đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș murray-bookchin-what-is-social-ecology.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:37:30. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: What is Social Ecology? Author: Murray Bookchin Date: 1993 Language: en Topics: social ecology, green anarchism, ecology Source: *Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology*, edited by M.E. Zimmerman, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1993. Notes: This text was substantially revised for
Murray Bookchin has long been a major figure in anarchlst and utopian
political theory, theory of technology, urbanism, and the philosophy of
nature. He is the cofounder and director emeritus of the Institute for
Social Ecology. His many books include Toward an Ecological Society, The
Ecology of Freedom, The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of
Citizenship, Remaking Society, and The Philosophy of Social Ecology.
---
What literally defines social ecology as âsocialâ is its recognition of
the often overlooked fact that nearly all our present ecological
problems arise from deep-seated social problems. Conversely, present
ecological problems cannot be clearly understood, much less resolved,
without resolutely dealing with problems within society. To make this
point more concrete: economic, ethnic, cultural, and gender conflicts,
among many others, lie at the core of the most serious ecological
dislocations we face todayâapart, to be sure, from those that are
produced by natural catastrophes.
If this approach seems a bit too âsociologicalâ for those
environmentalists who identify ecological problems with the preservation
of wildlife, wilderness, or more broadly, with âGaiaâ and planetary
âOneness,â it might be sobering to consider certain recent facts. The
massive oil spill by an Exxon tanker at Prince William Sound, the
extensive deforestation of redwood trees by the Maxxam Corporation, and
the proposed James Bay hydroelectric project that would flood vast areas
of northern Quebecâs forests, to cite only a few problems, should remind
us that the real battleground on which the ecological future of the
planet will be decided is clearly a social one.
Indeed, to separate ecological problems from social problemsâor even to
play down or give token recognition to this crucial relationship â would
be to grossly misconstrue the sources of the growing environmental
crisis. The way human beings deal with each other as social beings is
crucial to addressing the ecological crisis. Unless we clearly recognize
this, we will surely fail to see that the hierarchical mentality and
class relationships that so thoroughly permeate society give rise to the
very idea of dominating the natural world.
Unless we realize that the present market society, structured around the
brutally competitive imperative of âgrow or die,â is a thoroughly
impersonal, self-operating mechanism, we will falsely tend to blame
technology as such or population growth as such for environmental
problems. We will ignore their root causes, such as trade for profit,
industrial expansion, and the identification of âprogressâ with
corporate self-interest. In short, we will tend to focus on the symptoms
of a grim social pathology rather than on the pathology itself, and our
efforts will be directed toward limited goals whose attainment is more
cosmetic than curative.
While some have questioned whether social ecology has dealt adequately
with issues of spirituality, it was, in fact, among the earliest of
contemporary ecologies to call for a sweeping change in existing
spiritual values. Such a change would mean a far-reaching transformation
of our prevailing mentality of domination into one of complementarity,
in which we would see our role in the natural world as creative,
supportive, and deeply appreciative of the needs of nonhuman life. In
social ecology, a truly natural spirituality centers on the ability of
an awakened humanity to function as moral agents in diminishing needless
suffering, engaging in ecological restoration, and fostering an esthetic
appreciation of natural evolution in all its fecundity and diversity.
Thus social ecology has never eschewed the need for a radically new
spirituality or mentality in its call for a collective effort to change
society. Indeed, as early as 1965, the first public statement to advance
the ideas of social ecology concluded with the injunction: âThe cast of
mind that today organizes differences among human and other life-forms
along hierarchical lines of âsupremacyâ or âinferiorityâ will give way
to an outlook that deals with diversity in an ecological manner--that
is, according to an ethics of complementarity.â[1] In such an ethics,
human beings would complement nonhuman beings with their own capacities
to produce a richer, creative, and developmental wholeânot as a
âdominantâ species but as a supportive one. Although this idea,
expressed at times as an appeal for the ârespiritization of the natural
world,â recurs throughout the literature of social ecology, it should
not be mistaken for a theology that raises a deity above the natural
world or that seeks to discover one within it. The spirituality advanced
by social ecology is definitively naturalistic (as one would expect,
given its relation to ecology itself, which stems from the biological
sciences), rather than supernaturalistic or pantheistic.
To prioritize any form of spirituality over the social factors that
actually erode all forms of spirituality, raises serious questions about
oneâs ability to come to grips with reality. At a time when a blind
social mechanism, the market, is turning soil into sand, covering
fertile land with concrete, poisoning air and water, and producing
sweeping climatic and atmospheric changes, we cannot ignore the impact
that a hierarchical and class society has on the natural world. We must
earnestly deal with the fact that economic growth, gender oppressions,
and ethnic dominationânot to speak of corporate, state, and bureaucratic
interestsâare much more capable of shaping the future of the natural
world than are privatistic forms of spiritual self-regeneration. These
forms of domination must be confronted by collective action and major
social movements that challenge the social sources of the ecological
crisis, not simply by personalistic forms of consumption and investment
that often go under the rubric of âgreen capitalism.â We live in a
highly cooptative society that is only too eager to find new areas of
commercial aggrandizement and to add ecological verbiage to its
advertising and customer relations.
Let us begin, then, with basicsânamely, by asking what we mean by nature
and society. Among the many definitions of nature that have been
formulated over time, one is rather elusive and often difficult to grasp
because it requires a certain way of thinkingâone that stands at odds
with what we popularly call âlinear thinking.â This form of ânonlinearâ
or organic thinking is developmental rather than analytical, or, in more
technical terms, dialectical rather than instrumental. Nature, conceived
in terms of developmental thinking, is more than the beautiful vistas we
see from a mountaintop or in the images that are fixed on the backs of
picture postcards. Such vistas and images of nonhuman nature are
basically static and immobile. Our attention, to be sure, may be
arrested by the soaring flight of a hawk, or the bolting leap of a deer,
or the low-slung shadowy loping of a coyote. But what we are really
witnessing in such cases are the mere kinetics of physical motion,
caught in the frame of an essentially static image of the scene before
our eyes. It deceives us into believing in the âeternalityâ of a single
moment in nature.
If we look with some care into nonhuman nature as more than a scenic
view, we begin to sense that it is basically an evolving phenomenon, a
richly fecund, even dramatic development that is forever changing. I
mean to define nonhuman nature precisely as an evolving process, as the
totality, in fact of its evolution. This encompasses the development
from the inorganic into the organic, from the less differentiated and
relatively limited world of unicellular organisms into that of
multicellular ones equipped with simple, later complex, and presently
fairly intelligent neural apparatuses that allow them to make innovative
choices. Finally, the acquisition of warm-bloodedness gives to organisms
the astonishing flexibility to exist in the most demanding climatic
environments.
This vast drama of nonhuman nature is in every respect stunningly
wondrous. It is marked by increasing subjectivity and flexibility and by
increasing differentiation that makes an organism more adaptable to new
environmental challenges and opportunities and renders a living being
more equipped to alter its environment to meet its own needs. One may
speculate that the potentiality of matter itselfâthe ceaseless
interactivity of atoms in forming new chemical combinations to produce
ever more complex molecules, amino acids, proteins, and, under suitable
conditions, elementary life-formsâis inherent in inorganic nature. Or
one may decide, quite matter-of-factly, that the âstruggle for
existenceâ or the âsurvival of the fittestâ (to use popular Darwinian
terms) explains why increasingly subjective and more flexible beings are
capable of dealing with environmental changes more effectively than are
less subjective and flexible beings. But the fact remains that the kind
of evolutionary drama I have described did occur, and is carved in stone
in the fossil record. That nature is this record, this history, this
developmental or evolutionary process, is a very sobering fact.
Conceiving nonhuman nature as its own evolution rather than as a mere
vista has profound implicationsâethical as well as biologicalâfor
ecologically minded people. Human beings embody, at least potentially,
attributes of nonhuman development that place them squarely within
organic evolution. They are not ânatural aliens,â to use Neil Everndenâs
phrase, strange âexotics,â phylogenetic âdeformitiesâ that, owing to
their tool-making capacities, âcannot evolve with an ecosystem
anywhere.â[2] Nor are they âintelligent fleas,â to use the language of
Gaian theorists who believe that the earth (âGaiaâ) is one living
organism.[3] These untenable disjunctions between humanity and the
evolutionary process are as superficial as they are potentially
misanthropic. Humans are highly intelligent, indeed, very self-conscious
primates, which is to say that they have emergedânot divergedâfrom a
long evolution of vertebrate life-forms into mammalian, and finally,
primate life-forms. They are a product of a significant evolutionary
trend toward intellectuality, self-awareness, will, intentionality, and
expressiveness, be it in oral or body language.
Human beings belong to a natural continuum, no less than their primate
ancestors and mammals in general. To depict them as âaliensâ that have
no place or pedigree in natural evolution, or to see them essentially as
an infestation that parasitizes a highly anthropomorphic version of the
planet (Gaia) the way fleas parasitize dogs and cats, is bad thinking,
not only bad ecology. Lacking any sense of process, this kind of
thinkingâregrettably so commonplace among ethicistsâradically bifurcates
the nonhuman from the human. Indeed, to the degree that nonhuman nature
is romanticized as âwilderness,â and seen presumably as more
authentically ânaturalâ than the works of humans, the natural world is
frozen into a circumscribed domain in which human innovation, foresight,
and creativity have no place and offer no possibilities.
The truth is that human beings not only belong in nature, they are
products of a long, natural evolutionary process. Their seemingly
âunnaturalâ activitiesâlike the development of technology and science,
the formation of mutable social institutions, of highly symbolic forms
of communication, of esthetic sensibilities, the creation of towns and
citiesâall would be impossible without the large array of physical
attributes that have been eons in the making, be they large brains or
the bipedal motion that frees their hands for tool making and carrying
food. In many respects, human traits are enlargements of nonhuman traits
that have been evolving over the ages. Increasing care for the young,
cooperation, the substitution of mentally guided behavior for largely
instinctive behaviorâall are present more keenly in human behavior. The
difference between the development of these traits among nonhuman beings
is that among humans they reach a degree of elaboration and integration
that yields cultures or, viewed institutionally in terms of families,
bands, tribes, hierarchies, economic classes, and the state, highly
mutable societies for which there is no precedent in the nonhuman
worldâunless the genetically programmed behavior of insects is to be
regarded as âsocial.â In fact, the emergence and development of human
society is a shedding of instinctive behavioral traits, a continuing
process of clearing a new terrain for potentially rational behavior.
Human beings always remain rooted in their biological evolutionary
history, which we may call âfirst Nature,â but they produce a
characteristically human social nature of their own which we may call
âsecond nature.â And far from being âunnatural,â human second nature is
eminently a creation of organic evolutionâs first nature. To write the
second nature created by human beings out of nature as a whole, or
indeed, to minimize it, is to ignore the creativity of natural evolution
itself and to view it onesidedly. If âtrueâ evolution embodies itself
simply in creatures like grizzly bears, wolves, and whalesâgenerally,
animals that people find esthetically pleasing or relatively
intelligentâthen human beings are literally de-natured. In such views,
whether seen as âaliensâ or as âfleas,â humans are essentially placed
outside the self-organizing thrust of natural evolution toward
increasing subjectivity and flexibility. The more enthusiastic
proponents of this de-naturing of humanity may see human beings as
existing apart from nonhuman evolution, thereby dealing with people as a
âfreaking,â as Paul Shepard puts it, of the evolutionary process. Others
simply avoid the problem of humanityâs unique place in natural evolution
by promiscuously putting human beings on a par with beetles in terms of
their âintrinsic worth.â In this âeither/orâ propositional thinking, the
social is either separated from the organic, or flippantly reduced to
the organic, resulting in an inexplicable dualism at one extreme or a
naive reductionism at the other. The dualistic approach, with its
quasi-theological premise that the world was âmadeâ for human use is
saddled with the name of âanthropocentricity,â while the reductionist
approach, with its almost meaningless notion of a âbiocentric
democracy,â is saddled with the name of âbiocentricity.â
The bifurcation of the human from the nonhuman reveals a failure to
think organically, and to approach evolutionary phenomena with an
evolutionary way of thought. Needless to say, if we are content to
regard nature as no more than a scenic vista, mere metaphoric and poetic
description of it might suffice to replace systematic thinking about it.
But if we regard nature as the history of nature, as an evolutionary
process that is going on to one degree or another under our very eyes,
we dishonor this process by thinking of it in anything but a processual
way. That is to say, we require a way of thinking that recognizes that
âwhat-isâ as it seems to lie before our eyes is always developing into
âwhat-it-is-not,â that it is engaged in a continual self-organizing
process in which past and present, seen as a richly differentiated but
shared continuum, give rise to a new potentiality for a future,
ever-richer degree of wholeness. Accordingly, the human and the nonhuman
can be seen as aspects of an evolutionary continuum, and the emergence
of the human can be located in the evolution of the nonhuman, without
advancing naive claims that one is either âsuperior toâ or âmade forâ
the other.
By the same token, in a processual, organic, and dialectical way of
thinking, we would have little difficulty in locating and explaining the
emergence of the social out of the biological, of second nature out of
first nature. It seems more fashionable these days to deal with
ecologically significant social issues like a bookkeeper. One simply
juxtaposes two columnsâlabeled âold paradigmâ and ânew paradigmââas
though one were dealing with debits and credits. Obviously distasteful
terms like âcentralizationâ are placed under âold paradigm,â while more
appealing ones like âdecentralizationâ are regarded as ânew paradigm.â
The result is an inventory of bumper-sticker slogans whose âbottom lineâ
is patently a form of âabsolute good versus absolute evil.â All of this
maybe deliciously synoptic and easy for the eyes, but it is singularly
lacking as food for the brain. To truly know and be able to give
interpretative meaning to the social issues so arranged, we should want
to know how each idea derived from others and is part of an overall
development. What, in fact, do we mean by the notion of
âdecentralization,â and how does it derive from or give rise in the
history of human society to âcentralizationâ? Again: processual thinking
is needed to deal with processual realities so that we can gain some
sense of directionâpractical as well as theoreticalâin dealing with our
ecological problems.
Social ecology seems to stand alone, at present, in calling for the use
of organic, developmental, and derivative ways of thinking out problems
that are basically organic and developmental in character. The very
definition of the natural world as a development indicates the need for
an organic way of thinking, as does the derivation of human from
nonhuman natureâa derivation that has the most far-reaching consequences
for an ecological ethics that can offer serious guidelines for the
solution of our ecological problems.
Social ecology calls upon us to see that nature and society are
interlinked by evolution into one nature that consists of two
differentiations: first or biotic nature, and second or human nature.
Human nature and biotic nature share an evolutionary potential for
greater subjectivity and flexibility. Second nature is the way in which
human beings as flexible, highly intelligent primates inhabit the
natural world. That is to say, people create an environment that is most
suitable for their mode of existence. In this respect, second nature is
no different from the environment that every animal, depending upon its
abilities, creates as well as adapts to, the biophysical
circumstancesâor ecocommunityâin which it must live. On this very simple
level, human beings are, in principle, doing nothing that differs from
the survival activities of nonhuman beingsâbe it building beaver dams or
gopher holes.
But the environmental changes that human beings produce are
significantly different from those produced by nonhuman beings. Humans
act upon their environments with considerable technical foresight,
however lacking that foresight may be in ecological respects. Their
cultures are rich in knowledge, experience, cooperation, and conceptual
intellectuality; however, they may be sharply divided against themselves
at certain points of their development, through conflicts between
groups, classes, nation states, and even city-states. Nonhuman beings
generally live in ecological niches, their behavior guided primarily by
instinctive drives and conditioned reflexes. Human societies are
âbondedâ together by institutions that change radically over centuries.
Nonhuman communities are notable for their fixity in general terms or by
clearly preset, often genetically imprinted, rhythms. Human communities
are guided in part by ideological factors and are subject to changes
conditioned by those factors.
Hence human beings, emerging from an organic evolutionary process,
initiate, by the sheer force of their blology and survival needs, a
social evolutionary development that profoundly involves their organic
evolutionary process. Owing to their naturally endowed intelligence,
powers of communication, capacity for institutional organization, and
relative freedom from instinctive behavior, they refashion their
environmentâas do nonhuman beingsâto the full extent of their biological
equipment. This equipment now makes it possible for them to engage in
social development. It is not so much that human beings, in principle,
behave differently from animals or are inherently more problematical in
a strictly ecological sense, but that the social development by which
they grade out of their biological development often becomes more
problematicai for themselves and non human life. How these problems
emerge, the ideologies they produce, the extent to which they contribute
to biotic evolution or abort it, and the damage they infiict on the
planet as a whole lie at the very heart of the modern ecological crisis.
Second nature, far from marking the fulfillment of human potentialities,
is riddled by contradictions, antagonisms, and conflicting interests
that have distorted humanityâs unique capacities for development. It
contains both the danger of tearing down the biosphere and, given a
further development of humanity toward an ecological society, the
capacity to provide an entirely new ecological dispensation.
How, then, did the socialâeventually structured around status groups,
class formations, and cultural phenomenaâemerge from the biological? We
have reason to speculate that as biological facts such as lineage,
gender distribution, and age differences were slowly institutionalized,
their uniquely social dimension was initially quite egalitarian. Later
it acquired an oppressive hierarchical and then an exploitative class
form. The lineage or blood tie in early prehistory obviously formed the
organic basis of the family. Indeed, it joined together groups of
families into bands, clans, and tribes, through either intermarriage or
fictive forms of descent, thereby forming the earliest social horizon of
our ancestors. More than in other mammals, the simple biological facts
of human reproduction and protracted maternal care of the infant tended
to knit siblings together and produced a strong sense of solidarity and
group inwardness. Men, women, and their children were brought into a
condition of a fairly stable family life, based on mutual obligation and
an expressed sense of affinity that was often sanctified by marital vows
of one kind or another.
Outside the family and all its elaborations into bands, clans, tribes
and the like, other human beings were regarded as âstrangers,â who could
alternatively be welcomed hospitably or enslaved or put to death. What
mores existed were based on an unreflected body of customs that seemed
to have been inherited from time immemorial. What we call morality began
as the commandments of a deity, in that they required some kind of
supernatural or mystical reinforcement to be accepted by the community.
Only later, beginning with the ancient Greeks, did ethical behavior
emerge, based on rational discourse and reflection. The shift from blind
custom to a commanding morality, and finally, to a rational ethics
occurred with the rise of cities and urban cosmopolitanism. Humanity,
gradually disengaging itself from the biological facts of blood ties,
began to admit the âstrangerâ and increasingly recognize itself as a
shared community of human beings rather than an ethnic folkâa community
of citizens rather than of kinsmen.
In the primordial and socially formative world that we must still
explore, other of humanityâs biological traits were to be reworked from
the strictly natural to the social. One of these was the fact of age and
its distinctions. In the emerging social groups that developed among
early humans, the absence of a written language helped to confer on the
elderly a high degree of status, for it was they who possessed the
traditional wisdom of the community, the kinship lines that prescribed
marital ties in obedience to extensive incest taboos, and techniques for
survival that had to be acquired by both the young and the mature
members of the group. In addition, the biological fact of gender
distinctions were to be slowly reworked along social lines into what
were initially complementary sororal and fraternal groups. Women formed
their own food-gathering and care taking groups with their own customs,
belief systems, and values, while men formed their own hunting and
warrior groups with their own behavioral characteristics, mores, and
ideologies.
From everything we know about the socialization of the biological facts
of kinship, age, and gender groupsâtheir elaboration into early
institutionsâthere is no reason to doubt that people existed in a
complementary relationship with one another. Each, in effect, was needed
by the other to form a relatively stable whole. No one âdominatedâ the
others or tried to privilege itself in the normal course of things. Yet
with the passing of time, even as the biological facts that underpin
every human group were further reworked into social institutions, so the
social institutions were slowly reworked at various periods and in
various degrees, into hierarchical structures based on command and
obedience. I speak here of a historical trend, in no way predetermined
by any mystical force or deity, a trend that often did not go beyond a
very limited development among many preliterate or aboriginal cultures,
and even in certain fairly elaborate civilizations. Nor can we foretell
how human history might have developed had certain feminine values
associated with care and nurture not been overshadowed by masculine
values associated with combative and aggressive behavior.
Hierarchy in its earliest forms was probably not marked by the harsh
qualities it has acquired over history. Elders, at the very beginnings
of gerontocracy, were not only respected for their wisdom but often
beloved of the young, and their affection was often reciprocated in
kind. We can probably account for the increasing stridency and harshness
of later gerontocracies by supposing that the elderly, burdened by their
failing powers and dependent upon the communityâs goodwill, were more
vulnerable to abandonment in periods of material want than any other
part of the population. In any case, that gerontocracies were the
earliest forms of hierarchy is corroborated by their existence in
communities as far removed from each other as the Australian Aborigines,
tribal societies in East Africa, and Indian communities in the Americas.
âEven in simple food-gathering cultures, individuals above fifty, let us
say, apparently arrogated to themselves certain powers and privileges
which benefitted themselves specifically,â observes anthropologist Paul
Radin, âand were not necessarily, if at all, dictated by considerations
either of the rights of others or the welfare of the community.â[4] Many
tribal councils throughout the world were really councils of elders, an
institution that never completely disappeared (as the word âaldermanâ
suggests), even though they were overlaid by warrior societies,
chiefdoms, and kingships.
Patricentricity, in which male values, institutions, and forms of
behavior prevail over female ones, seems to have followed gerontocracy.
Initially, this shift may have been fairly harmless, inasmuch as
preliterate and early aboriginal societies were largely domestic
communities in which the authentic center of material life was the home,
not the âmenâs houseâ so widely present in tribal societies. Male rule,
if such it can be strictly called, takes on its most severe and coercive
form in patriarchy, an institution in which the eldest male of an
extended family or clan has a life-and-death command over all members of
the group. Women are by no means the exclusive or even the principal
target of the patriarchâs domination. The sons, like the daughters, may
be ordered how to behave and whom to marry and may be killed at the whim
of the âold man.â So far as patricentricity is concerned, however, the
authority and prerogative of the male are the product of a slow, often
subtly negotiated development in which the male fraternity tends to edge
out the female sorority by virtue of the formerâs growing âcivilâ
responsibilities. Increasing population, marauding bands of outsiders
whose migrations may be induced by drought or other unfavorable
conditions, and vendettas of one kind or another, to cite common causes
of hostility or war, create a new âcivilâ sphere side by side with
womanâs domestic sphere, and the former gradually encroaches upon the
latter. With the appearance of cattle-drawn plow agriculture, the male
begins to invade the horticultural sphere of woman, who had used the
simple digging stick, and her earlier economic predominance in the
communityâs life is thereby diluted. Warrior societies and chiefs carry
the momentum of male dominance to the level of a new material and
cultural constellation. Male dominance becomes extremely active and
ultimately yields a world that is managed by male elites who dominate
not only women but also other men.
âWhyâ hierarchy emerges is transparent enough: the infirmities of age,
increasing population, natural disasters, certain technological changes
that privilege male activities of hunting and caring for animals over
the horticultural functions of females, the growth of civil society, the
spread of warfare. All serve to enhance the maleâs responsibilities at
the expense of the femaleâs. Marxist theorists tend to single out
technological advances and the presumed material surpluses they produce
to explain the emergence of elite strataâindeed, of exploiting ruling
classes. However, this does not tell us why many societies whose
environments were abundantly rich in food never produced such strata.
That surpluses are necessary to support elites and classes is obvious,
as Aristotle pointed out more than two millennia ago. But too many
communities that had such resources at their disposal remained quite
egalitarian and never âadvancedâ to hierarchical or class societies.
It is worth emphasizing that hierarchical domination, however coercive
it may be, is not to be confused with class exploitation. Often the role
of high-status individuals is very well-meaning, as in the case of
commands given by caring parents to their children, of concerned
husbands and wives to each other, or of elderly people to younger ones.
In tribal societies, even where a considerable measure of authority
accrues to a chiefâand most chiefs are advisers rather than rulersâhe
usually must earn the esteem of the community by interacting with the
people, and he can easily be ignored or removed from his position by
them. Many chiefs earn their prestige, so essential to their authority,
by disposing of gifts, and even by a considerable disaccumulation of
their personal goods. The respect accorded to many chiefs is earned, not
by hoarding surpluses as a means to power but by disposing of them as
evidence of generosity.
Classes tend to operate along different lines. Power is usually gained
by the acquisition of wealth, not by its disposal; rulership is
guaranteed by outright physical coercion, not simply by persuasion; and
the state is the ultimate guarantor of authority. That hierarchy is more
entrenched than class can perhaps be verified by the fact that women
have been dominated for millennia, despite sweeping changes in class
societies. By the same token, the abolition of class rule and economic
exploitation offers no guarantee whatever that elaborate hierarchies and
systems of domination will disappear.
In nonhierarchical and even some hierarchical societies, certain customs
guide human behavior along basically decent lines. Of primary importance
in early customs was the âlaw of the irreducible minimumâ (to use
Radinâs expression), the shared notion that all members of a community
are entitled to the means of life, irrespective of the amount of work
they perform. To deny anyone food, shelter, and the basic means of life
because of infirmities or even frivolous behavior would have been seen
as a heinous denial of the very right to live. Nor were the resources
and things needed to sustain the community ever completely privately
owned: overriding individualistic control was the broader principle of
usufructâthe notion that the means of life that were not being used by
one group could be used, as need be, by another. Thus unused land,
orchards, and even tools and weapons, if left idle, were at the
disposition of anyone in the community who needed them. Lastly, custom
fostered the practice of mutual aid, the rather sensible cooperative
behavior of sharing things and labor, so that an individual or family in
fairly good circumstances could expect to be helped by others if their
fortunes should change for the worse. Taken as a whole, these customs
became so sedimented into society that they persisted long after
hierarchy became oppressive and class society became predominant.
âNature,â in the broad sense of a biotic environment from which humans
take the simple things they need for survival, often has no meaning to
preliterate peoples. Immersed in nature as the very universe of their
lives it has no special meaning, even when they celebrate animistic
rituals and view the world around them as a nexus of life, often
imputing their own social institutions to the behavior of various
species, as in the case of âbeaver lodgesâ and humanlike spirits. Words
that express our conventional notions of nature are not easy to find, if
they exist at all, in the languages of aboriginal peoples.
With the rise of hierarchy and human domination, however, the seeds are
planted for a belief that nature not only exists as a world apart, but
that it is hierarchically organized and can be dominated. The study of
magic reveals this shift clearly. Early forms of magic did not view
nature as a world apart. Its worldview tended to be such that a
practitioner essentially pleaded with the âchief spiritâ of the game to
coax an animal in the direction of an arrow or a spear. Later, magic
becomes almost entirely instrumental; the game is coerced by magical
techniques to become the hunterâs prey. While the earliest forms of
magic may be regarded as the practices of a generally nonhierarchical
and egalitarian community, the later forms of animistic beliefs betray a
more or less hierarchical view of the natural world and of latent human
powers of domination.
We must emphasize, here, that the idea of dominating nature has its
primary source in the domination of human by human and the structuring
of the natural world into a hierarchical Chain of Being (a static
conception, incidentally, that has no relationship to the evolution of
life into increasingly advanced forms of subjectivity and flexibility).
The biblical injunction that gave to Adam and Noah command of the living
world was above all an expression of a social dispensation. Its idea of
dominating nature can be overcome only through the creation of a society
without those class and hierarchical structures that make for rule and
obedience in private as well as public life. That this new dispensation
involves changes in attitudes and values should go without saying. But
these attitudes and values remain vaporous if they are not given
substance through objective institutions, the ways in which humans
concretely interact with each other, and in the realities of everyday
life from childrearing to work and play. Until human beings cease to
live in societies that are structured around hierarchies as well as
economic classes, we shall never be free of domination, however much we
try to dispel it with rituals, incantations, ecotheologies, and the
adoption of seemingly ânaturalâ ways of life.
The idea of dominating nature has a history that is almost as old as
that of hierarchy itself. Already in the Gilgamesh Epic of Mesopotamia,
a drama that dates back some 7,000 years, the hero defies the deities
and cuts down their sacred trees in his quest for immortality. The
Odyssey is a vast travelogue of the Greek warrior, albeit a more canny
than a heroic one, who essentially dispatches the nature deities that
the Hellenic world inherited from its less well-known precursors. That
elitist societies devastated much of the Mediterranean basin as well as
the hillsides of China provides ample evidence that hierarchical and
class societies had begun a sweeping remaking and despoliation of the
planet long before the emergence of modern science, âlinearâ
rationality, and âindustrial society,â to cite causal factors that are
invoked so freely in the modern ecology movement. Second nature, to be
sure, did not create a Garden of Eden in steadily absorbing and
inflicting harm on first nature. More often than not, it despoiled much
that was beautiful, creative, and dynamic in the biotic world, just as
it ravaged human life itself in murderous wars, genocide, and acts of
heartless oppression. Social ecology refuses to ignore the fact that the
harm elitist society inflicted on the natural world was more than
matched by the harm it inflicted on humanity; nor does it overlook the
fact that the destiny of human life goes hand-in-hand with the destiny
of the nonhuman world.
But the customs of the irreducible minimum, usufruct, and mutual aid
cannot be ignored, however troubling the ills produced by second nature
may seem. These customs persisted well into history and surfaced almost
explosively in massive popular uprisings, from early revolts in ancient
Sumer to the present time. Many of those demanded the recovery of caring
and communitarian values when these were under the onslaught of elitist
and class oppression. Indeed, despite the armies that roamed the
landscape of warring areas, the tax-gatherers who plundered ordinary
village peoples, and the daily abuses that were inflicted by overseers
on workers, community life still persisted and retained many of the
cherished values of a more egalitarian past. Neither ancient despots nor
feudal lords could fully obliterate them in peasant villages and in the
towns with independent craft guilds. In ancient Greece, religions based
on austerity and, more significantly, a rational philosophy that
rejected the encumbering of thought and political life by extravagant
wants, tended to scale down needs and delimit human appetites for
material goods. They served to slow the pace of technological innovation
to a point where new means of production could be sensitively integrated
into a balanced society. Medieval markets were modest, usually local
affairs, in which guilds exercised strict control over prices,
competition, and the quality of the goods produced by their members.
But just as hierarchies and class structures tend to acquire a momentum
of their own and permeate much of society, so too the market began to
acquire a life of its own and extended its reach beyond limited regions
into the depths of vast continents. Exchange ceased to be primarily a
means to provide for modest needs, subverting the limits imposed upon it
by guilds or by moral and religious restrictions. Not only did it place
a high premium on techniques for increasing production; it also became
the procreator of needs, many of which are simply useless, and gave an
explosive impetus to consumption and technology. First in northern Italy
and the European lowlands, laterâand most effectivelyâin England during
the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the production of goods
exclusively for sale and profit (the capitalistic commodity) rapidly
swept aside all cultural and social barriers to market growth.
By the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, the new
industrial capitalist class with its factory system and commitment to
limitless expansion began to colonize the entire world, and finally,
most aspects of personal life. Unlike the feudal nobility, which had its
cherished lands and castles, the bourgeoisie had no home but the
marketplace and its bank vaults. As a class, they turned more and more
of the world into an ever-expanding domain of factories. Entrepreneurs
of the ancient and medieval worlds had normally gathered their profits
together to invest in land and live like country gentryâgiven the
prejudices of their times against âill-gottenâ gains from trade. On the
other hand, the industrial capitalists of the modern world spawned a
bitterly competitive marketplace that placed a high premium on
industrial expansion and the commercial power it conferred, and
functioned as though growth were an end in itself.
It is crucially important, in social ecology, to recognize that
industrial growth does not result from a change in a cultural outlook
alone, and least of all, from the impact of scientific rationality on
society. It stems above all from harshly objective factors churned up by
the expansion of the market itself, factors that are largely impervious
to moral considerations and efforts at ethical persuasion. Indeed,
despite the close association between capitalist development and
technological innovation, the most driving imperative of the capitalist
market, given the dehumanizing competition that defines it, is the need
to grow, and to avoid dying at the hands of savage rivals. Important as
greed or the power conferred by wealth may be, sheer survival requires
that an entrepreneur must expand his or her productive apparatus to
remain ahead of other entrepreneurs and try, in fact, to devour them.
The key to this law of life-to survival-is expansion, and greater
profit, to be invested in still further expansion. Indeed, the notion of
progress, once identified by our ancestors as a faith in the evolution
of greater human cooperation and care, is now identified with economic
growth.
The effort by many well-intentioned ecology theorists and their admirers
to reduce the ecological crisis to a cultural rather than a social
problem can easily become obfuscatory. However ecologically concerned an
entrepreneur may be, the harsh fact is that his or her very survival in
the marketplace precludes a meaningful ecological orientation. To engage
in ecologically sound practices places a morally concerned entrepreneur
at a striking, and indeed, fatal disadvantage in a competitive
relationship with a rivalânotably one who lacks any ecological concerns
and thus produces at lower costs and reaps higher profits for further
capital expansion.
Indeed, to the extent that environmental movements and ideologies merely
moralize about the âwickednessâ of our anti-ecological society, and
emphasize change in personal life and attitudes, they obscure the need
for social action. Corporations are skilled at manipulating this desire
to be present as an ecological image. Mercedes-Benz, for example,
declaims in a two-page ad, decorated with a bison painting from a
Paleolithic cave wall, that âwe must work to make more environmentally
sustainable progress by including the theme of the environment in the
planning of new products.â[5] Such deceptive messages are commonplace in
Germany, one of western Europeâs worst polluters. Advertising is equally
self-serving in the United States, where leading polluters piously
declare that for them, âEvery day is Earth Day.â
The point social ecology emphasizes is not that moral and spiritual
change is meaningless or unnecessary, but that modern capitalism is
structurally amoral and hence impervious to any moral appeals. The
modern marketplace has imperatives of its own, irrespective of who sits
in the driverâs seat or grabs on to its handlebars. The direction it
follows depends not upon ethical factors but rather on the mindless
âlawsâ of supply and demand, grow or die, eat or be eaten. Maxims like
âbusiness is businessâ explicitly tell us that ethical, religious,
psychological, and emotional factors have absolutely no place in the
impersonal world of production, profit, and growth. It is grossly
misleading to think that we can divest this brutally materialistic,
indeed, mechanistic, world of its objective character, that we can
vaporize its hard facts rather than trans forming it.
A society based on âgrow or dieâ as its all-pervasive imperative must
necessarily have a devastating ecological impact. Given the growth
imperative generated by market competition, it would mean little or
nothing if the present-day population were reduced to a fraction of what
it is today. Insofar as entrepreneurs must always expand if they are to
survive, the media that have fostered mindless consumption would be
mobilized to increase the purchase of goods, irrespective of the need
for them. Hence it would become âindispensableâ in the public mind to
own two or three of every appliance, motor vehicle, electronic gadget,
or the like, where one would more than suffice. In addition, the
military would continue to demand new, more lethal instruments of death,
of which new models would be required annually.
Nor would âsofterâ technologies produced by a grow-or-die market fail to
be used for destructive capitalistic ends. Two centuries ago, the
forests of England were hacked into fuel for iron forges with axes that
had not changed appreciably since the Bronze Age, and ordinary sails
guided ships laden with commodities to all parts of the world well into
the nineteenth century. Indeed, much of the United States was âclearedâ
of its forests, wildlife, soil, and aboriginal inhabitants with tools
and weapons that would have been easily recognized, however much they
were modified, by Renaissance people who had yet to encounter the
Industrial Revolution. What modern technics did was to accelerate a
process that was well under way at the close of the Middle Ages. It did
not devastate the planet on its own; it abetted a phenomenon, the
ever-expanding market system that had its roots in one of historyâs most
fundamental social transformations: the elaboration of hierarchy and
class into a system of distribution based on exchange rather than
complementarity and mutual aid.
Social ecology is an appeal not only for moral regeneration but also,
and above all, for social reconstruction along ecological lines. It
emphasizes that an ethical appeal to the powers that be (that embody
blind market forces and competitive relationships), taken by itself, is
likely to be futile. Indeed, taken by itself, it often obscures the real
power relationships that prevail today by making the attainment of an
ecological society seem merely a matter of âattitude,â of âspiritual
change,â or of quasi-religious redemption.
Although always mindful of the need for spiritual change, social ecology
seeks to redress the ecological abuses that society has inflicted on the
natural world by going to the structural as well as the subjective
sources of notions like the âdomination of nature.â That is, it
challenges the entire system of domination itself and seeks to eliminate
the hierarchical and class edifice that has imposed itself on humanity
and defined the relationship between nonhuman and human nature. It
advances an ethics of complementarity in which human beings must play a
supportive role in perpetuating the integrity of the biosphere, as
potentially, at least, the most conscious products of natural evolution.
Indeed humans are seen to have a moral responsibility to function
creatively in the unfolding of that evolution. Social ecology thus
stresses the need for embodying its ethics of complementarity in
palpable social institutions that will give active meaning to its goal
of wholeness, and of human involvement as conscious and moral agents in
the interplay of species. It seeks the enrichment of the evolutionary
process by diversification of life-forms. Notwithstanding romantic
views, âMother Natureâ does not necessarily âknow best.â To oppose
activities of the corporate world does not mean that one has to become
naively romantic and âbiocentric.â By the same token, to applaud
humanityâs potential for foresight and rationality, and its
technological achievements, does not mean that one is âanthropocentric.â
The loose usage of such buzzwords, so commonplace in the ecology
movement, must be brought to an end by reflective discussion.
Social ecology, in effect, recognizes thatâlike it or notâthe future of
life on this planet pivots on the future of society. It contends that
evolution, whether in first nature or in second, is not yet complete.
Nor are the two realms so separated from each other that we must choose
one or the othereither natural evolution with its âbiocentricâ halo, or
social evolution, as we have known it up to now, with its
âanthropocentricâ haloâas the basis for a creative biosphere. We must go
beyond both the natural and the social toward a new synthesis that
contains the best of both. Such a synthesis will transcend them in the
form of a creative, self-conscious, and therefore âfree nature,â in
which human beings intervene in natural evolution with their best
capacitiesâtheir moral sense, their unprecedented degree of conceptual
thought, and their remarkable powers of communication.
But such a goal remains mere verbiage unless it can be given logistical
and social tangibility. How are we to organize a âfree natureâ that goes
beyond the rhetoric so plentiful in the ecology movement? Logistically,
âfree natureâ is unattainable without the decentralization of cities
into confederally united communities sensitively tailored to the natural
areas in which they are located. It means the use of ecotechnologies,
and of solar, wind, methane, and other sources of energy, the use of
organic forms of agriculture, the design of humanly scaled, versatile
industrial installations to meet regional needs of confederated
municipalities. It means, too, an emphasis not only on recycling, but on
the production of high-quality goods that can last for generations. It
means the substitution of creative work for insensate labor and an
emphasis on artful craftspersonship in preference to mechanized
production. It means the leisure to be artful and engage in public
affairs. One would hope that the sheer availability of goods and the
freedom to choose oneâs material lifestyle would sooner or later
influence people to adopt moderation in all aspects of life as a
response to the âconsumerismâ that is promoted by the capitalist
market.[6]
But no ethics or vision of an ecological society, however inspired, can
be meaningful unless it is embodied in a living politics. By âpoliticsâ
I do not mean the statecraft practiced by what we call
âpoliticiansâânamely, representatives elected or selected to formulate
policies as guidelines for social life and to manage public affairs. To
social ecology, politics means what it once meant in the democratic
polis of Athens some two thousand years ago the formation of policy by
popular assemblies and their administration by mandated, carefully
supervised boards of coordinators who could easily be recalled if they
failed to abide by the decisions of the assemblyâs citizens. I am very
mindful that Athenian politics, even in its most democratic periods, was
marred by the existence of slavery, patriarchy, and the exclusion of the
stranger from public life. In this respect, it differed very little from
most of the Mediterranean civilizationsâand Asian ones of the time. What
made Athenian politics unique, however, was that it produced
institutions that were extraordinarily democraticâeven directly soâby
comparison with republican institutions in the so-called âdemocraciesâ
of the Western world. Either directly or indirectly they inspired later,
more all-encompassing democracies, such as certain medieval towns, the
little-known âsectionsâ of Paris (which were essentially forty-eight
neighborhood assemblies) that propelled the French Revolution in a
highly radical direction in 1793, New England town meetings, and more
recent attempts at civic self-governance.[7]
Any community, however, risks the danger of becoming parochial, even
racist, if it tries to live in isolation and develop a seeming
self-sufficiency. Hence, the need to extend ecological politics into
confederations of ecocommunities, and to foster a healthy
interdependence, rather than an introverted, stultifying independence.
Social ecology would embody its ethics in a politics of confederal
municipalism, in which municipalities cojointly gain rights to
self-governance through networks of confederal councils, to which towns
and cities would send their mandated, recallable delegates to adjust
differences. All decisions would have to be ratified by a majority of
the popular assemblies of the confederated towns and cities. This
institutional process could occur in the neighborhoods of giant cities
as well as in networks of small towns. In fact, the formation of
numerous âtown hallsâ has already repeatedly been proposed in cities as
large as New York and Paris, only to be defeated by well-organized
elitist groups that sought to centralize power, rather than allow its
decentralization.
Power will always belong to elite strata if it is not diffused, in
face-to-face democracies, among the people, who are empowered as partly
autonomous, partly social beingsâthat is to say, as free individuals,
but as individuals responsible to popular institutions. Empowerment of
the people in this sense will constitute a challenge to the
nation-stateâthe principal source of nationalism, a regressive ideology,
and of statism, the principal source of coercion. Diversity of cultures
is obviously a desideratum, the source of cultural creativity, but never
can it be celebrated in a nationalistic âapartnessâ from the general
interests of humanity as a whole, without a regression into folkdom and
tribalism. The full reality of citizenship has begun to wane, and its
disappearance would mark an irrevocable loss in human development.
Citizenship. in the classical sense of the term, meant a lifelong,
ethically oriented education to participation in public affairs, not the
empty form of national legitimation that it so often indicates today. It
meant the cultivation of an affiliation with the interests of the
community, one in which the communal interest was placed above personal
interest, or, more properly, in which the personal interest was
congruent with and realized through the common.
Property, in this ethical constellation, would be shared and, in the
best of circumstances, belong to the community as a whole, not to
producers (âworkersâ) or owners (âcapitalistsâ). In an ecological
society composed of a âCommune of communes,â property would belong,
ultimately, neither to private producers nor to a nation-state. The
Soviet Union gave rise to an overbearing bureaucracy; the
anarcho-syndicalist vision to competing âworker-controlledâ factories
that ultimately had to be knitted together by a labor bureaucracy. From
the standpoint of social ecology, property âinterestsâ would become
generalized, not reconstituted in different conflicting or unmanageable
forms. They would be municipalized, rather than nationalized or
privatized. Workers, farmers, professionals, and the like would thus
deal with municipalized property as citizens, not as members of a
vocational or social group. Leaving aside any discussion of such visions
as the rotation of work, the citizen who engages in both industrial and
agricultural activity, and the professional who also does manual labor,
the communal ideas advanced by social ecology would give rise to
individuals for whom the collective interest is inseparable from the
personal, the public interest from the private, the political interest
from the social.
The step-by-step reorganization of municipalities, their confederation
into ever-larger networks that form a dual power in opposition to the
nation-state, the remaking of the constituents of republican
representatives into citizens who participate in a direct democracyâall
may take a considerable period of time to achieve. But in the end, they
alone can potentially eliminate the domination of human by human and
thereby deal with those ecological problems whose growing magnitude
threatens the existence of a biosphere than can support advanced forms
of life. To ignore the need for these sweeping but eminently practical
changes would be to let our ecological problems fester and spread to a
point where there would no longer be any opportunity to resolve them.
Any attempt to ignore their impact on the biosphere or deal with them
singly would be recipe for disaster, a guarantee that the
anti-ecological society that prevails in most of the world today would
blindly hurtle the biosphere as we know it to certain destruction.
[1] Murray Bookchin, âEcology and Revolutionary Thought,â initially
published in the ecoanarchist journal New Directions in Libertarian
Thought (Sept., 1964), and collected, together with all my major essays
of the sixties in Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Berkeley: Ramparts Press,
1972; republished, Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1977). The expression
âethics of complementarityâ is from The Ecology of Freedom (San
Francisco: Cheshire Books, 1982; revised edition, Montreal: Black Rose
Books, 1991).
[2] Neil Evernden, The Natural Alien (Toronto: University of Toronto
Press,1986), p. 109.
[3] Quoted in Alan Wolfe, âUp from Humanism,â in The Arnerican Prospect
(Winter, 1991), p. 125.
[4] Paul Radin, The World of Primitive Man (New York: Grove Press,
1960), p. 211.
[5] See Der Spiegel (Sept. 16, 1991), pp. 144â45.
[6] All of these views were spelled out in the essay âEcology and
Revolutionary Thoughtâ by this writer in 1965, and were assimilated over
time by subsequent ecology movements. Many of the technological views
advanced a year later in âToward a Liberatory Technologyâ were also
assimilated and renamed âappropriate technology,â a rather socially
neutral expression in comparison with my original term âecotechnology.â
Both of these essays can be found in Post-Scarcity Anarchism.
[7] See the essay âThe Forms of Freedom,â in Post-Scarcity Anarchism,
âThe Legacy of Freedom,â in The Ecology of Freedom, and âPatterns of
Civic Freedomâ in The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of
Citizenship (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1987).