đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș noam-chomsky-the-responsibility-of-intellectuals.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:00:27. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Responsibility of Intellectuals Author: Noam Chomsky Date: February 23, 1967 Language: en Topics: intellectuals, intellectualism, responsibility Source: Retrieved on 30th October 2020 from https://chomsky.info/19670223/ Notes: The New York Review of Books, February 23, 1967
TWENTY-YEARS AGO, Dwight Macdonald published a series of articles in
Politics on the responsibility of peoples and, specifically, the
responsibility of intellectuals. I read them as an undergraduate, in the
years just after the war, and had occasion to read them again a few
months ago. They seem to me to have lost none of their power or
persuasiveness. Macdonald is concerned with the question of war guilt.
He asks the question: To what extent were the German or Japanese people
responsible for the atrocities committed by their governments? And,
quite properly, he turns the question back to us: To what extent are the
British or American people responsible for the vicious terror bombings
of civilians, perfected as a technique of warfare by the Western
democracies and reaching their culmination in Hiroshima and Nagasaki,
surely among the most unspeakable crimes in history. To an undergraduate
in 1945â46âto anyone whose political and moral consciousness had been
formed by the horrors of the 1930s, by the war in Ethiopia, the Russian
purge, the âChina Incident,â the Spanish Civil War, the Nazi atrocities,
the Western reaction to these events and, in part, complicity in
themâthese questions had particular significance and poignancy.
With respect to the responsibility of intellectuals, there are still
other, equally disturbing questions. Intellectuals are in a position to
expose the lies of governments, to analyze actions according to their
causes and motives and often hidden intentions. In the Western world, at
least, they have the power that comes from political liberty, from
access to information and freedom of expression. For a privileged
minority, Western democracy provides the leisure, the facilities, and
the training to seek the truth lying hidden behind the veil of
distortion and misrepresentation, ideology and class interest, through
which the events of current history are presented to us. The
responsibilities of intellectuals, then, are much deeper than what
Macdonald calls the âresponsibility of people,â given the unique
privileges that intellectuals enjoy.
The issues that Macdonald raised are as pertinent today as they were
twenty years ago. We can hardly avoid asking ourselves to what extent
the American people bear responsibility for the savage American assault
on a largely helpless rural population in Vietnam, still another
atrocity in what Asians see as the âVasco da Gama eraâ of world history.
As for those of us who stood by in silence and apathy as this
catastrophe slowly took shape over the past dozen yearsâon what page of
history do we find our proper place? Only the most insensible can escape
these questions. I want to return to them, later on, after a few
scattered remarks about the responsibility of intellectuals and how, in
practice, they go about meeting this responsibility in the mid-1960s.
---
IT IS THE RESPONSIBILITY of intellectuals to speak the truth and to
expose lies. This, at least, may seem enough of a truism to pass over
without comment. Not so, however. For the modern intellectual, it is not
at all obvious. Thus we have Martin Heidegger writing, in a pro-Hitler
declaration of 1933, that âtruth is the revelation of that which makes a
people certain, clear, and strong in its action and knowledgeâ; it is
only this kind of âtruthâ that one has a responsibility to speak.
Americans tend to be more forthright. When Arthur Schlesinger was asked
by The New York Times in November, 1965, to explain the contradiction
between his published account of the Bay of Pigs incident and the story
he had given the press at the time of the attack, he simply remarked
that he had lied; and a few days later, he went on to compliment the
Times for also having suppressed information on the planned invasion, in
âthe national interest,â as this term was defined by the group of
arrogant and deluded men of whom Schlesinger gives such a flattering
portrait in his recent account of the Kennedy Administration. It is of
no particular interest that one man is quite happy to lie in behalf of a
cause which he knows to be unjust; but it is significant that such
events provoke so little response in the intellectual communityâfor
example, no one has said that there is something strange in the offer of
a major chair in the humanities to a historian who feels it to be his
duty to persuade the world that an American-sponsored invasion of a
nearby country is nothing of the sort. And what of the incredible
sequence of lies on the part of our government and its spokesmen
concerning such matters as negotiations in Vietnam? The facts are known
to all who care to know. The press, foreign and domestic, has presented
documentation to refute each falsehood as it appears. But the power of
the governmentâs propaganda apparatus is such that the citizen who does
not undertake a research project on the subject can hardly hope to
confront government pronouncements with fact.[1]
The deceit and distortion surrounding the American invasion of Vietnam
is by now so familiar that it has lost its power to shock. It is
therefore useful to recall that although new levels of cynicism are
constantly being reached, their clear antecedents were accepted at home
with quiet toleration. It is a useful exercise to compare Government
statements at the time of the invasion of Guatemala in 1954 with
Eisenhowerâs admissionâto be more accurate, his boastâa decade later
that American planes were sent âto help the invadersâ (New York Times,
October 14, 1965). Nor is it only in moments of crisis that duplicity is
considered perfectly in order. âNew Frontiersmen,â for example, have
scarcely distinguished themselves by a passionate concern for historical
accuracy, even when they are not being called upon to provide a
âpropaganda coverâ for ongoing actions. For example, Arthur Schlesinger
(New York Times, February 6, 1966) describes the bombing of North
Vietnam and the massive escalation of military commitment in early 1965
as based on a âperfectly rational argumentâ:
so long as the Vietcong thought they were going to win the war, they
obviously would not be interested in any kind of negotiated settlement.
The date is important. Had this statement been made six months earlier,
one could attribute it to ignorance. But this statement appeared after
the UN, North Vietnamese, and Soviet initiatives had been front-page
news for months. It was already public knowledge that these initiatives
had preceeded the escalation of February 1965 and, in fact, continued
for several weeks after the bombing began. Correspondents in Washington
tried desperately to find some explanation for the startling deception
that had been revealed. Chalmers Roberts, for example, wrote in the
Boston Globe on November 19 with unconscious irony:
[late February, 1965] hardly seemed to Washington to be a propitious
moment for negotiations [since] Mr. JohnsonâŠhad just ordered the first
bombing of North Vietnam in an effort to bring Hanoi to a conference
table where the bargaining chips on both sides would be more closely
matched.
Coming at that moment, Schlesingerâs statement is less an example of
deceit than of contemptâcontempt for an audience that can be expected to
tolerate such behavior with silence, if not approval.[2]
---
TO TURN TO SOMEONE closer to the actual formation and implementation of
policy, consider some of the reflections of Walt Rostow, a man who,
according to Schlesinger, brought a âspacious historical viewâ to the
conduct of foreign affairs in the Kennedy administration.[3] According
to his analysis, the guerrilla warfare in Indo-China in 1946 was
launched by Stalin,[4] and Hanoi initiated the guerrilla war against
South Vietnam in 1958 (The View from the Seventh Floor pp. 39 and 152).
Similarly, the Communist planners probed the âfree world spectrum of
defenseâ in Northern Azerbaijan and Greece (where Stalin âsupported
substantial guerrilla warfareââibid., pp. 36 and 148), operating from
plans carefully laid in 1945. And in Central Europe, the Soviet Union
was not âprepared to accept a solution which would remove the dangerous
tensions from Central Europe at the risk of even slowly staged corrosion
of Communism in East Germanyâ (ibid., p. 156).
It is interesting to compare these observations with studies by scholars
actually concerned with historical events. The remark about Stalinâs
initiating the first Vietnamese war in 1946 does not even merit
refutation. As to Hanoiâs purported initiative of 1958, the situation is
more clouded. But even government sources[5] concede that in 1959 Hanoi
received the first direct reports of what Diem referred to[6] as his own
Algerian war and that only after this did they lay their plans to
involve themselves in this struggle. In fact, in December, 1958, Hanoi
made another of its many attemptsârebuffed once again by Saigon and the
United Statesâto establish diplomatic and commercial relations with the
Saigon government on the basis of the status quo.[7] Rostow offers no
evidence of Stalinâs support for the Greek guerrillas; in fact, though
the historical record is far from clear, it seems that Stalin was by no
means pleased with the adventurism of the Greek guerrillas, who, from
his point of view, were upsetting the satisfactory post-war imperialist
settlement.[8]
Rostowâs remarks about Germany are more interesting still. He does not
see fit to mention, for example, the Russian notes of March-April, 1952,
which proposed unification of Germany under internationally supervised
elections, with withdrawal of all troops within a year, if there was a
guarantee that a reunified Germany would not be permitted to join a
Western military alliance.[9] And he has also momentarily forgotten his
own characterization of the strategy of the Truman and Eisenhower
administrations: âto avoid any serious negotiation with the Soviet Union
until the West could confront Moscow with German rearmament within an
organized European framework, as a fait accompliâ[10] âto be sure, in
defiance of the Potsdam agreements.
But most interesting of all is Rostowâs reference to Iran. The facts are
that there was a Russian attempt to impose by force a pro-Soviet
government in Northern Azerbaijan that would grant the Soviet Union
access to Iranian oil. This was rebuffed by superior Anglo-American
force in 1946, at which point the more powerful imperialism obtained
full rights to Iranian oil for itself, with the installation of a
pro-Western government. We recall what happened when, for a brief period
in the early 1950s, the only Iranian government with something of a
popular base experimented with the curious idea that Iranian oil should
belong to the Iranians. What is interesting, however, is the description
of Northern Azerbaijan as part of âthe free world spectrum of defense.â
It is pointless, by now, to comment on the debasement of the phrase
âfree world.â But by what law of nature does Iran, with its resources,
fall within Western dominion? The bland assumption that it does is most
revealing of deep-seated attitudes toward the conduct of foreign
affairs.
---
IN ADDITION to this growing lack of concern for truth, we find, in
recent published statements, a real or feigned naiveté about American
actions that reaches startling proportions. For example, Arthur
Schlesinger, according to the Times, February 6, 1966, characterized our
Vietnamese policies of 1954 as âpart of our general program of
international goodwill.â Unless intended as irony, this remark shows
either a colossal cynicism, or the inability, on a scale that defies
measurement, to comprehend elementary phenomena of contemporary history.
Similarly, what is one to make of the testimony of Thomas Schelling
before the House Foreign Affairs Committee, January 27, 1965, in which
he discusses two great dangers if all Asia âgoes Communistâ?[11] First,
this would exclude âthe United States and what we call Western
civilization from a large part of the world that is poor and colored and
potentially hostile.â Second, âa country like the United States probably
cannot maintain self-confidence if just about the greatest thing it ever
attempted, namely to create the basis for decency and prosperity and
democratic government in the underdeveloped world, had to be
acknowledged as a failure or as an attempt that we wouldnât try again.â
It surpasses belief that a person with even a minimal acquaintance with
the record of American foreign policy could produce such statements.
It surpasses belief, that is, unless we look at the matter from a more
historical point of view, and place such statements in the context of
the hypocritical moralism of the past; for example, of Woodrow Wilson,
who was going to teach the Latin Americans the art of good government,
and who wrote (1902) that it is âour peculiar dutyâ to teach colonial
peoples âorder and self-controlâŠ[and]âŠthe drill and habit of law and
obedienceâŠ.â Or of the missionaries of the 1840s, who described the
hideous and degrading opium wars as âthe result of a great design of
Providence to make the wickedness of men subserve his purposes of mercy
toward China, in breaking through her wall of exclusion, and bringing
the empire into more immediate contact with western and Christian
nations.â Or, to approach the present, of A.A. Berle, who, in commenting
on the Dominican intervention, has the impertinence to attribute the
problems of the Caribbean countries to imperialismâRussian
imperialism.[12]
---
AS A FINAL EXAMPLE of this failure of skepticism, consider the remarks
of Henry Kissinger in his concluding remarks at the Harvard-Oxford
television debate on Americaâs Vietnam policies. He observed, rather
sadly, that what disturbs him most is that others question not our
judgment, but our motivesâa remarkable comment by a man whose
professional concern is political analysis, that is, analysis of the
actions of governments in terms of motives that are unexpressed in
official propaganda and perhaps only dimly perceived by those whose acts
they govern. No one would be disturbed by an analysis of the political
behavior of the Russians, French, or Tanzanians questioning their
motives and interpreting their actions by the long-range interests
concealed behind their official rhetoric. But it is an article of faith
that American motives are pure, and not subject to analysis (see note
1). Although it is nothing new in American intellectual historyâor, for
that matter, in the general history of imperialist apologiaâthis
innocence becomes increasingly distasteful as the power it serves grows
more dominant in world affairs, and more capable, therefore, of the
unconstrained viciousness that the mass media present to us each day. We
are hardly the first power in history to combine material interests,
great technological capacity, and an utter disregard for the suffering
and misery of the lower orders. The long tradition of naiveté and
self-righteousness that disfigures our intellectual history, however,
must serve as a warning to the third world, if such a warning is needed,
as to how our protestations of sincerity and benign intent are to be
interpreted.
The basic assumptions of the âNew Frontiersmenâ should be pondered
carefully by those who look forward to the involvement of academic
intellectuals in politics. For example, I have referred above to Arthur
Schlesingerâs objections to the Bay of Pigs invasion, but the reference
was imprecise. True, he felt that it was a âterrible idea,â but ânot
because the notion of sponsoring an exile attempt to overthrow Castro
seemed intolerable in itself.â Such a reaction would be the merest
sentimentality, unthinkable to a tough-minded realist. The difficulty,
rather, was that it seemed unlikely that the deception could succeed.
The operation, in his view, was ill-conceived but not otherwise
objectionable.[13] In a similar vein, Schlesinger quotes with approval
Kennedyâs ârealisticâ assessment of the situation resulting from
Trujilloâs assassination:
There are three possibilities in descending order of preference: a
decent democratic regime, a continuation of the Trujillo regime or a
Castro regime. We ought to aim at the first, but we really canât
renounce the second until we are sure that we can avoid the third [p.
769].
The reason why the third possibility is so intolerable is explained a
few pages later (p. 774): âCommunist success in Latin America would deal
a much harder blow to the power and influence of the United States.â Of
course, we can never really be sure of avoiding the third possibility;
therefore, in practice, we will always settle for the second, as we are
now doing in Brazil and Argentina, for example.[14]
Or consider Walt Rostowâs views on American policy in Asia.[15] The
basis on which we must build this policy is that âwe are openly
threatened and we feel menaced by Communist China.â To prove that we are
menaced is of course unnecessary, and the matter receives no attention;
it is enough that we feel menaced. Our policy must be based on our
national heritage and our national interests. Our national heritage is
briefly outlined in the following terms: âThroughout the nineteenth
century, in good conscience Americans could devote themselves to the
extension of both their principles and their power on this continent,â
making use of âthe somewhat elastic concept of the Monroe doctrineâ and,
of course, extending âthe American interest to Alaska and the
mid-Pacific islandsâŠ. Both our insistence on unconditional surrender and
the idea of post-war occupationâŠrepresented the formulation of American
security interests in Europe and Asia.â So much for our heritage. As to
our interests, the matter is equally simple. Fundamental is our
âprofound interest that societies abroad develop and strengthen those
elements in their respective cultures that elevate and protect the
dignity of the individual against the state.â At the same time, we must
counter the âideological threat,â namely âthe possibility that the
Chinese Communists can prove to Asians by progress in China that
Communist methods are better and faster than democratic methods.â
Nothing is said about those people in Asian cultures to whom our
âconception of the proper relation of the individual to the stateâ may
not be the uniquely important value, people who might, for example, be
concerned with preserving the âdignity of the individualâ against
concentrations of foreign or domestic capital, or against semi-feudal
structures (such as Trujillo-type dictatorships) introduced or kept in
power by American arms. All of this is flavored with allusions to âour
religious and ethical value systemsâ and to our âdiffuse and complex
conceptsâ which are to the Asian mind âso much more difficult to graspâ
than Marxist dogma, and are so âdisturbing to some Asiansâ because of
âtheir very lack of dogmatism.â
Such intellectual contributions as these suggest the need for a
correction to De Gaulleâs remark, in his Memoirs, about the American
âwill to power, cloaking itself in idealism.â By now, this will to power
is not so much cloaked in idealism as it is drowned in fatuity. And
academic intellectuals have made their unique contribution to this sorry
picture.
---
LET US, HOWEVER, RETURN to the war in Vietnam and the response that it
has aroused among American intellectuals. A striking feature of the
recent debate on Southeast Asian policy has been the distinction that is
commonly drawn between âresponsible criticism,â on the one hand, and
âsentimental,â or âemotional,â or âhystericalâ criticism, on the other.
There is much to be learned from a careful study of the terms in which
this distinction is drawn. The âhysterical criticsâ are to be
identified, apparently, by their irrational refusal to accept one
fundamental political axiom, namely that the United States has the right
to extend its power and control without limit, insofar as is feasible.
Responsible criticism does not challenge this assumption, but argues,
rather, that we probably canât âget away with itâ at this particular
time and place.
A distinction of this sort seems to be what Irving Kristol, for example,
has in mind in his analysis of the protest over Vietnam policy
(Encounter, August, 1965). He contrasts the responsible critics, such as
Walter Lippmann, the Times, and Senator Fulbright, with the âteach-in
movement.â âUnlike the university protesters,â he points out, âMr.
Lippmann engages in no presumptuous suppositions as to âwhat the
Vietnamese people really wantââhe obviously doesnât much careâor in
legalistic exegesis as to whether, or to what extent, there is
âaggressionâ or ârevolutionâ in South Vietnam. His is a realpolitik
point of view; and he will apparently even contemplate the possibility
of a nuclear war against China in extreme circumstances.â This is
commendable, and contrasts favorably, for Kristol, with the talk of the
âunreasonable, ideological typesâ in the teach-in movement, who often
seem to be motivated by such absurdities as âsimple, virtuous
âanti-imperialism,â âwho deliver âharangues on âthe power structure,â â
and who even sometimes stoop so low as to read âarticles and reports
from the foreign press on the American presence in Vietnam.â
Furthermore, these nasty types are often psychologists, mathematicians,
chemists, or philosophers (just as, incidentally, those most vocal in
protest in the Soviet Union are generally physicists, literary
intellectuals, and others remote from the exercise of power), rather
than people with Washington contacts, who, of course, realize that âhad
they a new, good idea about Vietnam, they would get a prompt and
respectful hearingâ in Washington.
I am not interested here in whether Kristolâs characterization of
protest and dissent is accurate, but rather in the assumptions on which
it rests. Is the purity of American motives a matter that is beyond
discussion, or that is irrelevant to discussion? Should decisions be
left to âexpertsâ with Washington contactsâeven if we assume that they
command the necessary knowledge and principles to make the âbestâ
decision, will they invariably do so? And, a logically prior question,
is âexpertiseâ applicableâthat is, is there a body of theory and of
relevant information, not in the public domain, that can be applied to
the analysis of foreign policy or that demonstrates the correctness of
present actions in some way that psychologists, mathematicians,
chemists, and philosophers are incapable of comprehending? Although
Kristol does not examine these questions directly, his attitude
presupposes answers, answers which are wrong in all cases. American
aggressiveness, however it may be masked in pious rhetoric, is a
dominant force in world affairs and must be analyzed in terms of its
causes and motives. There is no body of theory or significant body of
relevant information, beyond the comprehension of the layman, which
makes policy immune from criticism. To the extent that âexpert
knowledgeâ is applied to world affairs, it is surely appropriateâfor a
person of any integrity, quite necessaryâto question its quality and the
goals it serves. These facts seem too obvious to require extended
discussion.
---
A CORRECTIVE to Kristolâs curious belief in the Administrationâs
openness to new thinking about Vietnam is provided by McGeorge Bundy in
a recent issue of Foreign Affairs (January, 1967). As Bundy correctly
observes, âon the main stageâŠthe argument on Viet Nam turns on tactics,
not fundamentals,â although, he adds, âthere are wild men in the wings.â
On stage center are, of course, the President (who in his recent trip to
Asia had just âmagisterially reaffirmedâ our interest âin the progress
of the people across the Pacificâ) and his advisers, who deserve âthe
understanding support of those who want restraint.â It is these men who
deserve the credit for the fact that âthe bombing of the North has been
the most accurate and the most restrained in modern warfareââa
solicitude which will be appreciated by the inhabitants, or former
inhabitants of Nam Dinh and Phu Ly and Vinh. It is these men, too, who
deserve the credit for what was reported by Malcolm Browne as long ago
as May, 1965:
In the South, huge sectors of the nation have been declared âfree
bombing zones,â in which anything that moves is a legitimate target.
Tens of thousands of tons of bombs, rockets, napalm and cannon fire are
poured into these vast areas each week. If only by the laws of chance,
bloodshed is believed to be heavy in these raids.
Fortunately for the developing countries, Bundy assures us, âAmerican
democracy has no taste for imperialism,â and âtaken as a whole, the
stock of American experience, understanding, sympathy and simple
knowledge is now much the most impressive in the world.â It is true that
âfour-fifths of all the foreign investing in the world is now done by
Americansâ and that âthe most admired plans and policiesâŠare no better
than their demonstrable relation to the American interestââjust as it is
true, so we read in the same issue of Foreign Affairs, that the plans
for armed action against Cuba were put into motion a few weeks after
Mikoyan visited Havana, âinvading what had so long been an almost
exclusively American sphere of influence.â Unfortunately, such facts as
these are often taken by unsophisticated Asian intellectuals as
indicating a âtaste for imperialism.â For example, a number of Indians
have expressed their ânear exasperationâ at the fact that âwe have done
everything we can to attract foreign capital for fertilizer plants, but
the American and the other Western private companies know we are over a
barrel, so they demand stringent terms which we just cannot meetâ
(Christian Science Monitor, November 26), while âWashingtonâŠdoggedly
insists that deals be made in the private sector with private
enterpriseâ (ibid., December 5).[16] But this reaction, no doubt, simply
reveals, once again, how the Asian mind fails to comprehend the âdiffuse
and complex conceptsâ of Western thought.
---
IT MAY BE USEFUL to study carefully the ânew, good ideas about Vietnamâ
that are receiving a âprompt and respectful hearingâ in Washington these
days. The US Government Printing Office is an endless source of insight
into the moral and intellectual level of this expert advice. In its
publications one can read, for example, the testimony of Professor David
N. Rowe, Director of Graduate Studies in International Relations at Yale
University, before the House Committee on Foreign Affairs (see note 11).
Professor Rowe proposes (p. 266) that the United States buy all surplus
Canadian and Australian wheat, so that there will be mass starvation in
China. These are his words:
Mind you, I am not talking about this as a weapon against the Chinese
people. It will be. But that is only incidental. The weapon will be a
weapon against the Government because the internal stability of that
country cannot be sustained by an unfriendly Government in the face of
general starvation.
Professor Rowe will have none of the sentimental moralism that might
lead one to compare this suggestion with, say, the Ostpolitik of
Hitlerâs Germany.[17] Nor does he fear the impact of such policies on
other Asian nations, for example, Japan. He assures us, from his âvery
long acquaintance with Japanese questions,â that âthe Japanese above all
are people who respect power and determination.â Hence âthey will not be
so much alarmed by American policy in Vietnam that takes off from a
position of power and intends to seek a solution based upon the
imposition of our power upon local people that we are in opposition to.â
What would disturb the Japanese is âa policy of indecision, a policy of
refusal to face up to the problems [in China and Vietnam] and to meet
our responsibilities there in a positive way,â such as the way just
cited. A conviction that we were âunwilling to use the power that they
know we haveâ might âalarm the Japanese people very intensely and shake
the degree of their friendly relations with us.â In fact, a full use of
American power would be particularly reassuring to the Japanese, because
they have had a demonstration âof the tremendous power in action of the
United StatesâŠbecause they have felt our power directly.â This is surely
a prime example of the healthy, ârealpolitik point of viewâ that Irving
Kristol so much admires.
But, one may ask, why restrict ourselves to such indirect means as mass
starvation? Why not bombing? No doubt this message is implicit in the
remarks to the same committee of the Reverend R.J. de Jaegher, Regent of
the Institute of Far Eastern Studies, Seton Hall University, who
explains that like all people who have lived under Communism, the North
Vietnamese âwould be perfectly happy to be bombed to be freeâ (p. 345).
Of course, there must be those who support the Communists. But this is
really a matter of small concern, as the Hon Walter Robertson, Assistant
Secretary of State for Far Eastern Affairs from 1953â59, points out in
his testimony before the same committee. He assures us that âThe Peiping
regimeâŠrepresents something less than 3 per cent of the populationâ (p.
402).
Consider, then, how fortunate the Chinese Communist leaders are,
compared to the leaders of the Vietcong, who, according to Arthur
Goldberg (New York Times, February 6, 1966), represent about âone-half
of one percent of the population of South Vietnam,â that is, about
one-half the number of new Southern recruits for the Vietcong during
1965, if we can credit Pentagon statistics.[18]
In the face of such experts as these, the scientists and philosophers of
whom Kristol speaks would clearly do well to continue to draw their
circles in the sand.
---
HAVING SETTLED THE ISSUE of the political irrelevance of the protest
movement, Kristol turns to the question of what motivates itâmore
generally, what has made students and junior faculty âgo left,â as he
sees it, amid general prosperity and under liberal, Welfare State
administrations. This, he notes, âis a riddle to which no sociologist
has as yet come up with an answer.â Since these young people are
well-off, have good futures, etc., their protest must be irrational. It
must be the result of boredom, of too much security, or something of
this sort.
Other possibilities come to mind. It may be, for example, that as honest
men the students and junior faculty are attempting to find out the truth
for themselves rather than ceding the responsibility to âexpertsâ or to
government; and it may be that they react with indignation to what they
discover. These possibilities Kristol does not reject. They are simply
unthinkable, unworthy of consideration. More accurately, these
possibilities are inexpressible; the categories in which they are
formulated (honesty, indignation) simply do not exist for the
tough-minded social scientist.
---
IN THIS IMPLICIT DISPARAGEMENT of traditional intellectual values,
Kristol reflects attitudes that are fairly widespread in academic
circles. I do not doubt that these attitudes are in part a consequence
of the desperate attempt of the social and behavioral sciences to
imitate the surface features of sciences that really have significant
intellectual content. But they have other sources as well. Anyone can be
a moral individual, concerned with human rights and problems; but only a
college professor, a trained expert, can solve technical problems by
âsophisticatedâ methods. Ergo, it is only problems of the latter sort
that are important or real. Responsible, non-ideological experts will
give advice on tactical questions; irresponsible, âideological typesâ
will âharangueâ about principle and trouble themselves over moral issues
and human rights, or over the traditional problems of man and society,
concerning which âsocial and behavioral scienceâ has nothing to offer
beyond trivalities. Obviously, these emotional, ideological types are
irrational, since, being well-off and having power in their grasp, they
shouldnât worry about such matters.
At times this pseudo-scientific posing reaches levels that are almost
pathological. Consider the phenomenon of Herman Kahn, for example. Kahn
has been both denounced as immoral and lauded for his courage. By people
who should know better, his On Thermonuclear War has been described
âwithout qualificationâŠ[as]âŠone of the great works of our timeâ (Stuart
Hughes). The fact of the matter is that this is surely one of the
emptiest works of our time, as can be seen by applying to it the
intellectual standards of any existing discipline, by tracing some of
its âwell-documented conclusionsâ to the âobjective studiesâ from which
they derive, and by following the line of argument, where detectable.
Kahn proposes no theories, no explanations, no factual assumptions that
can be tested against their consequences, as do the sciences he is
attempting to mimic. He simply suggests a terminology and provides a
facade of rationality. When particular policy conclusions are drawn,
they are supported only by ex cathedra remarks for which no support is
even suggested (e.g., âThe civil defense line probably should be drawn
somewhere below $5 billion annuallyâ to keep from provoking the
Russiansâwhy not $50 billion, or $5.00?). What is more, Kahn is quite
aware of this vacuity; in his more judicious moments he claims only that
âthere is no reason to believe that relatively sophisticated models are
more likely to be misleading than the simpler models and analogies
frequently used as an aid to judgment.â For those whose humor tends
towards the macabre, it is easy to play the game of âstrategic thinkingâ
Ă la Kahn, and to prove what one wishes. For example, one of Kahnâs
basic assumptions is that
an all-out surprise attack in which all resources are devoted to
counter-value targets would be so irrational that, barring an incredible
lack of sophistication or actual insanity among Soviet decision makers,
such an attack is highly unlikely.
A simple argument proves the opposite. Premise 1: American
decision-makers think along the lines outlined by Herman Kahn. Premise
2: Kahn thinks it would be better for everyone to be red than for
everyone to be dead. Premise 3: if the Americans were to respond to an
all-out countervalue attack, then everyone would be dead. Conclusion:
the Americans will not respond to an all-out countervalue attack, and
therefore it should be launched without delay. Of course, one can carry
the argument a step further. Fact: the Russians have not carried out an
all-out countervalue attack. It follows that they are not rational. If
they are not rational, there is no point in âstrategic thinking.â
Therefore,âŠ.
Of course this is all nonsense, but nonsense that differs from Kahnâs
only in the respect that the argument is of slightly greater complexity
than anything to be discovered in his work. What is remarkable is that
serious people actually pay attention to these absurdities, no doubt
because of the facade of tough-mindedness and pseudo-science.
---
IT IS A CURIOUS and depressing fact that the âanti-war movementâ falls
prey all too often to similar confusions. In the fall of 1965, for
example, there was an International Conference on Alternative
Perspectives on Vietnam, which circulated a pamphlet to potential
participants stating its assumptions. The plan was to set up study
groups in which three âtypes of intellectual traditionâ will be
represented: (1) area specialists; (2) âsocial theory, with special
emphasis on theories of the international system, of social change and
development, of conflict and conflict resolution, or of revolutionâ; (3)
âthe analysis of public policy in terms of basic human values, rooted in
various theological, philosophical and humanist traditions.â The second
intellectual tradition will provide âgeneral propositions, derived from
social theory and tested against historical, comparative, or
experimental dataâ; the third âwill provide the framework out of which
fundamental value questions can be raised and in terms of which the
moral implications of societal actions can be analyzed.â The hope was
that âby approaching the questions [of Vietnam policy] from the moral
perspectives of all great religions and philosophical systems, we may
find solutions that are more consistent with fundamental human values
than current American policy in Vietnam has turned out to be.â
In short, the experts on values (i.e., spokesmen for the great religions
and philosophical systems) will provide fundamental insights on moral
perspectives, and the experts on social theory will provide general
empirically validated propositions and âgeneral models of conflict.â
From this interplay, new policies will emerge, presumably from
application of the canons of scientific method. The only debatable
issue, it seems to me, is whether it is more ridiculous to turn to
experts in social theory for general well-confirmed propositions, or to
the specialists in the great religions and philosophical systems for
insights into fundamental human values.
There is much more that can be said about this topic, but, without
continuing, I would simply like to emphasize that, as is no doubt
obvious, the cult of the experts is both self-serving, for those who
propound it, and fraudulent. Obviously, one must learn from social and
behavioral science whatever one can; obviously, these fields should be
pursued as seriously as possible. But it will be quite unfortunate, and
highly dangerous, if they are not accepted and judged on their merits
and according to their actual, not pretended, accomplishments. In
particular, if there is a body of theory, well-tested and verified, that
applies to the conduct of foreign affairs or the resolution of domestic
or international conflict, its existence has been kept a well-guarded
secret. In the case of Vietnam, if those who feel themselves to be
experts have access to principles or information that would justify what
the American government is doing in that unfortunate country, they have
been singularly ineffective in making this fact known. To anyone who has
any familiarity with the social and behavioral sciences (or the âpolicy
sciencesâ), the claim that there are certain considerations and
principles too deep for the outsider to comprehend is simply an
absurdity, unworthy of comment.
---
WHEN WE CONSIDER the responsibility of intellectuals, our basic concern
must be their role in the creation and analysis of ideology. And, in
fact, Kristolâs contrast between the unreasonable ideological types and
the responsible experts is formulated in terms that immediately bring to
mind Daniel Bellâs interesting and influential âThe End of Ideology,â an
essay which is as important for what it leaves unsaid as for its actual
content.[19] Bell presents and discusses the Marxist analysis of
ideology as a mask for class interest, quoting Marxâs well-known
description of the belief of the bourgeoisie âthat the special
conditions of its emancipation are the general conditions through which
alone modern society can be saved and the class struggle avoided.â He
then argues that the age of ideology is ended, supplanted, at least in
the West, by a general agreement that each issue must be settled in its
own terms, within the framework of a Welfare State in which, presumably,
experts in the conduct of public affairs will have a prominent role.
Bell is quite careful, however, to characterize the precise sense of
âideologyâ in which âideologies are exhausted.â He is referring to
ideology only as âthe conversion of ideas into social levers,â to
ideology as âa set of beliefs, infused with passion,âŠ[which] âŠseeks to
transform the whole of a way of life.â The crucial words are âtransformâ
and âconvert into social levers.â Intellectuals in the West, he argues,
have lost interest in converting ideas into social levers for the
radical transformation of society. Now that we have achieved the
pluralistic society of the Welfare State, they see no further need for a
radical transformation of society; we may tinker with our way of life
here and there, but it would be wrong to try to modify it in any
significant way. With this consensus of intellectuals, ideology is dead.
There are several striking facts about Bellâs essay. First, he does not
point out the extent to which this consensus of the intellectuals is
self-serving. He does not relate his observation that, by and large,
intellectuals have lost interest in âtransforming the whole of a way of
lifeâ to the fact that they play an increasingly prominent role in
running the Welfare State; he does not relate their general satisfaction
with the Welfare State to the fact that, as he observes elsewhere,
âAmerica has become an affluent society, offering placeâŠand prestigeâŠto
the onetime radicals.â Secondly, he offers no serious argument to show
that intellectuals are somehow ârightâ or âobjectively justifiedâ in
reaching the consensus to which he alludes, with its rejection of the
notion that society should be transformed. Indeed, although Bell is
fairly sharp about the empty rhetoric of the ânew left,â he seems to
have a quite utopian faith that technical experts will be able to cope
with the few problems that still remain; for example, the fact that
labor is treated as a commodity, and the problems of âalienation.â
It seems fairly obvious that the classical problems are very much with
us; one might plausibly argue that they have even been enhanced in
severity and scale. For example, the classical paradox of poverty in the
midst of plenty is now an ever-increasing problem on an international
scale. Whereas one might conceive, at least in principle, of a solution
within national boundaries, a sensible idea of transforming
international society to cope with vast and perhaps increasing human
misery is hardly likely to develop within the framework of the
intellectual consensus that Bell describes.
---
THUS IT WOULD SEEM NATURAL to describe the consensus of Bellâs
intellectuals in somewhat different terms from his. Using the
terminology of the first part of his essay, we might say that the
Welfare State technician finds justification for his special and
prominent social status in his âscience,â specifically, in the claim
that social science can support a technology of social tinkering on a
domestic or international scale. He then takes a further step, ascribing
in a familiar way a universal validity to what is in fact a class
interest: he argues that the special conditions on which his claim to
power and authority are based are, in fact, the only general conditions
by which modern society can be saved; that social tinkering within a
Welfare State framework must replace the commitment to the âtotal
ideologiesâ of the past, ideologies which were concerned with a
transformation of society. Having found his position of power, having
achieved security and affluence, he has no further need for ideologies
that look to radical change. The scholar-expert replaces the
âfree-floating intellectualâ who âfelt that the wrong values were being
honored, and rejected the society,â and who has now lost his political
role (now, that is, that the right values are being honored).
Conceivably, it is correct that the technical experts who will (or hope
to) manage the âindustrial societyâ will be able to cope with the
classical problems without a radical transformation of society. It is
conceivably true that the bourgeoisie was right in regarding the special
conditions of its emancipation as the only general conditions by which
modern society would be saved. In either case, an argument is in order,
and skepticism is justified when none appears.
Within the same framework of general utopianism, Bell goes on to pose
the issue between Welfare State scholar-experts and third-world
ideologists in a rather curious way. He points out, quite correctly,
that there is no issue of Communism, the content of that doctrine having
been âlong forgotten by friends and foes alike.â Rather, he says,
the question is an older one: whether new societies can grow by building
democratic institutions and allowing people to make choicesâand
sacrificesâvoluntarily, or whether the new elites, heady with power,
will impose totalitarian means to transform their societies.
---
THE QUESTION is an interesting one. It is odd, however, to see it
referred to as âan older one.â Surely he cannot be suggesting that the
West chose the democratic wayâfor example, that in England during the
industrial revolution, the farmers voluntarily made the choice of
leaving the land, giving up cottage industry, becoming an industrial
proletariat, and voluntarily decided, within the framework of the
existing democratic institutions, to make the sacrifices that are
graphically described in the classic literature on nineteenth-century
industrial society. One may debate the question whether authoritarian
control is necessary to permit capital accumulation in the
underdeveloped world, but the Western model of development is hardly one
that we can point to with any pride. It is perhaps not surprising to
find Walt Rostow referring to âthe more humane processes [of
industrialization] that Western values would suggestâ (An American
Policy in Asia). Those who have a serious concern for the problems that
face backward countries, and for the role that advanced industrial
societies might, in principle, play in development and modernization,
must use somewhat more care in interpreting the significance of the
Western experience.
Returning to the quite appropriate question, whether ânew societies can
grow by building democratic institutionsâ or only by totalitarian means,
I think that honesty requires us to recognize that this question must be
directed more to American intellectuals than to third-world ideologists.
The backward countries have incredible, perhaps insurmountable problems,
and few available options; the United States has a wide range of
options, and has the economic and technological resources, though,
evidently, neither the intellectual nor moral resources, to confront at
least some of these problems. It is easy for an American intellectual to
deliver homilies on the virtues of freedom and liberty, but if he is
really concerned about, say, Chinese totalitarianism or the burdens
imposed on the Chinese peasantry in forced industrialization, then he
should face a task that is infinitely more important and challengingâthe
task of creating, in the United States, the intellectual and moral
climate, as well as the social and economic conditions, that would
permit this country to participate in modernization and development in a
way commensurate with its material wealth and technical capacity. Large
capital gifts to Cuba and China might not succeed in alleviating the
authoritarianism and terror that tend to accompany early stages of
capital accumulation, but they are far more likely to have this effect
than lectures on democratic values. It is possible that even without
âcapitalist encirclementâ in its various manifestations, the truly
democratic elements in revolutionary movementsâin some instances,
soviets and collectivesâmight be undermined by an âeliteâ of bureaucrats
and technical intelligentsia. But it is almost certain that capitalist
encirclement itself, which all revolutionary movements now have to face,
will guarantee this result. The lesson, for those who are concerned to
strengthen the democratic, spontaneous, and popular elements in
developing societies, is quite clear. Lectures on the two-party system,
or even on the really substantial democratic values that have been in
part realized in Western society, are a monstrous irrelevance, given the
effort required to raise the level of culture in Western society to the
point where it can provide a âsocial leverâ for both economic
development and the development of true democratic institutions in the
third worldâand, for that matter, at home.
---
A GOOD CASE CAN BE MADE for the conclusion that there is indeed
something of a consensus among intellectuals who have already achieved
power and affluence, or who sense that they can achieve them by
âaccepting societyâ as it is and promoting the values that are âbeing
honoredâ in this society. It is also true that this consensus is most
noticeable among the scholar-experts who are replacing the free-floating
intellectuals of the past. In the university, these scholar-experts
construct a âvalue-free technologyâ for the solution of technical
problems that arise in contemporary society,[20] taking a âresponsible
stanceâ towards these problems, in the sense noted earlier. This
consensus among the responsible scholar-experts is the domestic analogue
to that proposed, internationally, by those who justify the application
of American power in Asia, whatever the human cost, on the grounds that
it is necessary to contain the âexpansion of Chinaâ (an âexpansionâ
which is, to be sure, hypothetical for the time being)[21] âthat is, to
translate from State Department Newspeak, on the grounds that it is
essential to reverse the Asian nationalist revolutions or, at least, to
prevent them from spreading. The analogy becomes clear when we look
carefully at the ways in which this proposal is formulated. With his
usual lucidity, Churchill outlined the general position in a remark to
his colleague of the moment, Joseph Stalin, at Teheran in 1943:
The government of the world must be entrusted to satisfied nations, who
wished nothing more for themselves than what they had. If the
world-government were in the hands of hungry nations there would always
be danger. But none of us had any reason to seek for anything moreâŠ. Our
power placed us above the rest. We were like the rich men dwelling at
peace within their habitations.
For a translation of Churchillâs biblical rhetoric into the jargon of
contemporary social science, one may turn to the testimony of Charles
Wolf, Senior Economist of the Rand Corporation, at the Congressional
Committee Hearings cited earlier:
I am dubious that Chinaâs fears of encirclement are going to be abated,
eased, relaxed in the long-term future. But I would hope that what we do
in Southeast Asia would help to develop within the Chinese body politic
more of a realism and willingness to live with this fear than to indulge
it by support for liberation movements, which admittedly depend on a
great deal more than external supportâŠthe operational question for
American foreign policy is not whether that fear can be eliminated or
substantially alleviated, but whether China can be faced with a
structure of incentives, of penalties and rewards, of inducements that
will make it willing to live with this fear.
The point is further clarified by Thomas Schelling: âThere is growing
experience, which the Chinese can profit from, that although the United
States may be interested in encircling them, may be interested in
defending nearby areas from them, it is, nevertheless, prepared to
behave peaceably if they are.â
In short, we are prepared to live peaceably in ourâto be sure, rather
extensiveâhabitations. And, quite naturally, we are offended by the
undignified noises from the servantsâ quarters. If, let us say, a
peasant-based revolutionary movement tries to achieve independence from
foreign powers and the domestic structures they support, or if the
Chinese irrationally refuse to respond properly to the schedule of
reinforcement that we have prepared for themâif they object to being
encircled by the benign and peace-loving ârich menâ who control the
territories on their borders as a natural rightâthen, evidently, we must
respond to this belligerence with appropriate force.
---
IT IS THIS MENTALITY that explains the frankness with which the United
States Government and its academic apologists defend the American
refusal to permit a political settlement in Vietnam at a local level, a
settlement based on the actual distribution of political forces. Even
government experts freely admit that the NLF is the only âtruly
mass-based political party in South Vietnamâ[22] ; that the NLF had
âmade a conscious and massive effort to extend political participation,
even if it was manipulated, on the local level so as to involve the
people in a self-contained, self-supporting revolutionâ (p. 374); and
that this effort had been so successful that no political groups, âwith
the possible exception of the Buddhists, thought themselves equal in
size and power to risk entering into a coalition, fearing that if they
did the whale would swallow the minnowâ (p. 362). Moreover, they concede
that until the introduction of overwhelming American force, the NLF had
insisted that the struggle âshould be fought out at the political level
and that the use of massed military might was in itself illegitimateâŠ.
The battleground was to be the minds and loyalties of the rural
Vietnamese, the weapons were to be ideasâ (pp. 91â92; cf. also pp. 93,
99â108, 155f.); and, correspondingly, that until mid-1964, aid from
Hanoi âwas largely confined to two areasâdoctrinal know-how and
leadership personnelâ (p. 321). Captured NLF documents contrast the
enemyâs âmilitary superiorityâ with their own âpolitical superiorityâ
(p. 106), thus fully confirming the analysis of American military
spokesmen who define our problem as how, âwith considerable armed force
but little political power, [to] contain an adversary who has enormous
political force but only modest military power.â[23]
Similarly, the most striking outcome of both the Honolulu conference in
February and the Manila conference in October was the frank admission by
high officials of the Saigon government that âthey could not survive a
âpeaceful settlementâ that left the Vietcong political structure in
place even if the Vietcong guerilla units were disbanded,â that âthey
are not able to compete politically with the Vietnamese Communistsâ
(Charles Mohr, New York Times, February 11, 1966, italics mine). Thus,
Mohr continues, the Vietnamese demand a âpacification programâ which
will have as âits coreâŠthe destruction of the clandestine Vietcong
political structure and the creation of an iron-like system of
government political control over the population.â And from Manila, the
same correspondent, on October 23, quotes a high South Vietnamese
official as saying that:
Frankly, we are not strong enough now to compete with the Communists on
a purely political basis. They are organized and disciplined. The
non-Communist nationalists are notâwe do not have any large,
well-organized political parties and we do not yet have unity. We cannot
leave the Vietcong in existence.
Officials in Washington understand the situation very well. Thus
Secretary Rusk has pointed out that âif the Vietcong come to the
conference table as full partners they will, in a sense, have been
victorious in the very aims that South Vietnam and the United States are
pledged to preventâ (January 28, 1966). Max Frankel reported from
Washington in the Times on February 18, 1966, that
Compromise has had no appeal here because the Administration concluded
long ago that the non-Communist forces of South Vietnam could not long
survive in a Saigon coalition with Communists. It is for that reasonâand
not because of an excessively rigid sense of protocolâthat Washington
has steadfastly refused to deal with the Vietcong or recognize them as
an independent political force.
In short, we willâmagnanimouslyâpermit Vietcong representatives to
attend negotiations only if they will agree to identify themselves as
agents of a foreign power and thus forfeit the right to participate in a
coalition government, a right which they have now been demanding for a
half-dozen years. We well know that in any representative coalition, our
chosen delegates could not last a day without the support of American
arms. Therefore, we must increase American force and resist meaningful
negotiations, until the day when a client government can exert both
military and political control over its own populationâa day which may
never dawn, for as William Bundy has pointed out, we could never be sure
of the security of a Southeast Asia âfrom which the Western presence was
effectively withdrawn.â Thus if we were to ânegotiate in the direction
of solutions that are put under the label of neutralization,â this would
amount to capitulation to the Communists.[24] According to this
reasoning, then, South Vietnam must remain, permanently, an American
military base.
All of this is, of course, reasonable, so long as we accept the
fundamental political axiom that the United States, with its traditional
concern for the rights of the weak and downtrodden, and with its unique
insight into the proper mode of development for backward countries, must
have the courage and the persistence to impose its will by force until
such time as other nations are prepared to accept these truthsâor
simply, to abandon hope.
---
IF IT IS THE RESPONSIBILITY of the intellectual to insist upon the
truth, it is also his duty to see events in their historical
perspective. Thus one must applaud the insistence of the Secretary of
State on the importance of historical analogies, the Munich analogy, for
example. As Munich showed, a powerful and aggressive nation with a
fanatic belief in its manifest destiny will regard each victory, each
extension of its power and authority, as a prelude to the next step. The
matter was very well put by Adlai Stevenson, when he spoke of âthe old,
old route whereby expansive powers push at more and more doors,
believing they will open until, at the ultimate door, resistance is
unavoidable and major war breaks out.â Herein lies the danger of
appeasement, as the Chinese tirelessly point out to the Soviet
Unionâwhich, they claim, is playing Chamberlain to our Hitler in
Vietnam. Of course, the aggressiveness of liberal imperialism is not
that of Nazi Germany, though the distinction may seem academic to a
Vietnamese peasant who is being gassed or incinerated. We do not want to
occupy Asia; we merely wish, to return to Mr. Wolf, âto help the Asian
countries progress toward economic modernization, as relatively âopenâ
and stable societies, to which our access, as a country and as
individual citizens, is free and comfortable.â The formulation is
appropriate. Recent history shows that it makes little difference to us
what form of government a country has so long as it remains an âopen
society,â in our peculiar sense of this termâthat is, a society that
remains open to American economic penetration or political control. If
it is necessary to approach genocide in Vietnam to achieve this
objective, than this is the price we must pay in defense of freedom and
the rights of man.
In pursuing the aim of helping other countries to progress toward open
societies, with no thought of territorial aggrandizement, we are
breaking no new ground. In the Congressional Hearings that I cited
earlier, Hans Morgenthau aptly describes our traditional policy towards
China as one which favors âwhat you might call freedom of competition
with regard to the exploitation of Chinaâ (op. cit., p. 128). In fact,
few imperialist powers have had explicit territorial ambitions. Thus in
1784, the British Parliament announced: âTo pursue schemes of conquest
and extension of dominion in India are measures repugnant to the wish,
honor, and policy of this nation.â Shortly after this, the conquest of
India was in full swing. A century later, Britain announced its
intentions in Egypt under the slogan âintervention, reform, withdrawal.â
It is obvious which parts of this promise were fulfilled within the next
half-century. In 1936, on the eve of hostilities in North China, the
Japanese stated their Basic Principles of National Policy. These
included the use of moderate and peaceful means to extend her strength,
to promote social and economic development, to eradicate the menace of
Communism, to correct the aggressive policies of the great powers, and
to secure her position as the stabilizing power in East Asia. Even in
1937, the Japanese government had âno territorial designs upon China.â
In short, we follow a well-trodden path.
It is useful to remember, incidentally, that the US was apparently quite
willing, as late as 1939, to negotiate a commercial treaty with Japan
and arrive at a modus vivendi if Japan would âchange her attitude and
practice towards our rights and interests in China,â as Secretary Hull
put it. The bombing of Chungking and the rape of Nanking were
unpleasant, it is true, but what was really important was our rights and
interests in China, as the responsible, unhysterical men of the day saw
quite clearly. It was the closing of the open door by Japan that led
inevitably to the Pacific war, just as it is the closing of the open
door by âCommunistâ China itself that may very well lead to the next,
and no doubt last, Pacific war.
---
QUITE OFTEN, THE STATEMENTS of sincere and devoted technical experts
give surprising insight into the intellectual attitudes that lie in the
background of the latest savagery. Consider, for example, the following
comment by the economist Richard Lindholm, in 1959, expressing his
frustration over the failure of economic development in âfree Vietnamâ:
âŠthe use of American aid is determined by how the Vietnamese use their
incomes and their savings. The fact that a large portion of the
Vietnamese imports financed with American aid are either consumer goods
or raw materials used rather directly to meet consumer demands is an
indication that the Vietnamese people desire these goods. for they have
shown their desire by their willingness to use their piasters to
purchase them.[25]
In short, the Vietnamese people desire Buicks and air-conditioners,
rather than sugar refining equipment or road-building machinery, as they
have shown by their behavior in a free market. And however much we may
deplore their free choice, we must allow the people to have their way.
Of course, there are also those two-legged beasts of burden that one
stumbles on in the countryside, but as any graduate student of political
science can explain, they are not part of a responsible modernizing
elite, and therefore have only a superficial biological resemblance to
the human race.
In no small measure, it is attitudes like this that lie behind the
butchery in Vietnam, and we had better face up to them with candor, or
we will find our government leading us towards a âfinal solutionâ in
Vietnam, and in the many Vietnams that inevitably lie ahead.
Let me finally return to Dwight Macdonald and the responsibility of
intellectuals. Macdonald quotes an interview with a death-camp paymaster
who burst into tears when told that the Russians would hang him. âWhy
should they? What have I done?â he asked. Macdonald concludes: âOnly
those who are willing to resist authority themselves when it conflicts
too intolerably with their personal moral code, only they have the right
to condemn the death-camp paymaster.â The question, âWhat have I done?â
is one that we may well ask ourselves, as we read each day of fresh
atrocities in Vietnamâas we create, or mouth, or tolerate the deceptions
that will be used to justify the next defense of freedom.
Notes
It is interesting to see the first, somewhat oblique, published
reactions to The Politics of Escalation, by those who defend our right
to conquer South Vietnam and institute a government of our choice. For
example, Robert Scalapino (New York Times Magazine, December 11, 1966)
argues that the thesis of the book implies that our leaders are
âdiabolical.â Since no right-thinking person can believe this, the
thesis is refuted. To assume otherwise would betray âirresponsibility,â
in a unique sense of this termâa sense that gives an ironic twist to the
title of this essay. He goes on to point out the alleged central
weakness in the argument of the book, namely, the failure to perceive
that a serious attempt on our part to pursue the possibilities for a
diplomatic settlement would have been interpreted by our adversaries as
a sign of weakness.
It is useful to bear in mind that the United States Government itself is
on occasion much less diffident in explaining why it refuses to
contemplate a meaningful negotiated settlement. As is freely admitted,
this solution would leave it without power to control the situation.
See, for example note 26.
It is worth noting that historical fantasy of the sort illustrated in
Rostowâs remarks has become a regular State Department specially. Thus
we have Thomas Mann justifying our Dominican intervention as a response
to actions of the âSino-Soviet military bloc.â Or, to take a more
considered statement, we have William Bundyâs analysis of stages of
development of Communist ideology in his Pomona College address,
February 12, 1966, in which he characterizes the Soviet Union in the
1920s and early 1930s as âin a highly militant and aggressive phase.â
What is frightening about fantasy, as distinct from outright
falsification, is the possibility that it may be sincere and may
actually serve as the basis for formation of policy.
A major post-war scandal is developing in India, as the United States,
cynically capitalizing on Indiaâs current torture, applies its economic
power to implement what The New York Times calls Indiaâs âdrift from
socialism towards pragmatismâ (April 28, 1965).
As to Malaya, Stevenson is probably confusing ethnic Chinese with the
government of China. Those concerned with the actual events would agree
with Harry Miller (in Communist Menace in Malaya, Praeger, 1954) that
âCommunist China continues to show little interest in the Malayan affair
beyond its usual fulminations via Peking RadioâŠâ There are various harsh
things that one might say about Chinese behavior in what the Sino-Indian
Treaty of 1954 refers to as âthe Tibet region of China,â but it is no
more proof of a tendency towards expansionism than is the behavior of
the Indian Government with regard to the Naga and Mizo tribesmen. As to
North Thailand, âthe apparatus of infiltrationâ may well be at work,
though there is little reason to suppose it to be Chineseâand it is
surely not unrelated to the American use of Thailand as a base of its
attack on Vietnam. This reference is the sheerest hypocrisy.
The âattack on Indiaâ grew out of a border dispute that began several
years after the Chinese had completed a road from Tibet to Sinkiang in
an area so remote from Indian control that the Indians learned about
this operation only from the Chinese Press. According to American Air
Force maps, the disputed area is in Chinese territory. Cf. Alastair
Lamb, China Quarterly, July-September, 1965. To this distinguished
authority, âit seems unlikely that the Chinese have been working out
some master planâŠto take over the Indian sub-continent lock, stock and
overpopulated barrel.â Rather, he thinks it likely that the Chinese were
probably unaware that India even claimed the territory through which the
road passed. After the Chinese military victory, Chinese troops were, in
most areas, withdrawn beyond the McMahon line, a border which the
British had attempted to impose on China in 1914 but which has never
been recognized by China (Nationalist or Communist), the United States,
or any other government. It is remarkable that a person in a responsible
position could describe all of this as Chinese expansionism. In fact, it
is absurd to debate the hypothetical aggressiveness of a China
surrounded by American missiles and a still expanding network of
military bases backed by an enormous American expeditionary force in
Southeast Asia. It is conceivable that at some future time a powerful
China may be expansionist. We may speculate about such possibilities if
we wish, but it is American aggressiveness that is the central fact of
current politics.
[1] Such a research project has now been undertaken and published as a
âCitizensâ White Paperâ: F. Schurmann, P. D. Scott, R. Zelnik, The
Politics of Escalation in Vietnam, Fawcett World Library, and Beacon
Press, 1966. For further evidence of American rejection of UN
initiatives for diplomatic settlement, just prior to the major
escalation of February, 1965, see Mario Rossi, âThe US Rebuff to U
Thant,â NYR, November 17, 1966. There is further documentary evidence of
NLF attempts to establish a coalition government and to neutralize the
area, all rejected by the United States and its Saigon ally, in Douglas
Pike, Viet Cong, M.I.T. Press, 1966. In reading material of this latter
sort one must be especially careful to distinguish between the evidence
presented and the âconclusionsâ that are asserted, for reasons noted
briefly below (see note 22).
[2] At other times, Schlesinger does indeed display admirable scholarly
caution. For example, in his Introduction to The Politics of Escalation
he admits that there may have been âflickers of interest in
negotiationsâ on the part of Hanoi. As to the Administrationâs lies
about negotiations and its repeated actions undercutting tentative
initiatives towards negotiations, he comments only that the authors may
have underestimated military necessity and that future historians may
prove them wrong. This caution and detachment must be compared with
Schlesingerâs attitude toward renewed study of the origins of the cold
war: in a letter to the New York Review of Books, October 20, 1966, he
remarks that it is time to âblow the whistleâ on revisionist attempts to
show that the cold war may have been the consequence of something more
than mere Communist belligerence. We are to believe, then, that the
relatively straight-forward matter of the origins of the cold war is
settled beyond discussion, whereas the much more complex issue of why
the United States shies away from a negotiated settlement in Vietnam
must be left to future historians to ponder.
[3] Arthur M. Schlesinger, Jr., A Thousand Days; John F. Kennedy in the
White House, 1965, p. 421.
[4] The View from the Seventh Floor, Harper and Row, 1964, p. 149. See
also his United States in the World Arena, Harper and Row, 1960, p. 244:
âStalin, exploiting the disruption and weakness of the postwar world,
pressed out from the expanded base he had won during the second World
War in an effort to gain the balance of power in EurasiaâŠturning to the
East, to back Mao and to enflame the North Korean and Indochinese
CommunistsâŠâ
[5] For example, the article by cia analyst George Carver placed in
Foreign Affairs, April, 1966. See also note 22.
[6] Cf. Jean Lacouture, Vietnam between Two Truces, Random House, 1966,
p. 21. Diemâs analysis of the situation was shared by Western observers
at the time. See, for example, the comments of William Henderson, Far
Eastern specialist and executive, Council on Foreign Relations, in R. W.
Lindholm, ed., Vietnam: The First Five Years, Michigan State, 1959. He
notes âthe growing alienation of the intelligentsia,â âthe renewal of
armed dissidence in the South,â the fact that âsecurity has noticeably
deteriorated in the last two years,â all as a result of Diemâs âgrim
dictatorship,â and predicts âa steady worsening of the political climate
in free Vietnam, culminating in unforeseen disasters.â
[7] See Bernard Fall, âVietnam in the Balance,â Foreign Affairs,
October, 1966.
[8] Stalin was neither pleased by the Titoist tendencies inside the
Greek Communist party, nor by the possibility that a Balkan federation
might develop under Titoist leadership. It is, nevertheless, conceivable
that Stalin supported the Greek guerrillas at some stage of the
rebellion, in spite of the difficulty of obtaining firm documentary
evidence. Needless to say, no elaborate study is necessary to document
the British or American role in this civil conflict, from late 1944. See
D. G. Kousoulas, The Price of Freedom, Syracuse, 1953; Revolution and
Defeat, Oxford, 1965, for serious study of these events from a strongly
anti-Communist point of view.
[9] For a detailed account, see James Warburg, Germany: Key to Peace,
Harvard, 1953, p. 189f. Warburg concludes that apparently âthe Kremlin
was now prepared to accept the creation of an All-German democracy in
the Western sense of that word,â whereas the Western powers, in their
response, âfrankly admitted their plan âto secure the participation of
Germany in a purely defensive European communityâ â (i.e., nato).
[10] United States and the World Arena, pp. 344â45. Incidentally, those
who quite rightly deplore the brutal suppression of the East German and
Hungarian revolutions would do well to remember that these scandalous
events might have been avoided had the United States been willing to
consider proposals for neutralization of Central Europe. Some of George
Kennanâs recent statements provide interesting commentary on this
matter, for example, his comments on the falsity. from the outset, of
the assumption that the USSR intended to attack or intimidate by force
the Western half of the continent and that it was deterred by American
force, and his remarks on the sterility and general absurdity of the
demand for unilateral Soviet withdrawal from Eastern Germany together
with âthe inclusion of a united Germany as as a major component in a
Western defense system based primarily on nuclear weaponryâ (Pacem in
Terris, E. Reed, ed., Pocket Books, 1965).
[11] United States Policy Toward Asia, Hearings before the subcommittee
on the Far East and the Pacific of the Committee on Foreign Affairs,
House of Representatives, US Government Printing Office, 1966.
[12] New York Times Book Review, November 20, 1966. Such comments call
to mind the remarkable spectacle of President Kennedy counseling Cheddi
Jagan on the dangers of entering into a trading relationship âwhich
brought a country into a condition of economic dependence.â The
reference, of course, is to the dangers in commercial relations with the
Soviet Union. See Schlesinger, A Thousand Days, p. 776.
[13] A Thousand Days, p. 252.
[14] Though this too is imprecise. One must recall the real character of
the Trujillo regime to appreciate the full cynicism of Kennedyâs
ârealisticâ analysis.
[15]
W. W. Rostow and R. W. Hatch, An American Policy in Asia, Technology
Press and John Wiley, 1955.
[16] American private enterprise, of course, has its own ideas as to how
Indiaâs problems are to be met. The Monitor reports the insistence of
American entrepeneurs âon importing all equipment and machinery when
India has a tested capacity to meet some of their requirements. They
have insisted on importing liquid ammonia, a basic raw material, rather
than using indigenous naptha which is abundantly available. They have
laid down restrictions about pricing, distribution, profits, and
management control.â
[17] Although, to maintain perspective, we should recall that in his
wildest moments, Alfred Rosenberg spoke of the elimination of thirty
million Slavs, not the imposition of mass starvation on a quarter of the
human race. Incidentally, the analogy drawn here is highly
âirresponsible,â in the technical sense of this neologism discussed
earlier. That is, it is based on the assumption that statements and
actions of Americans are subject to the same standards and open to the
same interpretations as those of anyone else.
[18] The New York Times, February 6, 1966. Goldberg continues, the
United States is not certain that all of these are voluntary adherents.
This is not the first such demonstration of Communist duplicity. Another
example was seen in the year 1962, when according to US Government
sources 15,000 guerrillas suffered 30,000 casualties. See Arthur
Schlesinger, A Thousand Days, p. 982.
[19] Reprinted in a collection of essays, The End of Ideology: on the
Exhaustion of Political Ideas in the Fifties, Free Press, 1960. I have
no intention here of entering into the full range of issues that have
been raised in the discussion of âend of ideologyâ for the past dozen
years. It is difficult to see how a rational person could quarrel with
many of the theses that have been put forth, e.g., that at a certain
historical moment the âpolitics of civilityâ is appropriate and,
perhaps, efficacious; that one who advocates action (or inaction) has a
responsibility to assess its social cost; that dogmatic fanaticism and
âsecular religionsâ should be combated (or if possible, ignored); that
technical solutions to problems should be implemented, where possible;
that âle dogmatisme idĂ©ologique devait disparaĂźtre pour que les idĂ©es
reprissent vieâ (Aron), and so on. Since this is sometimes taken to be
an expression of an âanti-Marxistâ position, it is worth keeping in mind
that such sentiments as these have no bearing on non-Bolshevik Marxism,
as represented, for example, by such figures as Luxemburg, Pannekoek,
Korsch, Arthur Rosenberg, and others.
[20] The extent to which this âtechnologyâ is value-free is hardly very
important, given the clear commitments of those who apply it. The
problems with which research is concerned are those posed by the
Pentagon or the great corporations, not, say, by the revolutionaries of
Northeast Brazil or by SNCC. Nor am I aware of a research project
devoted to the problem of how poorly armed guerrillas might more
effectively resist a brutal and devastating military technologyâsurely
the kind of problem that would have interested the free-floating
intellectual who is now hopelessly out of date.
[21] In view of the unremitting propaganda barrage on âChinese
expansion,â perhaps a word of comment is in order. Typical of American
propaganda on this subject is Adlai Stevensonâs assessment, shortly
before his death (cf. The New York Times Magazine, March 13, 1966): âSo
far, the new Communist âdynastyâ has been very aggressive. Tibet was
swallowed, India attacked, the Malays had to fight 12 years to resist a
ânational liberationâ they could receive from the British by a more
peaceful route. Today, the apparatus of infiltration and aggression is
already at work in North Thailand.â
[22] Douglas Pike, op. cit., p. 110. This book, written by a foreign
service officer working at the Center for International Studies, M.I.T.,
poses a contrast between our side, which sympathizes with âthe usual
revolutionary stirringsâŠaround the world because they reflect inadequate
living standards or oppressive and corrupt governments,â and the backers
of ârevolutionary guerrilla warfare,â which âopposes the aspirations of
people while apparently furthering them, manipulates the individual by
persuading him to manipulate himself.â Revolutionary guerrilla warefare
is âan imported product, revolution from the outsideâ. (other examples,
besides the Vietcong, are âStalinâs exportation of armed revolution,â
the Haganah in Palestine, and the Irish Republican armyâsee pp. 32â33).
The Vietcong could not be an indigenous movement since it had âa social
construction program of such scope and ambition that of necessity it
must have been created in Hanoiâ (p. 76âbut on pp. 77â79 we read that
âorganizational activity had gone on intensively and systematically for
several yearsâ before the Lao Dong party in Hanoi had made its decision
âto begin building an organizationâ). On page 80 we find âsuch an effort
had to be the child of the North,â even though elsewhere we read of the
prominent role of the Cao Dai (p. 74), âthe first major social group to
begin actively opposing the Diem governmentâ (p. 222), and of the Hoa
Hao sect, âanother early and major participant in the NLFâ (p. 69). He
takes it as proof of Communist duplicity that in the South, the party
insisted it was âMarxist-Leninist,â thus âindicating philosophic but not
political allegiance,â whereas in the North it described itself as a
âMarxist-Leninist organization,â thus âindicating that it was int he
mainstream of the world-wide Communist movementâ (p. 150). And so on.
Also revealing is the contempt for âCinderella and all the other fools
[who] could still believe there was magic in the mature world if one
mumbled the secret incantation: solidarity, union, concordâ; for the
âgullible, misled peopleâ who were âturning the countryside into a
bedlam toppling one Saigon government after another, confounding the
Americansâ; for the âmighty force of peopleâ who in their mindless
innocence thought that âthe meek, at last, were to inherit the earth,â
that âriches would be theirs and all in the name of justice and virtue.â
One can appreciate the chagrin with which a sophisticated Western
political scientist must view this âsad and awesome spectacle.â
[23] Lacouture, op. cit., p. 188. The same military spokesman goes on,
ominously, to say that this is the problem confronting us throughout
Asia, Africa, and Latin America, and that we must find the âproper
responseâ to it.
[24] William Bundy, in A. Buchan, ed., China and the Peace of Asia,
Praeger, 1965.
[25] Lindholm, op, cit.