đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş anarchy101-org-anarchy-101.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:23:15. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anarchy 101 Author: dot matrix Date: 2012 Language: en Topics: introductory, FAQ, Little Black Cart Source: Retrieved 12/11/2021 from archive dot org Notes: edited by Dot Matrix with help from participants at anarchy101.org | *Anarchy 101* was originally published by Little Black Cart and can be found in book form https://littleblackcart.com/index.php?dispatch=products.view&product_id=101.
Thanks to my partners, and to anok, autumn leaf cascade, enkidu,
ingrate, rice boy, and taigarun, all long-term and thoughtful
contributors to anarchy101.org. Thanks also to the others on that site
(including many anonymous questionners). I truly appreciate getting to
have provocative conversations about things I care about with people who
I donât even know.
And thanks to Jessica, the excellent beginner.
I hope I have done justice to us all.
AnarchicSaint: ast
Anok: ank
Apio: api
Asker: asr
Aragorn: a!
Aragorn23: a23
Autumn Leaf Cascade: alc
Blacque: blq
Dot: dot
Enkidu: enk
Frenzy: frz
Funkyanarchy: fnk
Iconoclast: ict
Ingrate: ing
Inpraiseofchaos: ipc
KatherineD: kd
Lawrence: law
Madlib: mdb
MrThisBody: mtb
MattThePrick: mtp
MollytheAnarchist: mta
Nothing Resonates: nnn
Rice Boy: rby
Sabotage: sab
Squee: squ
Taigarun: tgn
Vindico Vaco: vvo
Anarchy is many things to different people: a vision, a plan, a
conversation, a process. It is my view (consistent with a whole raft of
contemporary anarchists, from Alfredo M. Bonanno to Voltairine de
Cleyre* and beyond) that anarchy is best understood, and is most
helpful, as a tension, a question, a rejection. This text operates from
that premise.
This book is composed of questions, answers, and comments (sometimes
lightly edited) taken from a website called anarchy101.org, in which
various anarchists answer questions posed by themselves and others. This
variety of voices (the answers and comments disagree with each other as
often as agree) is integral to any anarchist project that I want to be a
part of. There are many more questions there than could reasonably fit
into a book, so go, read, ask, and argue.
We welcome your engagement with these ideas, and look forward to hearing
your voice in the future.
answers in a book?
I think that much of what has been explored on this website would be a
welcome counter-perspective to the similar publication of the Anarchist
FAQ, which has never addressed perspectives beyond those of the
author(s) in a really honest and balanced way. There have been some very
thoughtful things posted here, and it would be cool to see them put into
some sort of printed collection, which, in my opinion, is easier to
digest for beginners, as it is presented in a more linear fashion.
One of the particular strengths of using this sort of site as a jumping
off place is that many different perspectives might be represented.
Though this leads me to wonder who determines which answers are deemed
suitable for print, and what the process or criteria for that would be.
Other issues I could see coming up would be particular posters not
wanting their answers included in book form, or not wanting to have them
be attributed to them in print, though it doesnât make much sense to be
concerned about that if youâve created a profile for this site, which is
far easier to come across at random than a book. Maybe a few of the
regular posters have expressed thoughts that might lead them to wanting
to defend their intellectual property, but fuck that.
Ingrate is right that it might be useful to have a book that addresses
perspectives that AFAQ does not, and I think that there have been some
pretty good/interesting questions and answers on this site.
My favorite aspect of this site is that there are usually several
answers to each question and this, I think, is part of what makes it
superior to AFAQ. I suppose that could be replicated in a book but on
the face of it it seems like something the internet is pretty well
suited for: I read the answers really differently than I would if they
were in a book simply because of my awareness that anyone can contest
everything thatâs being said, and whatever we say will have just as much
weight as the original claims. Even if you read a book really critically
and take notes and write response papers and stuff, itâs not the same
thing.
Another thing is that I donât write that carefully here, and I think
that is true for most people. I wouldnât really feel comfortable seeing
anything Iâve written here in a book because I donât feel the prose is
very good. One way around this might be to steal ideas but not use
anyoneâs exact phrasings?
I think a book of info from here using the format of Anarchy Works
(based on q&a under section headers such as âdecisionsâ or âeconomyâ)
could do well with a good editor who attempted to include diverse
perspectives, but it would make a really unorthodox and perhaps
incoherent book. It would have an advantage in diversity and a
disadvantage in the consistency. Iâm fine with that though.
Most of my posts are meant as starting places for a larger collection of
more completed writings but feel free to use whatever you want.
(including some names that you can research if so inclined)
Anarchism was initially coined as a term by Proudhon. It became more
defined and serious after Bakunin left the First International Working
Menâs Association because of disagreements on (among other things)
whether the dictatorship of the proletariat (a worker-controlled state)
would wither away (Marxâs claim), or be just another tactic for people
to maintain a hierarchy.
Classical anarchistsâMikael Bakunin, Pyotr Kropotkin, Emma Goldman,
Alexander Berkman, Voltairine de Cleyre, etcâtended to be pro-science
(since they were rebelling against domination by the christian church).
They also tended to be pro-communism (communism was the goal of
revolution, and would be a utopic time when workers would have power and
determine their own production, when there would be no bosses, when
people would be taken care of regardless of how much money they had).
The difference between anarchists and communists of this era was
primarily that a) anarchists did not believe that economics was the only
way that people were influenced (anarchists have almost always looked at
psychology, culture, education, etc, as ways that we are socialized and
coercedânot just work), b) that anarchists did not believe in creating a
state to get rid of states. (The anarchist perspective on
states-in-formation has been validated by the history of communists
killing former anarchist allies, including in Kronstadt and in the
Spanish Civil War.)
Contemporary with Marx and Bakunin there was also Max Stirner, who never
called himself an anarchist but who has been claimed by an anarchist
tendency because his polemic (badly translated into English as The Ego
and Its Own) rejects the idea that any of us should sacrifice ourselves
to anything. He held that causes (like Liberty, Freedom, even Anarchy)
are âspooksâ (ie abstractions that only serve to alienate us from our
own lives and selves). Some of the most inspirational anarchists were
heavily influenced by egoism, including Renzo Novatore and Alfredo
Bonanno. Anarchists influenced by Nietzsche and/or Stirner (egoists,
post-left anarchists, and post-anarchists are the three main tendencies
so influenced) reject the idea that workers are the group that will
create a revolution, that work (as it is currently understood, ie as
tasks that you get paid for, but with no immediate benefit for your life
or your friendsâ lives) would even continue to exist in the world we
want, or that revolution as a discrete event is something that we can,
or want to, aim for.
More recently, the Situationists, a radical group based in the art scene
in the 60s, particularly in Paris, created a new wave of more critical,
contemporary anarchist thinking; a wave that is continued today in
groups like Tiqqun in France and by unnamed window-smashers and
newspaper-box placement engineers everywhere.
There is no single foundational voice for anarchist thought (and some of
the most influential thinkers said some apparently conflicting things,
like Bakunin), so there is a lot of flexibility left for people to find
and focus on the person, or the ideas, that most appeal to them. This is
aided by the ethic that anarchists promote people finding their own
answers, so that decentralization and a million different trajectories
are both desirable and inevitable.
This leads to people calling themselves anarchists who disagree
intensely (and sometimes widely) with each other, and to an inherent
weakness of the label âanarchistâ (since calling oneâs self that doesnât
mean that anyone can make assumptions about what one thinks); this makes
the label not as pernicious as other labels (which in general act to
hide differences as much or more than to reveal similarities).
What do they disagree with each other about?
What do they agree on?
Hereâs how I break down what I consider the main trends in an Intro to
Anarchism talk I do.
Anarchist Communism
Anarchist communism proposes that the freest form of social organisation
would be a society composed of self-managing communes with collective
use of the means of production, organised democratically and using
consenus decision-making, and related to other communes through
federation. In anarchist communism there would be no money but everyone
would have free access to the resources and surplus of the commune.
Anarchist communism is thus said to operate on a gift economy.
Collectivism
Collectivist anarchism is similar to anarchist communism, except for the
fact that in collectivism workers would be compensated for their work on
the basis of the amount of time they contributed to production, rather
than goods being distributed âaccording to needâ as in
anarcho-communism. Some collectivist anarchists do not oppose the use of
currency. Some support workers being paid based on the amount of time
they contributed to production. These salaries would be used to purchase
commodities in a communal market.
Anarcho-syndicalism
Syndicalism focuses on radical trade unions as a potential force for
revolutionary social change, seeking to replace capitalism and the state
with a new society that is democratically self-managed by the workers.
Important principles include workersâ solidarity, direct action (such as
general strikes and workplace recuperations) and workersâ
self-management. Syndicalism is sometimes seen as simply a specific
strategic focus within communist or collectivist anarchism as opposed to
a distinct type of anarchism in itself.
Insurrectionary Anarchism
On the other hand, Insurrectionary Anarchism opposes formal
organizations such as labor unions and federations that are based on a
political programme and periodic congresses. Instead, insurrectionary
anarchists support informal organization and small affinity group-based
organization. Insurrectionary anarchists put value in attack, permanent
class conflict, and a refusal to negotiate or compromise with class
enemies.
Contemporary insurrectionary anarchism most often inherits the views and
tactics of anti-organizationalist anarcho-communism.
Anarcha-feminism
Anarcha-feminism is a form of anarchism that synthesizes radical
feminism and anarchism and views patriarchy (male domination over women)
as one of the (or the) primary dominations. Anarcha-feminism was
inspired in the late 19^(th) century by the writings of early feminist
anarchists such as Lucy Parsons, Emma Goldman and Voltairine de Cleyre.
Anarcha-feminists, like other radical feminists, criticize and advocate
the abolition of traditional conceptions of family, education and gender
roles and believe that the feminist struggle against sexism and
patriarchy is an essential component of the anarchist struggle. Susan
Brown put it: âas anarchism is a political philosophy that opposes all
relationships of power, it is inherently feministâ.
Green Anarchism
Green anarchism (or eco-anarchism) is a school of thought within
anarchism that puts an emphasis on environmental issues. Green
anarchists often criticize the main currents of anarchism for their
focus and debates about politics and economics instead of a focus on
ecosystems.
Anarcho-primitivism
Anarcho-primitivism is an anarchist critique of the origins and progress
of civilization. According to anarcho-primitivism, the shift from
hunter-gatherer to agricultural subsistence gave rise to social
stratification, coercion, and alienation. Anarcho-primitivists advocate
a return to non-civilized ways of life through deindustrialisation,
abolition of the division of labour or specialization, and abandonment
of large-scale organization technologies. There are other non-anarchist
forms of primitivism, and not all primitivists point to the same
phenomenon as the source of modern, civilized problems.
Primitivism is seem as extreme by some anarchists, but it does provide a
useful counterbalance to the cheerful Industrial Revolution optimism
expressed by the late 19^(th) and early 20^(th) Century anarchists like
Peter Kropotkin that technology and technological progress are
inherently liberatory and should be pursued by anarchists in a
post-revolutionary society.
Synthesism/Anarchism without Adjectives/Type 3 Anarchism
Anarchism without adjectives is an attitude that tolerates the
coexistence of different anarchist schools. It emphasizes harmony
between various anarchist factions and attempts to unite them around
their shared anti-authoritarian beliefs. Rudolf Rocker said that the
different types of anarchism presented âonly different methods of
economy, the practical possibilities of which have yet to be tested, and
that the first objective is to secure the personal and social freedom of
men no matter upon which economics basis this is to be accomplished.â
It is important to note that a large number of self-defined anarchists
might use more than one of these labels to describe themselves depending
on what they were doing or what kinds of group structures they find
themselves operating in: some anarchists prefer durable, structured
groups where members commit to certain ideological and tactical
principles; others prefer more flexible, small-scale affinity groups
that come and go as needed. Often, members of these latter groups
express concerns about how formal organisation can tend towards
bureaucracy and the perpetuation of the life of the group for its own
sake. There are a number of other types of so-called anarchism that are
problematic. Perhaps the worst of these is anarcho-capitalismâan
oxy-moronic view stemming from the belief expressed by some, that
personal freedom entails being free to compete in a capitalist-type
market.
dot
and individualist anarchism: the idea that the individual is the real
base for all decisions (although society tries to hide that fact), and
that society (as understood through law, education, morality, religion,
ideology, etc) has either little use or no use (except as a hindrance to
the desires of individuals). Individualists de-emphasize the importance
of revolution (as a single event that radically changes everything for
the better), since revolutions tend to just install new leaders, and
recommend slow, experientially based change instead. This covers wide
territory, and many individualists disagree with each other.
Also, post-left anarchy and post-anarchy have real similarities, since
both are updating classical anarchist thinking using the work of
philosophers like Stirner, Nietzsche, the Frankfurt School, etc.
I have broken this down by different ideas on this question among
anarchists, since they are many.
society is separated (even if they argue that class composition has
shifted since then) as being based on relations to the means of
production; they accept the argument for the proletariat as
revolutionary subject, and so on. This seems to be the predominant
definition, but only when one looks at the most official anarchists (who
are actually a minority of anarchists).
they also accept the Marxist definition. This definition of class is the
stance of most of the government (its institutions, economists, the
educational system, etc). It is the idea of stratification on the basis
of relative income, completely ignoring the relations to means of
production (which according to Marxists are the basis for the common
class interests of people who earn vastly different incomes, and
antagonisms between individuals who earn relatively similar incomes).
This idea of class is problematic to most Marxists and many anarchists
because it turns the proletariat against itself and produces a false
understanding of the way capitalism functions. But for better or worse
many anarchists are very influenced by this definition of class.
class (the developers of these being mostly more Marxist than
anarchist):Jacques Camatte, coming from a Marxist background, argues
that the class distinction is diffused in late capitalism through the
total domestication of humans and the establishment of a capitalist
human community. This does not mean there are not classes, but their
conflict is pacified and their relations are shifted. The relevant
conflict (if any) comes to be between humans and capital or individuals
and their own domestication, rather than between proletariat and
bourgeoisie.The Invisible Committee has said something similar to
Camatte but different. One way they put it is the conflict is now
between those who refuse work and those who want to work.The proletariat
defined as the dispossessed. This is the original definition of the term
and it is there in Marx but thereâs a shift in significance from the
industrial proletariat (which in Marxâs context was the position most
former peasants dispossessed of their land found themselves in) to more
accurately reflect the context in âpost-industrialâ societies where
surplus populations have become much larger since technological progress
gradually displaces the need for human labor.
centrality of its importance.
definitely true.
In sum, anarchists are too diverse in economic thought to be pigeonholed
in this, and for the most part have not developed economic theory
independent of Marxism, even if they feel free (a very common tendency
for anarchists) to adapt, reject, intersect, play with, or diminish the
importance of what theyâve inherited from the old man. Could any
anarchist definition of class be developed that escapes entirely from
Marxism (especially as this, whatever faults it may have, is based on
real situations that persist today even if in different forms)? I doubt
itâexcept, of course, in the very course of the abolition of the class
society that Marx set himself to describing. To actually realize this
abolition in practice so that new relations can flourish is, of course,
a worthwhile task which generations of anarchists have striven forâmuch
more so, I would argue, than Marxists as a whole.
anarchy?
Generally things arenât equal but if they were... Doesnât violence by
one person against an equal imply power-over them and thus a basic kind
of hierarchical relationship?
Violence is a pretty loaded word. The violence of me punching you in the
nose is different from the violence of dropping a bomb on a village or
starving an entire category of humans. One of those violences is not
antithetical to anarchy. The other clearly is. The family of ideas and
activities implied by the term âviolenceâ makes it unusable during most
conversations that anarchists would want to have about a better world,
or about anarchist ideas.
Regarding the violence of punching each other in the nose, the instinct
to do so is a pretty strong one. Perhaps even a fundamental one. If (or
since) that is the case then violence is part of being a person. The
desire for violence, the belief that âsomethingâ is solved with
interpersonal violence, is probably part of the human project. If
violence is human AND the desire to live without coercion and âpower
overâ is human then the only thing that is antithetical to humans is
humans. Which is probably a fair assessment of our current condition.
One last note. boloâbolo has a nice section about conflict in a
different world that may be worth quoting:
yaka: Every ibu (individual) can challenge any other ibu or a larger
community to a duel, according to those rules.
It may be possible to agree to terms by which conflict is human scale
and, perhaps, includes consensual violence. Scale is a huge factor in
these questions.
Violence is physical (sometimes emotional) pain inflicted on a living
being (or beings).
Property destruction is usually not considered violence.
Some people see a grey area when property destruction is committed
against people who are poor (more poor than usual?), As this could be
considered bad for peopleâs health (poverty is the biggest health risk,
as we all know).
This definition (violence is only against living beings) is ok as far as
it goes, but to me it seems to have humanist roots, which i disagree
with. But perhaps that is the beginning of another question.
Some anarchists define what anarchists (and other militants) do as self
defense, vs the violence of our daily lives inflicted by the state and
capitalism.
It occurred to me that scientists donât fit well into the proletarian or
bourgeoisie classesâbecause they donât own the means of production.
Furthermore scientists donât really produce anything except information,
so are they part of the service sector? I suppose what I am asking is:
since scientists take highly technical equipment and turn it into data
and theories, how do you envision scientists and scientific communities
working in an anarchist society.
If I understand the main thrust of your question, you want to know how
anarchist class analysis categorizes scientists. There isnât a single
answer. Many anarchists would take a marxian class analysis, in which
scientists would probably be considered petit-bourgeois. However,
anarchists are often critical of many aspects of marxist theory,
including its class analysis. Your example of scientists is one example
that in many cases there are economic classes that exist today that do
not easily fit into the bourgeois-proletariat model.
Instead of relying on an understanding of class that is a century and a
half-old, many anarchists analyze different economic classes in terms of
how they help to reproduce the state and capital. Scientific pursuits
are usually funded by the institutions we hate such as militaries or
pharmaceutical companies, and as such serve the interests of state and
capital. Some anarchists, especially animal liberationists, directly
intervene against scientific activity.
I will concede that it is possible that activities we call science could
exist in hypothetical anarchist societies. Some anarchists have
conjectured what science might be like in an anarchist society. One
conception is that scientists would cease to exist as a distinct class
as scientific knowledge and equipment become the domain of all people.
Kropotkin was a biologist, and a lot of contemporary anarchist ideas
about science originate with him. However, contemporary anarchists are
often far more critical of science than our 19^(th) century forbears. I
fall into this camp. I hope that contemporary anarchists who are
âpro-scienceâ at least take these critical perspectives into account.
Some of the answers to the question on scientists is also appropriate
here.
Some anarchists believe that technology is theoretically neutral, and
that appropriate societies will develop appropriate technology. this
definition of technology is basically no different from that for tools
(things that people use to solve problems).
Other people, including many green anarchists (and all primitivists) see
technology as one of the ways of formulating the problems that
technology is then supposed to solve... ie there is a deeper
philosophical challenge to the culture, a reciprocity between things and
processes and people...
(That said, i am obviously biased towards the latter position. so
perhaps someone who is not will also have a go at answering this.)
Do rights always and everywhere flow from the state? Donât some rights
(ideally) protect one from the state? Human rights as opposed to legal
rights say? Isnât it OK to have some basic standards for our treatment
of one another and canât that be totally independent of the concept of
the state? And, finally, canât new rights take political/social space
away from the state and capital? For example wouldnât the concept of
housing as a basic human right take some space away from the idea that
property rights should be primary and form the foundation of the social
order?
Can the concept of desire replace the concept of rights? What are the
implications of this? If it doesnât replace this concept what are some
of the consequences of eliminating a discourse of rights? How does one
talk about the importance of peopleâs access to basic resources or the
importance of eliminating torture (for example) outside of this
discourse.
Rights always come from the state. The idea that rights should be
written into law was developed when people were so pissed about getting
stepped on and ruled over by sovereign powers that the governments had
to do something. So they made a tremendous shift into a system of
politics called liberalism (not the same as liberalism as in liberal vs.
conservative or liberal vs. maoist) in which the law recognizes the
rights of citizens. These laws serve to not only convince citizens that
they arenât going to be stepped on as hard but also to ensure that
people will appeal for recognition of their rights to the state or for a
change in the rights written in law, rather than revolt when they have
grievances. It is a remarkably successful system, in which revolt now
tends to happen only when the system is clearly fucking people over and
clearly not going to change itself. Even then, revolt can be settled by
implementing some larger systematic change or having a revolutionary
government take over.
Anarchists do not want protection from the state. Or, to put it another
way, a truly anarchist life guarantees that one will not be promised
protection by the state, and instead punished by it. The state offers
protection to (certain normal, decent, law-abiding, good, productive,
etc) citizens in exchange for their preservation, reproduction, and
reformation of the status quo.
An alternative understanding would be that rights are first and foremost
inherent to our being human, and only secondly is this ârealâ human
essence recognized by the state. I would reject this because no one can
point to the existence of these essential rights except in the writings
of law (whether international or national). There isnât an inherent
human essence, or if there is it would be a highly paradoxical,
enigmatic âthingâ. To appeal (to the state) for the establishment of
greater rights does not âtake away spaceâ from the state. It would seem
that only revolt can actually wrench spaces from state control, but even
then, state-forms manage to creep in through the back door (the
implementation of self-management among the insurgents).
As for alternative discourse, I donât see the need for one. For anyone
to actually achieve the essence of what you are talking aboutâto live
free of the domination of state and capital in their livesâthey would
have to live fighting against domination and not appeal to it to
recognize the importance of their needs or how cruel torture is. In
other words, they would have to become a non-subject. And only subjects
can have rights.
Is there a difference? If so, whatâs the difference? Can someone adhere
to anarchy but not anarchism, and vice versa?
Very simply, âanarchyâ is descriptive of a human being, or a group of
humans, who live without hierarchy (social control & power). A way of
life most conducive to choices on behalf of life itself. Beyond that, I
donât believe it could really be said to have any crystalline character
to what it is or could be.
Anarchism is a distinct array of political ideas, ideologies,
literature, and just generally intellectual or practical pursuits
composed by a diverse milieu, as well as tradition, of people who oppose
hierarchy on principle and have largely given themselves the task of
expounding, illustrating, as well as demonstrating the values (namely
anarchy) that result from those principles. Anarchism exists in a world
where it is truly unwelcome and this divorces anarchism from even the
horizon of anything like a way of life it envisions itself as belonging
to. And so anarchism is also definitely a conceit which often betrays
itself as such.
In the interest of relating the siteâs content back to itself Iâll refer
to another answer given to a similar question:
âAnarchism is a political philosophy that aspires to a world without the
State and without exchange relations [relations dominated by the market
and economic value]. It is both the negative idea that there is a
laundry list of ideas, practices, and values in our current society to
be against and the positive idea that what is most âusâ about us (as
living creatures) should be free to pursue its own ends without coercion
or constraint.
Anarchism is also a variable. It means many different things to
different people. This open nature serves as a counter-point to ideas
that are connected to specific thinkers or traditions in that, while
there is a tradition, and there are important thinkers, there is also a
lot of room for you to write your own page to the story. To apply the
variable to your own life.
Anarchism is also a constraint. For many, if not most, anarchists there
is a central concept that the ends do â not â justify the means, or put
more gently, that an anarchist practice must embed the values and ideas
of a future anarchist society. This means that anarchists are often
broken into parts. One part acts against the constraints of this world.
The other part constrains themselves by an ethical ruler the calibration
of which is in a foreign unit.â
âanarchyâ?
The problem is that technically they are correct; Somalia has been
without a functioning government and state for over a decade.
One response to that observation is that there are no anarchists in
Somalia (at least none that weâve heard about), and that the state there
was deliberately destroyed not by anarchists, but by the US military,
and the US military is neither a humanitarian nor a progressive outfit.
Anarchists and other anti-state radicals would have destroyed the Somali
state in order to liberate the Somalis from government, all the while
encouraging Somalis to remember how to go about organizing themselves to
fulfill their own needs outside the realm of capitalism and statecraft.
The destruction of government in a situation where class domination
still exists means the nakedly oppressive rule of the most powerful
class without any pretense to legitimate authority (like parliamentary
democracy or something similarly goofy): in other words âwarlordsâ and
âpirates.â The destruction of governments and states needs to include
the destruction of all institutionalized hierarchies (class-based,
gender-based, ethnicity-based, etc)âotherwise all you get is the brutal
chaos seen in Somalia, parts of Haiti, parts of Afghanistan...
government?
Governments are all about representationâthey claim to work in the name
of, and to the benefit of, the people they govern. Aside from the
majority of the time when that is a lie (ie when the government is
motivated by corruption, incompetence, conflicting agendas, etc), even
in the best case scenarios, what representation does is to deny and
prohibit peopleâs agency, our willingness and capacity to act for
ourselves, based on our own understanding of what is the right thing to
do, and when, and to or with whom, etc.
The situation in Louisiana with Hurricane Katrina is a classic case in
point. Police and military did not act in the interest of the hurricane
survivors, and tried to stop people from helping each other.
Because, being based an an accumulation of capital (ie wealth) into the
hands of a few people at the expense of the rest, it requires the
accumulation of power into the hands of a few people operating through a
system of institutions of domination in order to protect the
accumulation of wealth. This system of institutions of domination is
what constitutes the state, and without it, the accumulation of capital
necessary to capitalism would be implausible, if not impossible, simply
because people wouldnât be that likely to put up with it.
abolish it with?
One simple answer: private property cannot be maintained without
authority to maintain it, because people would immediately appropriate
what they need, and the force of law, police, etc would not be there to
stop them. It is through these forms of state power that owners are
currently able to combat activities such as theft,
squatting/trespassing, etc, thereby keeping these activities relatively
in check, ie maintaining their property.
Of course there are privately-owned security forces, police, armies,
prisons, etc. âAnarchoâ-capitalists feel entitled to call themselves
such because they donât consider these to be forms of government. (They
also have a funny definition of capitalism.) To my mind these examples
just demonstrate a different form of governmental power in which it is
more transparent that the rich have hired mercenaries (a condition
somewhat obscured by the liberal form of government).
Private property itself functions as a form of authority in that there
is an authority held over individuals by the sanctity of property. In
this approach, one might view the forms taken by society to enforce
property as a social/material actuation of this ideological system. This
helps explain the existence of the moral systems in which people believe
it is wrong to infringe on property rights and so onâwhat we experience
is not simply a world full of private property that we cannot access
because it is protected by armed guards (as some anarchists portray it).
This is true, but it is also a world in which most people truly believe
in the existing system and in a whole lot of unquestioned abstractions
which they hold to be irreproachable, and without these beliefs the
armed guards would be nothing.
As for how private property can be abolished: The 1^(st) paragraph might
make it seems as if the abolition of the state would necessarily lead to
the abolition of private property through appropriation. However, just
as anarchists reject the idea of using authoritarian measures to abolish
private property, we also reject the idea that what we want is simply a
matter of abolishing the government, that âeverything elseâ will follow
from there. Anarchists are, after all, opposed to all forms of
authority, and generally do not believe in confronting them in
separation from one another. Most anarchists would probably agree that
private property can be abolished through the insurrection of
self-actualized individuals and collectivities that organize without
authority between each other nor between themselves and any higher
powers (state, god, property, etc) to free their lives from the systems
that have dominated them. This effort of making our lives our own (of
appropriating them) is from a certain viewpoint the abolition of private
property, although it may be much more as well. It may involve a lot of
willpower, but by no means requires authorityâin fact, Iâd argue that
authority as I define it can only be a fetter to this effort.
I have seen anarchists talk about Nietzsche, and there seems to be a new
fad of anarcho-nihlism. Yet Nietzsche himself spoke quite negatively
about anarchists, and many of his ideas seem quite counter to anarchism
(as practiced in the US). So what does Nietzscheâs nihilism have in
common with anarchism, and what does he have to offer anarchist
practice?
First: Nietzsche and nihilism... Nietzscheâs positions on nihilism were
complex, and it could be argued that he was a nihilist, or at least
aimed to be one.
Nietzsche saw nihilism as the most extreme form of pessimism, something
that comes from weariness and an alienation from values. When one can
recognize the existing value systems as meaningless and empty, and not
replace it with anything, they become nihilistic. He saw nihilism as
both positive and negative, as â...one of the greatest crises, a moment
of the deepest self-reflection of humanity. Whether man recovers from
it, whether he becomes master of this crisis, is a question of his
strength!â
I think that it is helpful to first point out the two different types of
nihilism you find in his works, passive nihilism and active nihilism.
The passive nihilist is the one who could not recover from this crisis.
It is a state in which a person, having recognized that all external
values are empty, with no true authority, begins to find their own
internal values meaningless, giving up their own authority. With all
sense of authority gone one gives in to the spirit of hopelessness and
fatalism, ridding themselves of all responsibility. They withdraw from
the world, give up.
But it is possible (Nietzsche argues that it is entirely desirable) that
this recognition of external value systems as meaningless can give way
to a sense of rebelliousness and strength. This active nihilist seeks to
destroy any and all remaining traces of an empty value system. The
strength of oneâs will is tested by whether or not it can recognize all
value systems as empty and meaningless, yet admit that these lies arise
out of the ego and serve a purpose; whether one can recognize that value
is necessary for life while denying the existence of any universal
truth.
Nietzsche saw this nihilism as a means to achieving an end, not an end
in and of itself. It is simply one step in the revaluation of values.
Nihilism is necessary to destroy what exists now in order to create a
place in which the ego/the will can truly take power and assert itself
fully.
As anarchists we are fighting to rid ourselves of the existing value
systems (the capitalist values of âmoney above allâ, the Christian
values of âself-sacrifice, and god above allâ, etc), and many of us
already feel that alienation from these values. What we can take from
his active nihilism is the deconstructive nature that gives way to
construction, a destruction that strengthens and empowers. The
realization that we need not only destroy what exists, but transcend it.
Nietzsche calls anarchists (and Christians) out on their apparent
inability to do this: âThere is a perfect likeness between Christian and
anarchist: their object, their instinct, points only toward
destruction.... both are decadents; both are incapable of any act that
is not disintegrating, poisonous, degenerating, blood sucking; both have
an instinct of mortal hatred of everything that stands up, and is great,
and has durability, and promises life a future.â However, I donât think
that this is permanent.
Second: What anarchists can learn from Nietzscheâs rejection of slave
morality.
Anarchists are some of the strongest adherents to the slave morality;
Nietzsche even said so outright. Our whole outlook on life, the way in
which we function within this world is based upon reaction, resentment.
We view people/events/etc through the eye of âgood vs evilâ. We look for
that which is âevilâ (capitalism, police, etc) and define anything that
isnât that as âgoodâ. We do not spend much time focusing on that which
is âgoodâ, but are obsessed with the âevilâ, we revolve our
ideals/projects/lives around it. How is the US anarchist idea of âevilâ
much different than Christian sin or devil; how different is the
anarchistsâ end of capitalism from the Christian apocalypse, anarchist
ideals from heaven? We have become the perfect (pitiful) disciples of
our own slave morality.
And while Nietzsche argues that all morality is something to be
destroyed, if anarchists are going to have a morality we would have
something to learn from the master morality. Maybe we would get
somewhere constructive with our ideas if we began focusing on what was
âgoodâ for us, what bettered us, our projects, our aims is certainly
more productive that focusing on what is not our enemies, labeling all
that is opposed to our enemies as âgoodâ, spending our time dissecting
âevilâ, learning about âevilâ in order to learn what is not evil, to
better understand how we can be not âevilâ. But we could strive to go
beyond morality entirely...
I think that Nietzscheâs critiques of anarchism can be taken as
constructive criticism, and can be learned from. I do not know much
about anarcho-nihilism, but I hope that it does not fall into the pit of
passivity.
I appreciate most of this response, KD, but this here got my goat:
Anarchists are some of the strongest adherents to the slave morality,
Nietzsche even said so outright. Our whole outlook on life, the way in
which we function within this world is based upon reaction, resentment.
We view people/events/etc through the eye of âgood vs evilâ.
Wow. first of all, you sound like you are speaking for (all) anarchists.
Then, as part of that, you state that (all) anarchists see things
through a moralistic lens of âgood vs evilâ. And I thought morals were a
concept placed above oneself, which one must (or at least should) defer
to. The very antithesis of what anarchy means to me.
Maybe I misunderstood something.
Youâre right, I make some sweeping generalizations in that answer. I did
lump all anarchists into that category.
I know that many individual anarchists actively do, or aim to, see the
world through a lens free of such morality. I find this to be totally
desirable and I appreciate that you are among those.
However, âanarchismâ as both an âismâ and a culture does have a
morality, and a strong one at that.
It would be nice to have more familiarity with such critiques to be able
to easily dispense with anti-capitalism = collectivism arguments.
European individualist anarchism tends to be highly influenced by
semi-aristocratic libertarian thinkers such as Friedrich Nietzsche and
Max Stirner. One of the most important causes that those thinkers are
for is individual authenticity and sincerity. So this is why for example
Nietzsche has been influential in something like the marxist Frankfurt
School.
The Frankfurt School might base some of its economics in marxism (mainly
the critique of the commodity form) but it is not hard to find in it
highly individualistic citations relevant to our consumer society such
as this:
The man with leisure has to accept what the culture manufacturers offer
him. Kant´s formalism still expected a contribution from the individual,
who was thought to relate the varied experiences of the senses to
fundamental concepts; but industry robs the individual of his function.
Its prime service to the customer is to do his schematizing for
him...There is nothing left for the consumer to classify.
Adorno and Horkheimer.
The dialectic of the enlightenment.
And another:
In the culture industry the individual is an illusion not merely because
of the standarization of the means of production. He is tolerated only
so long as his complete identification with the generality is
unquestioned. [ibid]
My thought is that as commercialism advances, the mediocrity and the
homogenizing grows. Even in small non-capitalist markets such as artisan
markets one has the constraint on personality and real emotions that
entails having to sell in order to make enough for survival. The famous
phrase âthe customer is allways rightâ shows this. Now as we enter the
capitalist market space the prospective employee has to sell
herself/himself, dress a certain way in order to sell an image. At the
top of all this we have the marketing technologues who have to learn
some form of psychology in order to learn the art of selling things no
matter if they like something or agree with something as long as the pay
is good.
As far as anarchism specifically a good essay on these themes is âThe
Soul of Man in Socialismâ by Oscar Wilde. In it he puts forward this
kind of view:
With the abolition of private property, then, we shall have true,
beautiful, healthy Individualism. Nobody will waste his life in
accumulating things, and the symbols for things. One will live. To live
is the rarest thing in the world. Most people exist, that is all.
Italian Individualist insurrectionist Renzo Novatore admired Wilde
highly and so went as far as to put him in his personal list of great
individuals:
Individualism is its own end. Minds atrophied by (Herbert) Spencerâs
positivism still go on believing that they are individualists without
noticing that their venerated teacher is the ultimate
anti-individualist, since he is nothing more than a radical monist, and,
as such, the passionate lover of unity and the sworn enemy of
particularity...But not because he has understood the anti-collectivist,
anti-social singularities capable of higher activities of the spirit, of
emotion and of heroic and uninhibited strength. He hates the state, but
does not penetrate or understand the mysterious, aristocratic, vagabond,
rebel individual!
And from this point of view, I donât know why that flabby charlatan,
that failed anthropologist, bloated more and more with the sociology of
Darwin, Comte, Spencer and Marx, who has spread filth over the giants of
Art and Thought like Nietzsche, Stirner, Ibsen, Wilde, Zola, Huysman,
Verlaine, MallarmĂŠ, etc., that charlatan called Max Nordau; I repeat, I
cannot explain to myself why he hasnât also been called an
Individualist... since, like Spencer, Nordau also fights the state.
So it is clear there are strong reasons why individualists have been
againts markets and of course their more totalitarian form, capitalism.
I think also the Situationist International delved in an important way
in all of this. In a book of Michel Onfray called âLa sculpture de soi:
la morale esthĂŠtiqueâ (the sculpture of oneself) briefly in some part he
finds a relationship with some important aspects of Stirner philosophy
with what the Situationist International spoke about.
In an ideal world, persuasion and discussion would settle all things,
but my ideal world has no room for ten hour consensus meeting more than
maybe once per lifetime. Lump that with the fact that my ideal world is
one of many, and they donât all fit together like a nice jigsaw puzzle
of anarchyland.
If we are assuming that the dirty grit of the real world in the here and
now will be present in whatever other realities we create (meaning that
they are non-utopic), where does coercion come in to play? At what point
does it cross the line in to domination?
Iâm not sure that I wouldnât put discussion outside of the category of
coercion. Depends on the situation.
The line between persuasion and coercion is a lot murkier than it seems
to be, once one starts questioning things like why some peopleâs skill
sets are more highly valued than others (talking over fist-fighting, for
example). I have seen plenty of verbal arguments finished where one
person was just more stubborn than the other, not that either had been
convinced (or convincing)...
To me, as a working premise, domination is a question of scale and
reification. If one person always argues circles around me without
taking my concerns into account and I donât want to or canât beat them
up, then I will just try to avoid them, or have someone else deal with
them. If I cannot do that because there is a whole apparatus in place
(like the police, to be simplistic), then I think that can be called
domination, especially if the apparatus is always composed of the same
people, or the same kind of people (whatever âkindâ might mean in a
given situation).
Edit: to be clearerâI think 10 hour meetings are absolutely coercive.
You have to continue talking to people in a specific format (meeting
procedures) in order to make decisions that impact your life? Or risk
having things come up that effect you without having any input? No.
theyâre free to walk away if I do?
Anarchy means you are welcome to try to coerce people, if that is what
you choose to do. It also means those people are welcome to walk away
without paying you any mind, or, should you be insistent in your
attempts to coerce, to punch you in the throat and then go on their way.
It might be unpopular to try to openly coerce others into acting against
their will, but that doesnât mean that people will suddenly all stop
doing so, or that there will be some law prohibiting coercion. Rather,
if we believe the anthropologists, coercion would be countered with
shaming about such behavior through things like mild needling and
teasing, sarcasm, etc. To whit, coercion would likely be countered with
coercion. Problem? No, not necessarily. The issue is one of power.
Anarchy is a delicate balance of societal needs and individual wants,
and of individual needs and societal wants. Ideally things would be
settled by persuasion as opposed to coercion, but that is talking about
ideals, which hold very little when dealing in real lives and desires.
Perhaps as a counter argument, I would ask, why attempt to coerce as
opposed to persuade? There are times where both are appropriate, in my
mind, but I would much rather create a new question than authoritatively
circumscribe that exploration.
Why exactly is hierarchy bad?
To the extent that hierarchy is bad (there is a question of semantics
hereâsee below), itâs because it encourages (or forces) people into
situations where they feel (or are) not responsible for their own lives
and actions. The military is full of extreme examples of people doing
things that ruin the rest of their lives because they were ordered to
(not just by their commanding officer, but by an entire social system
that a) tells them they should be ordered, and b) forces them into
situations like the military to be able to survive).
Some people donât put the issue in hierarchy, but in domination, and
argue that some amount of hierarchy is not a problem, as long as itâs
not institutionalized... Like, itâs ok if people pay more attention to
you when regarding something that youâre known to be good at. The
problem, for example, comes when you get to start making people do
things.
I think the valid critique that people bring to this ques- tion is that
of relationship, and the idea that we are all in some kind of
hierarchical relationship all the time (a la Foucault), that power flows
between people all the time, and that to resist hierarchy is to resist
relationships... So the issue becomes one of context and degree, rather
than simply a binary one.
If I may, I would alter your question to read: Why is hierarchy
considered to be detrimental to the positive principles of anarchism
like mutual aid, direct action, and voluntary cooperation? With a simple
understanding of what those principles are and what they look like, the
question almost answers itself.
I would wholeheartedly agree with dot that itâs a question of the
institutionalization of hierarchy rather than hierarchy itself that is
the problem, so a better way of discussing this issue is to call the
problem dominationâor if youâre feeling philosophical, call it
Herrschaft, because all the really heavy philosophical shit sounds
especially heavy in German.
I imagine a âhierarchyâ in a simplified sense as a pyramid where each
individual exists as a block in the structure: the closer your blockâs
position to the top, the less pressure you feel upon yourself and the
more pressure you put on others. The pressure symbolizes authority. So
this highly unequal distribution of force predictably breeds
institutionalized privilege, envy, and competition for dominance, at
bare minimum because of a want to escape the pressure. It seems like the
privilege and envy,
Now, beyond just intentions, and the way that power corrupts, we can
emphasize the consequences of structures of hierarchical control, how
they create incentives toward exploitation and obstacles toward
accountability, and how such systems by definition entail finite
positions of superior privilege and inferior classes held in
subordination. Power hierarchies mean that those most allowed to change
the status quo have the most investment in preserving itâtheir power,
prestige, profit, etc. rely upon the disempowered not taking back their
usurped initiative. Oftentimes even the mildest managerialism snowballs
away from accountability and toward authoritarianism through âemergencyâ
justifications that never roll back.
Systems that allow for and emphasize the role of hierarchical power have
totalitarian tendencies. They have pyramidal structures, stacked ranks,
centralized power, vertical organization. Their officials give commands
supported by threats. This creates a delicate stability through a shared
fear of repression.
In this spirit, their decision-making tends to utilize massive
restriction and coercion, representation, assimilation, and manipulation
by force or by fraud.
They develop impersonal bureaucracy, standardiza-tion, and conformity.
But other and contrary types of relations and organizing exist, such as
collaborative self-determination between peers, the kind that anarchists
propose.
Power hierarchies undermine communication. Hag-bardâs Law shows that in
a truly pyramidal structure, where authority figures create order
through threats, subordinates tend to tell their superiors merely what
hierarchy the superiors want to hear. This filtering multiplies to the
degree of verticality, by each level of mediation in that structure.
Those at the top therefore lose connection from the reality below them.
The (mis)information the authorities receive appeals to their
confirmation bias (the things they want to hear), resulting in misguided
intentions cloaked in truth, shielded by mistaken confidence, and armed
with monopoly, allowing for no opposition. And so, because of the
one-way decision-making and the filtered awareness, if those at the top
of the pyramid actually made a deliberate attempt to represent the
subordinates, they would tend toward a misrepresentation made invisible
to themselves.
If people possess the critical thinking and character assessment skills
to recognize in an authority the ways to lead competent, benevolent
lives, why must we have to delegate this capacity outside of ourselves?
Why do we need them to run our lives if we can tell how our lives should
be run? And however will the disempowered find freedom, if in each
instance where authoritarians act on behalf of the disempowered, to
shape or shield or crush them, the will of the disempowered continually
atrophies from lack of exercise? How else will the disempowered find
freedom, if not in seizing the direction of their own lives, the very
act that the authoritarians deny them? Stratification of power only
exacerbates the predicament. We alone experience the peculiar
circumstances of our situation. We alone bear the history of our
aspirations and sorrows, our passions and eccentricities, our capacities
and limitations.
Our lived experience grants us more qualification at determining our
path than any speculating manager could ever dream of. Further empowered
by collaboration with oneâs peers, people can experience authentic
freedom, and not the sad farce of begging those in power for mercy.
People may voluntarily seek for themselves a leader to guide them, but
when they deny others the ability to live autonomously, it results in
nothing but tyranny, no matter how many smily faces the tyranny hides
behind. Those of us who by conscience refuse systems of hierarchical
power will not voluntarily choose hierarchy to opt-in and cannot opt-out
without severe punishment. Those in power promise us the world but by
design they must keep our lives out of our own hands, and regardless of
whether or not they make decisions I would endorseâwhich they donâtâI
find the method irreconcilable with my conscience and my aspirations.
And that is the inequality and the abusiveness of the âpowerâ I refer
to, that is the mechanics intrinsic to hierarchal order.
If anarchists disagree with each other so much, how do you tell who is
one, and who isnât?
Rejection of capitalism and the state (among other things â but the core
points are being against political and economic hierarchies).
As long as thereâs agreement on those two points, thereâs anarchism.
Some of those other things to consider frz are work and civilization.
Yep! And opposition to forms of, ah, âsocial dominationâ I guess you
could sayâinstitutional and individual racism, sexism, heterosexism, et
cetera...
But I think these things come as very slightly secondary to capitalism
and the state. If an anarchist happens to be kind of a sexist douche,
they wouldnât necessarily be called ânot an anarchistâ but maybe ânot an
anarchist I would like to be aroundâ. On the other hand, if someone were
to defend the necessity or desirability of some level of capitalism or
statehood, then people would probably be pretty quick to say that that
person is not an anarchist at all.
The following test is remarkably accurate:
anarchist?
anarchist, is the latter likely to want to attack the former if they
have a fairly comprehensive knowledge of their ideas and actions?
If the answers are âyesâ to 1 and ânoâ to 2, the person in question is
an anarchist. Otherwise, they are not.
neighborhood/community watch organizations?
In my experience, neighborhood watch programs are really nothing more
than narcs, off-duty police, superiority-complex-ridden people that try
to be police, and then the occa-sional person who just wants to make
sure no one is being harmed. Itâs this last group of people that give me
hope for watches, and I think community watches can fit nicely with
anarchism; itâs volunteer, there are different watchers every night (or
week or whatever), and no one has authority over others. The Highway
Helpers in Iowa and other states are slightly reminiscent of this
organization (volunteers drive around the highways in trucks with
car-repair equipment and help anyone in need, free of charge). I can
easily see some anarchist societies having such organizations (people
patrolling to make sure no one is harming another or being harmed), and
I have heard Christiania has similar coordina-tion among residents,
although I canât confirm this.
But with incidents like that of the recent Trayvon Martin shooting and
many others like it, thereâs legitimate concern regarding these watches.
On top of the original question, what do all of you think?
Donât forgetâa neighborhood might need a fire watch, a medical watch, a
kiddy watch... a garden watch in freezing weather if folks are away...
there are a lot of negative connota-tions because of the way it gets
used. That doesnât keep us from using it for constructive purposes...
Old folk hasnât been seen in a few days? Did s/he fall down and get
hurt?
I mean, as of right now, the term âneighborhood watchâ carries a lot of
baggageâusually that of property owners, middle-class professionals, and
small entrepreneurs banding together to keep certain elements out of
their neighborhood. This usually translates to harassing poor people,
young people, and people of color (and especially combinations of the
three).
But the organizational structure is plenty anarchistic in theory, sure.
Itâs non-hierarchical and based on mutual aid. The problem is the
context in which it occurs.
To clarify, when I say that âthe organizational structure is plenty
anarchisticâ, I mean it in the sense that you could use a similar
organizational structure for wildly different things, such as the ones
illustrated in Askerâs commentâCopWatch, community defense vigilantes
committees, emergency response networks, etc.
The Neighborhood Watch, as it exists today, is obviously totally
incompatible with any kind of anarchist society or organizing, but that
much should be obvious since theyâre basically amateur cops.
To offer an alternative answer: I canât really imagine how a
neighborhood asr watch could ever be anything but a threat to us, much
less a helpful aspect of an âanarchist society.â It seems to me that
even if the form a neighborhood watch took were totally inclusive,
par-ticipatory, and whatever, that wouldnât matter. There are plenty of
organizations that work like that, (rotary clubs, alcoholics anonymous,
even some workplaces) but I would never think to link those
organizations to the anarchist project. In each case their purpose is
opposed to mine or at least unrelated.
As far as I can tell, the purpose of a neighborhood watch is
surveillance: they try to make sure that any crime that occurs in a
certain area is observed, so that it will be easier for the police to
deal with it. The assumption is that the neighborhood watch somehow has
the ability to determine what behaviors are appropriate within a certain
area (a side note: what the fuck is a neighborhood?).
In a situation where there are police available, people who do this are
straight up snitches. In a situation without police, I guess they would
simply be nosy ass-holes. I certainly canât think of any stateless group
I have read about where people thought that one of their biggest
problems is that people are committing crimes without being observed.
To complicate this, I can think of some situations where we might want
to organize in a somewhat analogous way, given the reality that right
now we live in a world with lots of enemies. For instance, copwatch,
neighborhood defense committees, barricadesâthings that might help us
keep police out of places...
I read in an anarchist 101 type pamphlet that anarchists are
egalitarians who seek the creation (in a long term and immediate sense)
of egalitarian social relationships and equality between people. And yet
in other places, I have read critiques of âequalityâ as an abstracting,
limiting, and quantifying view of humanity tied to liberalism and
capitalism. I understand anarchism to be a critique of capitalism and
liberalism.
Egalitarianism and equality are not necessarily the same things in the
way your are bring-ing them up. Egalitarianism as anarchists use it
normally refers to social relations lacking coercive or rigidly
hierarchical structures.
Often times when anarchists critique concepts of equality, they are
referring to legal definitions of equalityâaffirmative action programs,
state controlled redistribution of the wealth, and so forth. Often times
equality as used in contemporary north american politics is either a
code word for further state control or else is so detached of any real
meaning (pay attention, if you can stomach it, to how campaigning
politicians discuss equality for examples).
The critique of equality also extends to ideas that we should all have
exactly the same social standing, which is both impossible and not
really desirable. We are not all equal, but perhaps we can aim to live
in ways where we donât dominate each other.
I would just like to add to ingrateâs answer that while we could operate
on the understanding that the anarchists who promote âegalitarian
relationshipsâ and âequalityâ are just using the words in a good way
(usually under the rationale that they want to be able to speak to
people who donât think about the nuances that ingrate explains), it is
also reasonable to be suspicious of people who ignore the problems of
words and concepts that are appealing in a repressive society, and to
consider those people demagogues.
I think that perhaps the most important thing that anarchists do is to
encourage a deep questioning of the things that people take for granted,
especially things that people think of positively, like equality, love,
freedom, etc.
People who play on those assumptions are usually trying to manipulate
people, even/especially for âtheir own good.â
I understand egalitarianism as either
(a) no one has a privilege that everyone else doesnât also have,
(b) everyone has direct access to what they need,
(c) everyone has direct input in decisions that affect them,
(d) diversity exists without power hierarchies and exploitation of
labor.
Anthropologists distinguish between egalitarian societies, ranked
societies, and class-based societies, and I find these distinctions
useful. I donât like the term âequalityâ because to me it can too easily
become a vehicle for authoritarian conformity.
Two texts I find useful here are âEgalitarian Societiesâ by James
Woodburn, and âHow Hunter-gatherers Maintained Their Egalitarian Waysâ
by Peter Gray, equality both available online.
The wikipedia entry for âegalitarianismâ mentions one definition as âa
social philosophy advocating the removal of economic inequalities among
people or the decentralization of powerâ, so we can see obvious
parallels to anarchism.
Usually when I hear people utter this term or see it on banners I
understand it to mean equality of legal rights. This struggle is
reformist by anarchist standards, as we oppose the stateâs laws, equal
or not. Also, is this what the Circle E symbol is supposed to mean?
There are two broadly divergent tendencies in anarchist understandings
of equality. In the first perspective associated with class struggle
anarchism, equality is the utopian fantasy end-state that results from
the glorious revolution. Without equality, revolution has no utopian
dream to pursue, no raison dâetre. When the state and capital are
banished to history all people will magically be equal in the absence of
political and economic hierarchies and oppressions. We will thrive on
the fantastic bounty that utopian dreams bestow upon us.
For other anarchists the insistence on equality is a deplorable belief
in the weakness of humans, the drive to level everything and everyone to
protect us from ourselves and the world, to hedge against risk. It is an
abstraction that will occupy the vacant seat of the state, ensuring
freedom from harms. It is an abandonment and a betrayal of our greatest
abilities and dreams. It is settling for safety and repetition in the
place of our passions, our greatness, our in-domitable spirits, and a
real and dangerous world. Equality is the exaltation of the herd where
everyone stands on the same ground and where no one strays far from a
dull and unexceptional pack.
Whatâs the correlation between the two? Iâve heard some a-feminists say
all anarchists are (or should be) feminists. Is patriarchy really that
prevalent or that big of a problem?
Feminism just seems like a whiny way of saying women need to be treated
equally, yet differently and even better than men.
Firstâthis question seems to be trolling, both in its language and in
its content. But since this topic hasnât been fleshed out here much, I
will continue on the premise of good faith. This answer is not going to
be a tome, so it doesnât go into sufficient detail about the
complexities around gender vs sex, etc...
women-identified people, which includes tons of people, including
entirely straight men in certain contexts) are still attacked as women,
paid significantly less then men for the same type of work, devalued in
many levels of society (politics, etc), ignored, trivialized, etc.
That is just on the bare surface level. If you consider patriarchy to be
the thing that keeps us locked in a gender binary, which many feminists
(and anarchists) do, then the fact that most of us donât get to have the
kinds of relationships that we want, or be the people we want to be,
regardless of our gender/sex, is based on patriarchy.
anarchists (probably more).
things is a problem because of inherited and recreated hierarchies that
donât allow people our full expression, then yes, feminism and anarchy
can be seen as intimately related. On the other hand, some feminists
just want more women in government, so those feminists have nothing in
common with anarchists.
fundamental issue that is worth organizing aroundâand can be organized
around) has a lot of problems and weaknesses, it is one of the easiest
ways to (start to) look at many of the inequities of the system we live
in. Many people get to that stage and make a home there, replicating
power trips that mir-ror (as in reverse-image) the dynamics in the
larger society. Those people are particularly prone to contradictions in
what they are asking for (treat me the same and treat me differently).
But sometimes what appears to be a contradiction is actually someone
taking into account the different contexts of women and men. For
example, what self defense looks like for women vs what it looks like
for men can be significantly different, since women and men are mostly
socialized with diametrically opposed understandings of physical
violence.
âif you consider patriarchy to be the thing that keeps us locked in
gender binary...â
I see most feminist responses to patriarchy as absolutely perpetuating
the âgenderâ binary, just as patriarchy does. Some might see that as
inherently wrapped up in the bogeyman of feminism patriarchy, where
everything that âresultsâ from patriarchy is somehow explainable (or
even jus-tifiable) as such. I see that perspective as a far-too-easy
avoidance of the complexities of power dynamics in every relationship.
This raises a few related questions in my head. Are patriarchy and
feminism, by definition, manifestations of binary thinking?
Is feminism merely a response to patriarchy? Or is it a separately
existing concept/ideology, that would/could exist even without
patriarchy? One that is not really about gender, or race, or class, ...
Or perhaps is the same concept/ideology?
One final thought on the original question. Patriarchy is, at some
level, an institution (at least it is seen that way by many). Any
anarchist I care to hang with is against all institutions (which are
inherently controlling and homogenizing). A feminist who is against
patriarchy but not against other institutions (work/capitalism,
government; these seem to be the contexts within which patriarchal
behavior is measured, at least on the broad scale), is really no
different from the communist who is against one institution (capitalism)
but not the rest (including, but not limited to, the state,
industrialism, etc). Just my 2c.
âI see most feminist responses to patriarchy as absolutely perpetuating
the âgenderâ binaryâ
Sure. and most anarchists maintain fucked up patterns of behavior that
contradict what anarchy is too. Not trying to make an exact correlation
or anything, and I hang with anarchists not feminists for exactly the
reasons that you mention, but it is true that very few people push the
things that they believe in, in the directions that seem appropriate
(and/or obvious) to me.
supremacy over all other species (whether explicitly for domination or
under the guise of stewardship) has brought us to the brink of an
ecological collapse that will lead to a world of polluted wastelands and
destroy most species on Earth, including the human species. Divorc-ing
ourselves from values of aliveness, wildness, and regeneration has
achieved disastrous consequences for the majority of the human species
as well as all other species on Earth and all known habitats.
has forced humanism us into a roles that foster neuroses and madness; an
alienated existence inflicts increasing psychological and spiritual harm
to we who live and more and more in a sterile, deadened, mechanical,
symbolic world of control.
property arises from a humanist perspective that treats other species
and landbases only as utilitarian to certain humans rather than
possessing even the most rudimentary levels of intrinsic worth
(spirituality), self-ownership (philosophy), consideration for
ecological contribution (functionalism), or belief that they have no
superior or subordinate value (nihilism/egoism).
some measure (eg intellect, rationality, tool use) or content (eg soul,
nervous system) to justify authoritarian behavior toward anyone
classified as external. Such criteria change to rationalize the desire
for authoritarian behavior as desired. Humanism makes excuses and
rationalizations for human behaviors toward other species (slavery,
extermination) that humanists would never concede to other entities
(e.g. aliens or ma-chines) with greater of even the agreed-upon measures
or contents. Itâs an identity defense system, not a moral truth.
in the Myth of Progress, the belief that the state of humanity is always
positively improving socially or technologically in a straight, forward,
unidirectional line toward utopia, or at least claim this pattern has
occured so far with the development of the Neolithic Revolution.
Humanists believe that no other species does this, that humans are the
subject and consciousness of the cosmos, and therefore everyone and
everything else is an resource to exploit.
at the throne of authority with a particular and unquestioned image of
the human species (the rational, productive man), and creates a new
clerical class of scientists, technicians, bureaucrats, and others that
mediate and divvy out Progress.
constructed myths of an external environment and demonizes a concept of
nature that it perceives as hostile to human aims.Humanism therefore has
easily accommodated racism, as it is anti-nature and therefore to some
extent anti-any-ethnicity-that-resembles-nature, such as savages,
witches, barbarians, cavemen, Indians, Negroes, and supported those who
embody a struggle against nature, such as pilgrims, pioneers, mountain
men, Victorian-era masculine hetero males, Western scientists, who just
happened to also be the colonizers.
society that biotically cleanse landscapes to replace them with
monuments to the greatness of Man and and testaments to the glory of
Industry, artifacts of repression.
attachment to mass society and technophilia and drawdown of
non-renewables, and false notions that âEverything is naturalâ or âThat
which is natural is subordinateâ, and âTechnology is neutralâ. On a
spectrum of (a) all life-forms and landbases have value, to (b) only
humans and their settlements and artifacts and symbols have value, to
(c) only industrial technology has value, humanists are a lot closer to
(c) than theyâd like to admit, and have justified or rationalized the
eradication or subjugation of âbackwardâ peoples and entire species or
habitats for increasing technical complexity (see: Marxists,
transhumanists). For the most part, humanists today can more easily come
to terms with having no more traditional indigenous people on Earth, no
more migratory songbirds on Earth, no more old growth forests on Earth,
than having no more com-puters on Earth.
Humanist rhetoricians therefore often just cloak colonialism and
dominion, taking them for granted or ap-plauding them without giving
room to radical critiques of their origins, histories, and trajectories,
and in fact suppressing dissidents historically.
Stirner: How is it with mankind, whose cause we are to make our own? Is
its cause that of another, and does mankind serve a higher cause? No,
mankind looks only at itself, mankind will promote the interests of
mankind only, mankind is its own cause. That it may develop, it causes
nations and individuals to wear themselves out in its service, and, when
they have accomplished what mankind needs, it throws them on the
dung-heap of history in gratitude.
Some anarchists have trouble confining our op- humanism position to
slavery and extermination to just 1 in 8,700,000 species, during a mass
extinction no less.
Do you think altruism is possible? If itâs not, and everything everybody
does revolves around self-interest (i.e. what they will get out of it),
then why not choose Ayn Randâs Objectivism (I fucking hate it and her
with a burning passion) and laissez-faire capitalism (equally hated)? As
according to egoist thought, itâs unethical/immoral to put others before
the self. The way it is argued seems to make it impossible to disprove
or even deny. Thoughts on this?
Your question isnât taking into an account other egoisms that exist,
especially Stirnerâs egoism, which is quite different that Randâs. You
are right to say that Randâs stance was that it is unethical/immoral to
be altruistic or do anything altruistic, but ethics and morality would
be of no concern to Stirner in deciding what sort of action to take. So
Stirnerâs stance would be that one could do something altruistic if they
wanted to, or they could do something non-altruistic instead, it all
comes down to what that individual decides to do and this decision is
made with no consideration of what is considered âgoodâ or âbadâ,
âMoralâor âimmoralâ, âethicalâ or âunethicalâ, etc.
Letâs leave aside philosophy for a moment and go to the behaviour of
animals and humans. Science have shown that animals and humans both
engage in war and collaborate.
Peter Kropotkin in his book âMutual Aid: A factor of Evolutionâ showed
that the not so visible side of success in species survival is
collaboration inside the species against others or in mere
self-survival.
Egoism can be said to be the direct logical linguistic opposite of
altruism yet like every binary operation it is not that simple. Max
Stirner himself said: âWho, then, is âself-sacrificing?â[Literally,
âsacrificingâ; the German word has not the prefix âself.â] In the full
sense, surely, he who ventures everything else for one thing, one
object, one will, one passion. Is not the lover self-sacrificing who
forsakes father and mother, endures all dangers and privations, to reach
his goal? Or the ambitious man, who offers up all his desires, wishes,
and satisfactions to the single passion, or the avaricious man who
denies himself everything to gather treasures, or the pleasure-seeker,
etc.? He is ruled by a passion to which he brings the rest as
sacrifices.
And are these self-sacrificing people perchance not selfish, not egoist?
As they have only one ruling passion, so they provide for only one
satisfaction, but for this the more strenuously, they are wholly
absorbed in it. Their entire activity is egoistic, but it is a
one-sided, unopened, narrow egoism; it is possessedness.â
So one can be egoistic and also be altruistic at the same time if this
things outside me is of my love or desire. It is clear âegoismâ and
âself interestâ is involved here but of course it is also altruistic.
And so for example gift economies
(http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gift_economy) could be superficially
identified and mostly altruistic relationships but this is not exactly
the case. Anarchist antropologist David Graeber when speaking about
french antropologist Marcel Mauss says:
Instead, what anthropologists were discovering were societies where
economic life was based on utterly different principles, and most
objects moved back and forth as gifts and almost everything we would
call âeconomicâ behavior was based on a pretense of pure generosity and
a refusal to calculate exactly who had given what to whom. Such âgift
economiesâ could on occasion become highly competitive, but when they
did it was in exactly the opposite way from our own: Instead of vying to
see who could accumulate the most, the winners were the ones who managed
to give the most away. In some notorious cases, such as the Kwakiutl of
British Columbia, this could lead to dramatic contests of liberality,
where ambitious chiefs would try to outdo one another by distributing
thousands of silver brace-lets, Hudson Bay blankets or Singer sewing
ma-chines, and even by destroying wealth sinking famous heirlooms in the
ocean, or setting huge piles of wealth on fire and daring their rivals
to do the same...In gift economies, Mauss argued, exchanges do not have
the impersonal qualities of the capitalist marketplace: In fact, even
when objects of great value change hands, what really egoism/altruism
matters is the relations between the people; exchange is about creating
friendships, or working out rivalries, or obligations, and only
incidentally about moving around valuable goods. As a result everything
becomes personally charged, even property: In gift economies, the most
famous objects of wealth heirloom necklaces, weapons, feather cloaks
always seem to develop personalities of their own.
David Graeber. âGive It Awayâ
So gift economies include motivations that donât appear out of something
similar to âchristian loveâ but of other âegoisticâ tendencies such as
the desire of prestige and recognition as well as keeping good relations
with those who can help me in the future.
Hakim Bey thus establishes this bridge in this way:
The essence of the party: face-to-face, a group of humans synergize
their efforts to realize mutual desires, whether for good food and
cheer, dance, conversation, the arts of life; perhaps even for erotic
pleasure, or to create a communal artwork, or to attain the very
transport of blissâin short, a âunion of egoistsâ (as Stirner put it) in
its simplest formâor else, in Kropotkinâs terms, a basic biological
drive to âmutual aid.â (Here we should also mention Batailleâs âeconomy
of excessâ and his theory of potlatch culture.)
So a union of egoists is a form of mutual aid. Mutual Aid is not the
same as âchristian loveâ. Mutual aid is something done in the
self-interest of both sides.
I am not satisfied with the paradoxical assumptions of subjectivity that
support the concept of altruism. But, I am also not satisfied with a
constrained concept of subjectivity/self/ego/âIâ (from now on just
âegoâ). This is all tied up in the way that I understand subjectivity to
begin with.
That what we recognize as the ego is an expression of complicated
cognitive processes which make it possible for the boundaries of ego to
fluctuate: that the ego is capable of identifying with, appropriating,
connecting, or otherwise expanding to include other minds, bodies,
objects, and images. From the studies in developmental psychology that
Iâve read, it appears that the ego shrinks through development as theory
of mind develops, as a sense of self recedes from an undifferentiated
identification with all that is perceived. And from other studies of
subjectivity the ego appears capable of redefining its boundaries to
various extents: whether as a transcendental experience, a psychotic
break, consummate love (sometimes), empathy, and/or less powerful
experiences of identification with others.
So, if the ego is more of this sort of concept, then egoism is also less
bound. If my sense of self can egoism/altruism expand to include you (or
at the very least, my self-image and the image of you are intricately
bound up with each other), then my behavior is no longer towards you...
but towards myself. At the same time, if my sense of self doesnât expand
to include you and I regard you as an other, I would enter into a
self-other relationship and be more or less consider-ate. I could reason
that my self-interests include the happiness of those around me and wind
up with an âenlightened self-interestâ or I could reason that itâs
better to be calloused towards the conditions of others and wind up with
a ethic like Ayn Randâs.
If the ego is fairly amorphous and an ethics rooted in a static ego is
embraced, is that being true to the ego? Even worse, if the ego is the
expression of more fundamental psychological patterns that use it for
their unknown fulfillment... is it really the ego that can be the
grounds for an ethics? What if ego and environment are so intricately
entangled that it would make more sense to comprehend them as shades of
a common experience and not actually separate beings?
Why not choose Ayn Randâs Objectivism? Who the fuck wants to live in a
world filled with miserable people?
Why put others before the self? Interdependence... my existence depends
upon some others to such an extent that there is no clean cut in our
reciprocal relations.
Is altruism possible? Only to the extent that it includes the ego, even
if that inclusion is through some sort of identification.
distinctions?
What are the main ideas, texts, groups that embody these anarchism(s)?
Is there a middle ground between the two?
I think social anarchism has to be seen as a position putting forward a
social organization alternative to the current societal forms.
And so it gives a collective answer and it is associated with
anarcho-syndicalism, bakuninist collectivism and anarcho-communism. As
far as âanti-socialâ anarchism, that has not been an important term
within anarchist discourse although I have read it in insurrectionist
and individualist texts but it wasnât a central term where I read it.
A false dichotomy in a sense. Even egoist anarchists address society and
other people so it is not a âRobinson Crusoeâ dream and there have been
many individualists who have participated in anarchist trade unions and
large Anarchist Federations such as francophone Federation Anarchiste
and spanish and italian FAIs.
On the other hand Murray Bookchin wrote a book called Social Anarchism
and Lifestyle Anarchism: An Unbridgeable Chasm, which accused everything
that didnât go along with his particular view of âsocial anarchismâ as
being âbourgeoisâ. The word âsocial anarchismâ was proposed by the more
marxist like anarchists who wanted to establish an important difference
between their âclass struggleâ, platformist and economicistic approach
and the more âlifestyleâ and/or humanistic approach of individualist
anarchists such as Emile Armand or the outlaw âviolentâ frame of mind of
the illegalists and propaganda by the deed insurrectionists. Because of
this Sebastien Faure and Voline proposed pluralistic and anarchism
without adjectives âsynthesis anarchismâ as an organizational
alternative in which anarcho-communists, anarcho-syndicalists, and
individualist anarchists could collaborate and fit in. It seems to me
synthesis anarchism in a way to go beyond the bad effects of the
dichotomy âsocialâ and âindividualistâ and so large pluralistic
synthesis federations exist until today in mediterranean countries but
also anti-organizationalist insurrectionalists and individualists and on
the other hand cuasi-marxist platformist organizations.
I think philosophically the best middle ground that I have read is that
of Emma Goldman. She was an admirer of both Nietzsche and Stirner and
also an anarcho-communist. I think that can be called âegoist communismâ
and these anarchists from San Francisco wrote a whole lengthy book: The
Right To Be Greedy: Theses on The Practical Necessity of Demanding
Everything by For Ourselves.
Bontemps was a French individualist anarchist who wrote on a concept
central to him, âsocial individualismâ, but I donât think anything by
him has yet been translated. He was a humanistic individualist and so
social individualism most likely has to do with the individualist side
of humanism but also with the âaltruisticâ side of humanism which
advocates friendship and empathy towards others while retaining
individual autonomy and freedom of association with those more like
oneself.
In the end the problem here is the vagueness of the words âsocialâ and
âanti-socialâ. âAnti-socialâ sounds interesting in a romantic or poetic
sense but for conceptual clarity it is too unclear. The word âsocialâ
can make one think both of âsocietyâ and of âsocializingâ. âSocietyâ can
be a local society, a society of a country or state. Globalization
propagandists even talk of âglobal societyâ. On the other hand
âsocializingâ can mean talking with just one person and so misanthropics
or egoists by just talking with another similar type of person are
already socializing.
Joseph Dejacque, one of the first individuals to create in theory and in
practice the split that would form between the anarchists and the state
socialists/communists, wrote âLetâs make war on societyâ in the early
1800s. While he attacked statists and even the anarchist Proudhon on the
basis of questions of personal liberty, he saw the ideal environment for
individual freedom being a communist society.
Max Stirner, who decried the (humanist) communist cause because it puts
the greater good of society in the place of Godâs cause as the dominant
ideology, an ideology opposed to individual freedom and insurrection,
was involved in forming a milk cooperative. Interestingly enough, this
was the only project he is known for aside from his writing.
Renzo Novatore, possibly the most extremely anti-social anarchist I can
think of who wrote much, at one point declared to his anarcho-communist
comrades that he would fight alongside them in the destruction of the
existing society, and that when they established their new communist
society he would fight to destroy that one as well.
The current social vs. anti-social debate in anarchism is in many ways
reminiscent of and refers to this history, while at the same time it is
unique. The consciously anti-social tendency is probably strongest among
insurgents in Chile, where one can see that phrase as well as related
terms openly embraced in text after text. Or one could point to various
individuals influenced by Ted Kaczynskiâs theory and practice, which is
highly anti-social and is centrally about a critique of modern society
and particularly leftism (and is significantly different from
individualist anarchism, operating on a different plane). But perhaps
the most intense episode in this debate happened recently in the wake of
the Marfin Bank firebombing in Athens, Greece on May 5, 2010 (in which
three workers died from a fire started by anarchists during massive
demonstrations). While Iâm not familiar with all of the debate since it
occurred in Greek and little has been translated to English, it seems
that many anarchists blamed the deaths on what they described as
anti-social elements in the milieu. These elements were defined in terms
that will probably sound familiar to many of us: abandoning much of the
anarchist tradition, they rejected the idea of the revolutionary
potential of the masses and rather than placing sole blame upon the
bourgeois class, chose instead to direct their critique at the leaders
as well as the masses whose submission gives the leaders their power.
They also rejected the ideology of the oppressedâs liberation from their
oppression through their position as the oppressed and its social
movements (reminiscent here of Nietzsche among others). This contempt
for the workers, some argued, led a few anarchists to not be concerned
about whether their actions would cause the death of bank workers.
I will go out on a limb and say that I donât buy this attempt to
establish a firm connection between anti-social ideas and the actions of
the arsonists, especially when the anarchists making this argument
clearly have a double agenda: to distance themselves from the arsonists
to clear their own feelings of guilt while promoting their own ideology
of social revolution in hopes of doing away with a plague that they were
by all accounts already very interested in stomping out or at least
controlling. (During the De-cember 2008 insurrection, insurrectionary
anarchists who had set plenty a fire in their day were trying to direct
the younger, more wild insurgents to not burn certain buildings such as
local businesses.) For the most part, it doesnât seem that any of the
anarchists in the âanti-social tendencyâ in Greece (itâs unclear to me,
by the way, whether the anti-socials chose this term to explain their
differences with the social revolutionaries or whether some chose to
embrace the term that the social revolutionaries threw at them) acted
very differently in practice from insurrectionary anarchists, at least
not to the point of attacking anyone who is not a cop, politician, boss,
etc. But Iâve heard it claimed that a couple of actions distinguish
themselves, so I will examine them. The first was an action by a
little-known group who hijacked a commuter train, forced everyone off
it, and set it on fire. Their communique pointed out that the workersâ
daily activity is what reproduces the system they are against, and that
this action was to deny the workers their daily commute. No one was
hurt, and it seems by all accounts an exemplary action, with even the
social anarchists only objecting to their rhetoric and not to the action
itself. The other was an action of the Conspiracy of Cells of Fire, who
placed a bomb in an area where the ruling party leader was giving a
speech during the campaign season. The communique declares that their
hatred and contempt was not only for the politician but also for the
masses who went to hear him speak. However, their intention was not to
hurt anyone, and they called in a bomb threat to force the evacuation of
the area and prevent the speech from taking place. The area was
evacuated and no one was hurt. Compare these with Mario Budaâs bombing
of Wall Street...
I think it was easier in the 1800s into the early 1900s to have faith in
the movements of the oppressed to liberate themselves from their
oppression. 1968 was another glimpse of possibility. One might argue
that the recent wave of social movements should put the debate to rest
again (it reached its peak before the Arab Spring, in a time of
unprecedented social peace), since social revolution seems like a real
possibility. But a different way of looking at it is that all the social
revolutions of the past have ended in everyone going back to work for
the continuation of the capitalist society in which we find ourselves
today; that we should have no faith in this wave, which is steadily
showing itself to accomplish not anarchy but only new democratic regimes
and other forms of recuperation; and that the very form of social
revolution is a form we should reject in favor of anti-social
insurrection. Drawing on Stirner or Novatore here we might reach the
conclusion that the seed always planted in the heart of the social
revolution, which caused new arrangements to be formed, which led to the
communist dictatorships in Russia and China and elsewhere; the reason
why the workers went back to work at the end of May 1968 was the
insurgentsâ adherence to a higher cause and their need to act as a mass
rather than embarking on the more dangerous path of an egoist,
iconoclastic insurrection.
For the most part, anarchism has taken a middle ground on one
interpretation of this question. That is: anarchists are of course
against the existing society, so we are anti-social, but most anarchists
believe in creating a new anarchist society, so they are also social.
This is the 1^(st) layer of the middle ground, and it doesnât interest
me. The 2^(nd) layer arises from the debate between the individualist
anarchists (especially as inspired by Stirner) who are not interested in
a new society, and the anarcho-communists, who are. In this, there is
another middle ground which includes the Galleanists, the whole
insurrectionary anarchist approach, and some outliers such as Volta-rine
de Cleyre. Iâve discussed this in the past. This middle ground is
interesting to me. But I think the way in which it understands itself as
a middle ground is a problem. Why? Because although it is illuminat-ed
by the understanding of the intimate link between individual freedom and
social liberation, and this link cannot be understood as mutual,
nevertheless it has always been the case historically and presently that
the cause of social liberation has been wielded as a tool to push the
individual back into line, on a daily level and during insurrection. It
is for this reason that I will say that I am on the side of the
anti-social when I see these come into conflict. Because individual
insurrection and social insurrection can mutually feed each other, but
without individual insurrection, social insurrection could not be, since
it is the insurrection of many individuals together, not as a mass, but
as individuals on a common trajectory. And when the âcommon causeâ of
these individuals rears its headâthe liberation of the people, of the
masses, of the proletariat, of the class, of the nation, etcâit does so
to squash insurrection and turn it into the new (or old) social order.
I am against social anarchism, not because I do not agree with the
premise that the individualâs freedom is most possible in a world where
all are free, but rather because social anarchism is a force that uses
the argument âone cannot be free while another is in chainsâ to turn
around and say to the rebels âhow dare you try to be free while another
is in chains?!â As if one needed the approval of the masses in order to
embark on a process of liberation, as if what we need is more guilt! It
is a pathetic way to try to smooth out oneâs own insecurities about
being wedded to oneâs social position. Rather than seeing anotherâs
rebellion as a fuel to oneâs own, the social anarchist protests, âBut I
am oppressed and so many others are oppressed, so you must be oppressed
with us! You must be part of our fighting of our oppression together!â
There is not enough insurrection in the world. Each encounter I have
with an insurgent blows some air into my own fire. Platitudes and
pandering, attempts to help me, the insistence that only by serving
others can I make the world a better place: these are some of the wet
blankets tossed on top of the heaving mass that this world throws on my
flame. Focus on insurrection.
This does not mean swimming along with the masses.
But it does not mean you will be alone.
Yes, there is pro-social and anti-social anarchism. You can see the
pro-social in the whiny liberal-anarchist âbuild a movement,â support
âthe community,â make-friends-with-your-neighbors tendencies. These
tendencies often see the role of anarchism as supporting The Social and
keeping it functioning in a way very similar to how it is functioning
now.
Pro-social tendencies exist in other political movements in more
paradoxical ways, but most posi-anarchists just have bad ideas about how
revolution happens and often criticize or shit talk riots, revolts, and
rebellions for not having an explicit pro-social characteristic or
articulation. They also downplay or distance themselves from forms of
revolutionary violence such as kidnapping bosses or murdering racist
union bosses and coworkers.
Most posi-anarchists are not explicit about whether their position is
chosen strategically for the rev., morally, or in an effort to protect
their own comfort.
Anti-social anarchists do not concern themselves with the continued
functioning of the social. We see all interruptions of society as
immediately connected to interruptions of capitalism. Anti-social
anarchists are not concerned with preserving the reigning moral order
that permeates and gives cohesion to the social order. Revolutionary
acts will be feared and hated by all reasonable members of society, and
that is no discouragement. We see society as a thing with an inside and
an outside, a center and a periphery, and we want the periphery to come
crashing down on the center to make its order and function impossible.
We want society as such to be destroyed and we want the world after to
be completely unrecognizable from this one.
Fire to the Prisons and Vengeance are both antisocial texts, Vengeance
is anarchist, and FttP is pro-anarchist. Everything Bash Back! ever
wrote was anti-social as are most insurrectionary texts, including the
contemporary insurrectionary trans feminism current that is basically
the only inspiring contemporary anarchist writing.
Iâll let the pro-social people define themselves some-where away from my
petty, bitter, shit talking.
I think labeling FttP, BB!, and Vengeance as anti-social horribly
confuses things. BB! and FttP have had quite a few people with different
ideas write under their umbrellas. Vengeanceâs conception of anarchism
is 110% class-based, and is ENTIRELY about âbuild a movement, support
the community, make friends with your neighborsâ; it is one of the most
social anarchist publications Iâve ever encountered.
The only way in which these could all be called anti-social is that
theyâre opposed to the existing class society, but this is true of all
anarchists, making it completely useless as a distinction.
This is why the social vs. anti-social debate has to be about what one
thinks of society not only as it exists but as it might ideally exist
(communist/anarchist society), and whether oneâs (revolutionary) means
and ends are social in nature.
Also the recent insurrectionary transfeminist writings, mainly seemingly
based on the argument constructing a revolutionary class of people on
the basis of their bodies being unable to produce children, are some of
the least inspiring Iâve encountered in my entire life.
Depending on the circumstances, anarchists express disagreement or
dissent by:
anarchists?
I have noticed that both T and S are getting heat from anarchists lately
about live streaming protests. They are freely and openly documenting
the events that are happening, and I see this as a good thing when
compared to the main stream media. Can you educate me on the issues that
anarchists have with live streamers such as T and S?
By the way, I created this logo and I think it aptly portrays one of the
most helpful roles that live streamers have to play at protests. They
keep the powers that be responsible for their actions.
[]
The logo almost answers the question.
a. Recording peopleâs actions is more likely to be useful to our enemies
than it is to us, whether for the purposes of surveillance, criminal
charges, making it more confusing who is doing what (how does one tell
an âindependent journalistâ from a cor-porate one?), etc.
b. Recording peopleâs actions is part of making actions spectacular
(reifying them, making them abstract and separate from peopleâs lives).
c. The idea that these recordings are helpful in some kind of
âprotecting ourselvesâ or âgrowing our numbersâ way relies on the
extremely limited notion that more information is what is required to
make people free or active, or that the State cares very much when it is
recorded doing heinous things. As an example, while it is true that
having an Iraqi-war vetâwho was tailor-made to be a posterboy (white,
slight of build, unthreatening looking, etc)âbe attacked on national tv
did galvanize people, it is entirely open to question how relevant that
galvanizing was. And that was pretty much the best possible scenario for
public response...
This c. response basically loops back to a. (insufficient good for the
bad involved).
Every individual has their own unique biases. This is as true of
journalists as anyone else. Often with indy journalists these
perspectives fall in line with some massified political consciousness.
There are quite a few liberal-cum-socialist, grassroots-y journalists
for whom the legiti-macy of the state never comes into question. Their
coverage of events can easily collapse some vast and unbounded events
and movements into digest-ible, non-threating activism. For a really
great example compare the diversity of views of Egyptians and Tunisians
from a year ago to the reformist framing used by âalternativeâ media.
According to Democracy Now! as much as Fox News, the movement was
pro-democracy rather than the more obvious conclusion that it was at
base anti-Mubarak/Ben Ali.
Surely the movement bureaucrats and democracy activists were there in
the first days, but they were not necessarily representative of the
movement as a whole. We must remain aware that indy journalists may be
doing the stateâs work; recuperating radical actions by imposing
narratives in which such events are channeled into benign reformism.
I think it is helpful to distinguish the amateur, âcitizenâ (ew)
journalists from professional, âindependentâ journalists journalists.
âCitizenâ journalists can be quite a bit wider in their perspectives
than those for whom it is a job. Their biases might also be a lot more
obvious.
Maybe thereâs still some indy journalists out there perpetuating the
charade of objectivity. This should an unforgivable sin of journalism by
now. The ones most insistent about objectivity are usually the ones with
the biggest ax to grind.
This is a better way to talk about what I touched on with âhow can you
tell who is independentâ, but to be clear, Iâm not any more interested
in non-professional journalists than in paid ones. Mostly, intentions
are irrelevant to the harm caused.
anti-authoritarian sense)?
As an additional question, does anybody know whether thereâs been any
writing done on the subject? If so, links?
Obviously, we as anarchists oppose leadership in the form of authority
and hierarchies. However, Iâve read some things remarking on the organic
emergence of âleadersâ in anarchist groups, in the form of people who
are the most experienced, the most confident, and/or the most capable of
taking action.
Iâve also seen proposed something akin to âif you must take the role of
a leader, do so only for as long as it takes to share your knowledge and
experience with those around youâ. A leader who encourages others to
knock her off her pedestal, so to speak.
Basically, what Iâve run into is that a large portion of my friends are
either into anarchism or consider themselves anarchists (after being
exposed to it, through hanging around me), but donât have the
knowledge/experience/initiative to be confident in working on projects.
I really want to share what Iâve got, but honestly I donât have a lot of
experience with âleadershipâ and instilling confidence and inspiring
action. Maybe this is something totally out of my hands and itâs just a
matter of waiting for them to find their own initiative and desire to
act, but I really feel like what Iâve done thus far is equivalent to
saying, âHereâs what anarchism isâif you agree with it, cool. We should
do something about it.â And that doesnât seem like enough.
Time for an epic response; thanks for giving me an incentive to write it
out.
Concepts:
A. Guide: a leader who persuades by example and suggestion, based on
experience or informed speculation (expressed as such). Practices
voluntary relationships. Legitimate.
B. Master: a leader who manipulates through duress or deceit, based on
experience or misinformed speculation (often concealed). Practices
coercive relationships. Illegitimate.
---
In my opinion, legitimate leadership requires at least 13 conditions:
with informed consent, constantly re-evaluate
rather than followers
or direct need; guides and followers live in the same material
conditions
sharing information or materials, rotating roles, decentralizing agency,
and rendering further guidance unnecessary
upon goal(s)
guide(s)
honest and empowering explanations of guidesâ logic and aims
guides want responsibility to followers rather than power over them
the followers thwart guidesâ senses of entitlement, arrogance, &
contempt
the inclusion of all parties deserving agency, based on expressed or
implied need
---
Gently, she grasps her tender loverâs unpracticed cheek.
They brush faces, touch lips. She guides with her affection, encouraging
learning in the most compassionate of ways. As their intimacy grows,
they reach a balance together, her inexperienced partner becomes a
competent lover. And even with all of her practice, she could not help
but have her own learning stimulated. Now they walk their path
hand-in-hand; neither guides, neither follows.
He remembers his early youth, when his elders taught him to walk in the
forest and gather his nourishment. He remembers their confidence, his
apprehension, as he first stepped into the bush, nervous, with them. But
now he often walks under the pale light of the moon, fetching the
acorns, with only his memories keeping him company.
Soon he will teach his little ones to become sons of the leadership
oaks, the cycle starting afresh.
---
much as it does among children, and confine itself to taking initiatives
only when individual ones are impractical. The followers should be the
ones to decide whom they will follow and should be free to change
leaders as suits their convenience. In a continuum culture like that of
the Yequana, the functioning of leaders is minimal and it is possible
for any individual to decide not to act on the leaderâs decision if he
prefers...*
âJean Liedloff, The Continuum Concept
---
If we want to live without rulers, we need empowerment to immunize us
from the threat of authoritarian relationships and defeat the potential
pitfalls of leadership.. In order for that to happen, we need to
understand the psychology of perception and prejudice, creativity,
intelligence, learning, logic and fallacies, intuition, critical
thinking, argumentation, problem-solving, planning, systems analysis,
and risk management. Those of us who know these things (such as myself)
would do well to act as guides and share our knowledge. So here goes
psychology
(self-actualization processes; cognitive biases; psychological
heuristics)
prejudice
(cognitive, affective, and behavioral prejudices)
creativity
(imagination; inspiration; intuition)
increasing intelligence
(âseek novelty; challenge yourself; think creatively; do things the hard
way; networkâ)
increasing learning
(working memory; attention)
logic
(formal vs informal; inductive vs deductive)
reason
(logic) vs intuition (instincts, associations)
logical fallacies
(search: âCritical Thinking as an Anarchist Weaponâ)
awareness of disinformation techniques
critical thinking
as âthe process of purposeful, self-regulatory judg-ment, which uses
reasoned consideration to evidence, context, conceptualizations,
methods, and criteria.â
critical thinking components
(skepticism; logic; clarity; credibility; accuracy; precision;
relevance; depth; breadth; significance; fair-ness)
critical thinking requirements
âfalsifiability, logic, comprehensiveness, honesty, replicability,
sufficiencyâ
âhumility, integrity, courage, autonomyâ
âfollow through, open-mindedness, foresight, attention, inquisitiveness,
thoroughness, fair-mindednessâ
willingness to criticize oneself
âCritical thinking clarifies goals, examines assumptions, discerns
hidden values, evaluates evidence, accomplishes actions, and assesses
conclusions.â
argument mapping
(contentions, premises, co-premises, objections, rebuttals, lemmas)
problem-solving (techniques & methodologies; brainstorming;
collaboration; networking)
lateral thinking (idea-generating tools; altering focus; selection;
application)
planning principles (PsyBlog goal hacks: stop fantasizing; start
committing; start starting; visualize process not outcome; avoid the
what-the-hell-effect; sidestep procrastination; shifting task-or-goal
focus; reject robotic behavior; focus on the aim not the goal; know when
to stop; if-then plans; verbal-ization & visualization of processes;
contrast positive fantasy/indulging with negative reality/dwelling)
planning methodologies (STOP, OODA loops; SWOT analysis; PDCA cycles;
flow charts)
working backwards (goal; strategy; tactics; time-frames; deadlines;
review)
systems analysis (complexity; emergence; fragil-ity/resilience;
systempunkts; schwerpunkts)
risk management (risks; threats; vulnerability; mitigation)
TL;DRâSkeptical of Guides, Hostile to Masters, Deliberate as Fuck,
Destroy Power Through Collective Self-Empowerment, Tell Everyone.
Two more things...
One text that was interesting to me (despite her reputation) was
Starhawkâs book on group dynamics and structure (Truth or Dare). It
encouraged me to think about the different roles that people play, how
they can be played well, and how many (all?) of them have a place in a
happy group.
Which leads to the point that being a leader (good or bad) requires
participation from the group. To some extent we all are at the mercy of
our friends and context (ie part of the problem with how we view leaders
is the idea that âa good leader can overcome things on their ownâ). I
have been in many a group that defused a power play, made a comment into
a joke (or refused a joke and made it into a comment), etc without even
noticing what was happening. When the topic of leaders arises, the
context that the individual operates within is not given enough credit
for leadership what happens.
The example given by the question seems to be one of commitment, that
people are afraid or unwilling to act (which can be for a number of
different reasons), and I think that sometimes leaders are merely the
people who are willing to do something even if it means they might be
wrong (or be seen as wrong).
When I say âworker-owned businessesâ, Iâm talking along the lines of
workers democratically and collectively owning, making decisions for,
and obviously working the business in a non-hierarchical manner. Iâve
seen a lot of anarchist-friendly printing shops and book stores run this
way, along with bakeries, bicycle shops, and even some small
restaurants.
Hardass answer: this anarchist feels no way at all about worker-owned
businesses.
There are some businesses and fields that are more fun to work in. There
are some businesses that teach skills that are more useful in the rest
of my life.
There are some businesses (or jobs) that introduce me to people whom I
am more likely to enjoy.
But none of that has anything to do with anarchy or capitalism... only
with reform.
Not so hardass answer: being able to live our lives more the way we want
to (time off to fuck shit up, connecting with people who become good
parts of our lives, enough money to work short hours, etc) is a good
thing, and may help make changing the world more do-able.
Back to hardass: or it might not.
And the reality of these kinds of more-pleasurable jobs tends to be that
they pay less money and require more time, more commitment, and more
energy... vs working a job that one doesnât care about and can hence
exploit fully.
If there is a broad anti-authoritarian political tendency are
anarchists, by definition, a part of it?
Conceptually, if we start from the notion that authoritarians value
authority, order, and/or rule over freedom, that authoritarians value
obedience over autonomy, then anarchists are anti-authoritarian by
definition, no matter if the authoritarian manifested is a person,
policy, or practice.
It is easy to point to something that tramples the wills of people and
oppose it. But opposing the bad guy, the boss, the dictator is easy and
not very deep. If this is the extent of the analysis of
authoritarianism, that it picks off particular people or programs, but
leaves intact the structures that they plug into then this easy type of
anti-authoritarian stance is below the anarchist bar.
Stirner wrote:
former consists in an overturning of conditions, of the established
condition or status, the State or society, and is accordingly a
political or social act; the latter has indeed for its unavoidable
consequence a transformation of circumstances, yet does not start from
it but from menâs discontent with themselves, is not an armed rising,
but a rising of individuals, a getting up, without regard to the
arrangements that spring from it. The Revolution aimed at new
arrangements; insurrection leads us no longer to let ourselves be
arranged, but to arrange ourselves, and sets no glittering hopes on
âinstitutions.â It is not a fight against the established, since, if it
prospers, the established collapses of itself; it is only a working
forth of me out of the established. If I leave the established, it is
dead and passes into decay. Now, as my object is not the overthrow of an
established order but my elevation above it, my purpose and deed are not
a political or social but (as directed toward myself and my ownness
alone) an egoistic purpose and deed.*
I write: Insurrection does not have to mean the uprising of a single
ego, it can be the simultaneous uprising of many individuals together.
It differs from revolution, however, in that it is simply uprising.
Revolution may âfollowâ an insurrection in reestablishing a new order.
Most revolutionaries would say that an insurrection is necessary to the
process, but is not all of the process.
In the Marxist sense, revolution is the total overthrow of an
economic-political system and its replacement with another oneâthe most
accessible example being the bourgeois revolution which overthrew
feudalism and produced capitalism. So from a Marxist perspective we have
no examples of a full proletarian revolution (yet), only various
proletarian insurrections (the Paris Commune, etc), which have been put
down, or coopted for example by the Bolsheviks. Others would say that
the problem isnât that âwe havenât gone far enoughâ to full revolution
through insurrection, but that we are on the side of insurrection itself
because that is where anarchy or communism âlive,â while revolution is
itself a cooptation of insurrection (see Stirner).
seems like plain anarchism to me. Nothing sticks out about it that would
make this taxonomy appropriate. Maybe its effects have really become
that ubiquitous?*
There is a pretty good thread about this question, from 1/2011 on
anarchistnews.org. It starts out with a long statement about what
insurrectionary anarchy is against (capitalism, government, cultural
standards like the nuclear family, <and all their representations>which
is where the interpretation comes in, of course), and how the poster(s)
cannot say what they are for unless you are working with them (this
seems fairly representative, the point being that what one is for cannot
be spoken of without being co-opted/misunderstood)... Here is a good
bit:
IA mostly responds to the context of an organized left in power and
armed struggle in Italy in the late 70s and 80s. As it is a theoretical
and strategic response to this context, the FAI or other tendencies and
anarchists before this could not be considered âinsurrectionary
anarchist.
(So, this draws a distinction between insurrectionary tactics, which are
old, and âinsurrectionary anarchistâ which starts at a specific time &
place).
This thread also makes clear that i@ has more in common with illegalism
than with other kinds of anarchist thought, and that there is a conflict
between it and anarcho-syndicalism. To me this is where current rhetoric
muddies the waters, since groups like modesto anarcho claim both labels.
Insurrectionary anarchism is distinguished from âplain anarchismâ on
questions of approach more so than on what one is for and against.
IA is thus associated with the critique of formal organization,
practices of informal organization, attack, permanent conflict,
illegalism, and other matters that are primarily practical rather than
ideological.
But beneath this thrust are two clear ideasâone dealing with time and
another with relationshipsâthat are both refusals of mediation. Firstly,
IA is characterized by the rejection of a future revolution (waiting for
it or making progress toward it); instead, insurrection is seen as
something to be immediately practiced. Secondly, IA rejects the bodies
that mediate the spaces between individuals and organizes them in mass
revolutionary activity.
The distinction was first expressed by Stirner, whose ideas have been
enormously influential to all of the well-known insurrectionary
anarchists:
Revolution and insurrection must not be looked upon as synonymous. The
former consists in an overturning of conditions, of the established
condition or status, the State or society, and is accordingly a
political or social act; the latter has indeed for its unavoidable
consequence a transformation of circumstances, yet does not start from
it but from menâs discontent with themselves, is not an armed rising,
but a rising of individuals, a getting up, without regard to the
arrangements that spring from it. The Revolution aimed at new
arrangements; insurrection leads us no longer to let ourselves be
arranged, but to arrange ourselves, and sets no glittering hopes on
âinstitutions.â It is not a fight against the established, since, if it
prospers, the established collapses of itself; it is only a working
forth of me out of the established. If I leave the established, it is
dead and passes into decay. Now, as my object is not the overthrow of an
established order but my elevation above it, my purpose and deed are not
a political or social but (as directed toward myself and my ownness
alone) an egoistic purpose and deed.
things?*
Different analysis, different tactics, different approaches. But the
problem is that those who rail against âinsurrectionaryâ anarchists
almost always use a strawman argument. The insurrectionary anarchists I
know do not ignore, dismiss, or otherwise disregard a class analysis of
capitalism and the state. Those who refer to themselves as âclass
struggleâ anarchists are almost always using that terminology as a
short-cut way of describing their strategies and tactics. More
specifically it appears that they do not reject labor unions as
locations for revolutionary intervention, whereas most other anarchists
(and not just the crazed insurrectionaries) do. Perhaps the main
distinction is manifest around the organizational question; class
struggle anarchists tend to favor formal membership-based cadre
organizations, while insurrectionary anarchists reject them in favor of
networks and informal ones.
I see social war as a reaction to the focus on class war by certain
significant portions of political people. Class war tends to emphasize
rigid distinctions between classes that donât make sense anymore (if
they ever did), and a marxist/economic analysis that doesnât address
many other causes and effects of hierarchy. So social war emphasizes
both that we are all participants in this war (instead of just the
working class-as-revolutionary-agent), and that we are at war with
society, and that society is at war with itself.
That definitely leads to an amorphousness that communists especially (it
seems) donât like to deal with, but to me seems appropriate to the
blurry lines and shifting ground that we deal with all the time.
rationale: social war. Social war is our way of articulating the
conflict of class war, but beyond the limitations of class. Rather than
a working class seeking to affirm ourselves in our endless conflict with
capital, we desire instead to abolish the class relation and all other
relations that reproduce this social order. Social war is the discrete
and ongoing struggle that runs through and negotiates our lived
experience. As agents of chaos, we seek to expose this struggle, to make
it overt. The issue is not violence or non-violence. Whatâs at issue in
these forays against capital is rather the social peace and its
negation. To quote a comrade here in Oakland:*
shattered when we do something; blood is shed when we do nothing, so of
course blood will be shed when we do something.*
effort to rupture the ever-present deadliness of the social peace.*
<right>Occupy Everything</right>
social war: The narrative of âclass struggleâ developed beyond class to
include the complexities and multiplicities of all social relations.
Social war is conflict within all hierarchical social relations.
Social war means society against the state.
The above is from a few sources, and I think is a lot more on target
than what dot eludes to. The whole âwar on societyâ bit is totally
strange to me. More like most of society against a tiny elite that
control state and capital.
Just to clarifyâwhile there is a piece of the âmost of society against a
tiny eliteâ that makes sense (having a defined enemy is one important
perspective), ONLY paying attention to that ignores that we are all part
of the society that we are fighting. Power/hierarchy/authoritarianism
doesnât just exist in some external form, in some easily identified
other (the tiny elite); it is in all of us. it is We⢠(also known as The
Masses) who continue to accept the fucked up situation we are in, We who
have not risen up and cast off the chains. The only way to make sense of
that passivity (as far as I can tell) is to understand that we are all
implicated, even the people who seem to have the most to gain from a
revolution. Society, for lack of a better word.
politics. Anarchism is left but from what I read, left wing is more
liberal while right wing is conservative. Also, it seems that Liberals
promote more government and also advocate discrimination.*
liberal or conservative by nature? Iâm new to politics in general and
would love any answers. To me, liberal and conservative are just words
that keep getting changed along with Americaâs society, but Iâm
wondering how, specifically, Anarchism falls towards the left, which is
marked more âLiberalâ. Any help would be awesome!*
I used to believe anarchists were right-wing for this very reason, and
therefore looked upon them the same as I do neo-cons.
http://www.politicalcompass.org/index
This pretty nifty site rejects the one-axis âLeft-to-Rightâ political
spectrum in favor of a two-axis kind of chart. The X-axis is the
âeconomicâ spectrum, with collectivism/communism on the left and
neo-liberalism/free-market libertarianism on the right. On the Y-axis,
the top is authoritarianism/fascism and the bottom is
libertarianism/anarchism. Obviously itâs not perfect, but I think itâs a
hell of a lot better than the usual narrow depiction of the spectrum.
Some people (probably most people) consider anarchists to be part of the
left because anarchists have frequently (especially historically) called
themselves âanarcho-communistsâ (referring to the desire for communism â
a state-free society, without the interim stages usually insisted on by
people who call themselves just âcommunistsâ). Communists and anarchists
are both considered to be part of the left because of a focus on how the
state and context influences individuals. Ironically, conservatives
usually focus more on individual will power and responsibility (which,
in a society that is set up to be unequal, absolves institutions of
responsibility...).
But there is definitely a significant segment of anarchists who call
themselves neither right nor left.
Okay, but Anarchism is liberal in that it promotes Socialism but
Conservative in its anti-state tendencies? Just seems to be so many
contradictions with this.
Also, being that Conservatives are for more individuality, would
Anarcho-individualism be considered right wing? From what I read, both
Social and Individual Anarchism are opposed to capitalism, making it
more left wing?
dot
Anarchists are not promoting socialism as socialism is currently
understood. That is, socialism is now associated (like communism) with
the states that have called themselves socialist and communist, and
anarchists donât promote states or transitions that go through states.
Itâs clearer to say that anarchism is neither liberal nor conservative,
since both liberalism and conservatism are labels for groups of people
(as well as labels for collections of ideas), with which anarchists
usually have little in common. All anarchists are against capitalism, it
is one of the fundamentals of anarchism. (People who call themselves
anarcho-capitalists are basically playing word games.) And yes,
anarcho-individualism has been attacked by leftists as being right-wing
in its effects if not in intention.
We are against capitalism, but that does not make us left-wing. Most
people on the left wouldnât say that theyâre against capitalism at all,
just that they want a kinder, gentler capitalism.
The word âliberalâ is related to the word âlibertyâ and was originally
used to mean generous or unrestrained. In modern political parlance, it
has come to mean many things, but it usually implies progressivism; the
promotion of change. The word âconservativeâ comes from the word
âconserveâ and suggests maintenance and preservation. This word too has
been bastardized, bent for propagandistic purposes, but it still implies
reverence for the old ways. Thus, liberal politicians advocate reform
and development while conservative ones call for a return to traditional
values.
In the sense that anarchists reject so-called traditional values, and in
the sense that they agitate for a new society that is radically
different from the norm, they are leftists. Further, many people today
consider marxist movements to be a product of the left and capitalist
protractors a part of the right. So, since many anarchists are
socialists, communists, etc; anarchyâespecially European anarchyâis
often placed within the leftist milieu.
Post-left anarchy has developed thought in 6 main areas:
failure, and at key points a counterproductive force historically (âthe
left-wing of capitalâ)critiquing Leftist activists for political
careerism,celebrity culture, self-righteousness, privileged vanguardism,
and martyrdomcritiquing the tendency of Leftists to insulate themselves
in academia, scenes, and cliques while also attempting to
opportunistically manage struggles
a distinct phenomenon in favor of âcritical self-theoryâ at individual
and communal levels
growth-focused modes of organization in favor of temporary, informal,
direct, spontaneous, intimate forms of relationcritiquing Leftist
organizational patternsâ tendencies toward managerialism, reductionism,
professionalism, substitutionism, and ideologycritiquing the tendencies
of unions and Leftist organizations to mimic political parties, acting
as racketeers/mediators, with cadre-based hierarchies of theoretician &
militant or intellectual & grunt, defailting toward
institutionalization, and ritualizing a
meeting-voting-recruiting-marching pattern
victimization-enabled identities and social roles (i.e. affirming rather
than negating gender, class, etc.) and inflicts guilt-induced paralysis,
amongst otherscritiquing single-issue campaigns or orientations
anarchY as a living praxisfocussing on daily life and the
intersectionality thereof rather than dialectics / totalizing narratives
(except anarcho-primitivists tend toward epistemology)emphasizing
personal autonomy and a rejection of work (as forced labor, alienated
labor, workplace-centricity)critiquing Enlightenment notions of
Cartesian dualities, rationalism, humanism, democracy, utopia,
etc.critiquing industrial notions of mass society, production,
productivity, efficiency, âProgressâ, technophilia, civilization (esp.
in anti-civilization tendencies)
I know that post-Leftists are not anarcho-capitalists, so obviously
right wingers are out of the question. But most people who are not
Republicans or Libertarians are either liberals who vote for the
Democrats, or are some variety of Leftists (Socialists, Communists,
etc).
Seems there is a very limited pool of people post-Leftists can work with
if they refuse to work with Leftists. Surely they donât organize with
apathetic or apolitical people only?
It would depend on the situation. I am sure others will have much to say
about this, much of it that will conflict with me, but my take is that
post-left anarchists organize on a temporary basis with those they have
affinity with in order to achieve particular goals.
I donât mean such a broad answer as a cop-out, but rather to distinguish
between the traditional leftist model of organizing (building
institutions, fronts, and infrastructure with the goal of furthering
âthe revolutionâ), and that of the pl@ perspective (finding affinities
that work for a period, and letting those go when they donât). It isnât
a matter of never working with people who identify with the left, but of
always remaining apart from the left, of refusing to be assimilated in
to a mass for the good of the movement. Which tends to piss off lefties.
No post-left anarchist I know categorically refuses to work with
Leftists, we just prefer to not operate in the modes we associate with
the Left. Maybe some of us disassociate with everyone who identifies as
Left or Right, but I doubt that exists as a common pattern.
I talk with open-minded people, and deconstruct the ideologies of
close-minded people. I associate with green anarchists, luddites, &
zero-work advocates & productive play promoters, family, friends, people
who engage in direct action, solidarity unionists, unemployed people,
students, domestic and migrant laborers, festival goers, event
attendees, strangers, travelers, youth, onlookers...I can find at least
some common ground for interaction with most anarchists and point out my
own overlaps with people who do not call themselves anarchists, enough
to find resonance with them. I volunteer with youth and that gives me an
opportunity to engage in an introductory discussion about different
perspectives.
As a pl@ I differ in theory, orientation, & strategy from the Left, but
people who identify with the Left do not necessarily automatically
refuse my preferred methods of association (impermanent, direct,
spontaneous, intimate, mostly but not always informal) nor embody the
celebrity managerialism I loathe. Even if someone endorses bureaucratic
unions or political parties that usually doesnât prevent them from
relating outside of those. I typically âorganizeâ with people to the
extent that we share an affinity, mostly initiated by me interjecting
something critical of the status quo, leading to a search for shared
experiences (eg disliking having a boss, feeling powerless), and common
values (eg self-determination, partnership), refining a mutual critique
to our situation, and finally culminating in some sort of proposition
for action followed by review.
TL;DR: Post-left anarchists I know tend to organize with whomever it
makes sense to do so with at the time for as long as it makes sense, and
involve ourselves in intentional explorations of affinity that allow for
divergence, conflict, and disassociation.
and the massesâ˘
state-sponsored identities (gender, skin color, religion, etc)
I agree with dot, but I think some basics need to be examined even
before her list.
The Left is usually considered by most (sympathetic) commentators to
have something to do with a criticism of (the worst excesses of)
capitalismânaturally depending on how we understand capitalism. The Left
is often therefore equated with a generic Socialism. We have to
acknowledge that Socialism is internally incoherent enough to be able to
accommodate such diverse ideas as Maoism, right-wing (anti-Marxist,
anti-revolutionary) Social Democracy, revolutionary (or reformist)
Marxism, the left wing of the Democratic Party (Kucinich), and some
types of anarchism (NEFAC, syndicalists, pro-democracy folks like
Milstein). What they all share is a desire to use and/or take over most
of the functions of the state in ways that ameliorate those
aforementioned excesses. In this way they remain within the
authoritarian system common to all other forms of tinkering with
institutions of hierarchy and domination.
The reason post-left @s dislike Leftist categories and strategies is
that we (if I may speak for others for the moment) find those categories
and strategies to be historical failures; we judge them failures not
just because stupid people were doing them, but because of the inherent
philosophical problems with them. So a rigid organizational form like a
political party (point a) is a problem not because of its particular
program or platform or internal decision-making process, but because it
is organized as a supposedly representative body (point c) that requires
a division of labor (point b).
Ideological thinking (point d) is a problem because it uses backwards
logic. Ideologists begin from solutions or answers and only later
formulate questionsâthat just by coincidence happen to point precisely
to those solutions or answers. The questions are only questions in a
technical sense because they being with Why What Where Who Which When
How, but they have the (desired/expected) answers imbedded in them. Most
Leftist questions are How statements rather than Why questions. In this
way they remain in line with all other forms of authoritarian or
hierarchical methods of so-called discussion.
Because most forms of Leftism begin as a reaction to the ugly aspects of
capitalism, they all share strategies for curtailing its excesses. One
way to begin that process is to valorize not just work (point f) but
workers as workers, as those whose labor and effort produces the wealth
that is expropriated (by providing workers with a wage lower than the
value of the goods and services their labor goes to produce) by those
who own the means of production (whether capitalists or the state).
Whether workers are conceived of as the Revolutionary Subject of History
or just poor slobs who donât get enough pay and/or benefits, they are
elevated as the primary object (or agent) of salvation.
All leftist strategies are predicated on a redistribution of wealth,
which means that they all wish to maintain methods of calibrating value
in labor, in commodities, and in exchange. This is economy, and along
with retooled mechanisms of statecraft (whether enshrined as government
or the voluntarism so beloved of NGOs), certainly is a decent way of
understanding the primary problems associated with Leftism. It has been
pointed out by the left-anarchist critics of post-left @ that these are
basic anarchist criticisms of capitalism and the state and
authoritarianism in general. Fair enough; not many post-left @s trumpet
their analyses as particularly new or ground-breaking. But one of the
neglected points of post-left @ is that we are critics of false
opposition to capitalism and the state. Where Leftists (and many left
anarchists fall into this category) want to improve the lives of
workers, post-left @s wish to abolish work (as a coercive and separate
sphere of useful endeavor); where Leftists wish to expropriate the means
of production to turn them to social use rather than as generators of
profit, post-left @s wish to abolish economy, and at the very least
facilitate a large-scale discussion of which technologies to maintain
while destroying the ones that most folks donât want or need; where
Leftists want to develop or extend protections or compensations for
categories of people who have been historically oppressed, post-left @s
wish to abolish the ideology of victimization (point e).
Naturally there a ton of questions that arise from this brief overview,
but thatâs as it should be. For me the most interesting aspect of
identifying with post-left @ is that we actually yearn for more
questions than answers; with any luck, thatâs also a way of steering
clear of ideology.
To get to the heart of your question: depends how you define/understand
âsocialismâ (and ��anarchismâ for that matter). If socialism is
characterized by a generic opposition to capitalism, then sure,
anarchists are socialists. If socialism means that the state controls
the production and distribution of goods and services, then no,
anarchists are not socialists. If socialism means that people who have
no direct access to or control of the means of survival without working
or getting economic support from the state will get to have that access
and control, then sure, anarchists are socialists. If socialism means
that hierarchical institutions that foster a division of labor will
continue under the control and direction of the best and brightest, then
no, anarchists are not socialists.
As is the case with many of the questions being posed, there are at
least two or three more questions that need to be asked before a proper
answer is attempted, let alone agreed upon.
I define identity politics mostly negativelyâie, I think that most
people who use identity to mean something, tend to drastically simplify
and over-generalize what it means in a personâs (and/or a peopleâs) life
(whatever âitâ might beâusually race, class, sex, sexual preference,
physical ability, etc). So I get very wary when people talk about
identity. Also I think people talk about identity (or use identity-coded
language) as a way to identify themselves and each other as belonging to
a particular group (we are the people who use these words and by doing
so indicate that we care about the following things in the correct
manner...)
That said, I do think that socially created/understood markers do mean
something. I do think that being poor, rich, paraplegic, queer,
able-bodied, brown-haired, balding (etc) means *some*thing. I just donât
think that people know what it means, or have figured out a good way to
think about what it means, much less to talk about what it means.
Answers to this question will be determined by what anarchists mean by
âpoliticsâ which is a weighty question unto itself. Some answers to that
have been attempted on this site. To focus on the identity portion of
the term: Like dot, I tend to use the phrase as shorthand for certain
unfavorable approaches. These approaches tend to focus on a particular
identity group to the (near) exclusion of other subjects for analysis,
theory, and practice. The epitome of identity political analysis views a
specific form of oppression as the main oppression from which all others
stem. It then becomes hard to arrive at coherent analysis of other forms
of oppression. Even much of economic analysis can turn into identity
politics in the form of fetishization of workers.
Of course, identity is important. First of all because it is socially
enforced. Second because it is often internalized. For the foreseeable
future people will continue to distinguish themselves based on all sorts
of identity components, and our social experience will thus be informed
by vast categories of wildly diverse individuals. There is useful
information to be gleaned from the theorization about different identity
groups to which people assign themselves or are assigned by others.
There are tens of thousands of years of history based on identity
concepts like Woman or Slave or Deviant. Even if it is desirable to move
away from using such stock categories for the individuals that compose
society, these concepts are highly embedded in the culture and are
therefore important touchstones in any good analysis.
It is when we submit to essentialist thinking about these groups that we
limit the potential for our own identity-creation. For my whole life I
have taken it for granted that because I have certain sex
characteris-tics, I am a man. Everyone I have ever encountered has
treated me like a man (or boy), and yet there has always been some
nagging doubt. It is only recently that I am able to express that,
though I am easily categorizable biologically, that I have no affinity
to any gender identity. Though I now understand this, I am still stuck
in a society that wants to pigeon-hole me in the male gender. This is
just as disconcerting coming from leftist feminists as from aggressive
men.
So as an alternative to the extremes of identity politics and attempted
identity-blindness I try to understand peoplesâ own self-identity
constructions.
To clarify a bit, I find that identity discourse is often interesting
and worthwhile. As an example; I know a twin who has developed their own
unique discourse about the prejudices and stereotypes of âsingletsâ
toward âmultiplesâ. They have actually been asked such things as âHow do
you know which one you are?â!
Itâs the subsumation of all other discourses about oppressive behavior
to one particular identity discourse that I would disdainfully call
âidentity politicsâ.
Consensus means full agreement reached between all persons within a
group or set.
The term is used by anarchists as well as many others to refer to
internal decision-making processes in which full agreement is required
in decisions that (significantly) affect others in the group or are made
in the name of the whole group.
Generally it is understood that individuals and affinities always have
the power to act autonomously, and that consensus is needed only to
claim the approval of a larger body or make decisions that affect others
in the body. Unfortunately, however, consensus practice often finds
individuals and affinities acting subservient to the larger group and
unnecessarily requesting approval for insignificant decisions or for
decisions that would better be done autonomously. Individuals also often
forget that if they want something to happen they may have to do it
themselves. (A group cannot do anything unless individuals within it
take initiative). A common argument for why using consensus process
opposes hierarchy is something resembling: âIt allows us to make
decisions in the process of fighting against systems of hierarchy while
also not making those decisions hierarchically.â
But the word âhierarchyâ originally refers not to authorities having
power of decision-making, but rather to spiritual beings holding a
sacred power (of closeness to God). This meaning was transposed to the
Catholic hierarchy (made up of persons supposedly having sacred power),
and this transposition gave hierarchy an embodied and systematic force.
Following this, it could be argued that hierarchy originates in the
power that ideas have when held above us as sacred, and that this power
can take on a social and material form. (This would be too long of a
divergence to go into depth on here, but you could refer to Max Stirner
for more on the topic.) Perhaps, then, the issues I described above
concerning consensus, such as the inability of the individual or
affinity to feel able to act autonomously from the consensus-making
group, are related to a kind of hierarchy in which the sacredness of
consensus can have a power over the will of each individual whoâs part
of the whole.
Others will point to issues of social status, identity politics, etc as
âthe hidden hierarchies within consensus.â These claims may be true but
often the approach seeks to reduce everyone to a lowest common
denominator, equality, in which everyone is inoffensive, and walking on
the eggshells of their so-called privileges, which certainly is no way
to live freely much less constitute a force to destroy the immense
institutional structures of hierarchy that are this society.
An anarchist has a larger view of the world than its political systems
and politicians allow for. We must keep ahold of that perspective and it
is not a simple task; we are constantly bombarded with the simplistic
messages and world views conveyed by commercialism and politics. To
effectively vote, one must engage with the dynamics and arguments that
are being voted upon and this will necessarily narrow oneâs perspective.
It is not that the act of voting in a vacuum is bad or destructive, in
fact it just doesnât matter. But engaging in the liberal/conservative
banter renders one relatively thoughtless.
There have been many arguments made against voting that deserve to be
listed: here are three...
possibility (and an overlyvalorized one) among many ways to resolve
conflict or make decisions in a group, and is based on competition
instead of on finding the best option.
false choices and confirm our own powerlessness over a system that is
corrupt at its core.
soul who might somehow find themselves in a position of power (as if the
process of getting into office itself is not one of compromise and
power-brokering), this person will be forced to work the system or never
get anything done. Inevitably, campaign promises that sound lovely will
either not happen, or will happen in ways that lead to worse results.
The word âvotingâ, since it includes both electoral politics and
signifying oneâs preference for a certain resolution, seems rather
vague. Etymologically it comes from âa vow to do somethingâ, even more
vague.
Reasons I wouldnât vote (mostly in elections):
Futility. Trying to elect a ruler in any system competent enough to gain
a monopoly probably would not fundamentally challenge that system.
Distraction. I would not desire to empower an elite at the expense of
everyday people. Empowering one sector of a population at the expense of
everyone else would only at best distract me from actualizing anarchic
relationships or demolishing hierarchical ones. Example: guerilla
gardening, Food Not Bombs, and Black Panther food distribution offer
useful examples of autonomy from the welfare state.
Insufficiency. I can understand, and feel for, people voting in
elections out of a perspective of self-preservation, or against their
own enslavement. For example, a womyn trying to elect a politician who
opposes the criminalization of abortion, or a man trying to elect a
politician that opposes military conscription. At the same time,
bandaids do not cure diseases, and shuffling a deck or changing the
deckâs players does not change the cards.
Competition. Representative democracy/aristocracy institutionalizes
competing factions, with all of the pitfalls of politics in place.
Bureaucracy. Mass organizations tend towards sluggishness, and other
hindrances. More futility. Even if I voted for someone to introduce
systemic instability in furtherance of revolutionary conditions, that
one vote would still count as much as a drop in an ocean with todayâs
population sizes and the notion of âone person, one voteâ.
Incompatibility. Representation relies on reduction and substitution,
and always diminishes the represented. By necessity political
representation filters out aspects and experiences, especially when
politics removes representatives from the community/ context they
supposedly represent.
Inconsistency. I would not willingly compromise certain convictions,
namely, anti-authoritarianism. So when would I vote? If it seemed
effective, empowering, sufficient, non-oppressive, non-exploitative,
direct, compatible, and consistent with my principles, I would. I would
vote to abolish a law if I felt my single vote had a chance of changing
the outcome. I would probably also vote under duress. And I vote in
consensus decisions, formally and informally, quite often.
I was just listening to a philosophy professor talk about fear (mostly
in the context of fear as a tool of politicians) and he mentioned that
while one would think that universities are a place where fear is less
of an issue, professors (he included himself) were some of the most
timid people heâs ever spent time with. (He went on to say that the
academy is a place where people are always watching, always competing,
and always threatened by what can be taken awayâor not given in the
first place.) Professors are people who have shown that they are willing
to abide by the rules set up to contain and restrict creativity (to
color inside the lines).
The academy is like politics in the sense that people who are anarchists
or anarchist-friendly are frequently tempted to combine their anarchist
ideas with getting a job, or working within the system. But the academy
is a deeply hierarchical and authoritarian system, one that is designed
to co-opt new ideas and integrate them into first the academy and then
the larger society (capitalism runs on edgy new things to sell to people
who are dissatisfied, and sustains itself partly by integrating new
behaviors and ideas instead of resisting them).
Universities operate as a) screens to winnow out uncontrollables, b)
training camps for acceptable thinking, c) think tanks for corporations
and statists (think about the vast amount of information that exists in
all those theses and projects and who actually uses that information).
I have no problem with people who view school as a job. I know one
professor with politics I trust (who just got laid off, btw), who views
it as exactly that. My issue is when anarchists or
students-interested-in-anarchy extol the virtues of academia as the job
to have, as a valuable organizing position, as a way to make change. And
with how anarchists/students-interested-in-anarchy (regardless of their
motivations and the purity of their desires) both feed information into
the system that is against us (to the extent that anarchy informs their
studies), and frequently use the anarchist scene as fodder for their
professional lives.
The Situationist International, especially thesis 91â94 of Debordâs
Society of the Spectacle, formulated the clearest anarchist critique of
anarchism in the 1960s. This critique represents for many anarchists
(specifically anarchists who have since declared anarchism to be
distinct from the leftist heritage of Communism, Social Democracy, and
State Socialism) the beginning of a new era for anarchist thinking and
practice.
The inspiration for this thinking can be seen in the critique of work &
the left (Bob Black & Anarchy: a Journal of Desire Armed), an ongoing
dialogue with anarchists and so-called post-situationists since the
1970s, and the cultural influence that the SI had vis-a-vis punk rock
and bohemian counter-culture ever since. Here is a summary of the
critique of anarchists in Debordâs SoS.
1) Bakunin critiqued Marx for declaring that a stateless society must
pass through a âdictatorship of the proletariatâ while in practice
participating in a conspiratorial group that acted outside, and above,
the First International.
This is addressed in modern anarchist practice by a demand for
transparency in all aspects of organizational issues and an attempt to
have anarchist practice be indistinguishable from anarchist goals.
2) The ideology of pure freedom (Debordâs term for anarchist political
philosophy), flattens the difficulties of political struggles in reality
while demanding the all-encompassing goal of the total negation of the
current order. Both mystical and doctrinaire, anarchists have remained
emblematic of the soul of struggle and its impossibility.
This critique is ignored or addressed by different an-archist tendencies
in different ways. The most clear engagement of it is the Italian
anarchist analysis from the 1970s that has resulted in the simple
practice of Insurrectionary Anarchism.
3) Consensus and unanimity in anarchist practice (especially in the
Spain Revolution) has been a strategic failure. This critique has been
contested by anarchist practice and success in non-revolutionary moments
like the anti-globalization movement, alcoholics anonymous, and the
Occupy movement. The critique of anarchists as âspecialists of freedomâ
still rings true.
4) Anarchists believe that revolution is immanent. It is possible at any
time and does not require a particular historical process to unfold.
This faith means that there is not anarchist clarity around how to
extend partial victories. This critique still holds true and can be seen
as recently as the Occupy Movement.
care, like disabled people or the mentally ill.
One argument is that people will have more time, energy, and capacity to
care for other people because they will not be subsumed by capitalist
concerns (making enough money to survive themselves), and will be aware
of their own capacity to care for other people (instead of thinking that
they are not skilled enough, or not allowed to, take care of people).
Another argument is that there will be fewer instances of disability and
mental illness because the human world will make more sense.
Another argument is that itâs not awesome now, so changes are unlikely
to make things worse, even if they donât make them tons better.
was being robbed at gunpoint?
the till. You are old and weak, and believe that your ideology is some
sort of shield. A young man in a ski mask walks in and pulls out an semi
automatic handgun. The man asks for the money in the till, and all the
money that you have in your pockets. The man beats you senseless. The
man takes the money and runs away.*
in the robbery investigation?*
the suspect would you attend the preliminary examination to testify?
Would you testify at the trial? Would you subject yourself to the
court-power of the subpoena?*
The answer is either completely obvious, or unknowable (well, actually
both).
The straight answer to your question is no, the anarchist would not call
the cops, nor participate in the legal investigation in any way, because
the anarchist part is pretty straightforward.
The actual answer is that anarchists live in the world, and have
multiple motivations (frequently conflicting) as does every other group
(and individual). So the clerk part could potentially outweigh the
anarchist part, or the scared person part could potentially outweigh the
anarchist part, at least in that moment, or for this situation.
The question assumes not only that the clerk is frail (hence presumably
unable to fight backâalthough there is nothing to keep such a person
from having weapons of her own), and that the clerk does not know the
robber, and that the clerk is alone (without social resources to do
something about the robber). These are all fair assumptions given the
reality of life today, but deserve also to be called into question,
since all of those pieces of the question are ones that anarchists want
to do something about, not just the part about what happens when someone
hurts someone else.
aggression, and abuse?
that are directly linked to the maintenance of the political status quo.
On this basis, they must be challenged. However, the majority of us
would feel compelled to call the police should we be under attack. How
may an anarchist society reconcile this need for protection, with the
need for liberty and freedom from authority?*
Calling the police does not not always bring about âprotectionâ.
Protection vs liberty and freedom from authority, may be more closely
linked then we are otherwise lead to believe. It could be that perhaps
these âneedâ no reconciliation whatsoever.
Many peopleânot just anarchistsâdo not call the police when they are
threatened. The protection the police (claim to) offer is pretty
specific and extremely limited.
The fact that some people still donât think they have any other recourse
has as much to do with the fact that police are seen to be the only
legitimate users-of-force in this society, as it does with actually
protecting ourselves. Police, for a variety of reasons (not all of them
even in their control), also tend to escalate conflicts rather than
actually resolve anything. One of the basics of anarchist thought is
direct action, which means that we handle things ourselves. Handling
things can mean a wide variety of things, from violence to mediation (or
all of the above), and could include various numbers of people (ie â
âusâ is contextual).
what do we do about the rapists and murderers who are already in jail?
If we were to topple the state tomorrow all those people do not just
disappear.*
Who is we? What is violence? How are you picturing the state getting
toppled? Surely these are all crucial parts of the question?
I canât figure out how your question makes sense outside of a classic
revolutionary scenario (suddenly wetm have the power to decide how to
punish bad people, but theyâre still defined as bad by the same
constructs that some of us are fighting against). Put another way, the
people who have the violence done against them (and their friends and
family) would presumably be the people who would decide what to doâand
maybe this would include the friends and family of the person who done
wrong, and maybe the wrong-doer as well, depending on the situation.
Or maybe, no one would decide anything. Maybe people would just move
away, like they do now, and/or get ostracized by some folks and not by
others...I expect there would be a lot of different ways to deal with
messed up behavior, and all of them would work in some ways and not work
in others.
It sounds like youâre assuming a lot of things would stay the sameâlike
society-as-a-group-of-people-who-are-fundamentally-estranged-from-each-other
and who-have-and-use-the-power-to-control-other-peopleâs-lives.
I reject that.
We open up the prisons and start over with everyone. Some fucked up shit
will happen, no doubt. But the revolution (whatever that means) is not
about not-having-fucked-up-shit-happen. Itâs about changing the range,
the level, the scope of the fucked up shit that happens.
I love the way dot says it. âwe open up the prisons and start over with
everyoneâ but in my opinion those who disagree with anarchy will
probably start a groupâsimilar to policeâwho would âget ridâ of the
criminals. not because they would be paid in any way but because they
feel itâs important to âget rid ofâ the criminals.
One of the many frustrating aspects of the judicial system, for me, is
the acceptance of the idea that we canât decide what is right or wrong
for ourselves; that someone we have no connection to, who knows nothing
of us or our situation, is allowed to decide whether or not we have been
wronged by another and then make a decision about the fate of that
person. Is it so crazy to think that we could empower ourselves to take
back that authority in our own lives and communities?
Example (not the best, but there really never is a perfect example). If
someone breaks into my home, I donât desire to call a stranger (the
police) to make them whisk the person off, so that another stranger (the
judge/jury) can decided whether or not they were really in my home and
whether or not that was okay. I should be able to confront them at that
moment, in that place. In the time it would take to call the police, one
could instead call friends and neighbors if they felt they needed
someone else involved.
When you get into more serious matters, like instances of sexual assault
or murder, things will always be tricky. But the current âjusticeâ
system has proven that it is ineffective at both identifying the correct
perpetrator, and stopping them from doing something again (except in
cases of lifelong imprisonment/ death). Whose to say that the people
directly involved couldnât do a better job or finding out who did it and
finding a correct solution. And, while I do recognize the problematic
aspects of âvigilante justiceâ, I personally find no fault in physically
confronting someone who has harmed you or telling them that they must
leave town. But there is also room for talking through things,
understanding a situation, learning from our mistakes, and moving on in
ways deemed appropriate by those directly involved.
And we must recognize the cause of most crime. Personally, I donât
beleive that people are born murderers or rapists. Society, the
conditions of their lives (especially as children), and a variety of
other factors affect what decisions people make. So, we must take a look
at the causes of violence in the first place. The disempowerment that
comes from economic, racial, class based, etc oppression that may cause
someone to lash out and seek power over another. The obsession with
power that this society tries to force-feed us that causes those with
power to desire more at any cost. The message that empowerment or power
over are both powerâand therefore interchangeable, equal, and necessary
to our well-being.
I apologize if this sounds vague or intangible, but the abolition of
prisons is far more complicated than the simple destruction of a few
walls. We could rid ourselves of prisons tomorrow, but we would find
that people would simply replace them. Same goes for police; we could
kill all cops, but new cops, even if under a different name, would pop
up everywhere As long as there is a need for such institutions, they
will continue to exist. We need to change the way we view ourselves,
each other, our communities, our relations, etc. We must rid ourselves
of a need for prisons.
First and foremost we need to empower ourselves, our friends, our
communities, to take back that control, to recognize that we donât need
the mediation of strangers to decide what is good or bad, right or wrong
for us.
Finally:
The question itself is mildly absurd. The prison system isnât something
that can be done away with overnight. As long as we have system where
there are âcriminalsâ there will be jails, so that question kinda puts
the cart before the horse.
Secondly, we shouldnât do anything to/with them. What options do we
have? It would be ridiculous to re-incarcerate them in an âanarchist
prisonâ, put them through âaccountability processesâ or exile them from
communities they arenât a part of. I would argue that we simply let them
be. Most people in jail just want to get out and get on with their
lives. Those who continue to cause harm will be dealt with by those it
relates to, but I would speculate that this would be a small minority of
cases.
murder?
Iâm personally an anarcho-syndicalist; but, this is something that
perplexes me often. I donât see how a mutualistic society could intern
people, without state backing.
And you hardly want private police, like the cough anarcho-capitalists.
There are so many clarifying questions/ objections required by your
casual statement... For an anarchist to use a term like âcrimeâ is
automatically a problem; such a concept is meaningless in a context
where deviant (non-normative) behavior is dealt with by the affected
individuals making up a community/commune/affinity group (or whatever
other meaningful level of social organization you like). Thatâs commonly
called Direct Action. âCrimeâ is a legal category, requiring an
institutionalized system of allegedly neutral conflict resolution to
take the place of what the statists see as their purview alone:
retaliation, retribution, vengeance (the pretense to rehabilitation
should be, by now, completely discredited). This usually takes the form
of arrest, trial, and incarceration. In short, punishment for behaving
outside the parameters decided by those who run the State. By taking the
response to deviance out of the hands of those directly affected, the
legal authorities are merely delegitimizing (and making it a crime!) the
autonomy and cohesion of any meaningful level of social organization.
What would happen in an anarchist society to deal with rape and murder
would probably look a lot like what happens in other non-statist
cultures when someone does something particularly nasty: the survivor,
the family and friends decide how to proceed, whether itâs one or more
of the following. Public shaming or beating; concern coupled with
compassion and care; expulsion; executionâand a million other
possibilities in between. All options are on the table, unlike what
happens in statist cultures, where the authorities decide the punishment
in a sham neutrality for the good of âthe people.â
Anarchy Alive! â Uri Gordon
An examination of contested issues between and among anarchists. The
questions of Violence, Power, Technology, and Nationalism are each given
their own chapters.
Anarchy Works â Peter Gelderloos
A cross-cultural examination of how anarchist principles have worked,
whether the practitioners called themselves anarchists or not.
Recipes for Disaster â CrimethInc.
Big and small, legal and il-, 62 recipes that run the gamut from
dumspter-diving to banner drops, open relationships to locking down
streets, monkeywrenching to coalition building.
Anarchy after Leftism â Bob Black
Blackâs response to Murray Bookchinâs Social Anarchism or Lifestyle
Anarchism. Black accuses Bookchin of being a closeted authoritarian,
city-statist and Marxist with a penchant for high tech and the Athenian
polis. Black defends what he calls heterodox or post-leftist anarchism,
a kind of anti-work, individualist, and moderately primitivist form of
anarchism.
The Anarchist Tension â Alfredo M. Bonanno
One of the most influential (along with Armed Joy and At Daggers Drawn)
of the insurrectionary writings. Challenges anarchists to resist dogma
and easy answers.
anything written by Fredy Perlman (Against (His)Story, Against Leviathan
would be a good start)
To be healthy and sane we need to be grounded in a more direct
relationship with nature and with other people in comprehensible,
face-to-face communities. Leviathanic civilization destroys these basic
relationships â hence the pathology of the modern era. This book covers
all this. Itâs deep, itâs allegorical, itâs like nothing youâve ever
read before.
boloâbolo â p.m.
A sketch of how a future anarchist society could work, the only utopia
with enough diversity to deserve the name anarchist.
Society of the Spectacle â Guy Debord
One of the main texts of the Situationists, explaining (in aphorisms)
the concept of the Spectacle as the defining impetus of western culture,
one that is, through consumption, continually searching for meaning.
(1937-) A main theorist of contemporary insurrectionary anarchism who
wrote essays such as Armed Joy (for which he was imprisoned for 18
months by the Italian government), The Anarchist Tension and others; an
editor of Anarchismo Editions and many other publications, only some of
which have been translated into English. He has been involved in the
anarchist movement for over thirty years.
(1814â1876) A well-known Russian revolutionary and philosopher, theorist
of collectivist anarchism. He has also often been called the father of
anarchist theory in general. Despite (or because of) criminal status,
Bakunin gained great influence with the youth in Russia and all of
Europe. He was involved in the insurrection in Lyon, which foreshadowed
the Paris Commune.
In 1868, Bakunin joined the International Working Menâs Association, a
federation of trade union organizations with sections in most European
countries. The 1872 Hague Congress was dominated by a struggle between
Marx and his followers who argued for parliamentary electoral
participation and a faction around Bakunin who opposed it. Bakuninâs
faction lost the vote, and he was eventually expelled for maintaining a
secret organisation within the international. The anarchists insisted
the congress was rigged, and so held their own conference of the
International in Switzerland. From 1870 to 1876, he wrote much of his
seminal work such as Statism and Anarchy and God and the State.
A French writer, once a Marxist theoretician and member of the
International Communist Party. After collecting and publishing a great
amount of historical documents from left communist currents, and
analysing the most recently discovered writings of Marx, in the early
70s Camatte abandoned the Marxist perspective. He decided instead that
capitalism had succeeded in shaping humanity to its profit, and that
every kind of ârevolutionâ was thus impossible; that the working class
was nothing more than an aspect of capital, unable to supersede its
situation; that any future revolutionary movement would basically
consist of a struggle between humanity and capital itself, rather than
between classes; and that capital has become totalitarian in structure,
leaving nowhere and no-one outside its domesticating influence. This
pessimism about revolutionary perspective is accompanied by the idea
that we can âleave the worldâ and live closer to nature, and stop
harming children and distorting their naturally sane spirit.
Monsieur Dupont is a duo of ex-activist communists in the UK, who wrote
Nihilist Communism, in which they posit the irrelevance of most of the
agitational activities of people who want foundational political and
social change, partly because these âpro-revolutionariesâ are inculcated
by the same society that they are challenging, and partly because
dramatic social change, if it comes at all (which it is likely not to),
will only come from âthe essential proletariatâ, which are the workers
who control things that the system absolutely relies on (power,
transportation, etc). Frère Dupont, author of species being, is one of
the two.
(1870â1936) an anarchist known for his political activism and writing, a
leading member of the anarchist movement in the early 20^(th) century.
Soon after his arrival in New York City, Berkman became an anarchist
through his involvement with groups that had formed to campaign to free
the men convicted of the 1886 Haymarket bombing. He came under the
influence of Johann Most, the best-known anarchist in the United States,
and an advocate of propaganda of the deedâattentat, or violence carried
out to encourage the masses to revolt.
He attempted to assassinate businessman Henry Clay Frick as an act of
propaganda of the deed. Frick survived the attempt on his life, and
Berkman served 14 years in prison. His experience in prison was the
basis for his first book, Prison Memoirs of an Anarchist.
Berkman voiced his opposition to the Soviet use of violence and the
repression of independent voices in his 1925 book, The Bolshevik Myth.
While living in France, Berkman continued his work in support of the
anarchist movement, producing the classic exposition of anarchist
principles, Now and After: The ABC of Communist Anarchism. Suffering
from ill health, Berkman committed suicide in 1936.
(1866â1912) A prolific American anarchist writer and speaker, she
opposed the state, marriage, and the domination of religion in sexuality
and womenâs lives. She began her activist career in the freethought
movement. Her political perspective shifted throughout her life,
eventually leading her to become an outspoken proponent of âanarchism
without adjectives.â
For several years she associated primarily with the American
individualist anarchist milieu. Eventually, however, she rejected
individualism.
âSocialism and Communism both demand a degree of joint effort and
administration which would beget more regulation than is wholly
consistent with ideal Anarchism; Individualism and Mutualism, resting
upon property, involve a development of the private policeman not at all
compatible with my notion of freedom.âInstead, she became one of the
most prominent advocates of anarchism without adjectives. In The Making
of an Anarchist, she wrote, âI no longer label myself otherwise than as
âAnarchistâ simplyâ.
(1931â1994) A French Marxist theorist, writer, filmmaker, member of the
Letterist International, founder of a Letterist faction, and founding
member of the Situationist International (SI). He was also briefly a
member of Socialisme ou Barbarie (a French-based radical libertarian
socialist group of the post-World War II period).
Debord joined the Letterist International when he was 19. A schism
birthed several factions of Letterists, one of which was decidedly led
by Debord. In the 1960s, Debord led the Situationist International
group, which influenced the Paris Uprising of 1968. Some consider his
book The Society of the Spectacle to be a catalyst for the uprising.
The FederaciĂłn Anarquista IbĂŠrica (FAI, Iberian Anarchist Federation) is
a Spanish organization of anarchist (anarcho-syndicalist and
anarchist-communist) militants inside the ConfederaciĂłn Nacional del
Trabajo (CNT) anarcho-syndicalist union. It is often abbreviated as
CNT-FAI because of the close relationship between the two organizations.
The FAI publishes the periodical Tierra y Libertad. It was founded in
Valencia in 1927 to campaign for keeping the CNT on an anarchist path.
It viewed the CNT as having become a mediator between labour and
capital, rather than representative of the working class.
(1869 â1940) An anarchist known for her political activism, writing, and
speeches, she played a pivotal role in the development of anarchist
political philosophy in North America and Europe in the first half of
the 20^(th) century. Attracted to anarchism after the Haymarket affair,
she became a writer and a renowned lecturer on anarchist philosophy,
womenâs rights, and social issues, attracting crowds of thousands. In
1906, Goldman founded the anarchist journal Mother Earth .
Her writing and lectures spanned a wide variety of issues, including
prisons, atheism, freedom of speech, militarism, capitalism, marriage,
free love, homosexuality, and appreciation of Nietzsche. Although she
distanced herself from first-wave feminism and its efforts toward
womenâs suffrage, she developed new ways of incorporating gender
politics into anarchism.
After the outbreak of the Spanish Civil War, she traveled to Spain to
support the anarchist revolution there. She died in Toronto on May 14,
1940, aged 70.
An anonymous group of French intellectuals named as the authors of The
Coming Insurrection, a call to arms along the lines of the
Situationists.
(1842â1921) A Russian prince, zoologist, evolutionary theorist,
philosopher, scientist, pacifist, revolutionary, economist, activist,
geographer, writer, and one of the worldâs foremost anarcho-communists.
Kropotkin advocated a communist society free from central government and
based on voluntary associations be-tween workers. He wrote many books,
pamphlets and articles, the most prominent being The Conquest of Bread
and Fields, Factories and Workshops, and his principal scientific
offering, Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution. He also contributed the
article on anarchism to the EncyclopĂŚdia Britannica Eleventh Edition.
Mutual Aid provided an alternative view on human survival to the claims
of interpersonal competition and natural hierarchy proffered at the time
by some âsocial Darwinistsâ. He argued âthat it was an evolutionary
emphasis on cooperation instead of competition in the Darwinian sense
that made for the success of species, including the human.â
(1844â1900) was a German philosopher, poet, cultural critic and
classical philologist. He wrote critical texts on religion, morality,
contemporary culture, philosophy and science, displaying a fondness for
metaphor, irony and aphorism.
Nietzscheâs influence remains substantial within and beyond philosophy,
notably in existentialism, nihilism, and postmodernism. His style and
radical questioning of the value and objectivity of truth have resulted
in much commentary and interpretation, mostly in the continental
tradition. His key ideas include the death of God, the Ăbermensch, the
eternal recurrence, the Apollonian and Dionysian dichotomy,
perspectivism, and the will to power. Central to his philosophy is the
idea of âlife-affirmationâ, which involves an honest questioning of all
doctrines that drain lifeâs expansive energies, however socially
prevalent and radical those views might be.
The pen name of Abele Rizieri Ferrari (1890â1922), Italian individualist
anarchist, illegalist, and anti-fascist poet, philosopher, and militant,
now mostly known for his book (posthumously published), Toward the
Creative Nothing (Verso il nulla creatore).
He discovered Errico Malatesta, Peter Kropotkin, Henrik Ibsen and
Friedrich Nietzsche, and especially Max Stirner. From 1908 on he
embraced individualist anarchism. In 1910, he was charged with the
burning of a local church and spent three months in prison, but his
participation in the fire was never proved. A year later, he went on the
lam because the police wanted him for theft and robbery.
As the Great War approached he deserted his regiment on April 26, 1918
and was sentenced to death by a military tribunal. He left his village
and fled, propagating the desertion from the Army and the armed uprising
against the state. By the early 1920s Italy was about to be taken over
by Fascism. He decided to go underground and in 1922 he joined the gang
of the famous robber of anarchist inspiration: Sante Pollastro, and was
killed in a shoot-out.
(1934â1985) was an author, publisher and activist. His most popular
work, the book Against His-Story, Against Leviathan!, details the rise
of state domination with a retelling of history through the Hobbesian
metaphor of the Leviathan. The book remains a major source of
inspiration for anti-civilisation perspectives in contemporary
anarchism. His work both as an author and publisher has been very
influential on modern anarchist thought.
(1809â1865) was a French politician, mutualist philosopher, economist,
and socialist. He was a member of the French Parliament, and he was the
first person to call himself an âanarchistâ. He is considered among the
most influential theorists and organisers of anarchism. After the events
of 1848 he began to call himself a federalist.
The name of a French philosophical journal, founded in 1999 with an aim
to ârecreate the conditions of another community.â It was created by
various writers and dissolved in 2001 following the attacks of September
11, 2001. Tiqqun is also, more generally, the name of the philosophical
concept which stems from these texts, and is often used in a broad sense
to name the many publications containing the journalâs texts, in order
to designate âa point of spirit from which these writings come.â
The Situationist International (SI) was an internationalist group of
revolutionaries based mainly in Europe. It was founded in 1957 and
reached its peak of influence in the general strike of May 1968 in
France.
With ideas rooted in Marxism and the 20^(th) century European artistic
avant-gardes, they advocated experiences of life alternative to those
allowed by advanced capitalism, for the fulfillment of human desires.
They suggested and experimented with the construction of âsituations,â
which were environments favorable for the fulfillment of such desires.
Their theoretical work peaked with the highly influential book Society
of the Spectacle. The SI was dissolved in 1972.
A school of neo-Marxist interdisciplinary social theory, initially
consisting of dissident Marxists who believed that some of Marxâs
followers parroted a narrow selection of Marxâs ideas, usually in
defense of orthodox Communist parties. Many of the Frankfurt School
theorists believed that traditional Marxist theory could not adequately
explain the turbulent and unexpected development of capitalist societies
in the 20^(th) century. Critical of both capitalism and Soviet
socialism, their writings pointed to the possibility of an alternative
path to social development.