💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-anarchism-past-and-present.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:29:09. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchism: Past and Present
Author: Murray Bookchin
Language: en
Topics: class struggle, history, marxism
Source: Retrieved on April 28, 2009 from http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/anarchist_archives/bookchin/pastandpresent.html
Notes: This piece appeared as Vol. 1, No. 6 of Comment: New Perspectives in Libertarian Thought, edited by Murray Bookchin.

Murray Bookchin

Anarchism: Past and Present

Note: The following issue of COMMENT was presented as a lecture to the

Critical Theory Seminar of the University of California at Los Angeles

on May 29, 1980. My remarks are intended to emphasize the extreme

importance today of viewing Anarchism in terms of the changing social

contexts of our era — not as an ossified doctrine that belongs to one or

another set of European thinkers, valuable as their views may have been

in their various times and places. Today, more than ever, the viability

of Anarchism in America will depend upon its ability to speak directly —

in the language of the American people and to living problems of the

American people — rather than to resurrect ideas, expressions, slogans

and a weary vernacular that belong to eras past. This is not to deny the

internationalist spirit of Anarchism or its historical continuity, but

rather to stress the need to solidarize with libertarian traditions and

concepts that are clearly relevant to dominated peoples in the areas —

conceived in terms of place, time, and forms — in which libertarian

movements function.

I

There is a grave danger that Anarchism may be dealt with simplistically,

the way we deal with most radical “isms” today — as a fixed body of

theory and practice that so often reduces Socialism to the textual works

of Marx and Engels and their acolytes. I do not mean to deny the generic

meaning of terms like “Socialism.” There are many types of Socialisms

ranging from the utopian to the Leninist, from the ethical to the

scientific. I simply wish to stake out the same claim for Anarchism. We

must always remember that there are also many forms of Anarchism,

notably anarcho-syndicalism, anarcho-individualism,

anarcho-collectivism, anarcho-communism, and, amusingly enough,

anarcho-Bolshevism if I read the history of the Spanish Anarchist

movement correctly. These Anarchist theories and movements have been

burdened by all the intramural conflicts we encounter between

Socialists, albeit in a less bloody and lethal form.

What really concerns me with the wide range of Anarchisms, however, goes

well beyond the generic character of the term. I cannot stress strongly

enough that Anarchism not only encompasses a wide variety of theories

and movements but more importantly it has a very rich historical genesis

and development. This is crucial to an understanding of what I have to

say. More so than any radical movement with which we are familiar,

Anarchism is a profoundly social movement as distinguished from the

usual political movements we associate with The Left. Its vitality, its

theoretical form, indeed its very raison d’etre stem from its capacity

to express the millenia-long aspirations of peoples to create their own

egalitarian or, at least, self-administered social structures, their own

forms of human consociation by which they can exercise control over

their lives. In this sense, Anarchism really constitutes a folk or

people’s social philosophy and practice in the richest sense of the

term, just as the folk song constitutes the emotional expression of a

people in their esthetic or spiritual depths. The Hellenic origins of

the terms anarche or “no rule” should not deceive us into thinking that

it can be readily placed in the academic spectrum of social ideas.

Historically, Anarchism has found expression in non-authoritarian clans,

tribes and tribal federations, in the democratic institutions of the

Athenian polis, in the early medieval communes, in the radical Puritan

congregations of the English Revolution, in the democratic town meetings

that spread from Boston to Charleston after 1760, in the Paris Commune

of 1871, the soviets of 1905 and 1917, the Anarchist pueblos, barrios,

and worker-controlled shops of the Spanish Revolution of 1936 — in

short, in the self-directed, early and contemporary, social forms of

humanity that have institutionally involved people in face-to-face

relations based on direct democracy, self-management, active

citizenship, and personal participation.[1] It is within this electric

public sphere that the Anarchist credo of direct action finds its real

actualization. Indeed, direct action not only means the occupation of a

nuclear power plant site but less dramatic, often prosaic, and tedious

forms of self-management that involve patience, commitment to democratic

procedures, lengthy discourse, and a decent respect for the opinions of

others within the same community.

This institutional framework and sensibility is the authentic mileau of

Anarchism, its very protoplasm. The theories that emerge from the

activity of this protoplasm are the forms of self-reflexive rationality

that give it coherence and consciousness. To my thinking, the “Digger”

Winstanley, the Enrage Varlat, the artisan Proudhon, the worker

Pelloutier, and the Russian intellectuals Bakunin and Kropotkin voice at

various levels of consciousness different, often clearly delineable,

phases of humanity’s organic evolution toward freedom. One can often

associate these individuals or the ideas they developed with the actual

development of the popular social forms from which they emerged or to

which they gave ideological coherence. Thus one can justifiably

associate Winstanley’s ideas with the agrarian Anarchism of the yeoman

communities in seventeenth-century England, Varlat with the urban

neighborhood Anarchism of the revolutionary sections and Enrage movement

of Paris in 1793, Proudhon with the artisan Anarchism of craftspeople in

pre-industrial France, Bakunin’s anarcho-collectivism with the peasant

villages of Russia and Spain, Pelloutier’s anarcho-syndicalism, with the

industrial proletariat and emerging factory system and, perhaps most

prophetically, Kropotkin’s anarcho-communism with our own era, a body of

theory that readily lends itself to the ecological, decentralist,

technological, and urban issues that have come to the foreground of

social life today.

The anti-statist and anti-political views of these Anarchist thinkers

should not obscure the positive content of their views and their roots.

The Marxian notion that human “socialization” reaches its most advanced

historical form with bourgeois society — a society that strips humanity

of its remaining biosocial trappings — would have been emphatically

rejected by these Anarchists if only on the intuitive grounds that

society can never be totally denatured. As I have argued elsewhere (see

my “Beyond Neo-Marxism” in Telos, No. 36), society never frees itself of

its natural matrix, even in the internal relations between individuals.

The actual issue, if one is to learn from the ecological problems of our

time, is the nature of that nature in which society is rooted — organic

(as was the case in many precapitalist communities) or inorganic (as is

the case in market society). The clan, tribe, polis, medieval commune,

even the Parisian sections, the Commune, certainly the village and

decentralized towns of the past, were rooted in bio-social relations.

Market society with its atomization, competition, total objectification

of the individual and her or his labor-power — not to speak of the

bureaucratic sinews that hold this lifeless structure together, the

concrete, steel, and glass cities and suburbs that provide its

environments, and quantification that permeates every aspect of its

activity — all of these not only deny life in the biological and organic

sense but reduce it to its molecular components in the physical and

inorganic sense. Bourgeois society does not achieve society’s domination

of nature; rather, it literally desocializes society by making it an

object to be appropriated by inorganic nature, by the bourgeois in his

inner being and his social being. The bureaucracy colonizes the social

institutions of humanity; the concrete city, the organic relations of

nature; cybernetics and the mass media, the individual’s personality; in

short, market “society” colonizes every aspect of personal and social

life.

I cannot emphasize too strongly the umbilical cord that unites organic

societies, in the sense and with the qualifications I have described

them, with Anarchist theories and movements. Nor can I desist from

noting the extent to which Marxism, by contrast, is linked to the most

inorganic of all human structures, the state — and at other layers of

hierarchy, with that most inorganic of all oppressed classes, the

proletariat and such institutionalized forms of centralized power as the

factory, the party, and the bureaucracy. That the very “universality” of

the proletariat that Marx celebrates in the form of its dehumanization

by capital, its association with a technological framework based on

centralization, domination, and rationalization which presumably render

it into a revolutionary force reveals the extent to which Marx’s own

theoretical corpus is rooted in bourgeois ideology in its least

self-reflexive form. For this “universality” as we can now see

celebrates the “hollowing out” of society itself, its increasing

vulnerability to bureaucratic manipulation in industry and politics by

capital and trade unions. “Schooled” by the nuclear family, by

vocational supervisors, by the hierarchical factory structure, and by

the division of labor, the “universality” of the proletariat turns out

to be the faceleseness of the proletariat — its expression not of the

general interests of humanity in its progress toward socialism but its

particular interests, indeed, of interests as such, as the expression of

bourgeois egoism. The factory does not unite the proletariat; it defines

it — and no tendency more clearly expresses the proletariat’s human

desires than its attempt to escape from the factory, to seek what the

Berlin Dadaists of 1918 were to demand: “universal unemployment.”

II

These far-reaching distinctions between Anarchism as a social movement

and Marxism as a political one require further emendations. I have no

quarrel with the great wealth of Marx’s writings, particularly his work

on alienation, his analysis of the commodity relationship and the

accumulation of capital. His historical theories require the correction

of the best work of Max Weber and Karl Polanyi. But it is not Marx’s

writings that must be updated. Their limits are defined by their

fundamentally bourgeois origins and their incredible susceptibility to

political, that is, state-oriented ideologies. Historically, it is not

accidental that Anarchism in Spain, in the Ukraine, and, in its

Zapatista form in Mexico, could be crushed only by a genocidal

destruction of its social roots, notably the village. Marxian movements,

where they suffer defeat, are crushed merely by demolishing the party.

The seeming “atavism” of Anarchism — its attempts to retain artisanship,

the mutual aid of the community, a closeness to nature and enlightened

ethical norms — are its virtues insofar as they seek to retain those

richly articulated, cooperative, and self-expressive forms of human

consociation scaled to human dimensions. The seeming “effectiveness” of

Marxism — its attempt to replicate the state in the form of the party,

its emphasis on a political apparatus, its scientific thrust and its

denial of a prophetic ethical vision — are its vices insofar as they do

not demolish the bourgeois state but incorporate it into the very

substance of protest and revolution.

Not accidentally, Marxism has been most sharply alienated from itself.

The attempt to “update” Marxian theory, to give it relevance beyond the

academy and reformist movements, has added an obfuscating eclectic

dimension to its ideological corpus. In response to the Russian general

strike of 1905, Rosa Luxemburg was obliged to make the “mass strike” — a

typical Anarchist “strategy” — palatable to the Second International —

this, not without grossly distorting Engel’s view on the subject and the

Anarchist view as well.[2] Lenin was to perform much the same acrobatics

in State and Revolution in 1917 when events favored the Paris Commune as

a paradigm, again assailing the Anarchists while concealing Marx’s own

denigrating judgment of the uprising in the later years of his life.

Similar acrobatics were performed by Mandel, Gorz, et al in May-June

1968, when all of France was swept into a near-revolutionary situation.

What is significant, here, is the extent to which the theory follows

events which are essentially alien to its analysis. The emergence of the

ecology movement in the late 1960s, of feminism in the early 1970s, and

more belatedly, of neighborhood movements in recent years has rarely

been viewed as a welcome phenomenon by Marxist theorists until, by the

sheer force of events, it has been acknowledged, later distorted to meet

economistic, Marxist criteria, and attempts are ultimately made to

absorb it. At which point, it is not Anarchism, to which these issues

are literally indigenous, that has been permitted to claim its relevancy

and legitimacy to the problems of our era but rather Marxism, much of

which has become the ideology of state capitalism in half of the world.

This obfuscating development has impeded the evolution of revolutionary

consciousness at its very roots and gravely obstructs the evolution of a

truly self-reflexive revolutionary movement.

By the same token, Anarchism has acquired some bad Marxist habits of its

own, notably an ahistorical and largely defensive commitment to its own

past. The transformation of the sixties counterculture into more

institutionalized forms and the decline of the New Left has created

among many committed Anarchists a longing for the ideological security

and pedigree that currently afflicts many Marxist sects. This yearning

to return to a less inglorious past, together with the resurgence of the

Spanish CNT after Franco’s death, has fostered an Anarchism that is

chillingly similar in its lack of creativity to sectarian forms of

proletarian socialism, notably anarcho-syndicalism. What is lacking in

both cases is the proletariat and the historical constellation of

circumstances that marked the hundred-year-old era of 1848 to 1938.

Anarchist commitments to the factory, to the struggle of wage labor

versus capital, share all the vulgarities of sectarian Marxism. What

redeems the anarcho-syndicalists from outright congruence with

authoritarian Marxism is the form their libertarian variant of

proletarian socialism acquires. Their emphasis on an ethical socialism,

on direct action, on control from below, and their apolitical stance may

serve to keep them afloat, but what tends to vitiate their efforts —

this quite aside from the historical decline of the workers movement as

a revolutionary force — is the authoritarian nature of the factory, the

pyramidal structure fostered by syndicalist theory, and the reliance

anarcho-syndicalists place on the unique role of the proletariat and the

social nature of its conflict with capital.

Viewed broadly, anarcho-syndicalism, Proudhonianism, and Bakuninism

belong to an irretrievable past. I say this not because they lack

ideological coherence and meaning — indeed, Proudhon’s emphasis on

federalism still enjoys its original validity — but simply because they

speak to epochs which have faded into history. There is much they can

teach us, but they have long been transcended by historically new issues

— in my view, more fundamental in their libertarian implications — to

which the entire Left must now address itself. This does not mean the

“death” or even the “transcendence” of Anarchism as such once we view

the term in its generic and historical meaning, for the issues that

confront us are more distinctly social than they have ever been at any

time in the past. They literally involve the recreation of a new public

sphere as distinguished from the state with the forms, institutions,

relations, sensibilities, and culture appropriate to a world that is

faced with desocialization at every level of life. For Marxism, these

issues are fatal and, in fact, render Marxism itself into ideology in a

socially destructive sense.

III

We are no longer living in a world where revolutionary consciousness can

be developed primarily or even significantly around the issue of wage

labor versus capital. I do not wish to denigrate the significance of

this century-old conflict. That a class struggle exists between the

proletariat and the bourgeoisie (however broadly we choose to define the

term “proletariat”) hardly requires discussion, anymore than the fact

that we live in a capitalist society that is ruled by a capitalist class

(again, however broadly we choose to define the term “capitalist”). What

is really at issue is that a class struggle does not mean a class war in

the revolutionary sense of the term. If the past century has taught us

anything, I submit it has demonstrated that the conflict between the

proletariat and the bourgeoisie has been neither more nor less

revolutionary than the conflict between the plebians and patricians in

the ancient world or the serfs and the nobility in the feudal world.

Both conflicts did not simply end in an impasse; they never contained

the authentic possibilities of transcending the social, economic, and

cultural forms within which they occurred. Indeed, the view of history

as a history of class struggle is a highly convoluted one that is not

exhausted by conflicting economic interests, by class consciousness and

identity, or by the economically motivated methods that have so easily

rooted socialist and syndicalist ideologist in economic reductionism or

what is blithely called a “class analysis.”

What lies on the horizon of the remaining portion of this century is not

the class struggle as we have known it in the metaphors of proletarian

socialism — Socialist or Anarchist. The monumental crisis bourgeois

society has created in the form of a disequilibrium between humanity and

nature, a crisis that has telescoped an entire geological epoch into a

mere century; the expansive notion of human freedom that has given rise

of feminism in all its various forms; the hollowing out of the human

community and citizenship that threatens the very claims of

individuality, subjectivity, and democratic consciousness, perhaps the

greatest claim the bourgeois epoch has made for itself as a force for

progress; the terrifying sense of powerlessness in the face of

ever-greater urban, corporate, and political gigantism; the steady

demobilization of the political electorate in a waning era of

institutional republicanism — all of these sweeping regressions have

rendered an economistic interpretation of social phenomena, a

traditional “class analysis,” and largely conventional political

strategies in the forms of electoral politics and party structures

grossly inadequate. One must truly torture these issues and grossly warp

them into utterly distorted forms to fit them into Marxian categories.

Perhaps no less significantly, the far-reaching politicization of the

economy itself in the form of state capitalism or its various

approximations and the emergence of a highly elaborated bureaucracy have

given to the state sweeping historical functions that go far beyond its

earlier role as a so-called “executive committee of the ruling class.”

Indeed, to an appalling extent, they have turned the state into a

substitution for society itself.

One must realize the entirely new conditions this constellation of

circumstances has produced for radicalism, the extent to which they

redefine the revolutionary project theoretically and practically. The

technical progress that Socialism once regarded as decisive to

humanity’s domination of nature and as preconditions for human freedom

have now become essential in sophisticating the domination of human by

human. Technology now savagely reinforces class and hierarchical rule by

adding unprecendented instrumentalities of control and destruction to

the forces of domination. The wedding of the economy to the state, far

from simplifying the revolutionary project as Engels so naively believed

in Anti-Duhring, has reinforced the powers of the state with resources

that the most despotic regimes of the past never had at their command.

The growing recognition that the proletariat has become — and probably

has always been — an organ of capitalist society, not a revolutionary

agent gestating within its womb, has raised anew the problem of the

“revolutionary agent” in an entirely new and non-Marxian form. Finally,

the need for the revolutionary project to view itself as a cultural

project (or counterculture, if you will) that encompasses the needs of

human subjectivity, the empowerment of the individual, the

astheticization of the revolutionary ideal has led, in turn, to a need

to consider the structural nature, internal relations, and institutional

forms of a revolutionary movement that will compensate, if only in part,

for the cultural, subjective, and social negation of the public and the

private sphere. Indeed, we must redefine the very meaning of the word

“Left” today. We must ask if radicalism can be reduced to a crude form

of social democracy that operates within the established order to

acquire mass, mindless constituencies or if it must advance a

far-reaching revolutionary challenge to desocialization and to every

aspect of domination, be it in everyday life or in the broader social

arena of the coming historic epoch.

IV

Whatever else Anarchism meant in the past — be it the millenarian

movements of Christianity, the peasant movements of the Anabaptists,

-the Makhnovite and Zapatista militias, the Parisian Enrages and

Communards, the Proudhonian artisans, or the early industrial workers

who entered the CGT in France and the CNT in Spain — it is clear to me

that contemporary Anarchism must address itself in the most

sophisticated and radical terms to capitalist, indeed to hierarchical

society, in its advanced and, I genuinely believe, its terminal forms.

To relegate Anarchism to an ahistorical moral movement based on the

virtues of “natural man” and his proclivities for mutual aid, to define

it merely in terms of its opposition to the state as the source of all

evil, worse, to describe Anarchism merely in terms of one of its

variants — the Anarchism of Stirner, Proudhon, Bakunin, or Kropotkin, —

is to grossly misread Anarchism as a historical movement, to ignore its

existence as a social movement in a specific social context. Anarchism

does not have the proprietary character of Marxism with its body of

definable texts, commentators, and their offshoots. Conceived as a

social movement rather than a political one, it is not only deeply woven

into the development of humanity but demands historical treatment.

Do I mean to say, then, that Anarchism dissolves into history and has no

theoretical identity? My reply would be an emphatic “No.” What unites

all Anarchist theories and movements are not only their defense of

society against the state, of direct action against political action;

more fundamentally, I believe, Anarchism by definition goes beyond class

exploitation (whose significance it never denies) into hierarchical

domination, whose historical significance it increasingly analyzes as

the source of authority as such. The domination of the young by the old

in tribal gerontacracies, of women by men in patriarchal families, the

crude objectification of nature — all precede class society and economic

exploitation. In fact, they remain the crucial residual sphere of

authority that Marxism and Socialism retain all too comfortably in their

notions of a classless society. Anarchism, in effect, provides the

materials for an analysis of the nature of freedom and the nature of

oppression that go beyond the conventional economistic, nexus of

capitalist society into the very sensibility, structure, and nature of

human consociation as such. The genesis of hierarchy, which for Marx was

an inevitable extension of biology into society, is seen as a social

phenomenon within the Anarchist framework, one which has its most

consolidating source in patriarchy and the supremacy of the male’s civil

domain over the woman’s domestic domain. I know of no more brilliant

statement of this far-reaching shift than Horkheimer’s and Adorno’s

passage on “animals” at the end of the Dialectic of Enlightenment: “For

millena men dreamed of acquiring absolute mastery over nature, of

converting the cosmos into one immense hunting-ground. “ (p. 248)

Inevitably, the genesis of hierarchy and domination yields the

objectification of nature as mere natural resources, of human beings as

mere human resources, of community as mere urban resources in short, the

reduction of the world itself to inorganic technics and a technocratic

sensibility that sees humankind as a mere instrument of production.

I have tried to show elsewhere that Marx sophisticates and extends this

trend into socialism and, unwittingly, reduces socialism to ideology.

(See my “Marxism as Bouregois Sociology,” Our Generation, Vol. 13, No.

3) What concerns me for the present is that Anarchism, often

intuitively, assembles the materials for a deeper, richer, and more

significantly, a broads insight and grasp into the dialectic of

domination and freedom, this by reaching beyond the factory and even the

marketplace into hierarchical relations that prevail in the family, the

educational system, the community, and in fact, the division of labor,

the factory, the relationship of humanity to nature, not to speak of the

state, bureaucracy, and the party. Accordingly, the issues of ecology,

feminism, and community are indigenous concerns of Anarchism, problems

which it often advances even before they acquire social immediacy — not

problems which must be tacked on to its theoretical corpus and distorted

to meet the criteria of an economistic, class-oriented viewpoint. Hence,

Anarchism, by making these issues central to its social analyses and

practice has acquired a relevance that, by far, overshadows most trends

in present-day socialism. Indeed, Anarchism has become the trough in

which Socialism eclectically nourishes itself on an alien diet of

“socialist feminism,” the “economics of pollution,” and the “political

economy of urbanism.”

Secondly, Anarchism has faced the urgent problem of structuring itself

as a revolutionary movement in the form of the very society it seeks to

create. It should hardly be necessary to demolish the preposterous

notion that hierarchical forms of organization are synonymous with

organization as such, anymore than it should be necessary to demolish

the notion that the state has always been synonymous with society. What

uniquely distinguishes Anarchism from other socialisms is it commitment

to a libertarian confederal movement and culture, based on the

coordination of human-scaled groups, united by personal affinity as well

as ideological agreement, controlled from below rather than from

“above,” and committed to spontaneous direct action. Here, it fosters

embryonic growth, cell by cell as it were, as distinguished from

bureaucratic growth by fiat and inorganic accretion. At a time when

consociation is faced with the deadly prospect of dissociation,

Anarchism opposes social form to political form, individual empowerment

through direct action to political powerlessness through bureaucratic

representation. Thus Anarchism is not only the practice of citizenship

within a new public sphere, but the self-administration of the

revolutionary movement itself. The very process of building an Anarchist

movement from below is viewed as the process of consociation,

self-activity and self-management that must ultimately yield that

revolutionary self that can act upon, change and manage an authentic

society.

I have merely scratched the wails of a considerable theoretical corpus

and critique that would require volumes to develop in detail. Let me

emphasize that the most advanced Anarchist theories, today, do not

involve a mystical return to a “natural man,” a crude anti-statism, a

denial of the need for organization, a vision of direct action as

violence and terrorism, a mindless rejection of sophisticated theory, an

opaqueness to what is living in the work of all Socialist theories.

Anarchist critique and reconstruction reach far and deep into the

Socialist and bourgeois traditions. If Anarchism is the “return of a

ghost,” as Adorno once insisted, we may justly ask why this “ghost”

continues to haunt us today. This reality can only be answered

rationally if one remembers that the “ghost” is nothing less than the

attempt to restore society, human consociation at the present level of

historical development, in the face of an all-ubiquitious state and

bureaucracy with its attendant depersonalization of the individual and

its demobilization of the public and the public sphere. By the same

token, the bourgeois essence of Socialism, particularly in its Marxian

form, lies in its inglorious celebration of the massification of the

citizen into the proletarian, of the factory as the public sphere, of

cultural impoverishment as “class consciousness,” of the retreat from

the social to the economic, of the triumph of technics over nature and

of science over ethics. If Anarchism is a “ghost,” it is because human

consociation itself threatens to become spectral; if Marxism is a

“living presence,” it is because the market threatens to devour social

life. Adorno’s metaphors become confused in the name of a false

“historicism” where even the past actually enjoys more vitality than the

present, a vitality that can never be recovered without giving life to

the “ghost” itself. If the state, bureaucracy, and “masses” are to be

exorcised, it is not Anarchism that will be removed from the stage of

history but Marxism, with its centralized parties, hierarchies,

economistic sensibilities, political strategies, and class mythologies.

V

There is much I have been obliged to omit. My limited time makes it

impossible for me to deal with such delectable questions as the nature

of the “revolutionary agent” today, the relationship of Anarchist

practice to the political sphere (a more complex issue than is generally

supposed when one recalls that Anarchists played a significant role in

the electoral activities of the Montreal Citizens Movement), the details

of Anarchist organizational structures, the relationship of Anarchism to

the counterculture, to feminism, to the ecology movement, to neo-Marxist

tendencies, and the like.

But allow me to conclude with this very important consideration. At a

time when the proletariat is quiescent — historically, I believe — as a

revolutionary class and the traditional factory faces technological

extinction, Anarchism has raised almost alone those ecological issues,

feminist issues, community issues, problems of self-empowerment, forms

of decentralization, and concepts of self-administration that are now at

the foreground of the famous “social question.” And it has raised these

issues from within its very substance as a theory and practice directed

against hierarchy and domination, not as exogenous problems that must be

“coped” with or warped into an economistic interpretation subject of

class analysis and problems of material exploitation.

 

[1] It would be well, at this point, to stress that I am discussing the

institutional structure of the social forms cited above. That they all

variously may have excluded women, strangers, often non-conformists of

various religious and ethnic backgrounds, not to speak of slaves and

people lacking property, does not diminish humanity’s capacity to

recreate them on more advanced levels. Rather, it indicates that despite

their historical limitations, such structures were both possible and

functional, often with remarkable success. A free society will have to

draw its content from the higher canons of reason and morality, not from

— “models” that existed in the past. What the past recovers and

validates is the human ability to approximate freedom, not the

actualization of freedom in the fullness of its possibilities.

[2] A distortion all the more odious because the Social Democratic

rank-and-file had been deeply moved, ideologically as well as

emotionally, by the 1905 events. “The anarchists and syndicalists who

had previously been driven underground by orthodox Social Democracy now

rose to the surface like mushrooms on the periphery of the SPD,”

observes Peter Nettl rather disdainfully in his biography of Luxemburg;

“when it came to something resembling ‘their’ general strike they felt

they were close to legitimacy once more.” And, indeed, with good reason:

“For the first time for years anarchist speakers appeared on provincial

Socialist platforms by invitation. The orthodox party press led by

Vorwarts was much more cautious; but it, too, gave pride of place

[albeit if not of doctrine — M. B.] to Russian events and for the first

few months abstained from wagging blunt and cautious fingers over the

differences between Russian chaos and German order.” (Peter Nettl, Rosa

Luxemburg, Oxford University Press, 1969, abridged version, pp. 203–4).