the rage,

hatred, fear, envy that pervade the nation. Although the youth-radical

movements of the late ‘60’s in the U.S.A. exhibited so many familiar

themes of anarchism that the Movement might be described as

protoanarchist, a plausible interpretation of its collapse is that

(mainly unacknowledged, often magical) expectations of power, even of

instant power, were unfulfilled. Neo-Marxisms that retain a basic

affirmation of power and a reassuring vision of power-through-history,

while seeking to qualify themselves by incorporating libertarian themes,

make lesser psychological and ethical demands.

Whether, in a society (and world) in which the reality and ideality of

power are ubiquitous, anarchism, in the sense of generic liberation, can

have meaning other than to be a way of life for a small number, would

seem to depend on the possibility that the transcendence of power, i.e.,

integral freedom, becomes by many persons concretely imaginable,

concretely thinkable, as the resolution and liquidation of the

power-and-powerlessness polarity. Because such a consciousness has never

yet been realized on a large social scale, with the partial exception of

a certain period in Spain, its potentialities have never been tested.

But the choice of powerlessness, the choice, if run one must, to run

with the hares and not with the hounds, and, beyond that, the choice to

reject such definition of options, is a choice open to each person as a

life-choice, and its intrinsic meanings are not invalidated either by

choices others make or by verdicts of mindless History.

Anarchist Ethics

(a. Anarchist Principle)

I should like now to begin to present certain implications of an

anarchist view of power and liberation.

In theories justificatory of anarchism one encounters a confusing

variety of ethical arguments — a variety attributable in part but not

entirely to the authors’ desire to emphasize either the theme of

individuality or the theme of sociality. In anarchist movements and the

lives of anarchists, however, one finds something simpler — a consistent

emphasis upon principles and action from principle. Herein I believe

lies a key to the ethical meanings of anarchism.

To the bourgeois, anarchist principle signifies fanaticism, to Marxists

an unrealistic and irresponsible unadaptibility to objective

circumstance and historical necessity. On principle anarchists abstain

from all elections, refuse to form or support political parties or

party-like organizations, refuse to appeal to or accept the aid of

government to achieve immediate desired ends, refuse to accept positions

of power, oppose and seek the downfall of liberal as well as overtly

tyrannical states, oppose all wars and resist military service, refuse

to be married by state or church, and so on. Anarchists refuse to

recognize laws, courts, and police authorities, refuse to defend

themselves by accepted legal procedures. Anarchists make a principle of

direct (i.e., personal and non-mediated) action, a principle of

solidarity, a principle of personal responsibility. In general the word

‘compromise’ means for anarchists compromise of principles, and has only

pejorative connotations. The conclusion would be difficult to avoid,

that this inflexibility is somehow intrinsic to anarchism.

Action from principle has in different contexts very different meanings.

In the anarchist context these various principles, this attachment to

principle, this ethics and politics of strict (but not absolute)

principle, all this becomes intelligible and coherent when the various

principles are referred to a single principle, that one should neither

exercise nor submit to power over persons, either by collectivities or

persons; with the correlative belief that the downfall of power depends

upon action from this principle. By this interpretation, negation of

power can be described as the principle-of-principles of anarchist

action: in the end, perhaps it is, or should be conceived as the only

principle.

(It is important to note that the principles mentioned are nearly all

negative principles. Plainly they call for the supplement of concrete

alternative actions fitted to circumstances, and an anarchist movement

that knows nothing but its negative principles is a movement in decay.)

I believe that the central anarchist principle is best understood in

interconnection with certain more general ideas: that the individual is

the basic social reality; that individual voluntary consent is the

ground of cooperation (giving one’s word, in the traditional anarchist

movements, is the bond that unites); that everyone, oneself not

excepted, is responsible for their actions; that social freedom depends

on the self-discipline of each; and that the assumption of power or

submission to power in any sphere of human activity is a negation of the

fundamental reality of individuals, a negation intrinsically incapable

of offset by other types of considerations. These ideas are, I would

argue, existentially although not formally reciprocal, and are implicit

in the negation of power-overpersons as presented in Section II above.

(The argument would be difficult and would probably turn on explication

of ‘individual as basic social reality.’ Here I note only that ‘basic

social reality’ does not entail ‘basic metaphysical reality.’)

(b. Power and Violence; Fraternity and Love)

In two areas besides the question of property — which will be discussed

separately — anarchists have differed sharply about principles. The

dispute between anarchists who distrust formal organization, anarchist

as well as other, and for whom the term ‘organization’ is pejorative,

and those who hold organization to be essential, would seem chiefly to

represent a difference in sociological and psychological judgment,

disguised by semantics of ‘organization’ and ‘association,’ as to

conditions under which the individual is lost and power emerges. No

fundamental questions of ethics seem implicated.

The other area, deeply problematic, is that of pacifism, violence, and

revolution. The main anarchist tradition has been revolutionary in a

sense that endorses violence as a means of resisting and destroying the

apparatus of force and violence by which power is maintained. (That the

free society should be non-violent is agreed.) Within the framework of

anarchist principle, it can be argued reasonably that violence against

an oppressor who maintains his position by violence is not itself an act

of oppression since one does not seek to (and will not) enslave or bring

into subjection that person. The violence-affirming or

violence-condoning tendency would seem to be asserting that negation of

master/servant (slave) relationships takes priority over the claims to

respect for life of those who insist on being masters and, by violence,

direct or indirect, make that insistence good. Unfortunately, major

social oppression defends itself usually by hired or conscript

instruments — and, when defeated, by foreign armies. All these persons

are oppressors in their instrumental roles, and subject to seduction and

corruption by those roles, yet many in their own way are victims.

Here the anarchist who accepts violence is beyond clear guidance of

principle. Even in its terrorist phases, however, anarchist violence has

almost always been directed expressly and scrupulously against

principals or executives of political and economic oppression, so that,

by comparison with the anticivilian terror-warfare of governments, or

nationalist guerrilla warfare, or routine police terrorism in countless

nations, to say nothing of the savage reprisal taken upon defeated

working classes all through history, anarchist terrorism is ridiculously

misnamed. Prevalence of an ethics of principle, rather than a

utilitarianism that lends itself to selfdeception, may be a major ground

for this (self-) control; while the centering of principle in

power-negation rules out the taking of hostages or other instrumental

treatments of persons that are the usual transition from resistance to

militarized warfare. The breakdown of anarchist principle in the Spanish

anarcho-syndicalist movement, especially during the civil war and

revolution, is a large and complex topic into which I cannot enter here.

In twentieth century anarchism, not merely within the Tolstoyan

tradition, pacifism has been an important minoritarian tendency. Whether

evolutionary or non-violently revolutionary, pacifist anarchism asserts

that violence is even clearer negation of human being than is power, is

perhaps even the genus of power, and introduces into anarchism a concept

of love much stronger than the fraternity of the main tradition —

universal, because unlike fraternity not restricted to solidarity of the

oppressed — and tends thereby to transform the concept of the individual

and the concept of freedom. Love will then be the ultimate positive

concept, opposite to violence. I think that one can say that an

anarchist, of whatever specific persuasion, who does not feel (more than

think) such love and non-violence as ultimate values has not fully

experienced the meaning of anarchism, although love and non-violence are

not easily lived in the midst of the oppression and suffering of others.

In a sense, therefore, the motion of anarchism toward a full ethics of

love, although a motion intrinsic to the Idea, remains to be realized,

and may be realizable only in transition to anarchist society.

(c. Utilitarianism and Anarchism)

In certain anarchist theories, it should be noted, one finds instead of

appeal to principle, essentially utilitarian arguments against the

state, based on historical and scientific studies, that would have no

more than analogical presumption of applicability to other

power-relationships. The contentions of Kropotkin and Rocker, that the

arts and sciences, peace, evolutionary progress, would be favored by

abolition of the nationstate suggest that the question of political

decentralization, anti-statism in a narrow sense, may be distinct and

separable from other questions of power, and such writers have tended to

be somewhat less forceful in their critique of other forms of power.

(Both Kropotkin in 1914 and Rocker in 1939 found it possible to support

the Allied governments at war.) Bookchin’s ecological justification of

anarchism is kindred in method although he is rather more sensitive to

other issues.

With respect to anarchist movements and their ethos, however, I do not

see such speculation as foundational, and I would agree with Malatesta,

whose explicit voluntarism may have expressed most nearly the spirit of

the historical movement and the anarchist idea, that Kropotkin would

have been an anarchist even if his biological and historical theories

had been refuted. If so, the utilitarian and historical arguments would

be confirmatory or, perhaps, a ground recognizable and acceptable to

persons in the middle-privileged strata of society, for whom the

perspective of the oppressed, which is the perspective of anarchism, and

the anger of the oppressed, to which anarchism gives voice, often

stridently, might otherwise be strange, disquieting and frightening,

even abhorrent. Doubtfully would such arguments sustain the passion

invested in the Idea, a faith for which many have given their lives.

The arguments which I see as having priority are, rather than

utilitarian, arguments of morality (justice) or arguments of freedom,

or, when the argument takes eudemonistic form, appeal to actualization

of human being. I am not suggesting inconsistency in an anarchism

grounded in utilitarianism, especially if the concept of utility is

broad; I do suggest the utilitarianism, well-suited to decision-making

in collectivist societies and systems of sovereignty, does not much lend

itself to expression of anarchist intent.

(d. The Ethics of Freedom)

The role of principle in anarchist thought and action, as I understand

it, is to liberate the positive ethical life of human beings. Thus the

principle of power-negation is rather a constitutive principle of the

desired society than a rule for life within that society. Put more

concretely: an authentic relationships between persons, as understood by

anarchists, presupposes the absence of power of some over others, but

‘absence of power’ says nothing positive about the content of that

relationship, and that content will be the creation of those persons.

If such is the meaning of anarchist principles, it would seem to follow

that intercourse in an anarchist society would be conducted under

conditions of voluntary agreement (often tacit, of course) and personal

responsibility-for this seems to be what one would mean by ‘absence of

power.’ Faith in the possibility of anarchist society, then, would

signify faith that, in the absence of structured power, of dominant and

subordinate classes, and of habits of deference to authority and

exercise of power, human beings can use the gift of speech and other

subtle forms of communication to resolve their Intercourse into mutually

beneficial patterns or into intelligent confrontation and disagreement

and if necessary pacific disassociation, without need for commandments

of morality.

One would not, however, say of such a society that it is post-ethical —

as one might of a Marxist society, after the state has withered at last,

in which the economic form of communism would be the sociological

realization of the ethical. Of anarchy one might say instead that ethics

had resolved itself into new human being, a metaphor that would signify

that faith and trust of persons toward persons, rather than contingent

modes of cooperation, would be the vital center. Put otherwise: nothing

secures an anarchist society, whether of large extent or of communesize

or consisting of just two persons, except continuous realization of the

human potentiality for free agreement and disagreement, always in

recognition of the personhood of the other. If anarchism does not remain

clear to the last of the institutional thinking that Marxists call

materialist, it must finally become incoherent and the individualism (or

personalism) that, twinned with the corresponding version of sociality,

is the soul of anarchism, would be threatened with extinction.

In a society of hierarchies — of discriminations against classes or

castes and condemnation of various large numbers of persons to

particular kinds of limited existence to others’ advantage — coercive

institutional machinery is everything and its guarantee and enforcement

by state-power is of the social essence. If we think of voluntary

action, choice, decision, autonomy, as central to the meaning of being

human — as the main philosophical traditions assert — then anarchism can

be understood as seeking to dissolve those institutions of power that

make life-decisions for us, that offer to substitute themselves for our

freedom and relieve us of burdens of responsibility, and do so whenever

they successfully coerce us to accord our will to their demands. Then,

anarchism is expressive of a will to restore, and/or create, personhood

and human being; whereas in surrendering to or exercising dominion one

substitutes for oneself an institutional definition. an institutional

being, one ceases to be oneself. It will be plain, I think, given these

premises, that by voluntary surrender of freedom, by submission to a

protectorate such as the Hobbesian state is claimed to be, one yields

far more than the exercise of certain liberties.

Anarchism as Negative

It may now be clear why a name (an-archist) negative by etymology is

appropriate to the import of anarchism.

This appropriateness can be illustrated with respect to a familiar

species of power, that of racial oppression. If the thoroughgoing

negation of racial oppression is, as one might reasonably think, a

society in which recognition of racial identity has vanished, or in

which racial terms, if indeed sense can be made of them when oppression

does not define them, have become minor descriptive terms without social

consequence, then it would be foolish to ask what the theory of this

raceless society would be or how it would deal with racial relations.

For the U.S. integrationist movement of the 1950’s the slogan Freedom

Now said all that need be said, just as, more than a century before,

Abolition, a saying that of course earned one the title ‘fanatic,’ a

title yet to be repealed, was all that needed be said of chattel

slavery.

A second illustration, less obvious because even now barely thinkable,

would be a society, usually called androgynous, in which recognition as

male and female would make reference to nothing but certain

physiological matters and reproductive capacities and would be

non-indicative of personality, economic role, or worth. Sexes would not

constitute classes (or more exactly castes) and sexual identity would

have only the significance that each chose to give to it. What this

means requires no elaborate explanation, only a certain imagination, an

ability to rid oneself of preconceptions and to conceive of what seems

incapable of being thought without contradiction. What will be the

relations between the sexes in such a society? — the question makes

erroneous assumptions.

From every locus of power, it has always been inconceivable, because

contrary to the aprioris of the sustaining ideology, that its system be

abolished. From the standpoint of the priesthood it has always been

inconceivable that religion dispense with it, that its flock survive

bereft of shepherd.

With respect to the anarchist concept of social existence, the questions

Who will rule? Who will govern? and — what is less obvious intuitively —

Who will decide? become nonrelevant questions. No theory of

total-society decision-making would be called for. Power to the people,

Let the people decide, although of idealistic intention, perpetuate the

sovereignty of the whole and are not anarchist. In practice such

qualified (democratic) sovereignty means that representatives of the

people constitute a class of decision-makers over against a mass that

makes no decisions except (perhaps) to choose their rulers, a choice

inevitably reconstrued as majoritarian. Where the demos rules, power and

its problems remain; a people represented, as Rousseau said, is

enslaved. Anarchy means the dissolution and disappearance of democratic

sovereignty (or its pretense) also.

In an anarchist society every person decides and there is no class of

deciders. Cooperative actions result from voluntary agreements. This is

easier to visualize in a small society lacking complex relations of

production and distribution; larger scale cooperation presumes

longer-term agreements, reliance on the good will of others as norm,

agreement to standard procedures (non-coercive, non-power-based

institutions) to achieve commonly desired ends and to resolve

differences and conflicts. (A principle of individual decision and

voluntary agreement does not mean that driving on right or left, using

metric or nonmetric measures, not to say basic economic practices, are

continually in question and one knows not what to expect in a

topsy-turvy world.) What must be premissed is that the people involved

shall by and large he willing — as the way they live and are, rather

than by reflective commitment — to affirm each other’s humanity and

uniqueness and to pursue their differing interests under conditions of

voluntary agreement and responsibility for their actions.

In saying that everyone decides, one does not mean that each can cause

the world to be as (s)he would wish it: for there can be just one actual

world, and if I willed the world effectively then I would will it for,

and in lieu of, others. The others, instead, present me with their

spontaneity, their choosings, which of course foreclose many practical

possibilities for me; in more than compensation for which, one would

hope, my possibilities are enriched by living in a world of persons who

are themselves choosing rather than living out the consequences of

technology, market, and other impersonal forces that have preempted

their freedom and mystified their intelligence.

Nor, in saying that everyone decides, does one mean that everyone

conceivably affected by a particular decision participates in it. No

doubt we have, in our everyday experience, little ground for confidence

that the people on whom we depend, economically and otherwise, will

reliably do their best; and so we put faith in complex systems of

control over others, and of course over ourselves. But the anarchist

thought is that social cooperation can be founded upon the autonomy and

responsibility of individuals and groups in their spheres of activity,

so that the society is the product of the decisions of all, both

individually and jointly by agreement.

But it is obvious that no class of deciders, non-collectivity, even if

realizable in a moderately complex world, cannot well be applied to all

the familiar kinds of social processes, even if the society were

disburdened of many functions, such as the military, that would have no

possible place in an anarchy.

Practically, if we are all by our choosings to participate in making our

world, it would seem necessary that a principle — a practical rather

than an ethical principle — of minimum large-scale change be followed

generally, so that communication and intelligence be most effective and

so that individual choices, and in consequence agreements, contractual

and tacit, be made within a world one somewhat understands. The restless

technology of our centuries flourishes in a world where institutions of

power impose its innovations, provide its workforce, and manipulate its

consumers, and where dominant classes are eager to magnify their power

and wealth through technological supremacy. Anarchy would not provide

these conditions, nor could anarchist decision-making be expected to

cope with continuous major technological revolution. Ceaseless and rapid

demographic expansion that forces constant dissolution and reformation

of life-complexes (neighborhoods, towns, cities, regions) creates a

turmoil that free people cannot deal with any more intelligently than

can the present Institutions. Many technological patterns already

existing may also make demands for decision-making that cannot well be

met except on a basis of collective institutions that create

bureaucratic and other forms of power. That is, anarchist society would

not be readily compatible, if compatible at all, with certain practical

goals or ways of life or with certain societal rhythms.

In the era of unchallenged technological ideology, to which Marxism

contributed its share, such concessions would have been regarded as

determining conclusively the reactionary nature of anarchism. In the era

of ideologies of progress, they would similarly have stamped anarchism

as impossible of realization just because it does not extrapolate what

was then thought of as progress, and as undesirable because unsuited to

spiralling future progress. Today it may be easier to agree that

incompatibility with certain practical goals is not necessarily a defect

or limitation. The kinds of things that cannot be done well in an

anarchist society may be just those that release the blind and

uncontrolled historical processes that determine much of our existence

in a manner that renders our will ineffectual and that even determines

our will.

Perhaps the major thrust of serious social thinking for two centuries

has been toward solution of the problem of determination by history, by

the past, by yesterday: how shall we be free today to solve today’s

problems? Virtually all of this thinking, however, has posed the

question as one of achieving control. By sheer force, and sometimes also

by social sciences, statist societies seek to master these historical

processes, and have given very little evidence of ability to do so.

(Besides which, the values and interests in terms of which the attempt

is made are plainly those of the controlling groups or institutions.)

This ambition of control is a way of human pride.

In anarchist society human beings would, presumably, seek to free

themselves from processes of institutional momentum by consciously

choosing rhythms of change, and technologies, harmonious with viable

rhythms of life-choice, in order to avoid a need, for survival, to

create institutions of power. That we should cease to court disaster,

that we should simplify and make possible the solution of primary

life-problems in the mode of freedom, should not, especially in view of

the number and magnitude of disasters our species produces for itself,

be an unreasonable negative principle, particularly because there appear

to be no reasons why a comparatively stable and comparatively simplified

society need be reduced to spinning-wheel technology or to

changelessness. We might, if such a society were realized, become able

at last to apply an authentic spirit of experimentation to the practical

problems of life-something virtually impossible under present

conditions.

Individual and Society

Anarchist conceptions of individuality and socialization can be made

clearer through brief consideration of the relation between anarchist

theories labelled ‘individualist’ or ‘mutualist’ and those labelled

‘communist’ or ‘syndicalist.’ In these remarks I shall not encompass

certain bourgeois individualisms that call themselves anarchist but have

nothing in common with anarchism as a social movement and historic idea;

for example, so-called anarcho-capitalism.

The main anarchist movements communist or syndicalist, endeavor to

encompass the aspiration to socialism, so that predoctrinal socialism

could be regarded as that aspect of (generic) anarchism that is

specifically concerned with the politics of production, distribution,

and wealth. Individualist and mutualist anarchism, however, usually deny

that community or society have even the secondary substantiality

accorded to them in the communist or syndicalist versions. In the

present world (it is held) society and community are fictions by which

some individuals, cooperating for the purpose, justify their violent

domination and exploitation of others; while what might be mistakenly

regarded as community or society in a condition of true freedom would

actually be no more than the sum of the unhindered actions of

individuals and their associations. For individualists, the mutually

advantageous cooperation of individuals would be achieved through an

agreed-upon medium or principle of exchange and other conventions

intended to guarantee maximally the self-sovereignty of the individual.

But it is the plain intended consequence of the individualists’

proposals that the ends identified here earlier as socialist be achieved

— if one regards collective ownership as but one proposed means for the

abolition of classes and of kinds of property, governmentally

legitimated and protected, that make possible the exploitation of person

by person. The American individualist anarchist Stephen Pearl Andrews

(The Science of Society, 1848), while rejecting the forms in which

democracy and socialism were usually conceived, wrote that the

sovereignty of the individual represented the fulfillment of the spirit

of both, and the later individualist Benjamin Tucker held that

individualism was that species of socialism which chose the way of

liberty against the way of invasive autority, to which latter, he

thought, the anarchist communists, wittingly or unwittingly, succumbed.

And if the principle that every person decides correctly expresses the

communist and syndicalist versions of anarchism, the self-sovereignty

dear to individualists is given full recognition.

There is however plainly a tension between thinking of a society of free

individuals and thinking of a society of free individuals, particularly

if in the first case ‘society’ might better be placed in quotation

marks; and to opt for one or the other is to invite practical and

psychological consequences, perhaps just because one’s choice reflects

one’s sense of what is more painfully lacking in one’s world. In an

ethic of individualism, with its economic corrolaries, Kropotkin saw

something reminiscent of capitalist apologetics for the aggressive and

acquisitive and exploitative individual; in Kropotkin’s visions of

communism the individualists saw the absorption of the individual into a

sovereign whole.

Just this tension between individualism and socialism, experienced by

every anarchist movement, might be seen as rendering anarchism

indecisive and ineffectual. Looked at from the standpoint of ideas, or

of the search for requirements to fulfill a vision of human being, this

same tension can be seen as preserving anarchism against that tendency

to surrender to sovereignty of the whole, at first disguised and then

overt and practically irreversible, that individualists fear in

anarchist communism and which Marxist communism has again and again

instantiated. (If communism and syndicalism are more than standard

procedures, or institutions. in the sense of the preceding section, if

they do not allow for effective choice of alternatives, they are

incompatible with anarchism.) Malatesta’s anarchism, which rejected

hyphenation and sectarianism, sought to preserve this tension within an

unqualified undivided anarchism. Until and unless the polarity of

Individual and society is resolved into a world without social power, it

would seem important that a movement of people and ideas directed to

that end remain acutely conscious of the polarity and by one or another

means preserve that tension; for it is, on the anarchist view, only in

an anarchical society that individuality and sociality can cease to be

in systematic conflict.

The individualism of anarchism is no doubt equivocal, especially because

it must be prepared to let go ultimately what it jealously guards. But

it is certainly not a bourgeois individualism, as Marxism, beginning

with Marx’s attack on Stirner, has represented it. In Stinrer’s

philosophy, not called anarchist by him but generally affirmed by

individualist anarchists, philosophic egoism is absolute and others are

merely Instruments for my satisfactions. But this egoism is precisely

philosophic rather than psychological which means that egoism does not

bar love of others or voluntary cooperative association (free unions).

Although Stirner, a badly misunderstood philosopher if my reading of him

is correct, wrote of the self-interested self and praised it, he wrote

by habit in the first person plural, thus setting the problem of

uniqueness as the problem of all persons and not the problem (as posed

by Nietzsche later) of an elite or future Mite; he called for a general

rebellion of the unique ones, all of us, in our own behalf.

The question of ‘the individual as basic social reality’ runs deeper,

however, than I have so far pursued it here, deeper indeed than I shall

be able to. How this exploration might run, I shall briefly sketch. At

the center of anarchist critique of existing societies is the thesis

that they are characterized by the submergence of individuals in

networks of power-institutions — so that, insofar, the Marxist method of

analyzing past history in institutional terms is basically correct in

intention, if dogmatic and oversimplifying in its standard applications.

Thus the force of the statement that the individual is the ultimate

social reality is normative and programmatic, and the claim is

inseparable from other aspects of a complex ethical ideal of human

being. Here and now, this reality is an incompletely realized potential.

This view of the individual does not entail Stirner’s metaphysical and

epistemological individualism, which can be regarded as an effort to

ground a normative view in philosophy-proper. Yet, as I hope I have

succeeded in at least suggesting, the affirmation of the individual does

not reach its anarchist meaning, and its complete distinctness from

bourgeois and other alienating conceptions of individuality, until it is

thought in the context of the transcendence of power. For knowledge of

that transcendence we have to rely upon our severely incomplete

experience of ourselves and others in situations of love and caring and

community, where the subjectivity of others is significantly present to

us; about these, and about the anarchist ideal, a language of ‘person’

may be less misleading than a language of ‘individual.’ In that context,

by the hypothesis of anarchism, the individuals cease to be in

systematic antagonism, and ‘individual’ and ‘social’ cease to be

descriptive of conflict.

Such a view of the individual is not, so far as I can see, in essential

conflict with a philosophy of social sciences that prefers, for what I

would consider reasons of methodology, to regard relations as prior and

individuals as derivative.

Nature

I have spoken only about anthropos, and a few tentative words, no more,

about Nature and Humanity must be said. In a profound sense, anarchism

is atheistic. (By atheism I mean precisely the negation of theism, not

the negation of religious feeling or of spirituality.) The intense

atheism of traditional anarchism would seem to be more than terrestrial

in its ardor — no mere anticlericalism — and more also than negational

of God as legitimator of governmental and clerical authority.

Anarchist thought gains unity if its atheism is taken as assertion that

human being must establish its freedom within Nature. (By Nature I do

not mean a material universe merely. Nature I understand as coextensive

with what is.) Anarchism then would be expressive of universal rejection

of power, in the symbol, for the case of the institutional Christian

religions, of the Divine Monarch, the universal despot who, on grounds

of transcendental ideology, i.e., theology, claims Man’s obedience and

His priority in being. Correlatively, anarchists have generally set

great store, even excessive store, by science, philosophy, and reason,

thereby expressing faith, I believe, that these means will enable us to

achieve such understanding of Nature as will establish our freedom

within it.

Unlike Marxist socialism, however, unlike Marx, young Marx included,

anarchism is rarely anthropocentrically humanistic in the sense of a

vision of Nature as enemy, menace, object of conquest and control by

technology, arena for human dominance — the inverse of theistic

subjugation. I understand anarchism as affirming humankind and opposing

our subordination or subjugation to either divinities or to natural laws

that we do not understand and make our own — as seeking our freedom but

not our dominance or our independence of Nature.

To be careful I should not say that anarchists have always been clear

about these matters. The Christian context of the Western world to which

anarchism has mainly been limited has not made such clarity easy. I mean

to suggest that anarchism readily extrapolates, and that its spirit

calls for extrapolation, to a certain vision of Nature analogous to its

vision of society; where individual persons, human societies, and the

human species, live in relationship with other individual beings and

species, affirming our being our creative uniqueness, and our freedom,

but not seeking a supremacy that would signify an alienation of

humankind in antagonism to what we cannot control or understand. Thus

the harmony of society and person can be transposed to the larger case,

and anarchism gains force and scope and completion insofar as it stands

for such harmony of persons and world.

Whether only contingently, because anarchism took root mainly outside

Germanic Europe, or for more essential reasons, anarchism does not much

reflect that Feuerbachian humanism, according to which the God-idea is

merely a projection of human ideals, that Marx adopted and by which he

disposed easily of the religious question, with the consequence, one

might speculate, that Nature lost its sacredness, without which it is

difficult if not impossible that human beings be sacred to themselves.

For anarchism, perhaps more Catholic than Protestant in its religious

background and sources, God has had a more serious reality than for Marx

— reality as image of power, as pretended reality of power. One may not

be mistaken — but one may be — in thinking that the angry rebellion of

anarchist against the God of the Christian churches has represented a

profound and thwarted spirituality.

In contemporary anarchist literature, the theme of atheism is less

conspicuous, less urgent — perhaps because our cosmic freedom has been

gained, but in the mode of independence and dominance, or in the mode of

illusion of freedom, and our problem is rather one of rediscovering our

being in Nature, a different religious problem than that of the

God-monarch.

Anarchism as Social Philosophy

The chief thing that I have wanted to show is that anarchism represents

a fundamental ideal of human existence: that it represents something

other than mere absence of government, something other than the freedom

to do anything one wants, something different than a freedom limited by

what will harm others. It represents instead the aim of social union, on

a ground of unique individuality, where no class or caste divisions

exist between people and where integral individuality and integral

society, non-antithetical, have become two aspects of the same life. The

deepest meaning of this anarchist freedom, if I see rightly the

implications of what I have written, is that certain significant

barriers to the realization of potentialities of human being will have

been broken. Integral individuality and integral society are ancient as

well as modern values, and every system of ethics and social philosophy

could be said to have endeavored to accommodate them to each other. I

suggested that anarchism is a social idea of importance, and not merely

a peculiar kind of member in the series tyranny, monarchy, oligarchy,

democracy... anarchy, because it claims to identify, in power, the

missing clue. It presents both a conception of general and ultimate

social/personal harmony, which may well turn out to be an ideal beyond

reach, and a conception of social/personal harmony in any circumscribed

realm, any relatively closed human system, as small as the sphere of

one’s immediate life-circle, where the negation of Ideologically

justified, socially divisive patterns of domination are (by hypothesis)

a necessary condition for social/personal harmony. As a practical goal,

the free society can hardly recommend itself for its probability,

whatever exactly probability means in such matters; but the Idea

reflects itself, sometimes as a secular philosophy of love, into the

daily life of persons who derive from it their values.

If we are to discuss anarchism as a social philosophy, we will want it

to be more than a set of feelings at the core of an Idea, and something

more than an abstract resolution of power-and-powerlessness. During the

course of this article I have set down a number of propositions, beyond

the initial propositions of the first sections, that I would like to

recapitulate here:

metaphysical) reality;

negation of the fundamental human reality;

affirms the free development of individuality as the condition of

realizing our sense of humanity;

anarchy;

power/powerlessness that can be described as integral freedom;

person decides;

always realizable potentiality;

definition, institutional being, institutional will, for oneself;

from the determinism of history;

ground of union in freedom;

the lives of each and all;

foundation of free society;

continuously.

About these propositions I wish to claim that they indicate a

nonsimplistic view of society and human being that provides a mode of

social analysis, an image of the ethical potentiality of man, and a

proposal of method for realizing that potentiality.

If one is to consider anarchism as a philosophy, one will of course ask

about the nature of metaphysical and epistemological commitments and

their foundation. This question threatens to reintroduce the

fragmentation into schools that I have sought to overcome, for on these

questions anarchist differ sharply and I have chosen to view anarchism

in a way that avoids such commitments. I should like now, however, to

give a positive sense to this avoidance, and I offer the following

thoughts, intended to be no more than suggestive; their elaboration will

have to await another occasion.

We are a puzzle to ourselves, I believe, because we do not fully

experience our own humanity, and this in turn is because we cannot fully

experience the humanity of others so long as we exist in the many

interlocking relations of masterhood and servitude. We yield to those

structures of power in order to live in a human world that preexists

each of us and demands that we discipline ourselves to cultures

organized around Insignia, languages, persons, institutions,

mythologies, and philosophies of power. We move dialectically to a plane

of consciousness of our common humanity, instantiated uniquely in each

person, as we move dialectically to a plane of social existence in which

we wield no power over others and do not allow ourselves to be

determined in our being by the power that they wield. Only then do we

realize the meaning of subjectivity in another or, authentically, in

ourselves. By that move, we bring love to reality, for such recognition

of subjectivity is what I understand by love.

Put otherwise: Certain truths must be brought to be, must be made

living, before their meaning can be apprehended more than negatively.

(Thus anarchism, in this respect like Marxism, transposes the

philosophical questions into questions of actualization and

realization.) What I see in anarchism is the indication that human being

will become adequately self-conscious, and therefore free toward the

future, and dichotomies of thought and action will dissolve, only when

human beings free themselves from one another and, in certain

significant senses, from themselves.

Thus anarchism can be seen as proceeding from the hypothesis that there

is a negative task to be accomplished before we can genuinely experience

ourselves as human beings and grasp our relationships to one another.

Throughout, therefore, anarchism is, ideationally, essentially negative.

Whereas with respect to particular social problems this would be a gross

defect, anarchism is concerned with a far more fundamental kind of

question, and from its vision of the potentialities residing in our

actual human situation its thoroughgoing negativity would seem to follow

and to be the foundation of creation.