💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › mitchell-cowen-verter-self-and-property.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:38:20. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Self and Property
Author: Mitchell Cowen Verter
Date: May 15, 2009
Language: en
Topics: property, intellectual property, Emmanuel Levinas, Hegel, John Locke
Source: http://www.waste.org/~roadrunner/writing/Levinas/SelfAndProperty_FinalEssay_WEB.htm

Mitchell Cowen Verter

Self and Property

Introduction

One of the pillars of modern political economy is the notion of property

ownership. This idea has been important throughout the history of a

country like the United States of America, whose 18^(th) century

struggle for independence was largely motivated by the desire to prevent

the British from infringing upon its citizens’ “life, liberty, and

property.” This idea still motivates the contemporary US domestic and

international efforts to create “ownership societies” that would turn

socialized goods into private property. Although property relations may

seem inevitable to us living in today’s society, this idea of private

ownership is one whose importance depends on certain historical and

cultural conditions. Writing in 1821, G.F.W. Hegel expresses its recent

emergence saying “But it is only since yesterday, so to speak, that the

freedom of property has been recognized here and there as a principle”

(§62). Although property was an important legal category in ancient Rome

and throughout the medieval era, it was a privilege reserved only to the

portion of the populace whose status entitled them to own. In contrast,

modern political thinking is predicated on the notion that all

individuals are free persons, and that the general right to possess is

one component of this universal freedom. Because the relationship of

ownership is historical and dependent on a variety of cultural factors,

it should not be considered an inevitable one, but rather something that

is subject to change. With this in mind, this paper will endeavour to

examine the idea of property, starting with its most influential modern

exponent John Locke, and then looking at G.F.W. Hegel and Emmanuel

Levinas’s critiques of the ideas he presents.

The idea of property ownership is one that implies a certain kind of

relationship between the individual and the world. In order for the

world to be opened to ownership, it must appear as an assemblage of

objects that could potentially become possessions, and the human person

must be manifested as a subject who could potentially become an owner.

Furthermore, if the relationship between the owner and her property is

considered definitive for her identity, it might also entail that

persons relate to each other as owners, interacting with one another

through their properties. These roles for self, world, and other are

exemplified in the modern ideology which C. B. MacPherson calls

“possessive individualism”

Its possessive quality is found in its conception of the individual as

essentially the proprietor of his own person or capacities, owing

nothing to society for them. The individual was seen neither as a moral

whole, nor as part of a larger social whole, but as an owner of

himself.... The individual, it was thought, is free inasmuch as he is

proprietor of his person and capacities. … Society becomes a lot of

free equal individuals related to each other as proprietors of their own

capacities and of what they have acquired by their exercise (3).

According to MacPherson’s model, the modern conception of individual

freedom derives several intertwined ownership claims. First of all, the

individual is seen as the proprietor of her own internal nature; she

owes neither her identity nor her position to the surrounding social and

political environment. Secondly, property rights emerge from and are

justified by this initial possession: by exercising her internal

capacities through labour, she acquires the right to possess objects in

the external world. Finally, having no prior social debts to other

persons, each individual relates to the others through the medium of her

internal capacities and her external properties.

The idea that the capacities internal to the subject allow him to

appropriate something external raises the deeper question: what does it

mean to appropriate? The idea of the “self” is already complicated

enough, one which various philosophers and psychologists have sought to

define. Even if we understood what the self is, what would it then mean

to say that the self owns something, that (1) a thing which is not the

self nevertheless acquires the attribute of being-owned by the self, and

(2) the self extends some element of its selfhood onto things that are

not the self? This paper will argue that there are two possible ways of

construing this relationship between self and things. The first model is

an extrovertive and productive one: the self expands outwards into the

world, leaving marks of its selfhood upon things. The most influential

modern exemplar of this argument is John Locke’s Two Treatises on

Government, which argues that the self appropriates things by exerting

its labour upon external objects. Although Hegel is quite critical of

aspects of the Lockean theory of property, he even more directly grounds

property in the self’s extroversion. In contrast, Levinas construes the

relationship between the self and the world as an introvertive and

consumptive one: the self is created by internalizing the world, through

a process which he describes using metaphors of eating. By substituting

a consumptive model for the productive one, Levinas helps to undermine

the notion of property. The conclusion of this paper will meditate upon

the revolutionary implications of this substitution.

Locke

John Locke’s Two Treatises on Government provides perhaps the most

important and influential modern defense of individual property rights.

Locke’s thinking exemplifies MacPherson’s notion of “possessive

individualism” by defining the individual as a self-sufficient being who

employs his talents to appropriate property and relates to other

individuals through this property. Furthermore, Locke constitutes a

prototypical example what this paper considers to be an extrovertive and

productive theory of appropriation. Locke asserts that that exerting

one’s own internal energy onto external things – that labouring upon

things – is the foundation for claiming things as property. Whereas

most readers typically recognize Locke’s espousal of a productive labour

theory of property in the Second Treatise, we will also draw attention

to a prior grounding of property that Locke asserts in the First

Treatise.

In order to understand Locke’s notions of property ownership, it is

useful to trace its emergence from the tradition of natural law.

According to Karl Olivecrona, natural law theories of property began

with the Stoic principle suum cuique tribuere, according to everybody

his own (222). This maxim was typically interpreted negatively as a

prohibition against causing inuria (injury), forbidding one person from

harming another person and from infringing upon her belongings.

Olivecrona explains that this Stoic conception was grounded on the

notion that each person had a certain sphere that pertained to itself,

its suum. Assuming that nature itself provided individuals with this

sphere, various teachers of natural law delineated what was already

within it and how it could be extended. For example, Hugo Grotius argued

that each person owned things such as her life, body, limbs, reputation,

and honour. In addition to encompassing these various entities, the suum

also included a productive capacity, one’s actiones propriae (own

actions). According to Grotius, natural law also allowed one to sustain

one’s suum by collecting from nature means of subsistence.

Not only did the sphere of the suum already have some latitude within

nature, various covenants further allowed the human will to establish

dominium (legal property ownership). Natural law theorists argued that

all dominium originated from God’s original dispensation to Adam, as

described in the book of Genesis:

Have dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air,

and over every living thing that moveth upon the earth. And God said,

Behold, I have given you every herb bearing seed, which is upon the face

of all the earth, and every tree, in which is the fruit of a tree

yielding seed; to you it shall be for meat. And to every beast of the

earth, and to every fowl of the air, and to every thing that creeps upon

the earth, wherein there is life, I have given every green herb for

meat: and it was so (1:28–30).

Most legal scholars interpreted these verses to mean that God had given

all earthly creation to mankind in common. Therefore, they were left

with the problem of how individual ownership could have arisen from this

original communism. Early in human history, they posited, people must

have agreed to divide the whole of creation among themselves into

separate parcels, while still leaving a portion available for common

consumption. Writers had conflicting opinions about the nature of these

compacts: whereas Grotius maintained that individuals had a natural

right to acquire things necessary for subsistence, Samuel von Pufendorf

argued that even this private acquisition from the commons would

constitute an injury against others. Instead, he reasoned, there must

have already been some form of prior general consent.

In contrast to both Grotius and Pufendorf, Robert Filmer dispensed with

the idea that any general agreement was necessary to establish dominium.

In his justification of absolute political power and exclusive

ownership, Filmer argued that the only significant covenant was the one

detailed in the Bible. Whereas Grotius and Pufendorf interpreted Genesis

as an account of God’s dispensation of the earth to the entirety of

mankind in general, Filmer’s Patriarcha argued that God gave dominion

specifically to one man, Adam (7). From this first patriarch descended

genealogically all rightful political power and property ownership. This

divinely-sanctioned dominion, Filmer claimed, was ultimately inherited

by contemporary monarchs, who continued to maintain “a natural right of

a supreme father over every multitude” (11).

John Locke wrote Two Treatises on Government as a direct refutation of

Filmer’s absolutism. Against Filmer, he endorsed Grotius and Pufendorf’s

interpretation of the divine dispensation, explaining “it was not to

Adam in particular, exclusive of all other men: whatever dominion he had

thereby, it was not a private dominion, but a dominion in common with

the rest of mankind” (1^(st), §29). Like the natural law theorists,

Locke was then compelled to confront the question of how private

appropriation became possible. “But I shall endeavour to shew, how men

might come to have a property in several parts of that which God gave to

mankind in common, and that without any express compact of all the

commoners” (2^(nd), §25).

In the Second Treatise, Locke returns to the classical theme of the suum

and proceeds to explain how ownership arises through an extension of

one’s personal sphere. “Though the earth, and all inferior creatures be

common to all men, yet every man has a property in his own person; this

no body has any right to but himself” (2^(nd), §28). Not only are

property rights grounded in the very fact of one’s own identity as a

self and a body, Locke argues that this initial fact enables one to

extend one’s physical ownership to things in the outside world. Locke

seems to adapt within his own conception of labour the natural law idea

that one’s own actions (actiones propriae) are an extension of one’s

suum. He goes beyond the natural law concept by claiming that not only

does one own one’s actions, but also that the exertion of this embodied

action upon external things converts these objects into one’s property.

“His labour hath taken it out of the hands of nature … and hath

thereby appropriated it to himself.” (2^(nd), §29) With his labour

theory of property, Locke exemplifies the notion the extrovertive idea

of appropriation, that a force inside the self is projected upon

external objects, transforming those things into its property.

Although Locke claims that the self’s internal power of labour allows it

to appropriate things outside of the self, he does not seem to treat all

selves equally. Locke’s individualistic theory of appropriation becomes

problematic because not all individuals have their efforts rewarded with

property. Locke emphasizes throughout his treatise that labour is what

establishes personal property rights out of the common good. For

example, he states that labour “excludes the common right of other men:

for this labour being the unquestionable property of the labourer, no

man but he can have a right to what that is once joined to” (2^(nd),

§27). However, the achievement of this right seems to apply to those

labourers who are fully capable of asserting their dominion. In

contrast, another class of persons do not acquire property rights from

their labour. C.B. MacPherson argues that, by correlating labour with

property, Locke’s analysis not only justifies the acquisition of

property through labour, but also allows labour to be treated as a

commodity that can be owned or alienated (215ff).

Locke’s attitude towards the labouring class can be read most clearly in

his assertion that my property results not only from my own direct

labour but also from “the grass my horse has bit; the turfs my servant

has cut, and the ore I have digged in any place, where I have a right to

them in common with others, become my property, without the assignation

or consent of anybody. The labour that was mine, removing them out of

that common state they were in, hath fixed my property in them.”

(2^(nd), §28) Without fully explaining why, Locke asserts that the

labour of the servant does not establish his own property right, but

instead constitutes part of the labour of the master and helps to

establish the property right of the master. Although Locke neglects to

consider the position of the wage-labourer in the Two Treatises,

MacPherson points out that elsewhere he explains that labourers lack all

resources but their wages (216–7). Therefore, Locke seems to posit

labour both as a means to property and as itself a property that can be

exchanged for any other property. The fact that labour has this odd

double relationship with property would seem to indicate that it could

not be the simple root of ownership. If the person who labours is also

the person who lacks property, then one would be wise to re-examine

Locke’s labour theory of property.

Locke presents his theory of appropriation in his Second Treatise, in

the chapter entitled “Property,” famously asserting:

Though the earth, and all inferior creatures, be common to all men, yet

every man has a property in his own person: this no body has any right

to but himself. The labour of his body, and the work of his hands, we

may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he removes out of the state

that nature hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his labour

with, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it

his property. It being by him removed from the common state nature hath

placed it in, it hath by this labour something annexed to it, that

excludes the common right of other men: for this labour being the

unquestionable property of the labourer, no man but he can have a right

to what that is once joined to, at least where there is enough, and as

good, left in common for others.

Although Locke’s words are well known, Karl Olivecrona points out that

the process of appropriation is still obscure and requires further

investigation. What does it mean to “annex” a thing to oneself?

According to Olivecrona, Locke expresses this idea most clearly in the

following passage, “The fruit, or venison, which nourishes the wild

Indian, who knows no enclosure, and is still a tenant in common, must be

his, and so his, i.e. a part of him, that another can no longer have any

right to it, before it can do him any good for the support of his life.”

(2^(nd), §26) Olivecrona interprets Locke to mean that one owns

something because that thing has become a part of oneself. He argues

that Locke is assuming here that the personality is something that can

be extended — an assumption, Olivecrona claims, that Locke borrows from

natural law.

This extension of the personality was no random construction by the

teachers of natural law. They built on an idea that seems to be

universal. We all of us assume the existence of a spiritual ego. The “I”

is not identical with the body. But it is immanent in the body. In that

sense the body “belongs” to the ego. An attack on the body is

experienced as an attack on the ego itself. The same is the case with an

attack on, e.g., one’s reputation or honour. This is an attack on

oneself, on the spiritual ego. Similarly my actions are “my own” because

they are directed by the ego.

…

Since being one’s own means being a part of oneself, making a thing

one’s own means making it part of oneself. This is what Locke wants to

say in this passage. Something of oneself is infused into an object.

Then the object contains something of oneself; in this sense it is part

of oneself. Nobody else can have any right to it. That would imply that

he had a right over another free individual, which is out of the

question. (224–25).

Olivecrona’s analysis seems dubious on two points. First of all, he

asserts the self-evidence of the separation between spirit and body. He

claims that this is a “universal idea,” but there are countless examples

of thinkers and cultures that refuse to make this split. It seems

especially unlikely that Locke — an empiricist who grounds mental

processes in sensible phenomena — would separate the spiritual ego from

the physical body. Secondly and more importantly, Olivecrona collapses

together two inverse processes which may or may not be equivalent,

extension and incorporation. The first process, the extension of

personality, implies that some part of oneself marks the external object

or, as Olivecrona puts it, “is infused into an object.” The second

process, the incorporation into personality, implies that one brings

external things into one’s selfhood. The two processes work in opposite

directions: the first is externalizing and producing; the second is

internalizing and consuming. Olivecrona simply equates these two

dynamics, “Then the object contains something of oneself; in this sense

it is part of oneself” (225). In this assertion, Olivecrona seems to be

reiterating Locke’s idea that mixing oneself into a thing makes that

thing one’s own: “Whatsoever then he removes out of the State that

Nature hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his Labour with, and

joyned to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his

Property (2^(nd), §27).” Despite Olivecrona’s explanation, it is unclear

what Locke means here by ‘mixing labour’ with Nature. Even if one’s

own actions belong to one’s personal sphere, does that necessarily mean

that the things acted upon also become part of that same personal

sphere? Why would this cause the sphere of selfhood to expand rather

than just dispersing pieces of the self into the external world? This

question brings up an even deeper problem with the notions of

appropriation and acquisition: can acquisition even be considered as a

type of labour? Why should taking something as one’s own be considered a

positive, productive act? Doesn’t this seem more like an act of

consumption than of production?

When one reexamines the entirety of the Two Treatises to find how Locke

solves the mystery of property — the question of how a part of the

common good can become the property of a single individual – one quite

a discovers a more complicated answer than is often noticed. Whereas he

asserts his “labour theory of property” in the Second Treatise, this

explanation of appropriation is already predicated upon an argument from

the First Treatise. Locke’s egotistical theory of production is already

justified by an egotistical theory of consumption. Although Locke argues

that the earth was given to all men in common, he pays little attention

to the notion of communal well-being. Instead, he argues that welfare is

an individual matter, emphasizing the particular interests of each

separate individual. “The first and strongest desire God planted in men,

and wrought into the very principles of their nature, being that of

self-preservation, that is the foundation of a right to the creatures

for the particular support and use of each individual person himself”

(1^(st), §88). In this statement Locke seems to be staking out a

distinct opinion in the debate that had separated Grotius and Pufendorf.

Locke explicitly rejects Pufendorf’s notion that all humanity must have

reached a common agreement to divide property; people would have starved

to death while they waited for these negotiations to conclude (2^(nd),

§28). In addition, Locke also goes much further than Grotius: Grotius

claimed that persons have an immediate natural right only to

self-subsistence, but more substantial property rights require various

types of social agreement. In contrast, Locke argues that the individual

drive to self-preservation is so powerful that it validates all

ownership. He explains, “But how far has [God] given us [all things]? To

enjoy. As much as any one can make use of to any advantage of life

before it spoils, so much he may by his labour fix a property in”

(2^(nd), §31). Thus, Locke defines the matter of welfare as an

individual one rather than a social one. By doing so, he justifies the

appropriation of the commons with the idea that the individual has an

unlimited right to self-preservation and enjoyment.

In addition to claiming that one’s own personal welfare is the original

and primary right, Locke furthers his defence of private property by

arguing that the institution of ownership benefits the welfare of

others. He asserts that private labour creates the value of utility.

According to him, things left in their common natural state possess no

intrinsic value. It is only human industriousness that creates use

value, and enclosure of the commons that increases productivity. Thus,

Locke claims that the labour which determines private property

ultimately benefits the welfare of all, boasting that common labourers

in England are better clad than the native chiefs in America because

British industry has created value whereas everything in the Americas

has been left in its natural state.

Although Locke’s concern for social utility does seem to indicate a

concern for the well-being of others, he also employs this idea to

legitimate the concentration of ownership in the hands of a certain

class. Given that men have the natural right to promote their own

well-being and that human labour creates real use value from the raw

material of nature, those who most diligently expand their enterprise

are also those who most fully realize their purpose as human beings.

Locke argues that “God gave the world … to the use of the industrious

and rational, (and labour was to be his title to it;) not to the fancy

or covetousness of the quarrelsome and contentious.” (2^(nd), §36) David

McNally points out that Locke’s Two Treatises express the attitudes of a

nascent capitalist class identifying itself in opposition to the feudal

class that had maintained power and property solely by virtue of

heritage. He explains that Locke’s patron, the Earl of Shaftesbury,

represented a new breed of landowner who “looked on his estates not as a

passive rentier but, rather, as an improver who used his intelligence

and his capital to augment the productive powers of nature” (24). In

contrast to this rising class of rational capitalists, Locke regularly

remarks on the lack of rationality among the working class, explaining

that they never have the “opportunity to raise their thoughts above

[bare subsistence]” and that “when the hand is used to the plough and

the spade, the head is seldom elevated to sublime notions” (Quoted in

MacPherson, 223–4).

Locke’s discussion of spoilage similarly demonstrates how he assumes the

perspective of the proprietary class in considerations of social

well-being. As mentioned above, natural law theory expounded upon the

idea of inuria, the negation of one’s suum. Whatever rights one had to

one’s own personal sphere, one was always forbidden from injuring the

personal sphere of anyone else. Locke adopts this notion in his

discussion of spoilage. Given that the promotion of usefulness validates

the ownership of property, allowing things to degenerate into

uselessness would cause injury to others. Thus, Locke argues that if an

owner allowed his property to spoil, it would damage the potential

rights of other persons to promote their own well beings. “God has given

us all things richly … But how far has he given it us? To enjoy. As

much as any one can make use of to any advantage of life before it

spoils, so much he may by his labour fix a property in: whatever is

beyond this, is more than his share, and belongs to others.” (2^(nd),

§31) Although one does not need the common consent of mankind to

establish positively a property claim, dissent over negligence could

theoretically negate it. However, Locke quickly introduces an argument

that circumvents this apparent limitation to accumulation. Olivecrona

explains that the spoilage limitation only presented a real problem for

people during the first ages of the world. However, it also required

them to develop a solution to this problem. Locke explains that, through

mutual consent, men agreed upon establishing a standard that would not

spoil, affixing value to pieces of metal that would function as money.

Olivecrona explains that the effect of this agreement “was as follows:

One was no longer prohibited from appropriating more than one could

immediately consume” (230). This capacity to stockpile and accumulate

effectively enabled a class of owners to maintain control over the items

that would fulfill the consumer needs of other people, thereby

compelling them to labour for their subsistence. MacPherson cites

Locke’s economic treatises to explain how this occurs.

[Money] by compact transfers that profit, that was the reward of one

man’s labour into another man’s pocket. That which occasions this, is

the unequal distribution of money; which inequality has the same effect

too upon land, that it has upon money … For as the unequal

distribution of land, (you having more than you can, or will manure, and

another less) brings you a tenant for your land; … the same unequal

distribution of money (I having more than I can, or will employ, and

another less) brings me a tenant for my money (206)

Thus, Locke’s defence of property right is already predicated on

inequality: the accumulation of the proprietary class depends upon the

neediness of the other classes.

Locke’s inequitable view of consumption becomes apparent when he

presents his skewed understanding of the general welfare. He articulates

his notion of general social welfare when he explains why it is

necessary to form a political union. Locke defines society narrowly to

protect only a certain set of interests. What he calls a “common-wealth”

is formed through “the consent of any number of freemen capable of a

majority to unite and incorporate into such a society” (2^(nd), §99).

Locke’s analysis seems to beg the question of what would criterion make

a freeman “capable” of constituting a member of either the consenting

majority or the dissenting minority. Locke clarifies throughout his

justification of legitimate government that what makes these freemen

capable is their membership in the proprietary class. He explains that

government arises among people who are “willing to join in society with

others, who are already united, or have a mind to unite, for the mutual

preservation of their lives, liberties and estates, which I call by the

general name, property” (2^(nd), §123). In this passage and throughout

the Two Treatises, Locke equates the notion of social well being, of

common-wealth, with the promotion of the aggregated self-interests of

those classes which are socially and economically privileged enough to

acquire and maintain property.

Given that political societies are formed to protect the private

interests of property owners, Locke further argues that political power

is the capacity to make laws and penalties “for the regulating and

preserving of property, and of employing the force of the community, in

the execution of such laws, and in the defence of the common-wealth from

foreign injury; and all this only for the public good.” (§3) Locke’s

definition can again be understood as an adaptation of the Stoic and

natural law conception of inuria as the infringement upon suum. However,

throughout the Two Treatises, Locke always assumes the perspective of

the proprietor who is defending himself from injuries committed by

forces that are typically described as “foreign.” Locke justifies the

usage of absolute force in defence against this alien trespass. Already

within the pre-political state of nature, the right to self-preservation

is so paramount that it allows for murder. Locke asserts, “This makes it

lawful for a man to kill a thief, who has not in the least hurt him, nor

declared any design upon his life, any farther than, by the use of

force, so to get him in his power, as to take away his money, or what he

pleases, from him” (§18). The absolute right to protect one’s property

against any invasion applies not just to petty cutpurses but to the

sovereign himself.

Locke explains that acts akin to foreign injury can even emanate from

within the state, explaining “As conquest may be called a foreign

usurpation, so usurpation is a kind of domestic conquest” (§197). Once

men have consented to band together in order to protect their property,

Locke argues that it would be contradictory for any government to

infringe upon this right. No political power can ever have an absolute

power over the propertied class. If a ruler attempts to seize the

property of the people without its consent or even to impose a

non-consensual tax, this would effectively render this government

illegitimate and place it into a state of war with its citizens. Under

such conditions, Locke argues, one may “oppose the unlawful violence of

those who were their magistrates” in the same way that an “honest man

may oppose robbers or pirates” (§228). Just as an individual maintains

the right to kill the thief who invades his home, he may fight against

the ruler who endeavours to seize his property. Once the government has

dared to throw its people into a state of war, the people have a similar

right to respond in their own defence and to rebel, to bring back the

war (re + bellare, to war), against their government (§226).

Given that Locke attributes such importance to private property and

selfish enjoyment, it seems unclear how individuals could band together

for long enough to form a government. If individuals were motivated only

by self-interest, than any coalition between individuals would

constantly be threatened with disintegration, as various interests would

inevitably clash with each other. In contrast, G.F.W. Hegel’s Elements

of the Philosophy of Right proposes a new political model which presents

a more compelling case for a stable social order. For Hegel, the state

unites and supersedes the personalities which compose it, giving actual

shape to their interests while integrating them into the will of the

state. Rebalancing the interaction between the individual and the social

further requires Hegel to rethink the status of property and welfare,

and of production and consumption. The next section of this paper will

investigate these complex interactions.

Hegel

Like Locke, G.F.W. Hegel understands the central importance of

individual property for the modern era. Even more dramatically than

Locke, Hegel proposes an externalizing theory of property: property is

the first way that the individual expresses herself in the external

world. However, this initial expression of particular personality is

consummated and superseded by the universality of the ethical sphere,

which imposes social limits upon property rights and the expression of

personality. Whereas Hegel echoes Locke’s individually productive notion

of property, his analysis of consumption does not begin with individual

self-preservation but rather with social welfare. Nevertheless, Hegel

contends that individual particularity impacts the universal social

realm in a way that ultimately makes individual welfare dependent upon

productivity.

Within Philosophy of Right, Hegel employs logical terminology to explain

his political concepts. He explains that the basis of right is the

freedom of the will. At first, however, this freedom is expressed only

negatively, as the fleeing away from all commitments. To overcome this

stage, the will must strive to give a concrete actuality to its freedom

by positing itself as a particular, individual person. Private property

is one of the expressions of the subjective particularity, which Hegel

claims is “the pivotal and focal difference between antiquity and the

modern era” (§124). Unlike Locke, Hegel does not try to ground ownership

in the human necessity of self-preservation, but rather insists that it

has its own separate value. “In relation to needs – if these are taken

as primary – the possession of property appears as a means; but the

true position is that, from the point of view of freedom, property, as

the first existence of freedom, is an essential end for itself” (§45).

For Hegel, property is the initial way that the will establishes its

freedom in the world. The only way that a freedom becomes determinate is

when the subject fixes itself in a particular content, by establishing

its objective presence through property. In an even more radical manner

than Locke, Hegel describes property as the foundation of human right.

Jay Lampert explains, “It is not that we have a right to property but

rather that that right is at first property” (58). That is, property is

the manner in which self-determination is first enacted. In order for

the free subjective will to emerge as something actual, it must posit

itself as something in the external world, externalizing its interior

will in an object that becomes its property.

Whereas the person has a right to externalize himself, the external

world has no contrary capacity to resist acquisition. Only the human

being has a free will that can determine ends; raw matter does not.

Hegel assumes that the environment has no rights of its own. Nature is

volitionally empty, awaiting its animation by the human spirit. “A

person has as his substantive end the right of putting his will into any

and every thing and thereby making it his, because it has no such end in

itself and derives its destiny and soul from his will. This is the

absolute right of appropriation which man has over all ‘things’” (§44).

In this and other statements, Hegel clearly articulates the idea that

Olivecrona attributed already to Locke: the spirit of the self can

infuse itself into things, incorporating them into its personal sphere

and making them part of its property. Even more emphatically than Locke,

Hegel justifies ownership with the logic of productive extroversion.

Hegel employs the concept of res nullis to explain further how things

become capable of being owned. For a thing to become private property,

it must not already have a will attached to it; it must be a null thing,

a res nullis. According to Hegel, the actuality of ownership depends

upon the persistence of a present will. He asserts that a will is

present within a possessed object over the course of a certain time.

When this time elapses, all will is absented from the object. According

to Hegel, this justified the reappropriation of historical artefacts, as

well as the seizure of Church property during the Reformation (§64).

Hegel’s employment of the ancient legal concept of res nullis raises

important questions about how the world is constituted. Hegel insists

that one’s property claims persist as long as one’s will continues to be

expressed in them, and becomes res nullis after this. However, doesn’t

the fact that the world has been constructed by the labours of other

people already place an individual into a certain kind of debt? How does

one determine when the presence of a will has expired? There are many

cases in which a certain group of people fights to regain rights to the

artefacts of their culture. For examples, natives in the Americas still

petition for the repatriation of their ancestors’ burial remains from

the museums that display them as curiosities (“Reclaiming Identity”).

The question of whether or not to consider a given thing a res nullis

can easily become a contentious issue, with one party claiming that a

disputed item had been abandoned and the other party claiming it had

been usurped.

As a counterpoint to this notion of a will-annulled world, Hegel insists

that one’s property claims must necessarily respect the free wills of

others. A thing can become property (1) because things have no wills of

their own, and (2) when other wills have been absented from it. In

contrast, a thing could not become property if it were already possessed

by someone else. A will cannot appropriate something that is already

infused by the will of another. Because the will has absolute power over

things, ownership must be free, complete, and exclusive: at any given

time, property rights can only be claimed by one particular entity.

Therefore, Hegel explains that ownership and first occupancy are

correlative notions, because one can never make a claim on something

already occupied and one can always make a claim on something unoccupied

(§50).

Because a single property manifests an exclusive will, the totality of

properties can function as a medium through which various wills can

communicate. One person can interact with another through this

objectivity. According to Dudley Knowles, Hegel’s imperative of right

“Be a person and respect others as persons” (§36) thus results in a

corollary, “claim property rights and respect the property rights of

others” (56). Through property, the person establishes a concrete

existence in the external world. This substance is not merely a hunk of

anonymous matter: when one claims possession of a thing, one imposes a

representative mark upon it, indicating the presence of one’s will in

it, externalizing the subject into an objective thing that others can

recognize. By doing so, one indicates to others that one is the rightful

owner of this thing and that their acquisitive wills are excluded from

it. Thus, property provides the initial means through which one person

can rightfully recognize another. The first way in which this type of

mutual recognition can be exercised is the contract.

Contracts interest Hegel for the way that they transform the human will.

In a contract, separate parties relate to and exist for each other as

property owners. One person creates a bond with another by identifying a

common will that binds them. In an exchange of properties, each party

alienates his own possessive will infusing an object so that the other

party may possess it. At the same time, however, the contract itself

already expresses this wilful abandonment of the will: although the

particular will attached to the particular object is negated, volition

persists in a higher form. Thus, contract does not merely exchange two

objects but more importantly affects a synthesis between separate wills,

in which different wills surrender their differences to form a greater

unity, a common will, while still maintaining their own separation and

distinctiveness.

Whereas contracts create a common will out of two or more separate

wills, they can never produce the universal will embodied by the state.

The universality of the state conditions and makes possible every

transformation of individual particularity and every common agreement.

Hegel applies this argument to criticize the idea — found in Rousseau

but equally resonant with Locke — that the state emerges out of

contractual relationship of everyone with everyone.

In a contract, there are two identical wills, both of which are persons

and wish to remain owners of property …. But in the case of the state,

this is different from the outset, for the arbitrary will of individuals

is not in a position to break away from the state, because the

individual is already by nature a citizen of it. It is the rational

destiny of human being to live in the state. (§75)

Against the idea that the assemblage of individual wills is sufficient

to comprise the totality of the state, Hegel insists that the

imperatives of the state transcends the arbitrary interests of

particular personalities collected together. Thus, Hegel also dispenses

with the Lockean notion that the goal of the state is merely to promote

private interests. According to Locke, the state originates out of a

general contract made among all individual property owners to promote

and protect their separate properties. Although Hegel agrees that the

state provides a context within which each individual will can express

her individuality, it also constitutes a larger social unity. “Union as

such is itself the true content and end, and the destiny of individuals

is to lead a universal life; their further particular[ity] have this

…substantial and universally valid basis as their point of departure

and result” (§258). According to Hegel, one only achieves genuine

individuality when one becomes a member of the state (§258), when one’s

particular will is integrated into its universal will. Therefore, the

destiny of the state necessarily supersedes the interests of the

individual, transcending the mere protection of private property.

For Hegel, man’s substantial existence culminates with the development

of the state. However, the state does not eliminate the rights of the

individual but rather fulfills them in a concrete manner. The state must

respect individuality and safeguard the abstract rights of persons. As

mentioned above, Hegel asserts that the most significant development of

the modern age is its assertion of subjective personality. This spirit

only becomes manifested in the modern state: “The principle of modern

states has enormous strength and depth because it allows the principle

of subjectivity to attain fulfillment in the self-sufficient extreme of

personal particularity, while at the same time bringing it back to

substantial unity and to preserving this unity in the principle of

subjectivity itself” (§260). Thus, he criticizes Plato’s Republic for

denying the general value of individual personality and for violating

the specific right to hold private property (§262, §48). Because it is

such a fundamental part of being an individual, Hegel asserts that

everyone must have property, even though the amount does not necessarily

have to be equal.

Hegel explains how the state promotes and protects property through a

variety of institutions. Acquisitions of property and transactions

between owners do not occur in some pre-civilized state of nature, but

rather already within a social context. The rights of the person already

depend upon the laws of the state. In order to ensure that one can

exercise the freedom to acquire things and that one’s claim will be

respected by others, this appropriation must be given a universal

sanction. The ownership of this property must be socially recognized

through abiding with social formalities, such as physical boundary

markers and notarized deeds and state registries (§217). According to

Hegel, most property is acquired through contracts, which also must

accord with the legal norms stipulated by the government. Because

property is sanctioned and validated by society, crimes against it are

not just wrongs committed against individuals, but rather against

society as a whole (§218). For this reason, the state therefore must

maintain the security of society by enforcing the rights of property

owners through its administration of justice (§208).

As the universal element that sanctions the particular interests of

individuals, the state also maintains the capacity to curtail those

interests. Hegel thus disagrees with Locke’s notion that the right to

property is paramount above all else, even above any governmental

attempt to infringe upon it. Hegel directly contradicts this idea,

explaining that the state’s “substantial essence does not consist

unconditionally in the protection and safeguarding of the lives and

property of individuals as such. The state is rather that higher

instance which may even itself lay claim to the lives and property of

individuals and require their sacrifice” (§100). Hegel further asserts

that when the state supersedes an individual’s immediate self-interest,

it is actually fulfilling his more profound rights. The first place

where this is demonstrated is in the realm of criminal wrong. In the

Second Treatise, Locke focuses only on the injury of theft, the unjust

seizure of personal property. In contrast, Hegel argues that crime

develops from personality itself. When the person attaches more

importance to individual particularity than the universal, she can

become evil. Hegel asserts that “self-consciousness is capable of making

into its principle either the universal in and for itself, or the

arbitrariness of its own particularity, giving the latter precedence

over the universal and realizing it through its actions – i.e. it is

capable of being evil” (§139). The individual’s moral agency allows him

both to act out of particularity and to be held responsible for those

actions. Whereas one would have the freedom to do whatever one wished if

one lived in isolation, one already exists within a social sphere in

which one’s particular will and one’s private property maintains

relationships with the external world. Under such circumstances, one’s

arbitrary actions can potentially act bring harm to others. For this

reason, the state maintains a police force and other regulatory powers

to curb the potential misuse of property “with or without the consent of

individuals.” (§100) In the end, though, Hegel argues that these

punishments do not merely harm but actually honour the criminal

individual by treating him as a rational person.

Hegel declares that there is one moment within the ethical life of the

state in which it absolutely overrides all rights of personality and

property. In times of war, citizens have the substantial duty to defend

the sovereign state even at the sacrifice of their own lives and

property. Hegel remarks, “It is a grave miscalculation if the state when

it requires this sacrifice is simply equated with civil society and if

its ultimate end is seen merely as the security of the life and property

of individuals” (§324). He reasons that, because life and property only

take upon a concrete significance within the universal realm of the

state, it would be contradictory to refuse to support it on selfish

grounds. Moreover, war itself has an ethical meaning relative to

property. War is not a terrible accident that befalls unfortunate

nations, but rather is a necessary negative moment in the dialectical

development of world spirit, shaking nations free from stagnation and

strengthening them through conflict. Under such conditions, the

particularity of persons and their property is revealed as that which

should be sacrificed in order to reach a higher level of universality:

“War is that condition in which the vanity of temporal things and

temporal goods – which tends at other times to be merely a pious

phrase – takes on a serious significance, and it is accordingly the

moment in which the ideality of the particular attains its right and

becomes actuality” (§324). For Hegel, war is thus the ultimate example

of how universality can assert its prerogative over particularity,

disintegrating individual interests and property rights in favour of its

grander destiny.

One’s particular interests are limited by the universal not just in the

form of the state, but also within intersubjective relationships. Hegel

insists that any legitimate contract must allow each individual to

maintain the universal part of himself, his own free will. One can

rightfully alienate only what is alienable, either things produced or

moments of labour, but not the entirety of personality. Therefore, Hegel

claims that slaves always preserve an absolute right to free themselves

from their bondage (§66). In addition, Hegel also argues that certain

rights of other people are more universal than my own right to property.

As mentioned above, Hegel argues that property ownership is an

expression of human freedom rather than a fulfillment of human need. In

contrast, Locke had directly concluded the right to appropriate from the

right to self-preservation, the right to accumulate upon the right to

enjoy. Locke further claimed that this would allow one to kill a thief

because of the way he infringes upon this natural right. In contrast,

Hegel states that

Life, as the totality of ends, has a right in opposition to abstract

right. If, for example, it can be preserved by stealing a loaf, this

certainly constitutes an infringement on someone’s property, but it

would be wrong to regard such an action as common theft. If someone

whose life is in danger were not allowed to take measures to save

himself, he would be destined to forfeit all his rights, and since he

would deprived of life, his entire freedom would be negated (§127).

Thus, Hegel claims that the right to property is a restricted embodiment

of freedom, whereas the right to human life is an infinite right, the

very right to have any rights at all. Here, Hegel’s analysis seems more

sensible than Locke’s. Locke’s assertion that one has the right to

murder a thief seems unreasonable, a punishment whose severity far

exceeds the nature of the crime. Theft is a crime that is (1) inflicted

upon a thing and (2) damages part of one’s estate; whereas capital

punishment is (1) inflicted upon a person and (2) damages the entirety

of their life. In justifying the right to murder, Locke seems to be

taking the self’s right to self-preservation and property to a dangerous

extreme. Furthermore, Hegel’s analysis seems notable for the way that it

transcends the perspective of the property-owning self. Although he

agrees that theft constitutes a criminal wrong, Hegel recognizes that

even the criminal has rights. In certain cases, therefore, a crime

against a property-owning self might be mitigated because of the other,

criminal person’s more fundamental right to self-preservation.

Whereas property rights emerge initially from one’s particular freedom,

Hegel explains that the notion of welfare already involves the welfare

of other people. Not only does moral duty compel one to work towards the

general good (§134), one is already involved in the dynamic interactions

of civil society, which coordinates the self-interests of the

multiplicity of individuals. For this reason, one’s own personal needs

already relate to the needs of other people. Hegel explains

“particularity … is subjective need, which attains its satisfaction by

means of external things which are likewise the property and product of

the needs and wills of others” (§189). Within a political economy that

weaves together aggregate commercial relationships, an individual

discovers new social requirements and possibilities that are created by

other individuals.

Like Locke, Hegel asserts that human labour creates social value,

enabling one to transcend to the merely natural. However, Locke tends to

consider labour mostly from the perspective of the person who owns

labour power. When he discusses its role in fulfilling needs – for

example, when he contrasts the comforts of the native American with

those of the English day-labourer – he does so in order to promote the

concept of private ownership and private industry. In contrast, Hegel

provides a more multifaceted analysis of the economic dynamic,

explaining:

The mediation whereby appropriate and particularized means are acquired

and prepared for similarly particularized needs is work. By the most

diverse processes, work specifically applies to these numerous ends the

material which is immediately provided by nature. The process of

formation gives the means their value and appropriateness, so that man,

as a consumer, is chiefly concerned with human products, and it is human

effort which he consumes (§196).

In this passage, Hegel considers not only the role of the producer in

creating value but also that of the consumer who enjoys things produced

by others. Given that the productive effort of mankind generates the

capacity to consume, Hegel one must again confront the question of how

human welfare is distributed, of how the right to consume is predicated

on the duty to produce.

For Hegel, differences between particular individuals entail differences

in the degree to which one can partake in consuming value. Because it is

such a fundamental part of being an individual, Hegel asserts that

everyone must have property. However, he dispenses with the notion that

the amount should be equal, calling the notion that everyone should be

able to meet the needs of their subsistence a “moral wish” (§49).

Instead, he contends that the each person’s particular skills and

resources will inevitably produce inequality (§200). Nevertheless Hegel

argues that civil society must endeavour to provide basic livelihood and

social welfare for everyone, through the administration of civil

society’s regulatory police powers (§230), and through the corporations

that tend to the concerns of the commercial classes (§250).

By consistently linking together welfare and livelihood, however, Hegel

ultimately roots the right of consumption in the capacity for

production. Hegel’s logic is most evident in his discussion of the

social underclass, the rabble. Society, he argues, not only must be

concerned with the right to subsistence, but also with the duty to

perform. “It is not just starvation that is at stake here; the wider

viewpoint is the need to prevent a rabble from emerging. Since civil

society is responsible for feeding its members, it also has the right to

press them to provide for their own livelihood” (§240). Although Hegel

does assert that people should have enough to survive, he also warns

that the state should not indulge them. They must also maintain the

honour that comes from supporting themselves with their own labour. Even

subsistence consumption should require some sort of productive activity

— perhaps, Hegel suggests, the poor should be directed to beg (§245).

Hegel’s analysis of property and welfare advances significantly upon the

Locke’s model, introducing a social and ethical dimension into processes

which Locke considers to be fundamentally individual. Although Hegel

proposes a notion of property that is even more explicitly productive

and externalizing than Locke’s, he introduces social limits upon

ownership. Furthermore, he grounds the concept of welfare in social life

rather than in individual self-preservation. However, Hegel asserts that

the productive powers of the particular individual should rightfully

determine the extent to which one should be allowed to consume social

welfare. In contrast, Emmanuel Levinas’s notion of selfhood begins with

consumption rather than production, leading him to reconceptualise

radically the role of property.

Levinas

The work of Emmanuel Levinas attempts to rethink the position of the

individual self, reconsidering the way it is structured as a

responsibility to the other person. Such an inquiry into selfhood

necessarily raises the question of what is subsumed within the personal

sphere, the suum. In his first magnum opus, Totality and Infinity,

Levinas expresses this idea with a phrase borrowed from both Hegel and

Sartre, writing that individual is ‘for-itself.’ “The subject is

‘for itself.’ It represents itself and knows itself as long as it is.

But in knowing or representing itself, it possesses itself, dominates

itself, extends its identity to what of itself comes to refute its

identity” (87). Selfhood, Levinas explains, is not a stable identity but

a process of self-identification, of appropriating the diversity of

otherness and integrating it back into a unitary selfhood. Within

Totality and Infinity, he delineates the steps by which this procedure

occurs. Before the self involves itself in productive self-creation, he

explains, its experience begins through consumption.

Levinas explains that the ego is first produced as something that enjoys

existence. The ego is neither a particular instance of a universal

category nor something that partakes of elemental forces or codes, but

rather something that lives a contented life, living from its contents,

fulfilling itself by filling itself. Levinas describes this initial

relationship to the world using the metaphorical language of eating,

stating “Nourishment … is the transmutation of the other into the

same, which is in the essence of enjoyment: an energy that is other,

recognized as other … becomes, in enjoyment, my own energy, my

strength, me. All enjoyment is in this sense alimentation” (111). This

description of the dynamic emergence of selfhood contrasts dramatically

with the analyses of Hegel and Locke. For Hegel, particularity first

develops through the exercise of freedom, by the way one expresses

oneself through the externalization of one’s will in property. Although

Locke begins with self-preservation and the biblical dispensation for

enjoyment, it is productive labour that turns the world into one’s own.

In contrast, Levinas explains that the self initially relates to the

other through a process of incorporation and not externalization,

through consumption and not production. By emphasizing consumption,

Levinas seems to be drawing attention the way in which one begins one’s

existence — not as an agent asserting its sovereign will and projecting

its spirit onto things but rather as someone vulnerable who needs to be

sustained by the world in order to survive.

More than a reaction to either Locke or Hegel, Levinas’s emphasis on

consumption seems to be a response to the way that Heidegger initially

situates Dasein (human being). According to Heidegger, Dasein finds

itself already thrown into a situation that surpasses it (174:135).

Although this state of thrownness indicates certain susceptibility

within its constitution, Dasein overcomes this passivity by recognizing

how it is already engaged in the world. Dasein is already involved in a

variety of productive relationships; it is related to things through

relationships of utility that beckon to its hand. Once Dasein recognizes

its engaged existence through the possessive relationships of mine-ness

(Jemeinenigkeit) and authenticity / own-ness (Eigenlich), it can

actively grasp things as they refer to it as ready-to-hand (Vorhanden),

concerning itself by “producing, manipulating, and the like” (88) .

According to Levinas, one first relates to the world through the mouth

that eats rather than the hand that uses: man’s initial relationship is

consuming the elemental rather than acting within Being. He remarks,

“The consumption of foods is the food of life” (114). Therefore, he

criticizes Heidegger’s analysis for its overemphasis on productivity at

the expense of consumption, remarking, “[Heidegger’s model of the] world

as a set of implements ... bears witness to a particular organization of

labour in which foods take on the signification of fuel in the economic

machinery.... Dasein in Heidegger is never hungry” (134).

Levinas describes several phenomenological transformations that respond

to this dynamic of hunger. Part of this process entails the development

of an economy in which personal property can exist. In itself, pure

enjoyment does not engender any property ownership. Levinas employs the

notion of the “elemental” to explain why this is so. Whereas Hegel finds

a lack of will, a res nullis, within the natural world, Levinas

describes it as permeated by anonymous elemental forces. Qualities

without substances content sensible enjoyment. For example, Levinas

states that one enjoys the “blue of the sky” (141). Here, he seems to be

claiming that affectivity responds to the adjectival blue rather than a

nominal thing such as the ideal of blueness, or the particular object

described by blue, the sky. Affect responds to intensities, not to

objects. Thus, Levinas states that these elements are “coming always

without my being able to possess the source” (141). That is, within

sensibility, one does not find concrete things which could be seized as

property. Furthermore, Levinas explains enjoyment as a passive process,

in which one is affected, undergoing waves of sensation. Levinas thus

claims that ownership is ambiguous within this realm, writing “to

possess by enjoying is also to be possessed” (158). In order for private

property to emerge, the relationship of enjoyment must be transformed

into a new configuration, a phenomenon which Levinas calls the Home.

Levinas’s notion of the Home seems to be an adaptation of Heidegger’s

description of how the individual relates to the world. In Being and

Time, Heidegger argues that the self is not separated from things as a

subject is from an object, but is already engaged in the world.

According to Heidegger, the reason why Dasein is always already in a

productive, manipulative relationship with the world is because it is

always already “dwelling alongside” the world (54:80ff). Levinas’s

discussion of the “Home” seems to indicate his ironic critique of this

idea. For Levinas, the Home is precisely the event that terminates

engagement, separating the individual from the immediacy of his

enjoyment. “Man abides in the world as having come to it from a private

domain, from being at home with himself, in which at each moment that he

retires” (152). Emerging from the welcome granted to him by an other

person’s hospitality, the home establishes a private being, walled off

from the anonymity of sensible elements.

By situating oneself inside the private realm of one’s domicile, one can

relate the outside world back to oneself, laying claim to things within

it as one’s property. This home enables labour and possession by

creating a breach between the self and the elements in which it had been

absorbed. Through this distance, one can exercise the power of a

labouring hand which exercises labour and identifies property.

Overcoming the transience of sensual affect, the hand draws from the

element concrete things, objects that endure through time. In many ways,

Levinas’s description of how property is acquired echoes Hegel’s notion

that possession negates the independence of the thing (§59): “labour in

its possessive grasp suspends the independence of the element… as

property the thing is an existent that has lost its being” (158). For

Levinas as for Hegel, possession entails the absolute domination of the

property by the owner.

According to Levinas, my encounter with the other person prevents the

spread of this domination. This transcendental experience of confronting

another person is not akin either to sensual enjoyment or to masterful

possession. The other person is an exterior entity, someone that cannot

be absorbed into my internal sphere or made into part of my identity.

However, this encounter is not experienced as a negative limit but

rather as a something that is overly positive. The other person,

according to Levinas, is not something that eludes the grasp of

possession but someone who overwhelms it. In this experience, he claims,

“the I, nonetheless, contains in itself what it can neither contain nor

receive solely by virtue of its own identity” (27). Envisioning the

other person’s visage, one’s mind is confronted with a paradoxical

experience of containing more than its capacity, something that could

not have come from consciousness itself and that consciousness can not

integrate into the self’s own identity. When the other person expresses

herself, she produces an image or a work that can be appropriated, yet

simultaneously she also expresses a transcendence that cannot be

dominated. However she presents herself, she both preserves her own

privacy and maintains the ability to respond in unforeseeable ways.

According to Levinas, the other person transcends not just the self’s

power, but its power for power (198). The only way that one could

attempt to exercise absolute power over another person, to appropriate

them as property, would be to murder them. However, murder would grant

one possession of only a corpse, not the person herself.

The encounter with the other person alters the self’s intimate

relationship to the world it possesses and allows for the emergence of a

common sphere. Complementing the phenomenology of the Home, Levinas

describes another process that conditions ownership, the genesis of the

general. He explains that, because the other person halts the self’s

effort to appropriate, it both throws property into question and

conditions it. “Possession itself refers to more profound metaphysical

relations: a thing does not resist acquisition. Other possessors –

those whom one cannot possess – contest and therefore can sanction

possession itself” (162). The presence of other persons challenges my

immediate enjoyment of goods, and removes me from my solitary experience

of them. Paradoxically, however, this same interaction also allows for

the establishment of property. In order for appropriation to occur, a

subject must be counterposed against a field of objects. According to

Levinas, one achieves this separation by presenting oneself and one’s

goods to the outside gaze of the visage, to the other person’s vision.

“In order that I be able to see things in themselves, that is, represent

them to myself, refuse both enjoyment and possession, I must know how to

give what I possess” (171). According to Levinas, I become aware of the

general sphere once I generously offer my world to the other person.

With this analysis, Levinas’s account of the commons differs

dramatically from Locke and Hegel. Although Locke believes that the

world was given to man in common, only the negative duty to avoid

injuring others remains after creation. Since the right to existence and

the right to property are individuated, generality can only emerge from

a consent reached between separated persons pursuing their own ends. On

the other hand, Hegel understands the universal order of the state as

that which already conditions the substantial objectification of the

particular person. In contrast, Levinas asserts that I move from my own

solitary enjoyment to the common world through communicating with the

other person and entering into commerce with him. Levinas’s analysis of

the commons seems to be preferable than that of Locke, who treats the

commons either as a something natural that should be privatized or as

the epiphenomenal outcome of aggregated interests. The contrast between

Hegel and Levinas, the question of whether we move from the general to

the interpersonal or the interpersonal to the general, is much more

subtle. Here it seems worth noting, though, that within The Philosophy

of Right, Hegel only seems to consider the logical categories of

particularity and universality. He has no comparable term for alterity,

no way to discuss the unique phenomenon of the other person, as he did

in the Phenomenology of Spirit.

For Levinas, the realm of generality is populated not by property or by

objects, but by works. Labour not only incorporates things into my

existence, it also produces a thing exterior to myself, a work, a thing

that attests to the absence of the worker. Levinas uses this notion of

the work to argue against Locke and Hegel’s assertion that labour

creates property. “The product of labour is not an inalienable

possession, and it can be usurped by the Other. Works have a destiny

independent of the I, are integrated into an ensemble of works: they can

be exchanged, that is, be maintained in the anonymity of money” (176).

Whereas Hegel explained how property expresses the self by the way it

embodies the human will, Levinas insists that the work expresses the

will as something from which the will has removed itself. Production for

Levinas does not expand the personal sphere, but rather creates

something external to it, something that can be expropriated and

manipulated by other wills. For Levinas, my labour not only secures what

belongs to me, but also situates those expressions of myself in a

general economy where they can be appropriated by anyone. Therefore, the

very act of self-assertion and self-manifestation is already a primary

exposure and self-alienation. “The other can dispossess me of my work,

take it or buy it, and thus direct my very behaviour; I am exposed to

instigation. The work is destined to this alien Sinngebung

[meaning-giving] from the moment of its origin in me” (227).

Levinas describes the reverse process in a manner that further

complicates the idea of ownership. Just as our absence is signalled in

the ways that we express ourselves in our works, we also appropriate

absences through our acquisitions. The other person, Levinas explains,

is symbolized through the way that he has expressed himself in his

works. Thus, I can acquire a certain kind of access to him through the

way the person has expressed himself, but, Levinas explains, “we

penetrate into this interior world as by burglary” (177). Levinas’s

metaphor of burglary seems particularly striking in this discussion of

property. As mentioned before, the primary threat against which Locke’s

treatise defends is that of robbery: because the primary right of

individuals is to promote their own self-interest, any infraction upon

this privilege legitimates severe retribution. In contrast, Levinas’s

describes how property is already theft: property is already situated in

a public realm, and thus already subject to the economic dynamics of

dispossession. More strikingly, Levinas’s example reconstrues the notion

of thievery and the way it affects the personal sphere. For Levinas, the

thief does not represent someone who takes property away from the sphere

of selfhood, the suum, but rather someone who penetrates into it.

Levinas further explores the susceptibility of the personal sphere in

his second major book, Otherwise than Being. Otherwise than Being

reworks the conceptual architecture of Totality and Infinity, focusing

more closely on how the personal sphere develops from its responsibility

to other persons. According to Levinas, the Western idea of selfhood is

based on the idea that the self can possess itself through an act of

identification. “In self-consciousness we identify ourselves across the

multiplicity of temporal phases. It is as though subjective life in the

form of consciousness consisted in being itself losing itself and

finding itself again so as to possess itself by showing itself,

proposing itself as a theme, exposing itself in truth” (99). In this

statement, Levinas seems to be locating the problem of

self-consciousness in what he refers to in an early essay as

Heraclitus’s problem of the “illusory present” (“Reflections,” 65).

Given that everything changes through the dynamic flux of time, how

could one ever posit a stable identity for a thing such as the self? If

one is always changing, isn’t the self already dispersed in otherness?

Levinas claims that philosophy has consistently tried to resolve these

problems by developing ways that one can integrate this diversity. It

has proposed various themes through which one can grasp phenomena,

allowing one to convert the external other into internal property and

thereby establish self-possession.

Levinas challenges the authority of these thematic organizing principles

by demonstrating that before consciousness can appropriate the

ex-ternal, the self is already ex-posed, already open to otherness. From

the very beginning, the suum is already directed by its responsibility

to other people. Otherwise than Being explains this prior exposure by

clarifying one of the most puzzling aspects of Totality and Infinity:

how is the “other” related to the “Other.” Totality and Infinity had

presented two stages of the self’s development. First, the self emerges

by integrating the “other” into the same, creating the identity of the

self. Secondly, the self relates to the human “Other” as a

transcendental entity that can not be appropriated. In Otherwise than

Being, Levinas looks more carefully at the first stage of this process,

explaining how sensible enjoyment and consumption is already ethical.

Within sensibility, the self does not yet exist as a self-sufficient

entity. As in Totality and Infinity, Levinas explains that consumption

is the process by which the self achieves its identity. “The taste is

the way a sensible subject becomes a volume, or the irreducible event in

which the spatial phenomenon of biting becomes the identification called

me, which becomes me through the life that lives from its very life”

(73). Levinas argues that within this eating there is already a hunger

that drives it. Whereas consciousness is driven to fulfill itself with

contents, there is an underlying emptiness that perpetually troubles

this fullness. According to Levinas, this emptiness indicates the

presence of the other person’s absence. “The relationship with the other

puts me into question, empties of myself and empties me without end,

showing me ever new resources. I didn’t know I was so rich, but I no

longer have the right to keep anything for myself” (“Meaning”, 94).

One’s responsibility towards the other splits me open, preventing me

from isolating myself as a self-sufficient, self-possessed identity.

Levinas describes this process as an inversion and reversal of

consumption: eating not only creates identity by internalizing the

outside; it is also a “gnawing away at this very identity – identity

gnawing away at itself – in a remorse” (OTB, 114).

According to Levinas, the phenomenology of sensibility indicates an

underlying vulnerability and exposedness to other persons. In contrast

to Totality and Infinity‘s claim that the self could be characterized as

“for itself,” Levinas describes it in Otherwise than Being as a

“for-the-other.” The very movement of incorporating otherness is also

equivalent to being haunted by others already within oneself. The self

is already committed to others before it is concerned with itself: it is

exposed, posited in an external space filled with the wills of others.

In Totality and Infinity, Levinas explained that the sphere of

generality was comprised by works that testified to the absent wills of

other people. This would suggest that, when we consume what the world

offers, we are appropriating the remnants of others, incorporating their

works and their actions as our own. We are thus claimed by others from

the inside; we are created as entities who are already responsible for

the legacy that other persons have left behind. Levinas explains “There

is a paradox in responsibility, in that I am obliged without this

obligation having begun in me, as though an order slipped into my

consciousness like a thief, smuggled itself in me” (13). As in Totality

and Infinity, Levinas’s reference to the thief refers not to the act of

taking away an external object, but of penetrating into the interior. In

Otherwise than Being, Levinas pushes this metaphor even further, to

assert that consumption animates one’s own identity from the inside as a

responsibility towards others.

With this understanding of the world, Levinas helps us to reconsider and

perhaps to overcome the prominence that the notion of private property

has assumed in this moment of history. Levinas does so by reconsidering

the notions of self, world, and other upon which are founded the

ideology of possessive individualism and the institution of ownership,

as well as the theories of both Hegel and Locke. In both of these

writers, (1) the self is understood as an agent who exercises his labour

to extend his sphere of selfhood; and (2) the world is understood as an

empty vessel awaiting animation by the human will. Locke and Hegel do

differ significantly with regard to their views on other people. Locke

practically ignores social duties, whereas Hegel shows how universal

social concerns always limit individual actions. Nevertheless, even

Hegel argues that the particularity of each individual’s capacities and

resources counterbalance the general right to social welfare, thereby

sanctioning inequities in property ownership and modes of subsistence.

In contrast, Levinas does not understand the world as merely an empty

field awaiting human agency. For Levinas, the world is already occupied,

haunted by the efforts of past generations of workers. The self begins

its existence not as a productive labourer but as a consumer already

enjoying the environment that others have created. Whereas Levinas’s

viewpoint seems to be a vast improvement over both Locke and Hegel’s, he

still shares a blind spot with the two of them. All three writers seem

excessively humanist: for all of them, what matters the most in the

world is the presence of human wills, either the self’s or the other

person’s or society’s. The natural world itself exerts no significant

claim on its own behalf. For this reason, we still need to consider what

sorts of new ethical thinking will be adequate to respond to the

environmental challenges confronting our planet today.

Conclusion

By analysing the primary encounter between self and world as one of

consumption rather than production, Levinas becomes interesting for

modern political-economic thought. He dislodges the central category of

property ownership, conceiving selfhood as an absolute generosity. “The

subjectivity of a man of flesh and blood … is a being torn up from

oneself for another in the giving to other of the bread from one’s

mouth” (142). Although Levinas’s hyperbolic language is rhetorically

radical, it is not entirely clear the extent to which it can be read as

being politically radical. Despite Levinas’s occasional references to

Marx and his philosophical usage of the term “anarchy,” he still seems

to support politically the “pathos of liberalism” (TI, 120).

Nevertheless, this paper will conclude by trying to push Levinas’s

thought in a more revolutionary direction. This will be done by

analysing how this essay’s themes of property, production, and

consumption are discussed by the Peter Kropotkin in his seminal

declaration of anarchocommunism, The Conquest of Bread.

Kropotkin criticizes the idea of property ownership because, like

Levinas, he understands the world to be constituted by the works of

other people. Thus, Kropotkin argues that no individual can lay claim to

any particular object because the value of each thing depends on the

efforts of an incalculable number of others. “And even to-day; the value

of each dwelling, factory, and warehouse, which has been created by the

accumulated labour of the millions of workers, now dead and buried, is

only maintained by the very presence and labour of legions of the men

who now inhabit that special corner of the globe” (6). According to

Kropotkin, property claims are impossible because one’s existence

already depends upon an infinite debt to others. The world within which

one acts is already constituted by the historical deeds of past workers;

one’s actions only become significant because they occur within a

contemporary environment where other people currently labour.

Given that everyone’s personal effort depends radically upon the efforts

of others, Kropotkin further argues that ownership claims cannot be

based on labour. Here, his claim is quite different from the critique of

private property levelled by Karl Marx. In Although Marx’s early

“humanist” writings are quite concerned with social needs (Heller, 40),

his later critique of capitalism focuses more intensely on the inequity

of social production, on an analysis of how the capitalist extracts

surplus value from the labourer. In Capital, Marx roots the source of

social value in human labour. In the first chapter, he claims that the

total labour power of society can be divided into discrete units of

average labour expended in a given hour (129), further distinguishing

between simple and skilled labour. Kropotkin objects that Marxists and

other collectivists place too much emphasis on determining the

appropriate value of various kinds of labour. Thus, he argues:

It is utterly impossible to draw a distinction between the work of each

of these men. To measure the work by its results leads us to an

absurdity; to divide the total work and to measure its fractions by the

number of hours spent on the work also leads us to absurdity. One thing

remains: to put needs above works, and first of all to recognize the

right to live, and later on the right to well-being for all those who

took their share in production. (231)

Rather than focusing on labour, ownership, and production, Kropotkin

asserts that people should organize themselves in such a way as to

satisfy the human needs of consumption.

Kropotkin criticizes the tradition of political economy from Adam Smith

to Marx for consistently commencing their analyses with production

rather than consumption. He defends his own decision to reverse the

order by explaining

Perhaps you will say [putting production before consumption] is logical.

Before satisfying needs you must create the wherewithal to satisfy them.

But before producing anything, must you not feel the need of it? Is it

not necessity that first drove man to hunt, to raise cattle, to

cultivate land, to make implements, and later on to invent machinery? Is

it not the study of needs that should govern production? It would

therefore be quite as logical to begin by considering needs and

afterwards to discuss the means of production in order to satisfy these

needs (238).

Our capacity to produce, he claims, is sufficient to produce well-being

for all, enough housing, clothing, luxury items, and food. The thing

that prevents people from meeting their needs is the exploitation

practiced within the contemporary system of private ownership, a system

that reduces the majority of people to the barest subsistence. Instead

of allowing this economic system to legitimate itself with the alibi

that it practices efficient production, Kropotkin argues that we must

begin by considering consumption. Society, he declares could only hope

to meet the needs of all if it returns to the most fundamental question,

the question of bread. “We have the temerity to declare that all have a

right to bread, that there is enough bread for all, and that with this

watchword of Bread for All the revolution will triumph” (69).

Bibliography

Filmer, Robert. Patriarcha and Other Writings, ed. J. P. Somerville.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.

Friends Committee on National Legislation. “Reclaiming Identity: The

Repatriation of Native Remains and Culture.” March 17, 2008.

http://www.fcnl.org/issues/item.php?item_id=1470&issue_id=96

. (Accessed September 5, 2008)

Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson.

New York: Harper & Row, 1962.

Hegel, G. F. W. Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen W. Wood.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.

Heller, Agnes. The Theory of Need in Marx. New York: Saint Martin’s

Press, 1976.

Knowles, Dudley. “Hegel on Property and Personality” The Philosophical

Quarterly 33:130 (Jan 1983), 45–62.

Lampert, Jay. “Locke, Fichte, and Hegel on the Right to Property.” In

Hegel and the Tradition: Essays in Honour of H. S. Harris, ed. Michael

Baur and John Russon, 40–73. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1997.

Levinas, Emmanuel: “Meaning and Sense,” trans. Alphonso Lingis. In

Collected Philosophical Papers. New York: Kluwer, 2004, 75–108.

------. Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence, trans. Alphonso Lingis.

Pittsburgh: Duquesne Press, 2004.

------. “Reflections on the Philosophy of Hitlerism,” trans. Sean Hand.

Critical Inquiry 17:1 (Autumn 1990), 62–71.

------. Totality and Infinity, trans. Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh:

Duquesne Press, 1998.

Locke, John. Two Treatises on Government, ed. Peter Laslett. New York:

New American Library, 1965.

MacNally, David. “Locke, Levellers and Liberty: Property and Democracy

in the Thought of the First Whigs.” History of Political Thought. X:1

(Spring 1989), 17–42.

MacPherson, C. B. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism:

Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977

Marx, Karl. Capital: Volume 1, trans. B. Fowkes. New York: Penguin,

1990.

Olivecrona, Karl. “Locke’s Theory of Appropriation.” The Philosophical

Quarterly 24:96 (Jul. 1974), 220–234.

Wood, Allen W. Hegel’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 1990.