đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș david-graeber-beyond-the-monastic-self.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:04:39. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Beyond the Monastic Self Author: David Graeber Language: en Topics: inequality, academia, Individualism Source: Retrieved on Sept. 17th 2022 from https://davidgraeber.org/unpublished/letter/
One of the things I most admire about Maurice Bloch is that heâs never
forgotten what got him interested in anthropology to begin with. Most of
us do. How many after all are drawn to the discipline above all curious
about questions that only it can answer: questions like, what are
humans, in what ways are they the same, in what ways are they different?
Itâs one of the peculiar perversities of graduate and professional
training that we often forget this, and one of the perversities of this
peculiarly anti-theoretical moment that there are prominent figures
telling us we should forget them. Because to reject these questions out
of hand is not only to reject the very premise of anthropological
theory, but for anthropology to be able to offer any explanation of its
own existenceâto be able to ask (to adopt a phrase from Roy Bhaskar,
originally about experiments), both âwhat makes anthropology
possibleââwhy do we even have the capacity to understand someone living
in rural Madagascar, but also, simultaneously, âwhat makes anthropology
necessaryâ why that understanding is usually not transparent, and in so
many respects, extraordinarily difficult. <br/>
I want to address this by looking at what has always been the primary
anthropological method: conversation. Actually, I would argue itâs not
only our primary fieldwork method, but our primary method of coming up
with new theoretical ideas. Good ideas rarely, if ever, emerge from
isolation. True, often these theoretical dialogues are not carried out
face to faceâI myself have been engaged in a series of theoretical
conversation with Maurice Bloch for decades now, even though weâve
surprisingly rarely sat together in the same room and hashed matters out
directly. One of our peculiar fetishistic habits, as intellectuals, is
to efface the histories of most of these conversations after theyâve
happened, or at best carve up the results, so as to make it seem like
ideas emerge from isolated Great Thinkers. But in practice weâre all
aware, on some level, this is never really true: I have no idea, for
instance, the degree to which many of the ideas attributed to me are the
product of me, or some of my graduate student friends with whom I spent
long hours hashing out the meaning of the universe twenty years ago, and
ultimately I think itâs a meaningless question: the ideas emerged from
our relation.
The process of the collective, or dialogic emergence of ideas in turn
involves certain techniques, which only make sense in terms of a larger
context of exchange and answerability. One of these is the provocation.
An intellectual provocation, as we all know, usually consists of a
statement that makes sense from a certain theoretical perspective that
so clashes against received wisdom that it will inevitably spark a
debate from which new richer understandings are likely to emerge. An
example might be: poetry is an impoverished form of speech. Maurice as
we all know is a master of this and as a discipline weâve gained much
from the results, so it seems to me the best way to honor him is to
attempt in my own small way to do the same.
So I will propose one. It might be considered an expansion on some
arguments Maurice himself made in an essay calling âGoing in and Out of
Each Otherâs Bodies,â on the ambiguities of âthe distinctness of the
units of life,â including human beings, and which draws on the findings
of neuroscience to observe the fact that this includes âthe
interpenetration of mindsâ which, during acts of communication, involves
a kind of mind-reading in which identical neuronal configurations are
occurring in the brains of both parties, so that, in a certainâhowever
limitedâsense, they can be seen as part of a single configuration,
mediated by some kind of physical bridge (of sound waves, bodily
movements, images, whatever.) It strikes me almost no one has really
considered the full implications of this. Bloch makes some excellent
points about the sense of human solidarity (what Iâve myself referred to
as âbaseline communismâ) emerging in part from cumulative awareness of
this sort of practical mutual interpenetration, and the fact that the
very possibility of human life is built on it, but for the moment I want
to take it another way. I want to suggest that almost all existing
social theory is based on a misapprehension. We tend to veer between
looking at individuals and societies, transcendental subjects and
meaningful universes, where in fact, particularly when it comes to
questions of conscious thought, we are really speaking of something that
occurs not in one personâs head but within just these dyadic or if you
like âintersubjectiveâ relations. To put it more starkly: thinkingâor,
anyway, conscious, self-reflective thoughtâdoes not mainly happen in the
head. Neither does it mainly happen in our relations with our material
environments, as some have recently proposed, or in some great abstract
collective consciousness. Consciousness exists mainly in concrete
junctures between what have sometimes been called âembodied
personalities.â
In other words itâs not just our folk theories of how the mind works
that are wrong. Itâs our folk theory about what the mind is thatâs
wrong. This means
---
The usual response to such a statement is either to say âthatâs insaneâ
or âbut of course we already know thatââwhich as we know are both
equally modes of dismissal, since in fact the people saying this donât
know this, they just think they know it, since this âknowledgeâ has no
effect on anything else they say or do. (Consider the case of the rather
similar ideas that emerged from conversations amongst the Bakhtin circle
in â20s Russia; how many scholars claim to agree with them that thought
is dialogic, and then act as if all the ideas that emerged from their
dialogues were the product of one individual genius, Mikhail Bakhtin.)
Let me start with the subject of consciousness. There has been a burst
of publications in the last decade by social theorists trying to come to
terms with the findings of cognitive science, which might be summed up
as, âconsciousness isnât all its cracked up to beââthat in much of our
daily existence and activities, in fact, we might as well be sleep. In
what follows Iâll take just oneâbut I should emphasize this is for ease
of exposition only; I could just as easily have chosen at least a dozen
others to make the same point.
In a recent essay, geographer Nigel Thrift (2006:285) argues of
intellect itself that âresearch over many years has shown that it is at
best a fragile and temporary coalition, a tunnel which is always close
to collapse.â He continues by quoting Mervin Donald, one of the many
contemporary philosophers to engage with the findings of cognitive
psychology on the nature of that classic philosophical object,
consciousness:
During the past forty years, in countless laboratories around the world,
human consciousness has been put under the microscope, and exposed
mercilessly for the poor thing it is: a transitory and fleeting
phenomenon. The ephemeral nature of consciousness is especially obvious
in experiments on the temporal minima of memory- that is the length of
time we can hold on to a clear sensory image of something. Even under
the best circumstances, we cannot keep more than a few seconds of
perceptual experience in short-term memory. The window of consciousness,
defined in this way, is barely ten or fifteen seconds wide. Under some
conditions, the width of our conscious window on the world may be no
more than two seconds wide (Donald 2001: 15)
The question, then, becomes: how is it that we come to the
representation of the subject typical of Western philosophy, and which
forms the basis of all social science, as a fundamentally conscious,
rational, intentional, self-awareâone which appears to bear almost no
resemblance to any actual living human being?
The answer I think goes back to the origins of philosophy itself. One of
the remarkable things about the evolution of philosophy is that just
about everywhere we first encounter it, it is characterized by two
features which are gradually lost. One is that its intellectual
arguments are typically couched in the form of dialogues and
conversations. The second is that it is not considered a mere matter of
reflection, but a form of practice: as Pierre Hadot (1995, 2002) has
long since pointed out, not only Buddhism, Confucianism, or Taoism, but
even Greco-Roman schools like the Stoics and Epicureans promulgated
forms of meditation, diet, exercise, sexual practice or continence,
essentially ways of training the mind and body so as to create a form of
fully self-conscious subject. In other words, isolated, self-sufficient,
rational, self-reflective intellect was not assumed as the
starting-point; it was, rather, a telos; the ideal end point of a long
and painful process which no ordinary mortal, really, could ever be
expected to fully achieve.
What happened? Perhaps it is best considered as an example of what Iâve
elsewhere called âliberation in the imaginary.â It is not uncommon to
observe such patterns in intellectual life. In its early days, for
instance, cultural studies was seen as a theoretical tool for
revolutionaries, a way of facilitating working class resistance against
dominant values. Gradually it became a purely academic pursuit that
started from the assumption that all working class people were already
engaged in one or another form of semiotic resistance to dominant
values. It would seem something very similar happened to our
philosophical tradition, when it moved from the monastery to the
university, and therefore ceased to conceive itself as a form of
practiceâexcept on a much grander scale. As a result, even after they
abandoned the monastery, scholars maintained what was essentially a
monastic self.
---
What Iâd really like to emphasize here is a remark that appears really
as an aside in Thriftâs argument: he notes, true, âThis description [of
consciousness] is something of an exaggeration â it derives from
laboratory experiments and glosses over the richness of joint action in
which subjects do much betterâ (ib:285). In other words, even if the
window of consciousness is typically a few seconds long when one is by
oneself, with others, itâs much broader.
When I first read this passage I thought he was referring to primarily
to conversation. After all, while mindless conversations certainly
exist, we are all also aware that weâve had conversations (with loved
ones, or, on exciting topics) where we were quite vividly conscious for
hours at a time. During one such vivid phone conversation with my
girlfriend a few weeks ago, she suggested, âyesâthatâs why they say that
when youâre driving and afraid youâre going to fall asleep, the best
thing to do is to talk to someone else. Just listening to talk radio
wonât do itââmaking her incidentally one of the effective co-authors of
this piece. If we are really talking about differences on the magnitude
of seconds versus hours, itâs clear that the vast majority of our fully
conscious life is spent discussing things with others.
On some level this too should be self-evident. One need only consider
the etymology, which is con-science, which literally means, âknowing
things together.â But nonetheless, when I then went to consult the vast
literature on consciousness, starting with grand compendia like The
Oxford Companion to Consciousness, for example, I discovered that there
was almost nothing there on conversation at all. In most works on the
subjects, words like âdialogueâ and âconversationâ barely appear. For
the most part, the discussion is limited to âinternal speech,â imaginary
conversations one has in oneâs headâthe existence of this could be taken
of course as dramatic affirmation of the degree to which conscious
thought requires interlocutors, but rarely is. The great exception here
of course is thatâin psychology, very much subordinateâstrain of theory
that hearkens back to the Soviet Union in the 1920s: Vygotskyâs work on
egocentric speech in children, whereby he showed that abstract thinking
is made possible by internalizing verbal interaction with the outside
world, and of course the work of the Bakhtin circle. Bakhtinâs argument
that consciousness is the voices of others speaking in your heads is
perhaps the most radical statement in this respectâbut itâs now
considered distinctly marginal, relegated to a small school of
Bakhtin-studies; partly because of its now-outmoded premise that the
only possible medium for thought is language, but largely, I suspect,
because of the larger political content of the argument, with the clash
between voices of authority and their carnivalesque subversion. Whatâs
more, for all the importance they attach to dialogue as the essence of
human thought, neither the Vygotsky or Bakhtin schools spend much time
at all discussing actual conversations, that is, dialogues between two
or more mature individuals, as opposed to virtual dialogue in the mind
or works of literature.
My suspicion is no one really wants to address the matter because the
consequences threaten to unsettle everythingâincluding, as I say, our
very presumptions about the objects of our study. Let me give an
example. Work on âdistributed cognition,â the idea that in many
circumstances, thinking takes place outside the individual head, going
back to Edwin Hutchinsâ analysis of how each member of a shipâs crew
âoffloadsâ different aspects of navigation to each other, and how they,
together with the shipâs machinery, themselves form of a kind of larger
cognitive machine. Yet with only a few exceptions (mainly by those
extending Vygotskyâs insights in the field of education), the field has
tended to concentrate increasingly on the technological aspect: in our
reliance (and therefore trust) in machines as extensions of ourselves
rather than our reliance on each other.
This becomes strikingly true when these ideas are taken up by
philosophers. Andy Clark for instance has become famous for developing
whatâs often known as the âextended mind hypothesisââasking, why is it
we assume that our minds are coincident with the physical material of
our brains. If minds are dynamic processes of thinking, this is
obviously not the case. If one person can do long division in their
heads, and another must make recourse to paper and pencil, the brain
cells, and the paper and pencil, are playing exactly the same roleâitâs
simply incoherent and arbitrary to insist that there is a fundamental
distinction between them. Or to take a more ethnographic example:
traditional Malagasy houses are all organized on the same pattern, with
12 astrological positions mapped out from the northeast corner
clockwise, so that if one is sitting in the main room itâs possible to
make astrological calculations just by glancing from hearth to water-pot
to back door, etc. Clearly on such an occasion, the house is part of
oneâs extended mind. This position seems largely accepted now within the
philosophical community, but the logic is applied, almost exclusively,
to technologiesâespecially computers, as in Clarkâs own most famous
book, âNatural Born Cyborgs.â Thereâs something obviously missing here.
If thought, including conscious thought, is really a the interaction of
brain, body, and oneâs environmental (and of course, culturally
constituted) âcognitive scaffoldingââwell, what about other brains? In
his original essay on the extended mind, Clark and fellow philosopher
David Chalmers are willing to entertain the possibility, though as
always he frames it in a way that seems calculated to sidestep the most
serious implications: he notes, some people memorize names and phone
numbers, some people put them in little books, but thereâs one
basketball coach notorious for always relying on his wife. Surely, her
memory is part of his cognitive scaffolding, just like a waiter who
might remember what sort of sauce I like. True, but in a purely passive
wayâmuch as Roman senators notoriously tended to keep a favorite slave
constantly at their side, whose job was to remember the names, faces,
office, and personal or political significance of all their friends and
colleagues.
If we apply the same insight to more active forms of engagement between
what we call âmindsâ, we can see why the philosophical implications
might be unsettling. When we speak of the coordination of neuronal
processes between brains, are we just speaking of a kind of
âmind-reading,â as Bloch puts it, or the creationâat least at the point
of understandingâof a single mind? If minds are processes of interaction
not limited to the brain, then this pretty much has to be the case. Yet
the only philosopher I know who has fully embraced this point is the
philosopher of science, Roy Bhaskar, and it would seem he has only been
able to do so by abandoning the strictures of academic philosophy
entirely and returning to the older idea of philosophy as inseparable
for techniques for achieving freedom and self-consciousness rather than
describing it, a project which has meant active engagement with Buddhist
and Taoist and similar traditions that still operate in such terms, and,
being written off as a New Age flake or raving lunatic even by many of
his formerly most ardent disciples. The argument though is fascinating.
You will recall here that historically, that creature we now think of as
the self-conscious individual was largely created through disciplinary
techniques of isolation and reflection. Such techniques also, in a
sense, created a certain notion of the cosmos, of totality, against
which the individual was posed; and having created the difference, the
final step was often exploding it again by some mystical experience of
cosmic unity, often framed as unity with God. This entailed the
recognition of what in the Sanskrit tradition came to be known as
ânon-dualismâ, that atman and brahman, self and cosmos, however it was
framed in that particular tradition, were the same. All Bhaskar does is
argue that you donât actually need to sit on a mountain and beat
yourself with thorns for twenty years in order to have a mystical
experience. In a certain sense, any time you understand what someone
else is trying to communicate to you, you are having a direct experience
of non-dualism, of a unity between minds which is a direct result of the
underlying unity of all physical processes, which make it possible for
the mirror neurons in our brains to fire in the same way, for more or
less the same reasons outlined above. Our very existence as intelligent
beings is made possibly by an endless variety of minor, everyday
mystical experiences, that occur between âembodied personalitiesâ (his
phrase originally) rather than between some abstract, artificially
created âselfâ and cosmos.
---
If anyone should doubt the devastating implications if we apply the
extended mind hypothesis to dialogic consciousness, consider the
following four points, which, alas, can only be sketched out very
briefly:
âother minds problem.â Starting from the Cartesian cogito, how can we be
certain other minds exist? Actually, we canât start from the Cartesian
cogito, because the fact that we think does not prove we exist as
autonomous minds already separate from other ones; the real problem is
the joint relational work we do constructing situations in which we can
think of ourselves as autonomous selvesâa work of which the monastic
disciplines of the ancient philosophers (which did require the help of
other people: especially, again, slaves) are simply particularly extreme
examples.
is the work required on the part of an audience, the recipient of an
intentional act communication, to imaginatively identify with its
author, thus, effectively, creating the author as the imaginatively
recreated intentional agent whose will is assumed to bind all the
different elements in the message together. But if at the moment of
communication speaker and listener, author and reader, are actually the
same mind, then what we are really witnessing is the act of creating a
separation.
childhood involves a shared conceptual labor of teaching children to
distinguish themselves from others and the surrounding world, we assume
that this is simply the recognition of a truth and that the process ends
when this truth is realized, it would appear this is not really the
case. It is at best a half-truth, and for this reason the process of
individuation never really ends, the illusion, one might say, must be
endlessly maintained. Whatâs more, there is generally a decidedly
political aspect to this, since, the very most basic form of
exploitation would seem to be the process whereby one end of such nexi
individuates itself at the expense of another, rendering the other in a
strange state somewhere between individuation, empathy, and
nonexistence.
one with the capital Oâthat runs from Hegelâs master slave dialectic
through Kojeve, Sartre, Fanon and De Beauvoir, on through its endless
refractions in the present day. On the one hand, the dialectical
tradition from which this derives might seem to be one that actually is
aware of the ultimate identity of subject and object, and provide tools
for understanding this constant process of (often exploitative)
individuation; but here again, there is again the difference between
knowing something, and just thinking you know itâsince as the
dialectical tradition itself is famous for emphasizing, knowledge is not
knowledge unless itâs put to work. A century ago now, Lukacs was already
pointing out the philosophers have to continually rediscover the fact
that persons are really relations, just as things are really processes,
because in a system where the commodity form dominates, the simple
realization is meaningless, it has no effect. What I will leave then
with is only this. The very notion of dialectics originally derives from
the Socratic method, and that, from the peculiar form of so much ancient
philosophy: to use the dialogic form to create the ideal of a
self-reflexive consciousness that might transcend dialogue. (The result,
as we all know from Plato, is a peculiar one-sided form of dialogue, one
which Hegel, drawing, interestingly, on the non-dualistic assumption
that the structure of argument and that of even natural phenomenon are
ultimately one, subsumed into the mind of a cosmic Reason attempting,
again like an ancient philosophy student, to carry out a series of
exercises designed to ultimately achieve a fully self-reflexive state.)
In other words, in its classical form at least, it ultimately aims to
liberate us from the very situation Iâve been describing into a totality
whose political implications have tended to be perilous at best.
But what would a politics, an ethics, a science, look like that did not
run away from this situation, but simply embraced it: that turned our
received understandings inside out, and then, proceeded from there? We
have hardly really begun to ask.