đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș ruth-kinna-politics-ideology-and-utopia.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:40:04. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Politics, Ideology and Utopia Author: Ruth Kinna Date: 2011 Language: en Topics: utopia, politics, ideology, William Morris, utopian socialism Source: Retrieved on 11th November 2021 from https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/13569317.2011.607295 Notes: Published in Journal of Political Ideologies, 16(3), 279â294. doi:10.1080/13569317.2011.607295
This article examines a recent shift in radical thinking about utopia
and a critique of traditional socialist utopianism that has emerged from
it. It argues that this new form of utopianism mistakenly treats the
idea of future transformation as an illiberal ideological commitment and
that it fails to distinguish adequately between different models of
socialist utopian thought. The result is a form of utopianism that
strips utopia of one of its central elements, the eu-topian aspect. The
argument draws on the critique presented by Simon Tormey and a
comparative analysis of the socialist utopianism of William Morrisâthe
most celebrated British socialist utopian of the late 19^(th)
centuryâand Ernest Belfort Bax.
It is not unusual to find dramatic shifts in the evaluation of utopian
ideas. Writing at the end of the 1950s, Paul Goodman observed how a
âlong spell of Marxian âscientificâ realism and businessmenâs
âhard-headed realismââ had given way to an enthusiastic embrace of
utopianism.[1] In recent times, a similar shift is detectable. The
overtly utopian claim of the alter-globalization movement that âanother
world is possibleâ has inspired another positive re-evaluation of
utopianism. These two shifts have apparently little in common. Indeed,
the technological, consumption-patterned ideal that Goodman dubbed
âfuture-thinkingâ utopianism is an anathema to contemporary utopians.
Its urban, televisual, automotive vision is more likely to be identified
as a disastrous feature of the globalized world than an achievement.
Nevertheless, they share something in common: for both, the embrace of
utopianism is based on a re-appraisal of an older conception. Rather
than harking back to the ideas of the early 19^(th)-century utopian
socialists or, more proximately, the Marxist anti-utopian utopianism of
the late 19^(th) and early 20^(th) centuries, both reject the key
features of these earlier traditions.
The question Goodman asked about the utopianism of the 1960s was what it
concealed. My question is slightly different: what has been lost in the
critique of socialist utopianism? My answer, though, is similar to his.
Goodman argued that future-thinking utopianism, lacking the âcommon
sense and parsimonious sweetness of Fourier or William Morrisâ,[2]
failed to understand the âplea for communityâ that lies at the heart of
the socialist tradition.[3] My argument is that this new form of
utopianism tends to read into old-style socialist utopian thinking a set
of ideological commitments, which has encouraged a similar neglect.
Whilst contemporary utopianism is undoubtedly appealing by comparison to
the earlier image of utopia it conjures, its categorization of socialist
thinking is too blunt; and the ethical issues that an earlier generation
of writers attempted to address, albeit imperfectly, have been sidelined
rather than developed. To show this I examine Simon Tormeyâs conception
of ideological utopianism and discuss the utopianism of William
Morrisâthe most celebrated British socialist utopian of the periodâand
his friend and collaborator, Ernest Belfort Bax.
The novelty of the alter-globalization movement is often linked to its
internal complexity, plurality, rhizomatic behaviours and its ability to
serve as an umbrella for a range of alternative groups and cultures.[4]
Its utopianism is similarly complex and fluid, distinguished by
commitments to hallmarks or generic principles, rather than manifestos
or party pledges, and advanced by multiple groups operating on the
horizontal principles of organization, informally networked through
transitory, dynamic actions. Anarchism has played a central role in the
conceptualization of this brand of utopianism, but the relationship of
the âmovement of movementsâ to the anarchist tradition is not
straightforward. In an early analysis of the global justice movement,
Barbara Epstein referred to its âanarchist sensibilityâ but carefully
distinguished this from âanarchism per seâ.[5] More precisely, Saul
Newman identifies the utopianism of the alter-globalization movement
with an anarchistic shift from âscientific utopianismâ (identified
primarily with Marx but also Bakunin and Kropotkin) towards a
âutopianism of revoltâ; the rejection of scientism, rationalism and
positivism in favour of spontaneity, rebelliousness and the expression
of an unfilled âshared imaginaryâ.[6] In Simon Tormey and Andrew
Robinsonâs work, the distinction is between the old-style leftist
anarchist utopianism and the radical utopianism of the post-left
anarchy. These labels represent two entirely different approaches to
utopian thinking. The first is identified with âthe separation of the
present and the future, and the organizational tendency to reshape the
world according to a modelâ. The second overcomes that separation and
abandons the secret islands of planned utopia in order âto realize oneâs
desires immediately, in concrete social actions and relationsâ.[7]
Tormeyâs critique of leftist anarchist utopianism points to a broader
dissatisfaction with traditional socialist ideologies. His critique
identifies both philosophical and political failures in the tradition.
The philosophical failures flow from the identification of an essential
goalâfor example, distribution according to need, classlessnessâwhich
serves as the focus for revolutionary struggle and transformation.
However it is defined, this goal assumes the incorporation of
othersâvariously designated as the oppressed or the workersâin the
struggle for its realization. Moreover, it points to a concept of
transformation which is unrealistic and self-defeating. Typically,
political action is reduced to âthe teleological unfolding, recuperation
or construction of an endpoint that is rational and trueâ.[8] The
political failure of traditional utopianism is that it is fundamentally
oppressive. In the name of promoting a better way of life, he argues,
utopias stifle contestation, creativity and uncertainty in a presumed
consensus on shared commitments, harmonious coexistence and the
internalization of moral rules. Utopias spell the end of politics âor
the end of the political as a creative actâ. In utopia the âcreation has
already taken place: we already have the image of the world where we
want to be, whether we call it âcommunismâ, âanarchyâ, or âcapitalismâ.
Creativity exists only for the means not for the endâ.[9]
The claim that utopias typically stifle politics is a familiar one.
Marie Louise Berneri argued that utopians were characteristically
authoritarian, seeking happiness in material well-being and sinking
âindividuality into the groupâ.[10] Post-war liberal anti-utopians like
Isaiah Berlin and Karl Popper voiced similar concerns, linking utopian
dreamsâexpressed particularly strongly in socialist theoryâto the
dystopian realities of the European socialist experience. However,
Tormey locates the problem of utopianism in deferral and argues that
assumptions about historyâs progressive march are only a symptom of this
conception. Whatever role utopians assign to history, he argues that it
is the idea of rupture that is mistaken. Utopians wrongly âencourage us
to think of politics as the construction of a new Tomorrow, a model of
social and political rationality necessitating a complete or fundamental
break from Todayâ.[11] The promise of future happiness justifies
sacrifice and is utilitarian and elitist. Those who understand what the
future should be have a special capacity to determine both the
sacrifices it demands and who should make them. Tormey also points to
the problem of modelling or engineering. As Chamsy El-Ojeili notes, he
accepts much of the liberal critique of Marxism[12] but he does not
locate the failures of socialist utopianism narrowly in Marxâs thought
or even socialism. Any conception of the goodâstateless or otherwiseâis
just another form of negative utopianism. Indeed, insofar as liberal
anti-utopianism was always linked to a normative project and to a
particular idea of the good, Tormey argues that it was itself
âintrinsically utopianâ.[13] Authentically radical utopianism embraces
multiplicity. In declaring how we would like to live we must all
recognize that our ideals are only individual preferences and that the
problem of utopianism is one of âthe incommensurability of utopiasâ.[14]
As Tormey notes, in liberal politics, the term is usually linked to
antagonism, âagonismâ and contestation.[15] As it is brought to bear on
utopian thinking, however, the concept stretches beyond the embrace of
value pluralism or the defence of agonistic liberalism, to the
celebration of âautonomousâ, âanti-authoritarian spacesâ; âspaces of
imagination and creativityâ which are âcontingent, open, negotiated,
unpredictable, beyond captureâ.[16] The utopianism he endorses describes
a politics that gives free reign to diversity and seeks to create âa
space in which âall worlds are possible, where all may live the dreamââ.
The forms that he rejects he calls âideologicalâ: imaginary worlds that
conjure images of ânewâ or âbetterâ places and/or which operate âon the
basis of a definite axiom or logic of organisationâ.[17] The result is a
concept of utopianism which strips utopia of one of its central terms,
namely its eu-topian aspect.
In re-casting of utopia as a space for radical politics, Tormey does not
reject utopiaâs descriptive element. Nevertheless, his conception is
difficult to reconcile with the definition offered by Ruth Levitasâthe
âdesire for a better way of living expressed in the description of a
different kind of society that makes possible that alternative way of
lifeâ.[18] It fits more neatly with descriptions of utopiaâs disruptive
potential. Mannheimâs idea of utopia as the incongruity of states of
mind with existing realities that pass into actions and shatter the
order of things aptly captures its spirit.[19] However, insofar as it
draws together currents of socialist utopian thought that have usually
been treated separately, Tormeyâs critique points to an understanding of
socialist utopianism that is novel.[20] In particular, the association
of deferral and rupture with imaginary models and ideas of the good
blurs the distinction between the utopian socialism associated with
Fourier, Owen and St Simon, who devised detailed blueprints, on the one
hand, and Marxâs anti-utopian utopianism, on the other. Marx finds a
home with them becauseânotwithstanding his criticisms of the utopiansâ
failure to see the futility of their non-revolutionary approach and his
stubborn refusal to elaborate a detailed picture of the futureâhe
cherished an image of a re-shaped world âafterâ the revolution.
So defined, it is difficult to see how the gulf between socialist
utopianism and the utopianism of the alter-globalization movement might
be negotiated. In contrast to both Goodman and Colin Ward, who remained
open to the influence of traditional utopianism, especially the work of
19^(th)-century socialists, Tormey is suspicious of this literature.
Ward thought Morris a âwiseâ utopian.[21] Tormey describes Morrisâs
âgift-economyâ in News From Nowhere as a variant of essentialist Marxism
or anarchism.[22] What does he miss? My suggestion, based on the
discussion of Morris and Baxâs thought, is that he places too great an
emphasis on the notion of rupture and that he overlooks the very
different ways in which socialists of different stripes linked
revolutionary transformation to utopian possibility. As a result, he
overstates the case for incommensurability and neglects the significance
of the organizational frameworks which diverse groups might hope to
create in order to live in plurality.
In his study of English utopias, A. L. Morton categorized News From
Nowhere, William Morrisâ utopian romance, as the first utopia that was
not utopian.[23] By this, he meant that Morris broke new ground by
harnessing the idea of utopia to an analysis of socialist struggle. As
Morton puts it, he combined âthe imagination of a true poetâ with
âscientific methodâ gleaned from Marx.[24] Saul Newmanâs recent
discussion of anarchism and utopianism takes a contrary view: Morris was
a pioneer, but a precursor of new radical thinking, whose work
illustrates the limits of socialist utopianism. Grouping him with
Landauer and Le Guin, Newman classifies him as a utopian of a particular
imagination and contrasts his work with the âscientificâ anarchism of
Kropotkin and Bakunin.[25] The character of Morrisâs utopianism and the
extent to which he drew upon the scientific tropes of late
19^(th)-century thought is clearly germane to the consideration of his
utopianism. On Newmanâs account, Morris is an exception who proves a
rule and a poor choice to discuss socialist utopianism. On Mortonâs,
Morris is useful only insofar as he bucked a trend in scientific
socialism by embracing utopian aspirations. As will be argued below,
neither claim is quite accurate. Morrisâ significance as a
representative of the utopian socialist tradition restsâas Morton
arguesâon his engagement with scientific socialism. Yet the novelty of
his thought stems from the misgivings he had about the implications of
socialist science and his critical, utopian response to widespread
expectations about historical development in the late 19^(th) century.
This novelty did not lead him to reject notions of rupture, but to think
about the moment of revolution and deferment in a distinctive way.
As Morton argues, by the standards of the day Morrisâs Marxism was in
many ways quite orthodox. His insights into capitalismâs operation and
the goal of socialism dovetail with Marxâs, and he absorbed both through
his own reading of Capital and the instruction that he took from his
friend, the philosopher Ernest Belfort Bax. Morris tied the realization
of revolution to a dialectical process of change, assumed that history
was the history of class struggles, that capitalism was a progressive
stage of development shaped by changes in productive forces and that it
was a necessary precursor to socialism. Whilst Morris coupled these
theses to a theory of ethical development that was unconventional, this
departure did not in itself point to the imaginative approach to
utopianism that Newman identifies. The Manifesto of the Socialist League
(1885), jointly authored with Bax, summarized his general view. âSocial
evolutionâ, he argued, described a ârevolution in ethicsâ as well as an
âeconomicalâ change.[26]
The vision that emerged from this account of change was egalitarian, its
structural features shaped by a desire to overcome exploitation and
realize the communist principle of distribution according to need. In
the Manifesto, Morris also called for the destruction of international
boundaries, the introduction of free labour and the abolition of
marriage: freedom in reproduction as well as production. The lynchpin
for his utopia was the realization of productive leisure through the
transformation of labour through art. Assuming that individuals were
necessarily productive beings, Morris envisaged a society in which each
would develop a range of skills both to produce useful and beautiful
things and perform tasks with grace and ease, voluntarily for their own
joy, for the love of giving and/or the recognition attached to it.
Whilst still formally subject to the âtyranny of natureâ, individuals
would no longer feel tyrannized by the necessity to labour and would
thus be free to shape the world according to their creative desires.[27]
Morris described the ethic of communism as âbrotherhoodâ or, more
usually, âfellowshipâ. In general, this concept expressed an idea of
solidarity among strangers or, as Bax puts it, ââone for all and all for
one,â the spirit of common interest, of mutual standing with one another
as a body, quite irrespective of individual likes or dislikesâ.[28] More
richly he linked fellowship to a set of social relationships which arose
from the direct experience of oppression. These relationships were
inter-generational and they were sustained by ideas of hope, loyalty,
mutual support and individual sacrifice. Presenting a Christianized
version of the idea in The Dream of John Ball, Morris intimated that the
perfect demonstration of fellowship was the willingness to die a
martyrâs death. As a supreme expression of commitment, martyrdom
memorialized earlier struggles, providing continuity for future action.
Morrisâs viewââthough I die and end, yet mankind yet liveth, therefore I
end not, since I am a manââis inspired by John Ballâs belief that to die
is only to live âin some new wayâ.[29]
Morrisâs utopianism exhibits many of the features of traditional
socialist thinking. His communist utopia is cast into the future; it
clearly represents a break with the old world and its realization makes
a virtue of deferred benefit, motivating individual sacrifice. Yet the
way in which Morris cemented his ideas together suggests that the
relationship between deferral or rupture and ideological determination
is not as straightforward as Tormey assumes. Morris argued that there
was a disjuncture between the process of historical change and the
utopian goal. As Morton rightly argues, his utopia was informed by the
insights of scientific socialism, but the realization of his vision
depended on the negation of the future it presaged rather than its
fulfilment, leaving a space that could not be filled by incorporation.
Morris sought to fill the gap between reality and utopia by building
into the present a commitment to transformation that was motivated by an
aspiration to live differently. His treatment of the relationship
between the process of change and the goal of communism not only
represented a striking departure from orthodoxy; it also opened up a
division between his position and the already unorthodox Marxism of Bax.
At the heart of the divergence were two different accounts of ethical
change.
Morrisâs understanding of ethical transformation was restorative: in
looking forward to the future he hoped to rekindle a set of behaviours
which commercial competition had destroyed. In The Dream of John Ball he
identified these lost behaviours with artisans of the 1381 Peasantâs
Revolt, and he captured their quality by contrasting the peasantsâ moral
courage with the vacillation of 19^(th)-century workers. These two
groups were victim to different forms of oppression, but Morris argued
that they could nevertheless be characterized in the same broad terms:
their cause was to be free from âmastershipâ and âfleecingâ. The
significant difference between them lies in their response to
oppression. Whereas the artisans faced their oppressors with brave
determination, 19^(th)-century workers were typically sluggards: doltish
and cowardly, they had been seduced by the incentive systems on which
capitalist relations were based. As Morris told John Ball, the workers
had been âblinded to the robbing of themselves by others, because they
shall hope in their souls that they may each live to rob othersâ.[30]
The irony of the situation was that these workers stood at a point of
revolutionary transformation and had a real opportunity to deliver
themselves from exploitation and oppression. The artisansâ struggle was
never likely to have succeeded, for all their commitment and courage,
because historical forces had been stacked against them. In the earlier
period, the impending social rupture played in capitalismâs favour.
Morris found the proof in tracing the long-term results of the revolt:
the artisans were released from feudal obligation only to endure the
hardships associated with the market freedom of wage slavery.
The lesson that Morris took from history was that the success of the
19^(th)-century revolution hinged on the expression of fellowship, the
social force that had impelled the peasants to relocate mastership in
order to confront the historical forces ranged against them. Arguing
that its loss could be recouped and that it was possible to encourage
19^(th)-century workers to see beyond capitalismâs seductive barrier, he
embarked on the policy of âmaking socialistsâ, writing the story of the
Revolt as a small contribution to this educative project. In the story
itself, he also described his hope, reassuring John Ball that the âtime
shall come, when that dream of thine ... shall be a thing that men shall
talk of soberly, and as a thing soon to come aboutâ. Men âshall be
determined to be freeâ and âthe Fellowship of Men shall endure, however
many tribulations it may have to wear throughâ.[31]
Baxâs understanding of ethics was innovative.[32] He charted the process
of historical development by mapping three models of social relations to
three parallel forms of consciousness: first, âprimitiveâ or ânaturalâ
communism and pagan-classical thought; second, individualism and early
Christianity and Protestantism; and third, future communism and the
religion of socialism. Believing that history followed a dialectical
path in which material and ethical changes interacted in a continuous
movement, this sociological model enabled Bax to make some general
projections about the character of socialism. As the transcendence of
primitive communism and individualism, socialism would bear the primary
characteristics of primitive communismâduty and solidarityâbut in a
manner mediated by the history of individualism. So whereas primitive
communism had been limited by ties of blood or kinship, the religion of
socialism would support a global, generalized duty based on the
recognition of the equality of peoples.[33] Bax denied that the
progression he mapped followed a path defined by reason. Departing from
Hegel, whose idealism he generally embraced, he instead followed
Schopenhauer to argue that reason was itself animated by the alogical
principle associated with passion, feeling and sentiment. Nor did he
envisage the future as an improved version of the present. Reflecting on
the qualitative changes socialism would bring, he anticipated that the
movement leading to socialism would re-balance ethical with material
forces and bring a new set of relationships to the fore. The struggle
for subsistence had hitherto given general primacy to material forces,
but in socialismâthe realm of freedomâethical forces would for the first
time become primary motors of change. This meant that the mind would be
freer than ever before to determine the conditions of social existence.
For both Morris and Bax socialism was in some respects indeterminate. In
Morrisâs account, the indeterminacy described an uncertainty about the
commitment of ordinary people to fight slavery, reclaim mastership from
elites and realize a genuine alternative to capitalist practices and
state organization through the transformation of labour into art.
Capitalism was poised to collapse but there was a strong possibility
that the opportunities to bring the system to an end would not be
seized. For Bax, the process of change was certain, but there was
considerable space for individuals of a particular passion to hasten the
process of change. Moreover, whilst reason indicated the direction of
historical development, the form that socialism might take was unclear.
Viewed through Tormeyâs critical lens, both Morris and Bax used their
understanding of history to generate a utopian vision. Yet their account
of ethics led them in very different directions. Morris scholars argue
about the extent to which the vision he described in News From Nowhere
should be read impressionistically or taken as a literal picture of the
future, but however it is interpreted, there is little doubt that he
consciously encouraged readers to reflect on Nowhereâs goodness. As Ruth
Levitas puts it, Nowhere is âan imagined alternative future which serves
to transform the presentâ.[34] It was essential to think creatively and
imaginatively about the future, because in the absence of an
inspirational alternative, present trends would merely continue
unchallenged. Moreover, there would be no way of assessing the worth of
competing claims about how to organize in the here and now and whether
or not to enter into fellowship with others engaged in similar everyday
struggles. Though Morris disliked it intensely, Edward Bellamyâs Looking
Backward had been enlightening in this respect. Was his picture of
âextreme ... national centralizationâ or âState Communismâ worth
fighting for?[35] Bellamy presented it under the banner of socialism,
but Morris did not think so. He acknowledged that his utopia was as
idiosyncratic as Bellamyâs, an expression of his own temperament and a
reflection of his particular desires. The book was âegoisticalâ, he
said.[36] Yet, the fact that it captured a âprivate dreamâ did not mean
that it might not resonate more widely. By his own reckoning he was not
âso utterly differentâ from other people; a composite of at least âa
dozen personsâ. The facets of his complex personality were âbut types of
many others in the worldâ.[37] He was not surprised, then, to discover
that âa good many peopleâ (ultimately, not enough) found his
âaspirations pleasantâ.[38] By presenting the description of Nowhere as
a friendâs description of a comradeâs dream, Morris even structured the
correspondence of hope into the narrative. As the bearer of the
comradeâs testimony, the friend relates the dream in the first person,
emphasizing the identity of their desires. By this device Morris
established a line of transmission which lends the dream a prophetic
quality. At the end of the book he invites readers to consider its
relationship with their own aspirations, and his suggestion that they
have the power to transform the dream into a vision endows Nowhere with
the force of revelation.
Unlike Morrisâs vision, Baxâs could only be seen in the mindâs eye. He
not only denied that the picture of socialism was integral to the
process of transformation, but he also thought it irrelevant. All that
mattered was the insight into the process of change and the ability to
act upon it. Indeed, any suggestion that the future could be imagined
was preposterous. Though he thought that there was some purpose in
making policy in advance of the revolution, he characterized âUtopian
socialist writingsâ as mere travesties âof the society of the present,
or of the pastâ. It was possible to âdefine, that is, lay down, in the
abstract, the general principles on which the society of the future will
be based, but we cannot describe, that is, picture, in the concrete, any
state of society of which the world has had no experienceâ.[39] History
has taught that the future would expand the realm of freedom, but Bax
argued that it was impossible to tell how this freedom might translate
into everyday practices or ways of living. Indeed, whereas Morris was
willing to describe the organization of socialism by abstracting from
history and reflecting on the conditions for artâs rebirth, he argued
that historical change made the past itself impossible to grasp. Baxâs
contention that the alogical was something that reason could not
properly grasp, led him to the conclusion that individuals were always
trapped by the limits of current understanding. Although it was possible
to identify retrospectively patterns of historical change and use these
to predict the likely shape of the future, the past could not help fill
out the details of the future because both were inevitably mere
projections of the present. Baxâs fantastic and tantalizing conclusion
was that whilst the mind was poised to discover a new kind of freedom,
the nature of this freedom was utterly unimaginable.
The divergent character of Morris and Baxâs utopianism reflected their
equally different ideas about the relationship between the present and
the future. Of the two, Bax alone understood the future as a process of
unfolding. For Morris, socialism described a better place but one that
was contingent on action in the present. As a result, whilst Bax was
drawn towards utilitarianism, Morris was not. On the question of
socialist transformation, Morrisâ suggestion that it was possible to
find ethical continuity between communism and pre-capitalist society
indicated there was a qualitative difference between the present and the
future, but also a relationship between the two. Only the full flowering
of communism would facilitate the transformation of work into art. On
this account, the revolution did not mark the sudden death of corrupt
practices and the immediate birth of newly restored moral behaviours.
Fellowship, the ethic of socialism, was the central ingredient in the
struggle for socialism. Baxâs view, that individuals would be swept
along by the alogic of history into a new set of social relations, found
a parallel in Morrisâ work, but fellowship described conscious
commitment, not a developing consciousness. And although he adopted a
fairly standard view of what the revolution entailed, the expression of
an abstract ideal and the incorporation of the others as vehicles for
social transformation were notâas they were for Baxâpart of the package.
As Tormey suggests, by setting socialism into an imaginary future,
Morris was led to believe that the struggle for utopia involved an
emotional commitment to others, that it might well result in martyrdom
and that it typically involved sacrifice. His pessimism about the
possibility of securing meaningful change in the body of capitalism also
led him to associate revolutionary action with negative behaviours and
risk, rather than the creative development of challenging alternatives.
Having given up the possibility of living such an alternative in the
company of his fellow artists for the sake of fighting for capitalismâs
general destruction, he had concluded that it was impossible to hasten
the structural transformation necessary for the universal enjoyment of
art from the privileged space that he occupied. His gamble was that he
would lose both art as well as the revolution, because capitalism did
indeed provide him with a space to do what he wanted, albeit on terms he
did not like. Yet here, too, there was an important difference with Bax.
Morrisâs strategy was to demonstrate the superiority of socialism in the
hope that it might help inspire a similar desire for revolutionary
change in others. Issuing his appeals to ordinary people, he exemplified
the mundane acts of other, equally ordinary individuals. His response to
the death of Alfred Linnell is a good illustration of his approach.
Linnell had been involved in an anti-unemployment demonstration at the
Trafalgar Square on 20 November 1887, and died after sustaining an
injury inflicted by the police. Unlike John Ball, Linnell had expected
to return home after the demonstration, but this was irrelevant to
Morrisâs estimation of the value of his sacrifice. Linnell was everyman,
significant precisely because he was not extraordinary, and although his
presence was less spectacular than, say, an intervention to shield a
fellow demonstrator from harm or arrest, his death symbolized a living
commitment to fellowship. At the funeral Morris implored the mourners:
âLet us feel he is our brother.â[40] His speech at Linnellâs funeral was
reported in the press:
There lay a man of no particular partyâa man who until a week or two ago
was perfectly obscure, and probably was only known to a few .... Their
brother lay thereâlet them remember for all time this man as their
brother and their friend .... Their friend who lay there had had a hard
life and met with a hard death; and if society had been differently
constituted from what it was, that manâs life might have been a
delightful, a beautiful one, and a happy one to him. It was their
business to try and make this earth a very beautiful and happy
place.[41]
Possessing a keen sense of âthe chant of the goblins of destinyâ,[42]
Bax in contrast reserved a special role for those who understood the
beating heart of history. He even knuckled down to the prospect that
âthe energetic minorityâ would in all probability have to act âin
opposition to ... the inert massâ,[43] nominating the âEuropean
Socialist partyâ as the âauthoritative tribunalâ on the grounds that
they had the âreal welfareâ of the âcount-of-heads majorityâ at
heart.[44]
In sum: Morrisâ differences with Bax point to two different logics which
Tormeyâs critique fails to acknowledge. In Morrisâ thought the
realization of utopia is contained within the dynamic of struggle.
Although there was a significant difference between his view and, say,
Fourierâs (namely that he could no more tolerate the idea of utopia as
an oasis in the body of capitalism than Marx), like the utopians of the
early 19^(th) century, he relied on voluntary subscription, not
incorporation: the prospects for utopia rest on the engagement of
ordinary people. In Baxâs work, by contrast, the process of change is
transcendent. Socialism lies in the future but its achievement is part
of a process of dialectical change, necessitating judgements about
policies for its advancement. There is a clear understanding that those
best equipped to interpret social development and conceptualize the
collective benefit which the future will bring should determine
revolutionary policy.
If the rupture Morris imagined did not lead him to commit the same
strategic errors as Bax, his utopianism undoubtedly fails the test of
incommensurability. The vision of Nowhere is a particular idea of
socialism, where the privilege that Morris had to âplayâ and avoid
âworkââas he put it in The Dream of John Ballâwas enjoyed in common.[45]
It necessarily restricts the possible set of utopias that might be
contained within it. In addition, because Morris considered the
production of art a social act, critics have objected that it
anticipates a harmonization of interests that is both unrealistic and
undesirable.[46] Before turning to consider the formal constraints of
his utopia, it is worth considering this critique and Morrisâ Morris was
happy to describe Nowhere as a place without politics and by this he
meant not only that it had abandoned representative parliamentary
institutions, but that disagreements manufactured by sectarian interest
would disappear. His conception of politics chimed in with much
19^(th)-century socialist thinking and it was informed by a broad
distrust ingrained in the artistic circles he inhabited: the shock felt
by his friends on hearing his decision to give up art for socialism
reverberated not from the radicalism of his position, but his immersion
in a world linked with grubby deals and the compromise of principle. In
these circles politics was a dirty word, associated with hypocrisy,
duplicity and self-seekingâeverything that art and poetry were not.
Louisa Bevingtonâs description of the âpublic muddleâ and âprivate
scrambleâ of âLunatic Landâ and the peace and liberty of âCommon-sense
Countryâ where âprophets, or poetsâ thrived, aptly captured this
view.[47] Like her, Morris also understood politics as the antonym for
art: ugliness and, above all, pretence. Importing this idea into his
socialism, he concluded that removal of economic power advantages and
the recovery of mastership would release individuals from the grip of
these vices. As he explains in Nowhere, class politics never offered a
route for the articulation of genuinely or deeply held opinions; it
operated to conceal the actual coincidence of elite interests and as a
cover for oppression. How else, Morris asked, could elites have âdealt
together in the ordinary business of life ... eaten together, brought
and sold together, gambled together, cheated on other people
togetherâ?[48] With the abolition of elite politics, the theatricality
of performance would open the way for a new craft of honest exchange:
popular creative expression through social engagement.
The hypocrisy Morris identified in bourgeois politics corresponds with
what Tormey calls the rhetoric of liberalism: the freedom to contest
everything except âthe âfreedomâ of the free market, the rationality of
representation, the monopolising nature of anti-monopoly legislation,
the tyranny of âchoiceââ.[49] Nevertheless, the diversity he imagines in
Nowhere does not have the diffuse, permanently creative quality that
Tormey looks for. Instead, Morris points to the diversity of language
and culture and comments on the variety that springs from popular
art.[50] There are disagreements and even room for discontent. Violent
disputesâbetween men rather than against womenâspring from jealous
rivalry and romantic disappointment. Despite the achievement of gender
equality, in Nowhere men still fight for the love of women and women
continue to meddle with their emotions. This divergence is managed by
the principles of interaction which have freed women from the
restrictions of bourgeois law, but Morris supposed that these tensions
could never be eradicated. Yet life is convivial and for all the
diversity and occasional conflict, Morris downplayed the significance of
contestation. Rather than being defined by experimentation, the art of
utopia is based on creative refinement. Just as the inhabitants of
Nowhere learn how to perfect design techniques over time, matching
functionality with style and polish, they also become adept in dealing
with public disputes. As Laurence Davis has rightly argued, the
perfectibility of utopian politics in part reflected Morrisâ
oversimplification of the âinstitutional sources of social
conflictâ.[51] Perhaps optimistically, he assumed that the abolition of
capitalist markets and private ownership of the means of production
would overcome fundamental disputes about âthe build of the universe and
the progress of timeâ.[52] In the other part, however, the quality of
utopian politics was explained by the sophistication of political skills
that the inhabitants of Nowhere acquired. The ethic of
socialismâfellowshipâplayed an important role here, facilitating the
development of consensus decision-making. Although individuals disagree
about âreal solid thingsâ, these disagreements do not âcrystallise
people into parties permanently hostile to one anotherâ.[53] Admittedly,
in critiques of anarchism towards the end of his life, Morris adopted a
more strongly republican position which rooted resolution in the
identification of common interest, but in his more libertarian phases he
assumed that differences were reconcilable through open, equal,
reflective and direct discussion of the bodies concerned. Bourgeois
politics suggested that politics was about conflict. In Morrisâs view,
this was misleading. He believed that it was possible to secure
consensus through mutual respect and a wish to find agreement, and he
treated resolution as a social goal. In doing so, he adopted a
conception of politics clearly at odds with the post-left utopianism
Tormey supports.
The formal restrictions Morris introduced in communism placed a further
barrier between his idea of utopia and the anti-eutopian concept. Tormey
recommends indifference about the organization of utopian spaces. They
are offered âwithout constraints, obligations, contracts, permanently
binding rational or âuniversalâ featuresâ.[54] In contrast, Morris
sought to impose an absolute prohibition against âslaveryâ. In utopia it
was not permissible for any group or individual to institutionalize
exploitation or oppression. Morris imagined that all members of his
future federation would commit themselves to this rule, no matter how
they decided to organize themselves locally. But in the event of
deviation he allowed that breaches could be resisted with force. In
addition, Morris admitted that fellowship would function as a form of
social conditioning. He recognized that some socialists might find this
idea troubling and his response was that it was impossible to abolish
âthe tyranny of societyâ: the idea, which he associated with anarchism,
âthat every man should be quite independent of every otherâ was, he
said, ridiculous.[55] Individuals could live more or less isolated
lives, but their social conditions would always impose constraints. Yet,
just as it was possible to transform the âtyranny of natureâ by turning
work into play, it was also possible to uncouple this background
âtyrannyâ from the legal tyranny which prevailed in statist societies.
By providing a secure ground for fellowship, Morris perhaps imagined
that communism would shape utopia in the same way that bourgeois rule
and market relations conditioned social life in capitalismâand with
similar complexity. In seeking to change the terms of association he
certainly hoped that the informal regulation of society would overcome
the need to enforce the formal prohibitions on exploitation and
oppression that were essential to utopiaâs existence.
To summarize, in utopia different groups and individuals live well
together, expressing their particular interests and differences, because
they have taken an active role in shaping this ideal. Nowhere is not
filled with phalansteries or closed small-town communities; it leaves
space for movement, wandering and personal adventure. It assumes a
common commitment to an idea of social life that is defined by
resistance to slavery. Insofar as everyday politics was concerned,
Morris imagined a future in which agreement was the norm. His
anticipation of the dovetailing of desire and his faith in fellowship,
epitomized in Nowhere by the friendliness of strangers, led him to
believe that disparate individuals would all be able to feel at home in
socialism and work out their differences amicably. This embrace of
consensus is a significant marker of Morrisâs utopianism. The question
is: does this provide a reason for rejecting wholesale the idea of a
utopian world?
Tormeyâs criticism of socialist utopianism is that it wrongly
subordinates politics to ideology and assumes the incorporation of
others in apocalyptic struggles for future worlds that are illusory and
self-defeating. Morrisâs utopianism suggests that some of the arguments
on which this critique is based are mistaken. As Buber argued, to hold
an ideal of a future world does not necessarily entail the adoption of a
utilitarian or hierarchical idea of transformation. Similarly, the
attempt to define the parameters of utopia does not require a rejection
of politics in the name of ideological conformity. The consensual
politics Morris imagined failed to consider how forms of oppression
might escape public acknowledgement and how slavery might be defined. In
the society of art, it was still possible for everyday practices to
constrain or repress individual desires and for individuals to find
their behaviours out of step with prevailing currents. Yet this problem
remains even where experimentation is preferred to refinement as a model
for social engagement. Morrisâs utopia emerged from an attempt to
imagine the least tyrannous condition: the condition that he believed
allowed the greatest scope for individuals to determine the patterns of
their own lives. However, imperfectly, it recognized the space for
politics within an ideological frame.
Although indifferent about their organization, Tormey is concerned about
the quality of the spaces within which politics takes place. The test of
incommensurability is that the exact specification of how matters are to
be organized is to be left to âindividuals and the groups and
collectivities that the individual chooses to interact withâ.[56] But
not all spaces pass this test: liberal utopias are a case in point.
Nozickâs otherwise instructive analysis of incommensurability is deemed
inadequate because he situates the spatial utopia in a âcapitalist
laissez-faire world of precisely the kind that the movement for global
justice ... seeks to displaceâ.[57] Yet Morris falls foul of
incommensurability precisely because he attempted to outline an
alternative organizational principle and tried to imagine how diverse
groups and individuals might use the spaces it supported creatively. His
vision was in some respects naive and it left important questions about
the possibility of consensus and the resolution of difference
unanswered. However, these shortcomings might be addressed from within
the utopian tradition. There are resonances of Morrisâs approach to
utopiaâand his concern with labourâin Nowtopianism, for example. The
Nowtopian commitment to immediate practical action and the
transformation of life in the present offers more scope for action than
Morris thought realistic, but the vision of a world free of âproductive
laborâ and the belief that nowtopian behaviours will not, by themselves,
achieve this revolutionary change supports his utopianism.[58] Paul
Goodmanâs revisions of the older socialist traditions forged a similar
link between the present and the future. His judgement that â[a]ll human
societies are patterns of cultureâ echoes Morris, as does his
recognition that patterning does not assume an absence of conflict.[59]
Offering a different conception of politics, he argued that âconflict is
not an obstacle to community but a golden opportunityâ.[60] However, in
his willingness to jettison âwarmth and securityâ for social invention
and ânew character-typesâ, Goodman did not throw out utopia but asked
instead how models might be adapted and applied in everyday life. With
his feet planted firmly in the anarchist â socialist tradition, Ward
similarly conceptualized utopia as âa million private dreamsââthe
multiplicity of individual desires each encapsulating a desire âto do my
own thing in my own wayâ.[61] Seeing little more than vanguardism and
tyrannical conformity in utopia, the anti-eutopian critique Tormey
presents misses these possibilities and throws out a potent element in
the socialist tradition.
A version of this paper was presented at the Goldsmiths, University of
London RUPE seminar. I would like to thank participants for feedback and
Laurence Davis, Ian Fraser and Alex Prichard for their helpful comments
on earlier drafts of the revised paper.
[1]
P. Goodman, Utopian Essays and Practical Proposals (New York: Vintage
Books, 1962), p. 3.
[2] Goodman, ibid., p. 4.
[3] Goodman, ibid., p. 9.
[4]
G. Chesters and I. Welsh, âComplexity and social movement: process and
emergence in planetary action systemsâ, Theory, Culture and Society,
22 (2005), pp. 187 â 211.
[5]
B. Epstein, âAnarchism and the alter-globalization movementâ, Monthly
Review, 53(4) (2001), available at
=> http://www.monthlyreview.org/0901epstein.htm www.monthlyreview.org
(accessed 1 November 2010).
[6]
S. Newman, âAnarchism, utopianism and the politics of emancipationâ,
in L. Davis and R. Kinna (Eds) Anarchism and Utopianism (Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 2009), p. 207.
[7]
A. Robinson and S. Tormey, âUtopias without transcendence? Post-left
anarchy, immediacy and utopian energyâ, in P. Hayden and C.
el-Ojeili (Eds) Globalization and Utopia: Critical Essays (London:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2009), p. 161.
[8]
S. Tormey, âFrom utopian worlds to utopian spacesâ, Ephemera, 5
(2005), p. 399.
[9] Tormey, ibid.
[10]
M. Berneri, Journey Through Utopia (London: Freedom Press, 1982), p. 2.
[11] Tormey, op. cit., Ref. 8, p. 400.
[12]
C. el-Ojeili, âTwo post-Marxisms: beyond post-socialism?â, in Hayden
and el-Ojeili, op. cit., Ref. 7, pp. 42 â 43.
[13] Tormey, op. cit., Ref. 8, p. 399.
[14] Tormey, ibid., pp. 397, 402.
[15] Berlinâs critique of the ethical monism of utopianism is discussed
by L. Davis in âIsaiah Berlin, William Morris and the politics of
utopiaâ, in B. Goodwin (Ed.) The Philosophy of Utopia (London/Portland,
OR: Frank Cass, 2001), pp. 56 â 86.
[16] Tormey, op. cit., Ref. 8, p. 402.
[17] Tormey, ibid., p. 395.
[18]
R. Levitas, âThe future of thinking about the futureâ, in J. Bird, B.
Curtis, T. Putnam, G. Robertson and L. Tickner (Eds) Mapping the
Futures: Local Cultures, Global Change (London/New York: Routledge,
1995), pp. 257 â 266.
[19]
K. Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of
Knowledge (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979), p. 173.
[20] For a discussion see D. Leopold, âThe structure of Marx and Engelsâ
considered account of utopian socialismâ, History of Political Thought,
26(3) (2005), pp. 443 â 466; D. Leopold, âSocialism and (the rejection
of) utopiaâ, Journal of Political Ideologies, 12 (2007), pp. 219 â 237.
[21] Colin Ward, Utopia (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1974), p. 108.
[22] Tormey, op. cit., Ref. 8, p. 399.
[23]
A. L. Morton, The English Utopia (London: Lawrence & Wishart,
1978), p. 213.
[24]
A. L. Morton, Three Works by William Morris (London: Lawrence &
Wishart, 1986), p. 30.
[25] Newman, op. cit., Ref. 6, p. 207.
[26]
W. Morris and E. B. Bax, Manifesto of the Socialist League (London,
1885), note E, available at
=> http://www.marxists.org/archive/morris/works/1885/manifst2.htm www.marxists.org
(accessed 25 June 2010).
[27]
W. Morris, âUseful work versus useless toilâ, Signs of Change (Bristol:
Thoemmes Press, 1994), p. 107.
[28]
E. B. Bax, Problems of Mind and Morals (London: Grant Richards, 1912),
Ch. 6, note 2, available at
=> http://www.marxists.org/archive/bax/1912/probs/06-fundament.htm www.marxists.org
(accessed 25 June 2010).
[29]
W. Morris, âThe dream of John Ballâ, in Morton, op. cit., Ref. 24, p.
89.
[30] Morris, ibid., p. 24.
[31] Morris, ibid., p. 110.
[32] For a discussion see R. Kinna, âTime, history and utopiaâ, Journal
of William Morris Studies, XVIII(4) (2010), pp. 36 â 47.
[33]
E. B. Bax, The Ethics of Socialism (London: Swan Sonnenschein,
n.d.), p. 21.
[34] Levitas, op. cit., Ref. 18, p. 259.
[35]
W. Morris, âLooking backwardâ, in N. Salmon (Ed.) Political Writings:
Contributions to Justice and Commonweal 1883 â 1890 (Bristol:
Thoemmes Press, 1994), p. 422.
[36]
W. Morris, âHow shall we live then?â, in P. Meier (Ed.) âAn unpublished
lecture of William Morrisâ, International Review of Social History,
16 (1971), p. 223.
[37] Morris, ibid., p. 223.
[38]
W. Morris, The Collected Letters of William Morris 1889 â 1892, Ed. N.
Kelvin (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996), p. 310.
[39]
E. B. Bax, Outlooks From the New Standpoint, Preface, para. 3,
available at
=> http://www.marxists.org/archive/bax/1891/outlooks/00-preface.htm www.marxists.org
(accessed 25 June 2010).
[40]
F. McCarthy, William Morris A Life For Our Time (London: Faber & Faber,
1994), p. 573.
[41]
E. P. Thompson, William Morris, Romantic to Revolutionary, 2^(nd) edn
(New York: Pantheon Books, 1976), p. 494.
[42]
E. B. Bax, The Religion of Socialism (London: Swan Sonnenschein,
Lowrey & Co., n.d.), p. 82.
[43] Bax, op. cit., Ref. 33, p. 128.
[44] Bax, ibid., p. 122.
[45] Morris, op. cit., Ref. 29, p. 113.
[46] For a discussion see Davis, op. cit., Ref. 15.
[47]
L. S. Bevington, Common-sense Country (London: Liberty Press,
1890), p. 11, available at
=> http://www.indiana.edu/letrs/vwwp/bevington/common.html www.indiana.edu
(accessed 25 June 2010). I am grateful to Ingrid Hanson for
directing me to Bevingtonâs pamphlet.
[48]
W. Morris, âNews from nowhereâ, in Morton, op. cit., Ref. 24, p. 269.
[49] Tormey, op. cit., Ref. 8, p. 400.
[50] Morris, op. cit., Ref. 48, pp. 268 â 270.
[51]
L. Davis, âIsaiah Berlinâ, op. cit., Ref. 15, p. 66. Davis adopts a
more critical stance and finds Morris guilty of adopting an illusory
ideal of ethical consensus.
[52] Morris, op. cit., Ref. 48, p. 269.
[53] Morris, ibid., p. 269.
[54] Tormey, op. cit., Ref. 8, p. 403.
[55] Morris, op. cit., Ref. 48, p. 272.
[56] Tormey, op. cit., Ref. 8, p. 397.
[57] Tormey, ibid., p. 397.
[58]
C. Carlsson and F. Manning, âNowtopia: strategic Exodus?â, Antipode,
42(4) (2010), p. 950.
[59] Goodman, op. cit., Ref. 1, p. 8.
[60] Goodman, ibid., p. 21.
[61] Ward, op. cit., Ref. 21, p. 5.