đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș alfredo-m-bonanno-feral-revolution-introduction.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:16:34. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Feral Revolution (Introduction) Author: Alfredo M. Bonanno Date: 1999 Language: en Topics: anti-civ, Feral Faun, insurrection Source: Retrieved on April 7, 2011 from http://pantagruel-provocazione.blogspot.com/2009/12/introduction-to-feral-revolution.html][pantagruel-provocazione.blogspot.com]]. Proofread text source from [[http://www.revoltlib.com/?id=3733, retrieved on December 10, 2020. Notes: Introduction to âFeral Revolutionâ by Feral Faun, Elephant Editions, 1999.
This book has a lot to say, far more than it might seem at first sight.
But it requires a particular disposition on the part of the reader, a
disposition to understand rather than to simply inform oneself.
In fact, there is not merely âinformationâ here, there are âideasâ,
something that rarely happens in American (even âradicalâ) culture, and
this is somewhat disturbing. How many of us are prepared to consider
ideas? I donât know. Those who do not want to question their certainties
will find confirmation of their beliefs in this book in another guise,
ruining the authorâs solicitations to look at reality differently.
Anyone can spend years âin the wildernessâ, Feral maintains, referring
to the possibility of entering the reality of which the âwildernessâ
marks the extreme limit. It is the moment of truth when we discover
whether we are really capable of breaking our bonds with society, the
umbilical cord that protects and domesticates us. That is why this book
is revolutionary: because it does not interpret reality but tries to
take us into reality just as the author himself has ventured, although
for no measurable length of time.
It is not a question of clinging tightly to the vine that Feral has
thrown down to us from his tree and diving into the fray. It is not a
question of a wild attitude or something âsayableâ that can be set out
in a formula, but of a totally different idea of reality. Tourists who
travel around the world to âwildly inaccessibleâ places merely take time
off from their lives of accumulative delirium and let themselves go wild
within certain well-defined limits. They are always well equipped, take
a guide along with them, etc. In the face of this obscene spectacle it
might seem that all one has to do to avoid âdoing the touristâ is to
omit the safety measures and guide and leave oneâs baggage at home.
Feral, I think, is saying that this is pointless because there is no
sense in going to wild places if one carries on seeing them in the way
we have been conditioned to. Nature itself can even contribute to
domesticating us: âNatureâ domesticates â Feral writes â because it
transforms wildness into a monolithic entity, a huge realm separate from
civilisation. The same goes for any âmilitantâ ecologist conception we
might decide to choose. Ecologists â even âradicalâ ones â play right
into this. Rather than go wild and destroy civilisation with the energy
of their unchained desires, they try to âsave the wildernessâ. This
sheds a ray of light on some of the inconclusive debates that have been
going on in our papers (and also those of power) for a long time now.
Of course, the first (not very shrewd) impression we might have on
reading this book might be that we are face to face with a
âprimitivistâ. And many have had that impression when reading those of
Feralâs articles that we have published in our papers and reviews here
in Italy. I wonder whether Feral himself with his passion for âwildlifeâ
(in the first place, man) is sure whether or not he is a âprimitivistâ.
Something of the sort certainly strikes you when he throws you that
vine. The evil wilderness reveals its true essence to him and him alone:
âfrom my own experiences wandering in these placesâ, making all the
panoply of survival equipment unnecessary. It is as though someone,
having had a different kind of experience, forgets that this originates
within a specific logical itinerary, simply saying that for him things
were different. This is not criticism, simply to show that at times
authors seem to obstruct our understanding of their ideas. Deliberately?
I donât know. This idea of the world as an absolute, whole entity is
something we are reasonably well equipped to grasp on this side of the
ocean. It comes as a shock to see it reach us from an American
experience, not least from walks among the millenary redwoods. Indeed,
one of the significant points of this book is that it has dug into the
myth of wild American nature.
Now we are beginning to see that the vine that we caught hold of at the
beginning of this introductory adventure does not belong to the
specifically ânaturalâ world of exotic adventure that constantly summons
us in our dreams, telling us to abandon the trials and tribulations of
daily life. Feralâs vine is a rediscovery of the significance of
humanity as a whole.
This allows us to see the man-nature relationship differently. There can
be no doubt that, in the beginning, nature was considered to be a living
being, alive and separate from that weak, naked being, man. But it is
not considered hostile until history begins to unfold alongside human
beingsâ separation from nature as a result of technological conquest,
aided by religion. The ancient Greek concepts physis and logos appear at
the same time, marking this separation. They denote the transition from
the old idea of mother nature to that of nature as something to be
possessed and dominated. Man subsequently studied, catalogued, dissected
and categorised this nature so as (in all appearances) to make it his
kingdom to dominate and exploit.
The ideas expressed in this book all convey a âvital energyâ that has
been numbed, often killed, by the domestication of civilisation. The
real wild, not the caricature circulated by travel agencies in
illustrated brochures, cannot be tolerated by civilised society. The
latter must eliminate it in order to guarantee its own survival and
preserve order. As Feral writes, âCivilisation will not tolerate what is
wild in its midst. But I never forgot the intensity that life could be.
I never forgot the vital energy that had surged through me. My existence
since I first began to notice that this vitality was being drained away
has been a war between the needs of civilised survival and the need to
break loose and experience the full intensity of life unboundâ.
But what is this âvital energyâ? Feral does not tell us exactly,
although evidence of it is to be found in many parts of this book. Like
all leading concepts, it appears indirectly in considerations that would
be meaningless without its logical premise. The violent response to the
aggression and control constantly exercised by power is an attempt to
free ourselves from the domesticating conditioning that civilisation has
brought to every moment of our lives, and cannot simply be seen in terms
of defence. That would be a losing battle. You might as well just accept
the structures of power and find a niche to survive in. This rebellion â
contrary to that of the pacifists who maintain that nonviolence is the
best form of defence (not realising that the latter is simply the other
side of the same coin as violence) â is an âaggressive, dangerous,
playful attack by free-spirited individuals against societyâ. What
characterises the attack is its insurrectional nature. In the thesis
developed here it is not a question of something that is clearly visible
and transformed into codified behaviour with projects and programmes. It
is more a question of the âvital energyâ mentioned above.
I donât know if Feral realises how radical the consequences of these
ideas are. In the first place, how fruitful they will be to the readers
who have the courage to penetrate his theses completely and not be
influenced by first impressions of âprimitivismâ. But if this path â or
perhaps Heideggerâs idea of a clearing in the woods would be more exact
here â is to be travelled, there must be no doubt about the fact that
the world is constantly making distinctions between what is
transformable and what is produced by the logic of power. If this unity
of the world where nature is not distinct from humanity, or the
wilderness from the Japanese city with its advanced urban technology,
has any significance at all, it is in this âgoing beyondâ. That is to
say it is to be found at the very moment in which oneâs own personal
tension and wild vital energy comes alive and sets to transforming the
conditions of domestication. If we were to imagine this going beyond as
one single, circumscribed event to take us to a condition forever free
from domestication â as was the case with the Marxist thesis â the point
of arrival would be no more than a higher level of domestication, one
where we would not even be aware of being domesticated.
But let us not lose sight of our argument. Adventure, in order to be
such, is always adventure in act. If it were simply adventure tout court
it would end up being institutionalised and the wild, vital instinct
would become limitless and with no measure of contrast, so we would be
unable to dream or attack. When Feral says: âAll social relationships
have their basis in the incompleteness produced by the repression of our
passions and desires. Their basis is our need for each other, not our
desire for each other,â that certainly doesnât mean to say that the
objective is the abolition of society and the creation of a new human
condition to take the place of the incompleteness that comes from the
repression of our passions and desires today. The elimination of this
repression is a process, a going beyond, it is not something one simply
finds around the corner, the opposite of domestication. Even if things
were to go according to Stirnerâs idea of the âuse of the otherâ rather
than the âneed for the otherâ, that could never become something finite.
Anything I know to be finite is to be found in the graveyard, and even
there more surprises than the wildest revolutionary fantasy might
imagine possibly await us.
I quite agree that âsocial roles are ways in which individuals are
defined by the whole system of relationships that is society in order to
reproduce the latterâ, and so âsociety is thus the domestication of
human beings â the transformation of potentially creative, playful, wild
beings â who can relate freely in terms of their desires, into deformed
beings using each other to try to meet desperate needs, but succeeding
only at reproducing the need and the system of relationships based on
itâ. But, due to the principle of the man-nature unity that sees
separation as something that is useful only to power, I believe that the
elimination of this condition could never be completed once and for all.
This is an essential point as far as I can see. If we were to imagine a
condition where the explosion of vital (wildly insurrectional) energy
had become something permanent, that is to say, become a fait accompli,
we would be doing no more than finishing off the job of domestication.
In other words, we would simply have become more sophisticated
domesticators.
This is what happened to the Marxist ideas that appeared in the wake of
Hegelâs theses: the proletariat were to bring about their own extinction
and be victors in their struggle against the bourgeoisie. This would
mark the end of class society and philosophy, i.e., of the ideas that
had reflected this contradictory movement throughout the various phases
of its historical development. Stirner was also a prisoner of this
schema when he founded the union of egoists as the free condition of the
future. This was to be realised from the (vital?) energy activated by
oneâs own personal insurrection, but again was to be realised once and
for all. We can no longer have any faith in models that predict a clear
future, not even one that would give space to the âfullness of the
passionsâ.
But perhaps I am exaggerating here. Perhaps Feral has nothing complete
and finite in mind, and there are points in his book that seem to
indicate this. When he writes, âThe playful violence of insurgence has
no room for regret. Regret weakens the force of blows and makes us
cautious and timidâ, he is talking of finishing with the past. In the
joyous rebel violence of insurrection and individual liberation we
cannot take a retrospective look at the already done: having no regrets
cannot mean anything else. But anyone who has no regrets has no history
either. History is a retrospective look at what one has done as opposed
to what one might have done, and the difference is always a sorry list
of mistakes to be avoided in future.
So, anyone who, rather than dedicate themselves to this necrophilic
pastime prefers to cultivate their own life of destructive passion in
the eternal present of revolt against everything that is aimed at
regulating their life, can have no future either. The culture that
suffocates us sees this lack of future as something negative, proposing
a perspective in the logic of âa little at a timeâ in its place, the
method suggested by Popper in the scientific field. The present world is
entirely based on such theories of accommodation. The fire only reaches
a few who, like Feral, are burning their fingers to support the thesis
of the oneness of the world and the fact that it is quite inseparable.
That might make us wince, but it is the way things are and corresponds
to our original thesis. If we eliminate all regulating ballast we have
no reserves to put in the place of what we destroy. Otherwise it is not
really a question of destruction. When Durruti said in the early months
of the Spanish revolution that the workers could destroy everything
because, having built it all once they could do so again, he was
referring to a situation that has now disappeared for ever.
The same problem arises concerning certain passages in âThe Cops in Our
Headsâ. Here Feral points out: âThe attempt to make a moral principle of
anarchy distorts its real significance. Anarchy describes a particular
type of situation, one in which either authority does not exist or its
power to control is denied. Such a situation guarantees nothing â not
even the continued existence of that situation, but it does open up the
possibility for each of us to start creating our lives for ourselves in
terms of our own desires and passions rather than in terms of social
roles and the demands of social order. Anarchy is not the goal of
revolution; it is the situation that makes the only type of revolution
that interests me possible â an uprising of individuals to create their
lives for themselves and destroy what stands in their way. It is a
situation free of any moral implications, presenting each of us with the
amoral challenge to live our lives without constraints. Since the
anarchic situation is amoral, the idea of an anarchist morality is
highly suspect. Morality is a system of principles defining what
constitutes right and wrong behaviour.â â Here I get clear confirmation
of what I am trying to say, yet, at the same time I perceive a
contradiction. Perhaps I am splitting hairs, but the question seems to
me to be of no little significance. The confirmation is all in the
movement that guarantees nothing, even in a situation based on the
refusal of authority. But a situation enclosed in the refusal of
authority would be contradictory. In fact, Feral sees the problem and
says that anarchy is not and never could be the aim of the revolution,
but is the situation (I would say the personal situation) that makes the
revolution possible. And I agree, but this can only define itself as
âamoralâ if it continues in the perspective of âgoing beyondâ, never
becoming something established. Otherwise this final âwholeâ condition
would require moral rules in order to organise itself and persist in
time.
The cops in our heads, along with the domestication they reflect,
represent the opposite pole to the concept of âwild natureâ. It is this
separation from nature that makes civilisation possible, producing the
techniques that change the latter into something artificial and
enjoyable in small doses, when kept at a safe distance. Everything
becomes clear in this framework and Feral dwells upon it in detail,
excitingly at times.
Thus he writes, âThere can be no program or organisation for feral
revolution, because wildness cannot spring from a program or
organisation. Wildness springs from the freeing of our instincts and
desires, from the spontaneous expression of our passions. Each of us has
experienced the process of domestication, and this experience can give
us the knowledge we need in order to undermine civilization and
transform our livesâ. And we cannot deny this. But only on condition
that everything continues in the never-ending process of going beyond,
in the movement of freedom that does not see what is freed as something
other than oneself and oneâs desire to unleash this âvital energyâ that
continues to flow from an inexhaustible source. Feralâs acrobatic
juxtaposition of ideas culminates in this endless transition, the
tension that never solidifies, the barricades that never cease fighting,
the violence that never quells. Well, as a soliloquy, itâs not bad. It
fascinates and redeems us from our daily chores. The individual rising
up with the torch of freedom in one hand and hatchet in the other, as
one unforgettable comrade once said, is the classic image of anarchist
iconography. And many anarchists still dream of reaching this condition
of privilege. Not the privilege of the elite, for goodness sake, but of
someone who has held the truth in his hands and with superhuman strength
is extirpating the world at its roots. And the others? Feral has not
read Stirner so superficially as not see that the next step must be that
of reaching others, a community of individual insurgents, a totality of
individuals each developing his or her own personal insurrection. But
this condition cannot be reached through one specific experience.
Nothing in the world of domestication can force us to decide in favour
of this condition of privilege, this âgoing beyondâ in act.
Let me explain. If we decide to do something, this something must
already be within our reach in some way. It is there in front of us,
visible and comprehensible, even if it concerns the strangest and most
remote utopian fantasy. If I decide to break the chains of
domestication, I can only do so because I feel the chains and suffer the
effects of domestication on my own skin. This historicist interpretation
of revolt differs little from the innatist one that assigns the
possibility of rebelling to oneâs own character, maintaining that some
individuals are born with genes of rebellion whereas others are more
acquiescent and accept the rules of civilisation. Basically, this â
questionable if you like â genetic element does also exist within the
individual. It is the element we are talking about, the one called upon
to unleash rebellion.
Let us continue. No matter how we look at it, we see that the individual
must act, i.e. become conscious that this something, whatever it is, is
to be found in front of or within them, and admit that the two
hypotheses (the historicist and the innatist) interrelate. The born
rebel puts up with less than those who are not in conflict with
domestication and chains. So we come back to the wholeness of man,
within which distinctions do operate, but only up to a point. We deduce
from this that individual insurrection is only possible when the two
elements exist, meet and interact. And I think that Feral takes this for
granted. But this cannot be compared to anything else. There are no
rules to support this condition other than those that might come from
further domestication following the breaking of the chains. In this case
the rebel would have ended up conforming to the reality of his dreams,
now solidified into something permanent.
If we exclude this hypothesis, as Feral does, all that remains is the
reappearance of the enemy, recognising it and being moved to
insurrection, to infinity. With all my admiration for what Feral says,
it seems to me that this situation threatens to become a stalemate. By
remaining on the barricades one risks losing sight of what one is
actually doing. It is not true that freedom cannot be imagined, or that
all one can think about freedom is incomplete, for example âlibertiesâ,
the definition of oneâs own limits and those of others. I know that all
that is not true. I know that the fool is he who finds the grain of corn
in a world where most people are pecking around blindly in the logic of
power which has been embellished with a few adjustments. When his heart
floods with hatred for the owners of the chains and the logic of
domestication, this being who wants to rebel against all rules â because
freedom is above all the absence of rules â has one aim and one alone.
And the latter is not utility or domestication but to make the world of
suffering caused by the chains and the stupidity that results from
domestication disappear forever.
This aim, as clear as day, is the one about which nothing better can be
thought, so includes all strategies and any logic of adjustment,
including the single clash and partial conquests of freedom. And there
can be no doubt that this reality, of which nothing better can be
thought, can be thought, even if it is not physically tangible. It is
not simply a question of the chains disappearing or the links of
domestication being broken. It is something else, something that gets
greater and more marvelous and cannot be obfuscated by the specificity
of going beyond. It involves more (or should do), a continual going
beyond that never stops, seeing the chains and domestication in their
most intimate significance, not simply as the means to a better life as
those in power would have it.
If freedom were just a dream, lack of future would be no more than a
great black hole and everything would be reduced to either putting up
with the chains and domestication as far as possible or to living oneâs
own personal insurrection. Seen in these terms, and given that the
capacity to choose between better and worse is determined by laws that
are part of oneâs domestication, there would be no criteria for choice.
One would go forward blindly, guided by the genetic lumen, not knowing
whether to accept or rebel.
If we choose rebellion we do so because something exists in the future,
not just in our genetic and historical past. And this something is not
merely part of our intelligence, simply a thought. If that were so the
other thought, the logic of acceptance and domestication, would be
equally valid. In the best hypothesis in that case I would die of both
hunger and thirst just like Buridanâs ass, prostrated before the choice
of a bucket of hay and a bucket of water.
But things are not like that. I choose because I consider both the
breaking of the chains and the elimination of domestication to be acts
that thrust me towards a different perspective, throwing me into the
process of going beyond a condition that I loathe and which offends my
good taste. If I define myself wild and a lover of the real wilderness
(not that of the tourists), allowing a certain âprimitivismâ to be
understood between the lines without ever actually admitting it, that is
nothing but a set of choices. Only those who have taste can choose. And
taste, love and desire are expressions of that genetic-historical
combination that continues to be what we are and impels us to go
forward. When I think of freedom, unspecified freedom which has nothing
better beyond it, it is my whole self that I put into this thought. I am
not a dreamer talking about his visions, but an experimenter who goes
into his visions and is prepared to risk his life for them.
Admission to such a condition of freedom cannot be gained through normal
procedures of reason. It cannot be deduced from what we know through our
daily experience (chains and domestication) but is born elsewhere in the
genetic-historical interrelation that produces our most radical
impulses, our wildest desires and dreams of eternal love that nothing
can ever dim, and the taste for wild adventure. In a word, everything
that Feral talks about and much more besides. If I were to limit myself
to thinking about this coldly I would never be able to convince myself
that it existed or that it was something worth involving myself in and
risking the tranquility of the chains which the culture of domestication
renders more or less bearable. If I go beyond this level, (and how many
millions of people never do!) it is because at some point I become
unreasonable, throw all care to the winds, and act. But in practice it
is impossible to put all oneâs projects, taste, desire and love aside.
In fact, in throwing down his vine, this wild man who lives in a tree
and wanders free among the American redwoods is throwing me an object of
love. He is linking me to him with love in the hope of taking me with
him to that tree of freedom, another wild man like himself. Because life
in freedom would be a poor thing indeed if it were simply a territory of
complete desolation with no relationships, therefore relations. Like
everything that passes between human beings, the latter depend on taste,
desire, love, pleasure, but also hatred, fear, anxiety, and much more
besides.
I do not think that this vine would ever be capable of consolidating
itself once and for all. I do not think that one can interpret the wild
condition as merely âvital energyâ in act from Feralâs writing. His
freedom is what one cannot have anything better than. It is the totality
of freedom, the completely free condition, without limits, impediments
or order, not even of a moral or aesthetic character. Once taken into
consideration, this totality can only be conceived as complete if one
sees it as something in movement. Freedom is growth to infinity,
otherwise I would have to admit that I, free at last, would end up dazed
in a complete stupor: absolute freedom would become the absolute
cancellation of man. Totality is therefore always in the course of
development. It is in act, yet always totally present at the moment I
think it. That is the totality I have in mind when I think of absolute
freedom, which destroys limits and domestication. If I were to see it as
something circumscribed I would be thinking of God, merely putting one
word in place of another. And this absolute totality would upturn itself
and become the concept of absolute tyranny, throwing me out of my
involvement, obliging me to adore it as something other than myself.
So, if we agree with the idea of freedom as something both infinite and
in act there is no reason why we cannot acknowledge different processes
of approach within this totality and actively go beyond the conditions
of submission dictated by chains and domestication. Is there anything
contradictory in that? I donât think so.
Basically, this concern can be summed up in the decision to develop a
project. So the question is: can the totality of my wild rebellion and
freedom, precisely as Feral intends, be linked to a project? Or should
the latter be considered something that needs to be destroyed along with
the other creations of power because it belongs to the world of limits
and rules? In other words, can a project be realised within the context
of the wild insurrection that Feral is talking about? Or does this by
its very nature refuse such a thing because it is a residue of
domestication?
Allow me to develop these questions as I believe them to be of
considerable importance.
If I negate the past, and this procures me the means for attack by
essentialising my destructive strength; if I negate history â as we have
said â I can have no future either. In itself this can only upset
palates that have been ruined by Macdonaldâs hamburgers. But this
absence of future is not simply a great black hole. It is an absence
that I avert as a presence. Although a lack of something, it is not
âabsurdâ. That is to say, it is not something that I cannot understand,
otherwise it would be a mystical kind of faith which might even have
subversive connotations at times, but could never accept practical
destruction.
So this void contains a great many things, and the more I go ahead in my
rebellion the more freedom takes form and talks to me. It tells me of
the dream of my life, because that is what is at stake here, not just
one of the many games that I can play during my life. In severing all
links with the past and rebelling against domestication, I am presenting
myself bare to the future. This new bareness is all that I have and is
also the whole of freedom, without any hidden parts or reserves. I feel
freedom flare up in my veins, even for an instant in that room full of
books under the severe expression of a revolutionary of times gone by.
It is not a place fixed in time that I can retire to every now again in
my mind. It is my whole self, my totality, always. It is my love that
cannot be dissected, a little here, a little there. It stays whole,
always, a totality that continues to grow. We can only experience
infinity if we erase from our minds the idea of something static such as
the whole of everything that exists. And this totality would be sterile
were we not able to stretch out a hand and widen its range at any
moment. I, adventurer of the incredible, am capable of extending to
infinity in the same way that I can live freedom and not allow myself to
be guaranteed by it.
It is within this absolute tension that I place my project, not in vain
distinctions that assign degrees or procedural levels to doing. I sketch
out a path in the absolute, howl and jump for joy, and only here do I
allude to this tiny portion of reality: a smile, a handshake, a walk
among the fireflies in the evening shadows. And there is nothing I can
do about it if someone points to the moon but only sees their finger,
the stages in the journey. These levels, the specific occasions, are all
illusory. They dress up an idea that lives elsewhere. They are analyses,
even subtle ones, of something that, seen in its individual parts, is
nothing more than brute reality. The vital lymph of all that is
elsewhere in the illusion that supports it. Reason can only weaken it,
scientific seriousness only mask it.
It is the light of freedom in its âwildâ totality that illuminates the
project and makes it perfectly useless to this world. How many see the
project in quantitative terms and ask themselves what the point of it
all is. But why make such an effort only to stop half way? Their
intuition tells them to gaze at their finger, the moon is too far away
and too difficult to comprehend. But tell me, in all sincerity, is that
a good enough reason not to have a project?
I have many in my heart, and I cannot turn them into talking ghosts to
make them become objects of fascination for others except by dressing
them up in cast-off clothing: analyses, considerations of events,
organisational conditions. These are at the root of the vigorous
certainties of the world of the domesticated, but can also be
interpreted differently by those who rebel. I do not think such efforts
are an obstacle to rebellion. I do think they need to be seen for what
they are: mere reflexes of totality which can only be expressed in the
modest language of progressive experience.
And now I ask one last question: can the totality we carry in our
hearts, the wild experience that Feral talks about, be said in any way
other than by having recourse to language, which is always locked within
progressive experience? After all, the pieces of writing we are
presenting here are merely words. We need to encounter what these words
betray rather than illuminate, elsewhere, in our hearts, at the cost of
our lives. Otherwise they will lose their meaning and return to the
circumscribed, miserable activity of talking for the sake of it. The
same goes for the project: words, mere words, that it is up to us to
read in another way.
Â
Alfredo M. Bonanno
Catania, April 18, 1999