đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș laura-riding-contemporaries-and-snobs.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:10:40. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Contemporaries And Snobs
Author: Laura Riding
Date: 1928
Language: en
Topics: poetry, modernism, art criticism, literature, history, academy, sociology, individualism, gertrude stein, ts eliot,

Laura Riding

Contemporaries And Snobs

Contemporaries and Snobs

CONTEMPORARIES AND SNOBS

MODERN AND CONTEMPORARY POETICS

Series Editors

Charles Bernstein

Hank Lazer

Series Advisory Board

Maria Damon

Rachel Blau DuPlessis

Alan Golding

Susan Howe

Nathaniel Mackey

Jerome McGann

Harryette Mullen

Aldon Nielsen

Marjorie Perloff

Joan Retallack

Ron Silliman

Jerry Ward

CONTEMPORARIES AND SNOBS

LAURA RIDING

Edited by Laura Heffernan and Jane Malcolm

THE UNIVERSITY OF ALABAMA PRESS

Tuscaloosa

Introduction, supplemental notes, bibliography, and index copyright ©

2014

The University of Alabama Press

Tuscaloosa, Alabama 35487-0380

All rights reserved

Manufactured in the United States of America

Contemporaries and Snobs © Cornell University Library

First published 1928. Restored © owned by Division of Rare and

Manuscript Collections, Cornell University Library.

Typeface: Minion and Futura

Cover image: Courtesy of Laura Heffernan and Jane Malcolm.

Cover design: Mary Elizabeth Watson

∞

The paper on which this book is printed meets the minimum requirements

of American National standard for information sciences—permanence of

Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1984.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Riding, Laura, 1901–1991.

Contemporaries and snobs / Laura Riding ; edited by Laura Heffernan and

Jane Malcolm.

pages cm. — (Modern and contemporary poetics)

Originally published: Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday Doran, 1928.

Includes bibliographical references and index.

ISBN 978-0-8173-5767-2 (quality paper : alk. paper) — ISBN

978-0-8173-8737-2 (e book) 1. Poetry. I. Heffernan, Laura, editor. II.

Malcolm, Jane editor. III. Title.

PN1136.J27 2014

808.1—dc23

2013030768

Contents

Cover Page

Series Page

Title Page

Copyright Page

Contents

Acknowledgments

We Must Be Barbaric: An Introduction to Contemporaries and Snobs

1. Poetry and the Literary Universe

I. Shame of the Person

II. Poetry, Out of Employment, Writes on Unemployment

III. Escapes from the Zeitgeist

IV. Poetic Reality and Critical Unreality

V. Poetry and Progress

VI. The Higher Snobbism

2. T. E. Hulme, the New Barbarism, and Gertrude Stein

3. The Facts in the Case of Monsieur Poe

Editors’ Notes

Chronological Bibliography

Index

Acknowledgments

We Must Be Barbaric: An Introduction to Contemporaries and Snobs

1. Poetry and the Literary Universe

I. Shame of the Person

II. Poetry, Out of Employment, Writes on Unemployment

III. Escapes from the Zeitgeist

IV. Poetic Reality and Critical Unreality

V. Poetry and Progress

VI. The Higher Snobbism

2. T. E. Hulme, the New Barbarism, and Gertrude Stein

3. The Facts in the Case of Monsieur Poe

Editors’ Notes

Chronological Bibliography

Index

i

ii

iii

iv

v

vi

vii

viii

ix

x

xi

xii

xiii

xiv

xv

xvi

xvii

xviii

xix

xx

xxi

xxii

xxiii

xxiv

xxv

1

2

3

4

5

6

7

8

9

10

11

12

13

14

15

16

17

18

19

20

21

22

23

24

25

26

27

28

29

30

31

32

33

34

35

36

37

38

39

40

41

42

43

44

45

46

47

48

49

50

51

52

53

54

55

56

57

58

59

60

61

62

63

64

65

66

67

68

69

70

71

72

73

74

75

76

77

78

79

80

81

82

83

84

85

86

87

88

89

90

91

92

93

94

95

96

97

98

99

100

101

102

103

104

105

106

107

108

109

110

111

112

113

114

115

116

117

118

119

120

121

122

123

124

125

126

127

128

129

Cover Page

Begin Reading

Copyright Page

Contents

Acknowledgments

Editors’ Notes

Chronological Bibliography

Index

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank the Division of Rare and Manuscript Collections,

Carl A. Kroch Library, Cornell University for their assistance.

Elizabeth Friedmann's knowledge of Laura Riding's life and letters is

vast, and she provided us with crucial insight at key stages of our

research. Charles Bernstein and Josephine Park were our earliest readers

and supporters. Our thanks also to Jeremy Braddock, Lisa Samuels, and

Rachel Buurma for their help along the way.

We Must Be Barbaric

An Introduction to Contemporaries and Snobs

Laura Heffernan and Jane Malcolm

I was, as a poet, an inveterate propounder of a necessity of

non-distinction between person and poet.

—Laura (Riding) Jackson, “An Autobiographical Summary”

Laura Riding's Contemporaries and Snobs, first published in 1928, drew a

line down the center of the literary scene in the late 1920s. With

characteristic incisiveness, Riding divided friends from foes: she

counted as enemies those “snobs,” or critics, who sought to systematize

and professionalize modern poetry. As allies, Riding counted all

“contemporaries” who continued to honor poetry as an individual and

eccentric practice. Yet Riding's bold and uncongenial treatise was not

merely a call to arms in and of the modernist moment. For readers today,

it offers a compelling account—by turns personal, by turns historical—of

how the institutionalization of modernism denuded experimental poetry.

Most importantly, Contemporaries offers a counter history of the

idiosyncratic, of what the institution of modernism left (and leaves)

behind. With Gertrude Stein as its figurehead, the book champions the

non-canonical, the “barbaric,” and the under-theorized. Riding's nuanced

defense of a poetics of the person in Contemporaries represents a

forgotten but essential first attempt to identify and foster what is now

a well-defined poetic lineage that leads from Stein to the experimental

avant-garde.

Riding began writing Contemporaries in 1926, but the book did not appear

until early 1928. The latter half of the 1920s was a prolific period for

Riding. Her A Survey of Modernist Poetry, written with Robert Graves,

appeared in late 1927, followed by Contemporaries in February of 1928,

Anarchism Is Not Enough (the creative sequel to Contemporaries) in May,

and A Pamphlet Against Anthologies (also written with Graves) in July.

Contemporaries is the most ignored of this varied bunch, perhaps because

it responds so directly to the criticism and poetry of its moment.

Riding takes her readers on a remarkably thorough tour through the

“self-critical, severe, sophisticated” literary scene of the 1920s (53).

Among other influential treatises, she considers T. S. Eliot's The

Sacred Wood and his editorial essays in The Criterion, Allen Tate's

“Poetry and the Absolute,” John Crowe Ransom's essays on the modernist

poet, Edgell Rickword's essays in The Calendar of Modern Letters, and

Herbert Read's posthumous publication of T. E. Hulme's essays.

All of this criticism, Riding notes, gave modern poets a sheen of

seriousness and professionalism, but was it good for poetry? Her

decisive answer is “no.” Poets, taking their marching orders from

criticism, had begun to churn out deadened, impersonal poetry that gave

voice to an imagined “zeitgeist” rather than individual experience.

Contemporaries was Riding's attempt to stem this tide—to resist the

consolidation of poetic experimentalism into monolithic modernism. Not

only a critical diatribe, Contemporaries was also a self-help manual for

those poets who wished to write “outside the shelter of contemporary

criticism” (4). To sustain these “incorruptible individuals,” Riding

builds a purely provisional canon of poets as persons, writers who use

language to sense the unknown (4). Her perceptive reading of Stein forms

the cornerstone of this revaluation of the personal in poetry, and she

uses the example of Stein's “barbaric” writing to question the very

process of self-representation that language—Stein's “arrangement in a

system to pointing”—makes possible (Tender Buttons 245). At a moment

when poet-critics were offering poets a loaded choice between naive

expressionism and sophisticated impersonality, Riding denounced both as

escapist. As modernism turned self-referentially inward, Contemporaries

forged a pathway outward toward newly referential uses of language,

toward an unknown and unsanctioned poetry of the person.

From A Survey of Modernist Poetry to Contemporaries and Snobs

Riding was better situated than most to reflect on modernism's

condensation. By 1928, she had come into contact with an astonishing

number of modernist groups in Nashville, New York, London, and Paris. As

an early member of John Crowe Ransom's Fugitive Group in Nashville, she

befriended Allen Tate and Robert Penn Warren. Her poetry first appeared

in the pages of The Fugitive in 1923 and later in Harriet Monroe's

Chicago-based Poetry: A Magazine of Verse. In 1925, Riding moved from

Louisville to Greenwich Village where she befriended Hart Crane and met

Eugene O'Neill, Edmund Wilson, and Kenneth Burke. While in New York,

Riding corresponded with Robert Graves who had written in admiration of

her poem “The Quids.” She soon moved to England to live with Graves and

his wife, Nancy Nicholson. Riding and Graves's collaboration (and

eventual romantic relationship) continued throughout the 1920s, when

they moved between Egypt, Islip, Vienna, Hammersmith, Germany, Paris,

and Mallorca. During this time, Riding published creative work with

Leonard and Virginia Woolf's Hogarth Press, was introduced to Gertrude

Stein, exchanged work with Wyndham Lewis, and contributed essays to

Eugene Jolas's Joyce-centric little magazine transition. Of the three

essays collected in Contemporaries, two had debuted in other venues. The

second chapter and core of the book, “T. E. Hulme, the New Barbarism,

and Gertrude Stein,” was published in transition in 1927 as “The New

Barbarism and Gertrude Stein,” and again, in altered form, as the

“Conclusion” to A Survey of Modernist Poetry, while a version of the

volume's third chapter, “The Facts in the Case of Monsieur Poe,”

appeared in transition as “Jamais Plus” and was given as a talk to the

undergraduate Oxford English Club in March of 1927 (Friedmann 102).

Riding herself was one of the first critics to coin the term “modernist”

to describe a group of contemporary poets, and she and Graves are cited

accordingly in the Oxford English Dictionary's entry. Their A Survey of

Modernist Poetry (1927) was the first formal study to consider the work

of E. E. Cummings, Hart Crane, Conrad Aiken, Marianne Moore, Ezra Pound,

Vachel Lindsay, T. S. Eliot, John Crowe Ransom, Edith Sitwell, and Allen

Tate as a single movement. In that volume, Riding and Graves set out to

consider whether the “plain reader” was justified in his complaint that

the modernist “poet means to keep the public out” (Survey 10). Selecting

a few representative examples of modern poetry, Riding and Graves

carefully considered the significance of the poems' format, or the ways

in which their radical formal departures, viewed together, came to

signify a new modernist poetry. Through such close interpretations

Riding and Graves modeled how the plain reader might “make certain

important alterations in his critical attitude” in order to appreciate

Cummings as much as Shakespeare, John Crowe Ransom as much as Wordsworth

(10).

Though Survey of Modernist Poetry defends modernist poets from charges

of willful obscurity, Riding and Graves resisted the urge to put forward

an overarching definition or theory of modernism. Indeed, we can already

see in that volume the beginnings of Riding's fears that poetic theories

were overtaking poetry. In frequent asides, the Survey warns poets about

the danger of “granting too much respect to theories” or committing

oneself to the “official programmes of such dead movements as Imagism”

and expresses disdain for those “who need the support of a system” or

adopt one as a way of “attempting to justify [poetry] to civilization”

(Survey 126). In the “Conclusion” to Survey, a version of Chapter 2 of

Contemporaries, Riding and Graves jettison the “contemporary sympathy”

they have shown for modernist poetry in order to consider it as a

movement that “may have already passed”:

We have been writing as it were from the middle of the modernist

movement in order to justify it if possible against criticism which was

not proper to it. . . . It is now possible to reach a position where the

modernist movement itself can be looked at with historical (as opposed

to contemporary) sympathy as a stage in poetry that is to pass in turn,

or may have already passed, leaving behind only such work as did not

belong too much to history. (258)

Here, at the end of Survey, we see Riding and Graves “leaving” modernism

“behind”: no longer defending it from the inside, they now scrutinize it

from the outside.

Contemporaries extends this newly skeptical perspective on a “modernist

movement” that, having just come into clear view, now seems about to

“pass in turn.” Indeed, the modernism of Contemporaries is markedly

different from that of Survey. Where Survey presented close readings of

individual poems, Contemporaries takes a distant, multicentury view of

modernism's development. Where Survey presented modernism as “unpopular”

with contemporary critics and readers, Contemporaries finds evidence

everywhere of modernism's newfound prestige, even—perhaps

especially—among the mainstream press and the middle classes. From the

suburban Bournemouth Poetry Society's advertisement for a “paper by Mrs.

Leslie Goodwin on ‘Further Aspects of Modern Poetry,’” to the fact that

the London Mercury dares not question [T. S. Eliot's] The New Criterion,

(28) to the way Eliot's poems become instant classics upon their

publication, all signs point to the sanctification of modernism—a status

that seems, in Contemporaries, as ill-deserved as its negative

reputation seemed in Survey (29, 28).

One way to understand the drastic shift in perspective between the two

volumes is to consider that modernism's new recognition and popularity

did not extend to Riding herself. Having once felt herself working in

concert with many modernist groups and owing allegiance to none, Riding

suddenly found herself an onlooker to the mainstream of modernism—a

mainstream dominated by male critics. Indeed, Riding begins a 1927

letter to Wyndham Lewis by explaining: “I belong (most decidedly) to no

group.” Reviewers (most famously, William Empson) repeatedly failed to

credit Riding as co-author of Survey, despite Graves's insistence that

their collaboration had been “word by word” (Friedmann 100). Riding's

correspondence from this era, preserved in the Laura (Riding) Jackson

archive at Cornell University, documents her dogged attempts to make

publishers and authors responsible for their errors of attribution.

Riding's archive tells a similarly bleak tale about the publication and

reception of Contemporaries. Though the book was a solo effort (written

over several years and for various venues), Graves traded on his own

success to secure its publication: when Jonathan Cape sought to publish

Graves's popular biography of T. E. Lawrence, Lawrence and the Arabs

(1927), Graves made it a condition of his contract that they also

publish Contemporaries (Friedmann 107). In 1933, Riding's publisher

wrote to request her permission to remainder the unsold copies from the

modest print run of Contemporaries. Indeed, the volume was so under-read

that no one would bat an eyelash two years later when Geoffrey West

matter-of-factly adopted Riding's own opposition between the

“philosophical” criticism of T. E. Hulme and T. S. Eliot on the one hand

and Stein's writing on the other, in order to dismiss Riding herself. In

Deucalion: Or the Future of Literary Criticism, written for Kegan Paul's

To-Day and To-Morrow series, West announced that “philosophical critics”

like T. E. Hulme and T. S. Eliot were “of greatest importance” to the

future of literary criticism, “while reference may . . . be omitted to

such isolated, unrelated phenomena as the smoky brilliances of Miss

Rebecca West and the ultra-feminine Steinish incoherencies of Miss Laura

Riding” (48–49).

Despite the chauvinism that Riding faced, Contemporaries hardly reads

like a personal complaint, nor does the gossipy feel of the title extend

to the essays. Graves wrote to T. S. Eliot in 1926 that “her critical

detachment is certainly greater than mine” (qtd. Friedmann 78). Instead,

Contemporaries offers perhaps the most distanced, historical analysis

possible of how and why Riding's fellow modernists traded their

individuality for the security of a professional institution. And though

Riding advocates, in Contemporaries, for a poetics of the “person,” the

volume's voice is hardly personable. Riding insists that readers

understand her embrace of Stein and a poetics of the person not as

feminist revaluations but as matter-of-fact corrections to modernists'

symptomatic, even effeminate, attempts to escape from personality.

Indeed, it is Riding's own detachment, imperiousness, and misogynist

mud-slinging that makes Contemporaries such a fascinating document—a

critical book that denounces criticism's growing influence. (The

self-contradictions of Riding's position would only increase. After

denouncing critical organs like The Criterion in Contemporaries, Riding

would in 1935 found Epilogue, a little magazine which, as Joyce Wexler

has documented, Riding edited with an iron fist in an attempt to

institutionalize her very particular point of view.) These paradoxical

positions, perhaps even more than Riding's specific argument, reveal a

moment in which the range of avant-garde possibilities seemed suddenly

whittled down into equally distasteful options: to become an “affiliated

member” (53) of modernism, which held a monopoly on intellectual

seriousness, or to find oneself shelved with the book-club “poetry

enthusiasts” (29).

The Argument of Contemporaries and Snobs

The opening sections of Contemporaries offer a broad historical account

of how the rise of scientific empiricism has gradually marginalized

poetry. Crucially for Riding, science and poetry are equal forms of

knowledge but with different orientations to the world. Science uses

what Riding terms “concrete intelligence,” which “regards everything as

potentially comprehensible and measurable” (5). In contrast, “poetic

intelligence” evinces “an accurate sensation of the unknown, an inspired

comprehension of the unknowable” (5). Centuries ago, Riding argues, the

two coexisted without rancor—each occupying its own “corner of human

knowledge” (33). But over the course of the nineteenth century, which

“showed a more material increase than perhaps any other preceding

century in this mass-consciousness of human knowledge,” scientific

empiricism began to take precedence and to popularize the false idea

that all life might be measured and known (7). Riding describes, for

instance, how concrete intelligence gives birth to “natural man,” a

scientific specimen “who did not act originally; he did not act at all.

It was his function to be observed” (2). This passive, statistical

version of man takes the place of the “erratic person,” upon whose

activity and unknowability poetry had thrived.

Turning to the twentieth century, Riding describes how poetry has

gradually become ashamed of itself. In the face of natural man, it

develops a distaste for idiosyncrasy and a “shame of the person” (11);

in the face of concrete intelligence, it ceases to regard its

“illuminating ignorance” as a species of knowledge at all (1, 5).

Riding's metaphors suggest that poets, within a rationalized modernity,

have come to seem like unprofitable workers: society gives poetry its

“dismissal papers” (28) and “Poetry, Out of Employment, Writes on

Unemployment” (5). Like underemployed workers, poets begin to reflect

upon their social position, develop a collective consciousness, and

unionize in order to put themselves back to work. Riding describes how

individual poets have, increasingly in the twentieth-century, gathered

together under the auspices of the “public institution” of literary

criticism. Rather than looking to their own erratic personhood for

poetic inspiration, they look now to the collective, critical mandates

of their time. Yet in the inhospitable atmosphere of rationalized

modernity, these critical mandates have themselves become increasingly

directive and systematized. Riding likens poetry to any

organization—“the army, or the navy, for example”—that introduces

“greater internal discipline” when its “prestige . . . is curtailed”

(53).

In the remainder of Chapter 1 and in Chapter 2, Riding looks to the

modernist literature and criticism around her to offer an astonishing

array of examples of literary culture's increased discipline. She

describes a new injunction to “write about nothing” or about the death

of poetry itself (as in Edwin Muir's Chorus of the Newly Dead or Eliot's

The Hollow Men) (8). She detects a new scholastic tendency to look back

on the literature of the past as a continuous “tradition.” (She points

here, among other things, to James Joyce's “Oxen of the Sun” episode of

Ulysses in which Joyce provides a catalogue of past literary styles.)

Reviewing the table of contents for one issue of Eliot's The New

Criterion, Riding finds a new love of “pedigree, learning and literary

internationalism” (25). She describes a new “emphasis on the medium as

material,” as in Ezra Pound's book on the sculptor Gaudier-Brzeska (72).

She notes a new imperative for poets to express the “Zietgeist” to the

point of “self-extinction,” as in Eliot's “posthumous” poetry or Edith

Sitwell's “strict technical organization of her non-humanistic universe”

(9). Above all, she finds a new philosophical inquiry into the function

of poetry itself—Allen Tate's philosophizing about “Poetry and the

Absolute,” Pound's “mathematical and geometric” metaphors, Eliot's

insistence that “in our time the most vigorous critical minds are

philosophical minds,” and everyone's elevation of T. E. Hulme's

“barbaric” criticism into a dogmatic philosophy of art (75, 25, 63).

Riding regards all of the above as signs of the increasing and

pernicious influence of literary criticism, which seeks to present poets

as serious specialists and thus to win back a modicum of status from an

uninterested society: “The reason why contemporary critics are so

interested in inquiring into the nature of the function of literature is

not, as Mr. Eliot suggests, because they do not wish ‘to take for

granted a whole universe’, but because a whole universe has given

literature its dismissal papers” (28).

For Riding, then, the danger of this “forced” systematism is that it has

begun to change how poets write. A “group poetic mind,” the book argues,

lurks “at the elbow of the individual poet,” preventing him from writing

authentically because he is burdened by a self-referential network of

modernist institutions that dictate the terms of poetic composition

(54). A “professional conscience dawns on the poet,” creation and

criticism become folded into a single act (as Eliot had predicted), and

the poet begins to edit himself in the process of writing (53). The

results, in Riding's view, are disastrous: homogeneous, vacant poetry

that is “really more interested in maintaining a defensive attitude

toward the literary past than in sponsoring a ‘new’ poetry” (4). Riding

mentions a few poets—Arthur Rimbaud, Robert Graves, and Hart Crane, for

example—who have succeeded in avoiding these mandates, but the vast

majority have succumbed to the imperative to write impersonally.

Impersonality/Personality

Riding's preoccupation with the dangers of impersonality critically

shapes the argument in Contemporaries. The rise of an impersonal

aesthetic and the waning of emotion in modernist poetry are, for Riding,

symptomatic of an ironic romanticism, a need to “suppress the obvious

because the obvious is often romantically (personally), therefore

sentimentally beautiful” (70). Unlike many of her contemporaries, she

did not believe that the surrender of meaning or the disappearance of

the personal signaled bold shifts in literary practice. On the contrary,

Riding argues throughout Contemporaries that poets who disavow their own

“vulgar humanity” (75) are in fact ashamed of it and of the emotions

that shape their “organic existence” as poets:

It is romantic to say, while denouncing as romantic the meanings which

the creative mind gives to its fictions, that these can only be valid if

they confess their meaninglessness. Is not a belief in the lack of

meaning in organic existence merely a new meaning that art is to adopt

for the sake of the prestige given it by the metaphysics from which it

is drawn? (68)

Poets who “confess their meaninglessness,” to a certain extent do so in

order to avoid the shame and human difficulty of modernity, which for

Riding are precisely the realms poetry should confront.

Riding's seemingly anachronistic reclamation of the person, of the poet

as person, evinces her supreme ambivalence about modernism, and her

reasons for promoting a poetics of personality are as fascinating as

they are complex. Poets, Riding insists, might shed the “classical

desideratum” of mentors likes Eliot and Pound by embracing emotion,

personality, and embodied language as a condition of their art, so that

poetry might tell the truth (70). Yet this definition of poetry seems

contrary to the very underpinnings of modernism—the unstable “I,” the

erased ego, the elevation of language over subject. Riding, whose own

Survey coined the term “modernist” to describe a generation of poets

invested in suppressing the “I,” declares that poetry should be

personal, that we cannot “substitute poetics for persons” (47). This

statement is perhaps the best condensation of Riding's argument in

Contemporaries, the closest the book comes to providing a rallying cry

for her fellow poets. As a thesis it is controversial, to say the least,

and in this respect, Contemporaries seeks to refute Eliot's key

assertion, in “Tradition and the Individual Talent” (1919), that “poetry

is not a turning loose of emotion, but is an escape from emotion; it is

not the expression of personality, but an escape from personality”

(Sacred Wood 58). If Eliot welcomes impersonality as a creative

reprieve, Riding laments it and the “general degradation of the person”

as the compromised methodology of institutional modernism that “set

about . . . exterminating the person” as a matter of aesthetics (68).

Riding sees in this methodology a deeply rooted fear of innovation and

understands the reluctance to produce truly new poetry as the inevitable

result of a group mentality.

Throughout Contemporaries, Riding portrays poetic impersonality as the

warped outcome of an intensely felt shame of the person. Thus, for

instance, she depicts Eliot's desire to “escape from emotion” and

“escape from personality” as childish, effeminate, and fearful. Calling

The Waste Land the “great twentieth-century nursery rhyme” (45), she

argues that, by avoiding emotion, or as in Eliot's theory of the

“objective correlative,” displacing the weight of emotions onto objects

rather than subjects, the poet compels his readers to engage in

psychologically driven close readings, mining the poem for evidence of

authorial trauma (45). Hard modernism, she explains, should confront

humanity (a dangerously amorphous entity) in all of its emotional

complexity. The poet as person should not seek to sever personality from

poetics. Accordingly, Riding refers to Eliot, Joyce, and Co.

collectively as “ladies” precisely because they “avoid the temptations

to sentimentality inherent in the poetic faculty” and thus reject the

humanity inherent in their medium, language (48). Riding's ironic use of

gender demonstrates the depth of her scorn for the calculated modernist

(im)persona, even as it suggests that we should understand her

reclamation of the poet as person not as the romantic agenda of an

iconoclast woman modernist, but as the cornerstone of a grittier, more

authentic, and truly hard (both difficult and obdurate) poetics in and

of the modernist moment. Why insist upon and theorize the “‘difficulty’

of modernist poetry,” Riding asks, when “well-written poetry is always

difficult” (54)?

Riding's ideal poet, then, displays true originality by refusing to

reflect a shared modernist dogma, by casting aside a poetics of

impersonality, and by acknowledging language itself as a unique medium

(and burden), one “to accept . . . from humanity at large” (57). Indeed,

Riding's poetics of the person emerges in precisely this matter-of-fact

way, as a kind of recognition and reminder that the poet and poetic

language remain always embedded in unsystematized life. As Lisa Samuels

explains, Riding “is always personal and always looking for unfoldings

of what the self cannot quite conceive” (Anarchism is Not Enough xi).

For Riding, the “person” behind a poem cannot ever be “exterminated.”

Poets are persons always, not persons when life is messy and poets when

they are at work on clean and sharp angles. Nor does Riding's emphasis

on the person arise from a lyric expressivism in which poetry emanates

from the poetic mind. Rather, good poets, for Riding, stand in a

respectful and somewhat diminutive relation to their relatively

independent poems: “The poem itself is supreme, above persons; judging

rather than judged; keeping criticism at a respectful distance; it is

even able to make a reader of its author” (23). In A Survey of Modernist

Poetry, Riding and Graves likened the relation between a poet and his

poem to the relationship between a “wise, experimenting parent” and

child. Just as a parent would not wish to keep a child in “its place” by

“suppressing its personality or laughing down its strange questions, so

that it turns into a rather dull and ineffective edition of the parent,”

poets are likewise “freeing the poem” and “encouraging it to do things,

even queer things, by itself” (124–125). Riding continues this logic in

Contemporaries, arguing that the role of poetry is to create “an ever

immediate reality confirmed afresh and independently in each new work,”

a reality “confirmed personally rather than professionally” (56). Only

by fostering this relation of connection and freedom can poets write

poems that are not mere copies of what already exists, but that bring,

out of language, something new into being.

Gertrude Stein and the “New Barbarism”

Contemporaries finds its ambassador of the everyday, its poet as person,

in Gertrude Stein. Riding first became familiar with Stein's work in

1926 when the Hogarth Press published her own collection of poems, The

Close Chaplet, as well as Stein's “Composition as Explanation,” a text

whose influence in Contemporaries cannot be underestimated. Riding began

writing about Stein in Survey, and the two became friends and frequent

correspondents after “The New Barbarism and Gertrude Stein” appeared in

the June 1927 issue of transition. (Stein was understandably pleased to

have been so thoroughly championed by Riding.) That essay prompted Stein

to send Riding and Graves a manuscript version of An Acquaintance With

Description, which their Seizin Press published in 1929. The intensity

of their relationship during these years, particularly as reflected in

Riding's letters, translates into an equally intense critical devotion

in Chapter 2 of Contemporaries, in which Riding explains and lauds

Stein's “barbarism.”

As a continuation of her essay in transition, the Stein chapter clearly

responds to Eliot's ominous denunciation of Stein in “Charleston, Hey!

Hey!,” a review written for Nation & Athenaeum in January 1927:

“[Stein's] work is not improving, it is not amusing, it is not

interesting, it is not good for one's mind. But its rhythms have a

peculiar hypnotic power not met with before. It has a kinship with the

saxophone. If this is the future, then the future is, as it very likely

is, of the barbarians. But this is the future in which we ought not to

be interested” (595). Riding seizes upon the word “barbarians,” upending

Eliot's dismissive analogy, and proceeds to sketch out a positive

poetics of barbarism in Contemporaries (66). Riding argues that by

“taking everything around her very literally and many things for granted

which others have not been naive enough to take so,” Stein has

fundamentally altered poetic modernism (78). She insists that “no one

but Miss Stein has been willing to be as ordinary, as simple, as

primitive, as stupid, as barbaric as successful barbarism demands,” and

that Stein, by doing “what everyone else has been ashamed to do,” is the

only modernist whose compositions are firmly rooted in the everyday

(78). Because Stein writes so far outside the generic parameters of her

contemporaries, Riding argues, she has managed to achieve authenticity,

while at the same time subverting modernism's prestige-obsessed

institutions: “She has courage, clarity, sincerity, simplicity. She has

created a human mean in language, a mathematical equation of

ordinariness, which leaves one with a tender respect for that changing

and unchanging slowness that is humanity and Gertrude Stein” (84). If

Stein is a “barbaric” writer, or if, as Eliot warns, she is “going to

make trouble for us,” for Riding this trouble will be the salvation of

the avant-garde.

At least one reviewer of Contemporaries recognized that Riding was

attempting, through a revaluation of Stein, to radically redefine poetic

practice for the modernist moment. A 1928 Times Literary Supplement

review finds merit in Riding's preoccupation with the person and in her

insistence that “poetry should be a humanity” (254). As a treatise

“riding on the backs” (pun certainly intended) of contemporary poets,

the reviewer argues, Contemporaries articulates a much needed theory of

poetic practice wedded to personal language and the commonplace, to the

“apples and napkins of poetry, associations of which no poet should be

queasy” (254). Riding does indeed extol the “apples and napkins of

poetry,” both in her insistence that poetry cannot be divorced from

everyday language, and in her theorization of Stein's radical poetics.

Professional modernists, Riding argues, try to make language an external

medium—like paint to the painter or stone to the sculptor. In so doing,

modernists transform poetry into a specialist discipline—a rigidly

defined cultural production, one “Art” among others. As Jerome McGann

puts it, Riding replaced modernism's vision of poetry as “an art of

making” (which she saw as an evasion of “what is most human about the

way we use language”) with a vision of poetry as an art “of telling”

(McGann 313). Returning, as Stein does in Tender Buttons, to the apples

and napkins—the everyday and everywhere of language—Riding reinvents the

poet as person and sets the terms for a poetic practice that grapples

with the uncertainties of language and personhood.

Above all, Riding and Stein both value particularity, and Riding uses

the Stein chapter in Contemporaries to argue for the everyday

singularity of poetic language in the hands of the poet as person.

Stein's influence is most evident in the pages devoted to the

“time-sense,” as Riding's own exposition and locution begin to echo the

recursive diction in “Composition as Explanation.” Much like Stein's

often quoted adage, “everything is the same except composition and time,

composition and the time of the composition and the time in the

composition” (500), Riding's definition of the “time-sense” is derived

from her own understanding of Steinian language: “The composition is

clear because the language means nothing but what it means in her using

of it” (82). Stein's version of modernist composition is “divinely

inspired in ordinariness” and uses utterly contextual, ahistorical

language: “[n]one of the words Miss Stein uses have ever had any

experience” (80). Most happily, Stein's work is unburdened by criticism

and is conceived outside of the dreaded Zeitgeist: “This is how Gertrude

Stein wrote in 1906 and this is how she was still writing in 1926.

Writing by always beginning again and again and again keeps everything

different and everything the same” (83). For Riding, Stein radicalizes

poetic language by refusing metaphysical complexity and by making the

reader's primal encounter with language truly new. Thus the difficulty

in reading Stein lies not in the words themselves, but in the ways they

are rendered unfamiliar in the moment of the composition and in the act

of reading. Stein exemplifies barbaric modernism by writing

authentically as herself in the present, by creating a language-based

poetry that lies at the very foundation of avant-garde poetics, even to

the present day.

Out of these valuations of Stein's barbarism, Contemporaries sketches an

alternative modernist project that works against, rather than with, the

specialization and disciplinarity that had come to define poetic

practice by the late 1920s. If modernists, as Riding extensively argues,

accept and even accelerate modernity's gradual separation of the spheres

of human knowledge and activity, a poetics of barbarism might return us

to a state in which these activities and orientations had equal range:

“In a barbaric society religion does not occupy one mental compartment,

philosophy another, science another, painting another, poetry another,

and so on. But religion is everything and everything is religion,

philosophy is everything and everything is philosophy, and so on. In a

civilized society, religion is a sentiment, philosophy a speculation,

science a pursuit of knowledge, painting and poetry arts” (58). In a

sense, Riding's desire to return to this barbaric state finds a close

cousin in Eliot's description of the literary periods that predate the

“dissociation of sensibility,” in which poets “possessed a mechanism of

sensibility which could devour any kind of experience” (“The

Metaphysical Poets” 669). Yet the two differ—crucially for

Contemporaries—in their responses to this shift in human experience.

Eliot studies it, while Riding audaciously invites poets to overcome it,

so that poetry “might be normal without being vulgar, and deal naturally

with truth without being trite” or so that poetry might be “everything,”

and “everything” poetry (55).

After Contemporaries and Snobs

In the years following the publication of Contemporaries, Riding

gradually distanced herself, both physically and philosophically, from

the modernist debates she took on in the book. On the heels of

Contemporaries, she wrote Anarchism is Not Enough, a text written in

response to Wyndham Lewis's The Art of Being Ruled (1926), which derided

the “picturesque dementia of Gertrude Stein” and her “childish” cohort

(416). After Riding's suicide attempt in 1929 (the impetus for which

remains the subject of great debate), she and Graves relocated to

Mallorca and lived there in relative isolation until the impending

Spanish Civil War forced them to flee. During Riding's convalescence,

Stein ceased to communicate with her, and after several of Riding's

letters went unanswered, their friendship ended in 1930. In the years

leading up to the Second World War, the problem of professionalism

descried in Contemporaries and the importance of the modernist project

more generally were eclipsed by the increasingly sinister geopolitical

landscape and by Riding's own growing frustration with abstract language

and metaphor. During this period, she drafted an “Open Letter” to

hundreds of writers and artists asking “What shall we do?” about the

rise of fascism; she wrote Everybody's Letters, a semi-fictional

compendium of her correspondence from various friends and writers, and

The Word ‘Woman,’ which investigates gender, language, and the

ambivalent muse (and is almost certainly a reflection on her

relationship with Graves). In 1938, Riding published her Collected

Poems, after which she publicly repudiated poetry and ceased to write

it. As Charles Bernstein has noted, Riding, like many public

intellectuals in the midst of war, experienced a “crisis of and for

expression, in which the abuse of language became inextricably

identified with the abuse of the human” (259). Leaving Europe (and

Graves) behind by 1940, Riding relocated to New York and married

journalist Schuyler Jackson, changing her name (for the final time) to

Laura (Riding) Jackson, with intentional parentheses. Increasingly

reclusive in her writing and personal life, she and Jackson moved to

rural Florida and adopted an ascetic lifestyle—living in a cabin with no

electricity or running water, cultivating oranges, and writing together

a Dictionary of Related Meanings. After Jackson's death in 1968, Riding

continued to work on the Dictionary, which went through several

iterations, and eventually became a lengthy philosophical treatise on

language itself that was published posthumously as Rational Meaning: A

New Foundation for the Definition of Words (1997).

Completely severed from those “contemporaries and snobs” she analyzed in

the 1920s, Riding achieved in her later writing—especially The Telling

and Rational Meaning—the idiosyncrasy that even her peripheral

involvement in modernism never fully allowed. Reflecting on those years

in “The New Immorality,” she explains: “I have, thus, been given the

role, in the historical drama Twentieth-Century Literature, of a

non-belonger, one resisting the camaraderie of spoken-word literary

linguisticism—and accorded the shabby honor of being dubbed ‘neglected’

by specialists in obscurities of literary justice. And I have deemed it

my duty to bear myself, against that role-assignment, as the true

belonger—were there a contemporary actuality of literature as the home

of the written word (the word of purposeful thought) to which to belong”

(261). Despite Riding's sense of her own isolation—that she belonged in

a canon of one—and despite the increasingly arch, even mystical tone she

adopted in her later work, the long view of modernism Riding outlines in

Contemporaries inaugurates its own significant tradition. Whether or not

she would welcome the associations, Contemporaries prefigures later

feminist critiques of male modernism, as well as Marxist understandings

of criticism and its effect on literature as a discipline. Above all,

Contemporaries gives critical shape to an avant-garde tradition with

Stein as its figurehead—a genealogy of poets who value and uphold the

eccentricities of poetry, the particularity of the poet, and the true

difficulty of human language. We cannot underestimate, then, the value

of Riding's treatise in the history of modernist criticism, nor the

value of her outsider perspective on modernism. Neither contemporary nor

snob, she was uniquely situated to recognize its radicality as well as

its weaknesses. In view of both, it is Riding's instinctive defense of

the poet as person and of the inherent idiosyncrasy of the poetic

endeavor that distinguishes Contemporaries and asks us to revisit and

reevaluate the modernist enterprise.

Works Cited

Anonymous. “Contemporaries and Snobs by Laura Riding.” Times Literary

Supplement, April 5, 1928, 254.

Bernstein, Charles. “Riding's Reason.” In My Way: Speeches and Poems,

255–267. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999.

Eliot, T. S. “Charleston, Hey! Hey!” Nation & Aethenaeum. January 1927,

595.

———. “The Metaphysical Poets.” Times Literary Supplement, October 20,

1921, 669.

———. The Sacred Wood: Essays on Poetry and Criticism. London: Methuen,

1960. First published 1920.

Friedmann, Elizabeth. A Mannered Grace: The Life of Laura Riding

Jackson. New York: Persea, 2005.

Graves, Robert, and Laura Riding. A Survey of Modernist Poetry. London:

William Heinemann, 1927.

Jackson, Laura (Riding). “An Autobiographical Summary.” Laura (Riding)

Jackson and Schuyler B. Jackson collection, #4608. Division of Rare and

Manuscript Collections, Cornell University Library, n.d., series 1, box

1, folder 1.

———. “The New Immorality.” In Under the Mind's Watch: Concerning Issues

of Language, Literature, Life of Contemporary Bearing. Edited by John

Nolan and Alan J. Clark. Bern, Switzerland: Peter Lang, 2004, 241–259.

Lewis, Wyndham. The Art of Being Ruled. London: Chatto and Windus, 1926.

McGann, Jerome. “The Grand Heretics of Modern Fiction: Laura Riding,

John Cowper Powys, and the Subjective Correlative.” Modernism/modernity

13, no. 2, (2006): 309–323.

Riding, Laura. Contemporaries and Snobs. New York: Doubleday Doran &

Company, 1928.

———. “The New Barbarism and Gertrude Stein.” transition 3 (June 1927):

153–68.

———. to Wyndham Lewis, April 22, 1927. Wyndham Lewis collection, #4612.

Division of Rare and Manuscript Collections, Cornell University Library,

box 112, folder 97.

———. See also Jackson, Laura (Riding).

Samuels, Lisa. “Creating Criticism: An Introduction to Anarchism Is Not

Enough.” Anarchism Is Not Enough by Laura Riding. Berkeley: University

of California Press, 2001, xi–lxxviii.

Stein, Gertrude. “Composition as Explanation.” In A Stein Reader, edited

by Ulla Dydo. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1993, 493–503.

———. Three Lives and Tender Buttons. New York: Signet Classics, 2003.

West, Geoffrey. Deucalion: Or the Future of Literary Criticism. London:

Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1930.

Wexler, Joyce. “Epilogue: How Modernist Authority Became Authoritarian.”

In Little Magazines and Modernism: New Approaches, edited by Adam

McKible and Suzanne W. Churchill. London: Ashgate, 2007, 133–147.

1

Poetry and the Literary Universe

I: Shame of the Person

There is a sense of life so real that it becomes the sense of something

more real than life. Spatial and temporal sequences can only partially

express it. It introduces a principle of selection into the

undifferentiating quantitative appetite and thus changes accidental

emotional forms into deliberate intellectual forms; animal experiences

related by time and space into human experiences related in infinite

degrees of kind. It is the meaning at work in what has no meaning; it

is, at its clearest, poetry.^(=> #calibre_link-1 1

)

Unfortunately this sense, which can in its origin be only a personal

one, is easily professionalized. From observations of it in written

works, rules are made for it, intentions ascribed to it. There results

what has come to be called criticism. Criticism in turn uses this sense

against itself. It dissociates it from its creative origin. In the end

the “literary” sense comes to be the authority-to-write which the poet

is supposed to receive, through criticism, from the age that he lives

in. It is not even in each age a new literary sense, but merely a

tradition revised and brought up to date. More and more the poet has

been made to conform to literature instead of literature to the

poet—literature being the name given by criticism to works inspired by

or obedient to criticism. Less and less is the poet permitted to rely on

personal authority. The very word genius, formerly used to denote the

power to intensify a sense of life into a sense of literature, has been

boycotted by criticism; not so much because it has become gross and

meaningless through sentimentality as because professional literature

develops a shame of the person, a snobbism against the personal

self-reliance which is the nature of genius. What is all current

literary modernism but the will to extract the literary sense of the age

from the Zeitgeist at any cost to creative independence? The readiness

to resort to any contemporary fetish rather than to the poetic person?

To strengthen its argument this snobbism may use all the unfortunate

examples in poetry of reliance on the person: they are the moral lesson

to which it does not even need to point. The fortunate examples it does

not explain as reliance on the person but as authorized literature.

It was not until the late sixteenth century that the literary sense

began to be professionalized in English literature, and then only

loosely. The Elizabethan literary sense was capricious and eccentric. It

contradicted itself. It was a grotesque but charming combination of

coarse exuberance and elaborate refinement. There are uniform

eccentricities in Elizabethan poetry because Elizabethan poets were

personally alive in an eccentric age, not because, as a mass, they

obeyed a contemporary programme. A constant human character runs through

all the literature of this period, accentuated by the active share that

most of the writers took in public life, which must be distinguished

from the constant literary character of eighteenth-century literature,

most of whose writers were also active in public life, but in a public

life standardized in party politics. And although Elizabethan literature

had a certain conformity of manner, it had little conformity of

structure. It is impossible to treat any of the prevailing literary

habits as items in a contemporary corpus. Euphuism, the luxurious

politico-allegorical conceits of Spenser, the Arcadian refinements of

Sidney, the pastoral affectations of Lodge, Peele and Greene, the

philosophical realism of Shakespeare, even the foreign fashions

reborrowed after Chaucer from the French and the Italian Renaissance—all

of these were the erratic creative gestures of a time of erratic

personality.

The period following the post-Elizabethan decay and the Puritan

usurpation (roughly covering the first three-quarters of the eighteenth

century) pulled itself together with French classicism. It wished to

wipe out Elizabethan irregularity and its consequences. It looked down

upon the Elizabethans because they had been too much alive. Said Johnson

of Shakespeare: “A minute analysis of life at once destroys that

splendour which dazzles the imagination; whatsoever grandeur can display

or luxury can enjoy, is procured by offices of which the mind shrinks

from contemplation.” It is natural that this shrinking mind should have

found its happiest expression in a form as negative as satire.

For between these two periods there was born the natural man, the

common-sense antithesis to the erratic person. He was now in the centre

of the stage and on all fours. Serving as a literary and sociological

convenience, he did not act originally; he did not act at all. It was

his function to be observed. “The proper study of mankind is man.”

Conduct in the abstract now became, in the hands of these early

behaviourists, the morbid final value of the cultivated mind. The sole

provision left the creative genius was an impersonal intelligence which,

not guided by feelings, had to be guided by good manners.

Donne, an advanced contemporary of Shakespeare's, stands like a Janus

between these two periods, in a separate period of his own, however—“to

himself a Diocletian.” On the one hand, he had more intellectual reserve

than the Elizabethans; his poetry did not prove enduringly popular, as

so much Elizabethan poetry did, because the proportion of

surface-entertainment in it was smaller. On the other hand, his satiric

epistles have a lyrical flexibility generally foreign to satiric poetry.

The strength of the satires of Dryden, or, after him, Pope, lies in an

energetic critical obedience, a contemporary piety, we might say; of

Donne, in a sturdy and unruly self-reliance. The eighteenth-century

satire was a literary custom, the least human and experimental form

possible; while in Donne the satire was a vehicle of strong humanity and

daring. Eighteenth-century literary policy demanded a formal inhumanity

of the poet, since humanity was according to contemporary belief merely

a philosophical abstraction upon which to moralize. Instead of passion,

there was intelligence; and intelligence meant a servility to certain

canonical ideas according to which the learning of the time was framed.

Poets became, in the satire, ministers of instruction. By philosophy the

poet was conceived and by classicism he had grace.

But what was philosophy more than the callow sophistries of deism or

optimism or perfectionism? And what was classicism more than a plausible

gloss to sophistries that could not without verbal pompousness support

their inconsistencies? The poet was not a person but the spokesman of

his age, a mechanical recorder of time. But time is only criticism and a

poet is supposed to have to do with poetry. Poetry is not contemporary

poetry. It is not philosophy. It is not even literature. As between

literature and life, it is closer to life. But life invents time rather

than poetry, a sanctimonious comment on itself, a selflessness. Poetry

invents itself. It is nearly a repudiation of life, a selfness. Unless

it is this, it is a comment on a comment, sterile scholasticism.

Public interference with poetry rests on the popular delusion that an

immediate commerce exists between historical truth and poetic truth;

that the historical universe is potentially the poetic universe. The

historical universe is, however, only a temporary aggregate of ideas.

These ideas may direct the structure of the literary universe, which

produces the philosophical journalism of a period; the structure of the

poetic universe is directed by a person in single-handed conflict with

the time-community. Science, the present-day aggregate of tribal ideas,

puts on the creative mind a social compulsion to accept these ideas; and

criticism acts, as usual, as the nattered instrument of conversion.

Official literature is born of a critical rather than of a literary

sense; it is a social institution which the poet is hired to serve.

Criticism makes time-poets, who court favour for literature from the

historical universe. A great deal of up-to-date poetry is thus written

which becomes immediately out-of-date and is therefore rejected by the

criticism that called for it; which consoles itself with a cynical

classicism, a cult-cult of previous exemplary time-poets (such as Pope).

The truth is that critical modernism is really more interested in

maintaining a defensive attitude toward the literary past than in

sponsoring “new” poetry. It equivocates between an unreserved adherence

to poetic formalism and an unreserved disavowal of poetic formalism. It

outformalizes formalism and thus has a ready snobbism to employ against

formalism or irregularity, as may be required. Any new poetry which

finds it necessary to disconnect itself from previous poetry, as

Rimbaud's did, must be written outside the shelter of contemporary

criticism of any sort; its creator must be “le grand malade, le grand

criminel, le grand maudit—et le suprĂȘme savant. Car il arrive Ă 

l'inconnu.”^(=> #calibre_link-2 2

) Even the most advanced phase of critical modernism is in many respects

more reactionary than the most conservative phase of contemporary

critical traditionalism. For the latter, in its greybeard innocence, is

sentimentally inclined toward any new idea that can be socially

administered and justified personally on inspirational grounds: it has a

pious hunger for the unknown and a superstitious respect for prophecy.

The former, on the contrary, has an intellectual distaste for the

unknown and an abhorrence of personal exhibitionism: shame in the

person, as found in the various inhibitions which govern critical

modernism, is the real reason for abetting the known historical

universe. Even the element of obscurity resulting from an observance of

the official shame-taboo is strictly limited to an obscurity of

reference.

The presence of excessive criticism in a time is a sign that it fears

its own literature; and overzealous critics are the agents of a

compromise between poetry and society. They keep peace by forcing poetry

to hide its personal criminalities behind the privilege-walls of

literary tradition; they apply pressure only to poetry in the making,

never to society. The gospel of contemporaneity is an expression of the

mob-fear of the organized society of time against those incorruptible

individuals who might reveal life to be an anarchy whose only order is a

blind persistence. In the energy of this persistence occur intense

flashes, the poetry or lightning of sense. The mob, looking on, reads an

official code of revelation. Otherwise it must admit the mind of man to

dwell in man; which would be as troublesome as fire in the brain and as

shameful as thunder in the stomach.

II: Poetry, Out of Employment, Writes on Unemployment

The social office of poetry in both classical and romantical periods has

been to formulate progress. It has been called upon to do this because

history, philosophy, religion, science, even literature itself in so far

as it is a knowledge-category, are constantly changing forms of wisdom

that need the language of finality to help them impose themselves as

absolute upon their periods. So it is that human tyrannies have enlisted

poetry to conceal their insufficiencies, at the same time denying to

poetry its own self-sufficiency. It was against such tyrannies that

Shelley rebelled. But though he felt the social subjection of poetry

more intensely than any poet before him, he attempted to justify its

independence by its social excellence.

For while poetry was “at once the centre and circumference of knowledge,

which comprehends all science and to which all science must be

referred,”^(=> #calibre_link-3 3

) it had also a civic usefulness (“The production and assurance of

pleasure in this highest sense is true utility”) since “the great

instrument of moral good is the imagination; and poetry administers to

the effect by acting as the cause.” Poetry still remained, even in

Shelley's view, a first-rate public servant jealous of its duties. He

could go so far as to prove the superiority of poetry to other forms of

human wisdom in its benefits to society; he could not go so far as to

dissociate the critical from the social values of poetry, because he

still thought of poetry as communal poetry, of the poet in his primitive

function as the community's all-round medicine-man and of society as the

origin of poetry through the action and interaction of the social

sympathies. Indeed he seems to be defending poetry not so much for its

own as for society's sake and thus translating his poetic

incorruptibility into social orthodoxy instead of into real criticism.

Much of the criticism and much of the poetry he wrote was only earnest

propaganda for goodness.

This common misapplication of poetry to supplementary offices is the

result of a confusion between an intelligence that we may call concrete,

because it regards everything as potentially comprehensible and

measurable, and the poetic intelligence, which is an accurate sensation

of the unknown, an inspired comprehension of the unknowable. The

concrete intelligence suffers from the illusion of knowledge since it

does not recognize a degree in knowledge at which all its laws and

implements cease to operate and at which another order of intelligence

enters. It is at this degree that the poetic intelligence begins, an

illuminating ignorance in which everything is more than certain, that

is, absolute because purely problematical. The degree, which is one of

clarity, is presupposed in the poet, whatever the condition of knowledge

may be at his time, however far knowledge may be from the

knowledge-limit. The poetic intelligence is a fixed proportion, the

concrete intelligence a relative one. Confusion of these has led to the

establishment of false rational equivalents to the poetic intelligence:

so that, as in the present time, when the illusion of knowledge seems

completely to satisfy the vanity of the concrete intelligence, poetry

becomes a superfluous office and is either peremptorily dismissed or

allowed to continue as a graceful tribute to the triumph of the concrete

intelligence. However, the dignity historically conferred by society on

poetry for its prophetic usefulness makes it impossible for poetry to

accept this humiliation. (To use Shelley's distinction, society was

using prophecy in the gross sense of the word, in which poetry was an

attribute of prophecy, while poetry applied to this public charge the

most favourable interpretation possible, in which prophecy was an

attribute of poetry.) A competition ensues between the concrete

intelligence and the poetic intelligence, futile because it cannot

produce an increase in knowledge and because it has the effect on the

poet of a snobbish display of contemporary sophistication. Indeed, in an

actual hand-to-hand conflict between these two intelligences, the

concrete intelligence would necessarily occupy the defensive position,

since it takes only a very small pressure from the unknown to overthrow

the most quantitatively formidable known. As a matter of fact no such

practical contact can exist between them. For though one begins where

the other leaves off, they are separated by the very degree which marks

the change from one kind into another. Even if it were possible for the

concrete intelligence to arrive at the full knowledge-limit, it would

not automatically pass into the next stage but have achieved

self-destruction and exhaustion; and the poetic intelligence would

continue irrespective of accidents to the concrete intelligence, it

being not a consumable surplus of intellectual power but a constant

surplus. The relation between these two kinds of intelligence is further

falsified by making the poetic intelligence the internal consciousness

of the external concrete intelligence; whereas both have a strictly

separate set of internal and external experiences, the external

experience of the poetic intelligence being the personal life of the

poet, the internal experience of the concrete intelligence being the

impersonal mechanical soul which facts in a certain stage of

assimilation assume and which gives to them a false poetic appearance of

significant unity. Poets sin most of all perhaps in identifying this

mass-consciousness, which contemporaneous facts seem to form

automatically, with the self-consciousness of the poetic intelligence.

(Paul Valéry is an exaggerated contemporary instance of this weakness.

He made a gigantic effort to accomplish poetically the synthesis of the

various modern knowledge-forms of the concrete intelligence and got, not

a poetic equivalent, but a mathematical sum, a mystical number not

further translatable into poetry. Having thus brought the concrete

intelligence and the poetic intelligence of the present time to a

deadlock and exerted a damping influence on creative enthusiasm, he was

obliged to write his own poetry in the past to remove it from the

necessity of accounting for itself otherwise than technically.)

The nineteenth century showed a more material increase than perhaps any

other preceding century in this mass-consciousness of human knowledge

which had for so long been feeding on poetry while pretending to feed

it. There was a chance that, dismissed from pseudo-poetic occupations,

poetry might enter into its proper domain. But the old connection was

too strong a literary habit and poetry continued to search for a poetic

equivalent to the newly enlarged universe long after this universe, so

increasingly intelligible to itself, had begun to deny the reality of

poetic values (as it was right in doing if poetic values are understood

as interpretative values). As an epic is the most tangible poetic

equivalent to a group of associated rational experiences, poets went on

writing in an epic vein, but without producing an epic, since normally

an epic cannot be produced without a historical demand for it—the

nineteenth century was finding its own epic in progressive material

expansion. The character put upon this futile Victorian type was

realism, to describe the rational tests to which poetry submitted itself

and which therefore made it slavish and petty in substance, in manner

disproportionately grandiose. Tennyson's Princess and other similar

writings designed to make poetry keep pace with progress never looked

anything but feeble and old-fashioned beside progress itself.

With the advance of the twentieth century, progress was gradually

dropped from the vocabulary of the concrete intelligence as too small a

word for so large a thing; and relativity permitted to take its place,

not for its mathematical sense, but because it was the most poetic word

available in scientific language to convey the immensity of the great

atomic epic of the concrete intelligence.^(=> #calibre_link-4 4

) Poetry, as the diminutive prophet of progress, was also dropped out.

Even history, the life-size image of man, made a philosophical

recantation of faith in the personal mind, and a new century had its

moment when it declared formally that the myth of humanity was no more.

This meant a complete isolation of the poetic intelligence in the

personal unknown, in an unconquerable interior: a state that had been

the unconscious desire of poetry since its beginnings as a community

handmaiden of tribal success, that is, of progress. The liberation of

the poetic intelligence from its indenture would coincide, naturally,

with the disappearance of poetry as such in the social sense of the

word. Poetry had become the property of society and like any other

manufactured commodity had ceased to have any organic connection with

its makers. It might now be possible to re-establish this connection.

It was to be hoped that criticism would use its offices to bring this

about. But as criticism's professional status depended on the

maintenance of the old order, it could not be expected to celebrate

poetry's forced dissociation from social uses. The best it could do was

to believe cheerfully that nothing had really changed and protest

against poetry's exclusion from social uses. It could insist upon

looking for the joke. The joke was found. The universe still had a myth

requiring the ritualistic services of poetry. The new myth was that

there was no myth. Delighted with this discovery, criticism rushed to

the rescue of the unnumbered poets who, being individuals and not, like

criticism, a public institution, had perhaps not noticed that anything

was happening at all but continued to write as they had always written,

for reasons that they left to others to discover. For people never

really live in contemporary history: they live either in the past or

completely outside the time-sense. So the course of criticism (or of

certain forces and influences which, by their effect, become criticism)

was to announce, first, that historical conditions had put an end to

poetry, removing all hope in order to bring home to poets the proper

time-sense, then, to follow this melancholy report with the cheerful

amendment that, after all, all hope was not gone, since, if poetry had

all subjects taken away from it, there was always one subject of which

poetry could not be deprived, namely, that poetry had come to an end.

Here was an ingenious method for indefinitely postponing the end of

poetry; and, after the general applause which followed this remarkable

solution, many volunteers stepped forward and declared feelingly that

the time-sense had been brought home to them and that, now that it had

been made clear to them that poetry was at an end, they felt sure that

they could write better poetry than ever. Never indeed, they said, had

such an urgent reason for writing poetry been presented to poets. Under

the spell of this enthusiasm a tremendous revival of poetry took place;

and not only was better poetry, but more poetry than ever written. Since

poetry was to write about nothing, it could write about everything from

the standpoint of nothing; it could still have its epic without the

burden of having to have convictions about it.

The most notable exponent of this non-committal epic was T. S. Eliot.

His period poem fulfilled the time-sense requirements even to the point

of self-extinction. It was indeed everything and nothing. It composed

and decomposed. It was contemporaneously sympathetic and

contemporaneously apathetic. It ran from classical minor to romantic

major, to romantic minor, to classical major and back again. It

disciplined itself learnedly in the pious unbelief of scholasticism.

Everything is Nothing. But Nothing is eternal. “We have not reached

conclusion. . . . ”^(=> #calibre_link-5 5

)

Unreal City,

Under the brown fog. . . .

Falling towers

Jerusalem Athens Alexandria

Vienna London

Unreal^(=> #calibre_link-6 6

)

One would have thought this left nothing to be desired. But one thing

had been overlooked in this revival, the importance of not being

earnest. Poetry had perhaps taken the time-sense too literally, had been

too much of an advocate and therefore too little of a snob against

itself: even irony can betray convictions if it becomes too ironical.

Or, to put the complaint practically, this posthumous poetry was not

formal enough: it bore too little resemblance to poetry proper. This was

the general objection made by many who were on the inside, so to speak,

of the movement to keep poetry going. Mr. Edwin Muir is a typical

spokesman of the reaction against intensity.^(=> #calibre_link-7 7

) T. S. Eliot, he protests in effect, is a true posthumist, but too

heartbreaking. Edith Sitwell is also a true posthumist and has, besides,

a strict technical organization of her non-humanistic universe of

death-in-life. She has, in fact, managed to leave the heart-break out.

But even this does not satisfy Mr. Muir, to whom such a complete

extinction of the heart-break seems to bespeak a stoicism likely to

become, in its own way, paradoxically intense; so that he begs Miss

Sitwell to reinstate the heart-break. Nor does Robert Graves satisfy in

any respect, since he is too casual, and so not a posthumist at all.

Because he constantly changes (as he makes personal rather than critical

interpretation of the time-sense) he is, Mr. Muir concludes, creatively

unbalanced; that is, he disregards the official demise of the poetic

intelligence and writes on a realistic basis, making private terms with

the time-sense instead of negotiating with it through critical

headquarters. (This desire to look for secret understandings in Mr.

Graves' poetry has led Mr. Muir to morbid misinterpretations of certain

of his poems, such as The Clipped Stater, in which Mr. Muir reads only

as a flirting with the theory of metempsychosis what is a poetic

narration of the personal absolute, dramatized as the deified Alexander

the Great, experimenting with the time and space humiliations of

historical life.)

To illustrate just what he considers to be the proper tone for

posthumist poetry, Mr. Muir has gone to the trouble of writing a little

specimen poem to be used, perhaps, as the standard posthumistic primer

and very fittingly named, indeed, Chorus of the Newly Dead. A single

stanza will serve to show what Mr. Muir means. The Poet says:

And through our souls the vast tormented world

Passed slow in splendid pictures without pain.

Where, in what distant night, have these been hurled?

When shall dawn rise on those lost mounts again?

As this method seems to be no more than the adoption of the Tennysonian

hat, mantle and trousers with Tennyson left out, posthumistic poets

should not find it difficult to follow, especially since such minute

instructions for the playing of the part are contained in T. S. Eliot's

Hollow Men.

The throw-back to the ordinary poetic tradition in which the fanatic

observance of the contemporary time-sense has culminated reminds us that

this time-sense is nothing but the familiar historical Zeitgeist in a

more complicated disguise than usual. It would be well to recall here

the distinction between the formal Zeitgeist, as it is manifested in

literature—in contemporary poetry for example—and the personal literary

sense, as it was possessed by the Elizabethans. The former translates a

whole period into a single emotion which is used as artificial colouring

for the period's literature. The latter is the actual, the moving nerve

of many emotions, which do not need to have existed as worn-out history

before they can enter poetry: they are historical only in the sense that

they may compose poetry—but not historical until the poetry is composed.

Zeitgeist poetry is out-of-date poetry, because it describes an emotion

derived from history. A faithful, up-to-date historical record of this

emotion may be inspired by the Zeitgeist, but not an up-to-date poetry;

for the poetry it purposes to inspire was or was not written in the time

when the period was a period, before it was called a period. All

Zeitgeist poetry is, in truth, posthumous poetry; and it is periods of

poetry that die, because periods die, not poetry. Byron, Goethe and

Lamartine, for example, who considered themselves poetic universalists,

were typical Zeitgeist writers, much more important as the recording

spirits of a period of revolution and reaction which they helped to

bury, than as poets: their poetry died as it was being written. There is

a way of living in history that goes forward, but by facing backwards;

and poetry written in this way cannot claim to belong anywhere.

III: Escapes from the Zeitgeist

Satire

A certain amount of poetic activity naturally seeks to protect itself

from the Zeitgeist by making use of one of two historically respectable

modes—the nature-mode or the satire-mode; or, disdaining these, it may

retire to the proud exile of what is known as the poetic absolute. With

the coming of age of the universe the infant call of nature is supposed

to have been superseded by the vast silence of intelligence in matter

(so that the poet has no more questions to answer, having lost his job

as tutor in the nursery of time). The pathetic fallacy, however, still

remains a possible romantic escape for sentiment in flight from a new

system of facts; as irony, the antipathetic fallacy, for wit in flight

from a new system of intellectual expediency.

Although the formal eighteenth-century satire was in some respects a

romantic escape by classicism from threatening romanticism, it was more

definitely an instrument of subjection to the Zeitgeist, one of

literature's social mannerisms. Conforming satire must be distinguished

from the satire of revolt, which is a weak gesture of social

non-conformity. The former is the satire in its literal sense, an

elegant and conscientious exercise in a form, a medley of localisms (the

satire being by derivation a medley) on which stylistic uniformity is

superimposed. When Dryden described wit as “the essence of all verse,”

he was using it in this satiric scissors-and-paste

sense.^(=> #calibre_link-8 8

) (It is interesting to notice that he did not say the essence of all

poetry. Dryden is perhaps the founder of the snobbism, developed by

eighteenth-century contempt of the person, which limits the use of

poetry to great poetry, that is, bad poetry which succeeds in spite of

itself. Before Dryden verse had been chiefly a poetical word; with

Dryden it came to denote critical respectability. In the eighteenth

century it was regularly applied to poetry too superior to be great

poetry. Verse still prevails today, except in old-fashioned corners, as

a term of deprecation which gratifies contemporary shame of the person

and emphasizes the vulgarity of poetry.) Indeed Dryden was opposing

practical wit to impassioned Elizabethan wit—“a finer speech than the

language will allow,” as it was defined for Euphues or The Anatomy of

Wit.^(=> #calibre_link-9 9

) Donne, it will be remembered, was abused by Johnson because he had

employed wit too earnestly. Speaking of Cowley, whom he considered

superior to Donne, Johnson said: “The fault of Cowley, and perhaps of

all writers of the metaphysical race, is that of pursuing his thoughts

to their last ramifications, by which he loses the grandeur of

generality.”^(=> #calibre_link-10 10

) Wit in the eighteenth century did not mean “happiness of language”

(for which Johnson had to condemn even Pope) or happiness of thought, as

it was for the metaphysicians.^(=> #calibre_link-11 11

) It was the wit of the formal satire, a cozenage of contemporary

banality called “strength of thought,” the common sense of the

prevailing system of intellectual expediency.

In the satire of revolt wit performs a philosophical evasion. It

compromises with that which it opposes by treating it with a

semi-playful, semi-sorrowful pessimism. Irony defeats sentiment, but in

doing so it proves itself to be inverted sentiment, self-defeated. The

most successful romantic satirist in contemporary poetry is John Crowe

Ransom,^(=> #calibre_link-12 12

) who by a happy conjunction of sentiment and irony, has managed to

elevate defeat to a note of such unembittered renouncement that it

amounts, in its suppressed optimism, to a dignified compromise with the

all-conquering time-sense. This fortunate solution permits him to be a

gentle and aristocratic non-conformer in his métier and a democrat in

the adjustment of his poetry to its social milieu. A less astute satire

of revolt is to be found in the poetry of Siegfried Sassoon. In his

high-principled refusal of a helping hand from the Zeitgeist—a mixture

of the fanatic and the debonair—he has a paradoxical bond with perhaps

his most removed contemporary, James Joyce; who, by a colossal evasion,

which involved swallowing the Zeitgeist and then vomiting it up again,

accomplished the dual and monstrous feat of capitulation and revolt in

one huge, involuntary reflex-spasm.

Satire in this non-conforming sense is obviously unfit to supply the

period-poem which the age, through criticism, demands as its tribute

from poetry. At its best it produces, like the conforming satire,

period-tracts. The conforming eighteenth-century satire dissolved when

its wit had exhausted its material, and the period-epic was driven into

such obscurity as Darwin's Botanic Garden.^(=> #calibre_link-13 13

) Only satire in a broad, summarizing sense may culminate in a

representative epic, a large-scale poem of cancellation and

substitution. And then it is generally accompanied by a prose morality

which makes the work of cancellation easier. If however the age is in

motion and yet lacking in constructive substitute values (whether

specious or real) to replace disappearing values, the contemporary

satire will probably be confined solely to the prose morality; it will

be merely an epic of cancellation. Fielding was thus the real author of

the eighteenth-century satiric epic. The nineteenth century was

deficient in cancelling power and therefore produced no great

contemporary satire. Like the eighteenth century, the present period can

get no further than such an epic of cancellation as Ulysses; with the

difference that, though both epics are equally devoid of creative values

and alike designed to produce a catharsis of stale emotional matter (it

is remarkable how closely the Fielding-epic and the Joyce-epic tally in

material and structure—the use of obscenity, destructive literary

criticism, minute reports of the working of the minds of plain people),

the eighteenth-century view of literature made a place for the prose

morality, while the ethics of contemporary criticism force the epic of

cancellation to conclude with a cancellation of itself. Criticism is the

voice of the age; and as the age feels itself the consciousness of an

arrived universe, it does not call for an expression of new values or

for a summary of the distribution of values, but merely for

congratulation. The poetic consciousness, which criticism treats as a

historical consciousness, has become superfluous. Poetry, however, will

be permitted to indulge in the bravado of despair, the universe's mark

of pity for poetry thus obliged to sever its connections with it. Poetry

seeking to escape the Zeitgeist, and therefore not properly of this age,

the universe leaves to an out-of-date criticism that seems to have

survived by grace to take care of it. For poetry that is trying to win a

postponement of judgment by good behaviour, the universe finds itself

fortunately provided with an advanced criticism recruited largely from

the ranks of poetry itself; so that the universe expects no trouble to

come of its clemency—that is, it is not likely to have poets, though

much poetry of an obituary nature. The important thing to be remembered

by poetry is that shifting historical values have been brought to a

state of equilibrium by the heavy forefinger of science and that there

can therefore be no new values, only a methodic resolution of the values

we have, which are, potentially at least, all the values there are: in

life, if not in literature, we have reached conclusion. This is the

lesson poetry is supposed to learn, and no more; lest, by meddling in

science itself, it acquire the confidence of science and be tempted to

observe that every age has had the illusion of an equilibrium and the

illusion of new learning through revolutions in nomenclature.

The Poetic Absolute

The satire-escape and the nature-escape, creating as they do a moral

barrier of protective contempt between the poet and the Zeitgeist,

involve perhaps less equivocation than any other forms attempting to

live in spite of the age.^(=> #calibre_link-14 14

) A hypocritical and suppressed romanticism lurks in the resignation of

professedly Zeitgeist poetry, a depression difficult at times to

distinguish from self-pity. Not that there is anything wrong with

romanticism in itself, but suppressed romanticism is pathological; which

is why the only possible interpretation for much contemporary poetry is

psycho-analytic. As the detachment in such poetry, of which The Waste

Land is an easy clue for identification (and imitations of it like Nancy

Cunard's Parallax), is not voluntary but forced on the poet by the

universe from which he has been banished, its romanticism can be easily

detected in its wasting, its loss of appetite and weight, its obvious

pining for home. It is more difficult, however, to recognize suppressed

romanticism in poetry which tries to achieve detachment by a pretentious

creative system.

A great deal of literary shop-talk is devoted to the aesthetic absolute

and a forced dignity attends any effort to free the poem from

destructive circumstances which the poet is himself subject to. But

there is a difference between that absoluteness in a poem which is the

poet's own irrefutability, his power to write a poem that does not have

to support him in his weakness, or be supported by him in its weakness;

and that absoluteness which is philosophically read into a poem to give

it an authority that the poet is unable to find in life. In the first

sense absoluteness is a critical term that may be applied

retrospectively to any good poem. In the second it is a

moralistic-philosophical term to be applied prospectively to the

compensating function the poem is supposed to perform in the poet's and

everybody's life. Not until this distinction is perceived do we become

aware of the romantic unfulfilment and disappointment which most

theories of the absolute conceal.

The imposition of an absolute on the poem means the exclusion of all

loose relative references, the use of symbols that have no association

outside of the literary range of the poem itself, and an effect of great

technical rigidity that we may call creative strain. Hart Crane is

perhaps the only contemporary romantic absolutist who succeeds in

matching technical tenseness with emotional

tenseness.^(=> #calibre_link-15 15

) He maintains the ideal of romantic absoluteness by admitting the

philosophical dualism on which it is really based: he postulates a

normal and an abnormal reality, and his poems are real in so far as they

identify one reality with the other. In this he is an exception to the

usual romantic absolutist whose poems achieve a fixed mechanical reality

by excluding all correspondences—they are real because they admit no

reality but their own. Rimbaud, the last-century absolutist most relied

on by contemporary absolutists, made intellectual monstrosity the first

condition of poetic finality—an “immense et raisonnĂ© dĂ©rĂšglement de tous

les sens.”^(=> #calibre_link-16 16

) But in him intellectual monstrosity was a personal fact rather than a

poetic theory, one so intensified by poetic abuse that he was obliged,

in the end, to turn normal, to suppress his personal monstrosity in

order to avoid destruction through creative strain.

Evidences of creative strain in contemporary poets who profess no theory

of the absolute reveal the same effort to escape from the destructive

influences of the Zeitgeist into the constructive possibilities of the

poem when viewed as totality. In virtue of his creative strain E. E.

Cummings may be considered effectively an absolutist. His technical

caprice is a deliberate dissociation from contemporary reason. (He is

generally labelled an impressionist; but this only means that he treats

his absolute, his poem, as a stage-joke, and that humour introduces

sympathy, memory and related experience. His absolute may be more

properly called the comic relief of the absolute.) In Marianne Moore,

from whom all thoughts of the absolute must be far removed, creative

strain is a conscientious, scientific analysis of the germs which are

assumed to be responsible for the poetic condition; and her absolute is

that pure residuum of mental activity which is left when the imagination

has been excluded and, with it, sympathetic affiliations with emotional

environment. Edith Sitwell's absolute is perhaps more perplexing than

any of these. For though the technical pattern is maintained by strain,

the strain itself proves to be merely the romantic inventiveness of

frankly trivial emotions. But it would be absurd to deny that Miss

Sitwell's poetry had an absolute simply because it was romantic, that

is, because it confessed the triviality of escape. It is this refreshing

and disarming frankness which makes her work so popular. Her absolute

seems all the more genuine because, besides being fixed, formalized

romance, it is also an imitation of the practical absolute of modern

pictorial art. The absolute of painting is a technical necessity imposed

by the limitations of the medium. It may therefore develop into a mature

creative fact in painting, while in poetry, except where the methods of

painting are deliberately imitated, it rarely goes beyond the stunt

stage. Since Miss Sitwell arbitrarily adopts the methods of painting,

her poetry passes beyond the stunt stage. Yet it is not quite fair to

say that it is poetry written with the methods of painting, for this

would mean that it was something neither poetry nor painting. Miss

Sitwell, by the careful use of a limited number of symbols (of constant

value and fairly uniform recurrence), actually creates paintings, not

poems; which, from the inferred poetic value of these symbols, may be

made into poems by the reader. By confining herself to painting (which

is her real medium) in poetry, she succeeds in writing poetry and in

immortalizing it in picture-frames labelled romantic. Inside the

picture-frame everything is, as has so often been pointed out,

motionless. But the label reminds one that the painted cherry is able to

hang so still only because it is painted.

The safest form of poetic absolute is probably one derived from a

theological absolute. In France—where poetry has a great tendency to let

itself be written by the Zeitgeist; where the poet is supposed to be the

man of numbers who is sensible, in the words of Paul Valéry, the present

high-priest of Zeitgeist mysticism, of the passage de l'infinité des

individus;^(=> #calibre_link-17 17

) and where national vanity makes poetry an opportunistic blend of the

romantic and the classical, of accidental crowd literature and academic

grand homme literature—Catholicism provides a practical refuge in which

the poet can write with creative purity. Absolutes must go in pairs, one

the assumption, the other the demonstration; and when the assumption on

which the poetic absolute is based is vaguely formulated, as it is

likely to be if a critical assumption, the poem gives an effect of

insincerity and false power. The principle of technical dissociation

from influences, on which the absolute poem is supposed to depend, best

follows from such an article of faith as Jean Cocteau expresses

uncritically in: “J'apprendrai à fabriquer les poùmes (le mot est de La

Fontaine) et pour le reste Ă  laisser faire

Dieu.”^(=> #calibre_link-18 18

) If the absolute poem is, as the professed absolutist pretends, a

superior experience, then it can have no value as superior experience

unless it is accompanied by an expressed belief in the possibility of a

superior experience: the poetic absolute at its most literal implies

religious experience. A child is the perfect absolutist, since by an

initial acquiescence of the imagination in everything, it makes the

general one absolute, the particular another. The result is an

independence of the particular from the general, though it suggests the

general as one complementary colour suggests another: a quality for

which simplicity is perhaps a happier term than absoluteness. The want

of simplicity is the striking discrepancy in most “absolute” poetry and

poetic theory.

An absolute confers freedom in return for recognition, and freedom

should confer health, clearness, courage and variety. What is our

contemporary absolute poetry like?—Health? It is ashen with

misanthropy—Clearness? Where technical intricateness permits any light

to shine through, it is a light thinned out by a mystical vanity in

defeat. An absolute implies fulfilment; and mysticism is a simple

instrument of success. Indeed, a poetry that takes its absolute from a

religious absolute does not have to trouble to be either mystical or

religious; it does not have to confound its own intensity with argument.

The non-religious romantic absolute in poetry, having no supporting

absolute, is obliged to be overcharged with sophistication.—Courage? How

may such an evasive dogmatism presume to make attacks on open,

intrenched dogmatisms? On science? On literature itself? “Imaginez, mon

cher Jacques, la joie d'une langue dégagée de Rimbaud (à l'heure

actuelle plus encombrant que Hugo) et de la superstition de Maldoror. La

jeunesse respirerait.”^(=> #calibre_link-19 19

)

*

We gasp for the air in which to make declarations of similar freedom.

Our most uncompromising poetic programme is a string of fine names

(Donne, Poe, Rimbaud) worn as a charm round the neck of the

snob-aesthete.—Variety? The only material sign of absoluteness in

so-called absolute poetry is a technical limit the approach to which

means an increasing effect of monotony: the absolutist is only

interesting in his lapses.

What is here concealed? A timid desire or a perverse will to write

poetry which shall not involve personal accountability; disguised as a

protective snobbism against the Zeitgeist, which is seen as vulgarity

sitting in moral judgment. But if the poem is to be protected from moral

judgments it must have a morality of its own; and the morality of a poem

cannot reside in mere technical integrity. Technical integrity should

presuppose a scrupulous respect between the poet and the poem, and this

cannot exist if the poem is a convenience of the poet, a kind of moral

dummy. It is then but an annex of the poet, and without morality, as the

poet, being without morality, becomes an instrumental annex of the poem.

The poem cannot be absolute unless it belongs to itself; and it cannot

belong to itself unless the poet belongs to himself. The poet, then, is

the true companion absolute of the poetic absolute, which in this light

acquires a simpler and more explicit critical character: it is the

goodness of a poem without regard to its supplementary experience-value

to the poet. But for a poem to be free of the necessity to provide

experience-value the poet must have no poetic prejudice toward actual

experience. He must not ask poetic truth of reality or realistic truth

of poetry. He must see that there is logic but also illogic, “reality”

but also an equally real or more real unreality. And he must be strong

enough to endure in one person both kinds of experience. If the romantic

absolute is the harmless invention of a personality strong enough to

endure only one kind of experience, it is perhaps a legitimate device by

which such a personality may have an illusion of power both in poetry

and life. If, however, it threatens to impose as a doctrinaire

metaphysic of poetry what is only a hypocritically and elegantly worded

counsel of personal evasion, then it demands to be refuted by a complete

rehabilitation of the poetic mind and by a bold reinstatement of the

person in poetry. A rampant, undisguised romanticism is preferable to

it, or an ingenuous religious profession.

This is the kind of extreme which the poetic intelligence may be driven

to when the victorious concrete intelligence seems to have taken

possession of all the facts of actual experience, leaving the poetic

intelligence nothing but shadow with which to build a shadowy empire. It

at first seems strange that the poetic intelligence should accept defeat

so easily from the concrete intelligence. This is due, however, to the

illusion of numbers which the concrete intelligence has always been able

to practise. For it is, as has already been suggested, a

mass-consciousness whose numerical index is a social unit rather than a

personal one; a synthetic force, as the poetic intelligence is an

analytic one, which at its weakest may disintegrate into its component

groups (whose variety is a sign of its weakness, as the present

inclusion of everything in one category, science, is a sign of its

strength), such as the religious mind, the philosophical mind, the

political mind, but never into individual units—when it reaches

individual units it is the mass-consciousness once more. All arts except

poetry are a cross between the concrete intelligence and the poetic

intelligence: they have, by nature of their respective mediums, group

rather than individual motivation. The poetic intelligence has therefore

to fight alone against the aggressions of the concrete intelligence and,

at times of intense synthesizing like the present, is even forced to

disappear from itself or to cover its tracks with the dry leaves of

philosophical sentiment. But for whom is poetry being advertised as

possessing when read the virtue of an absolute? The concrete

intelligence does not read, nor is reading done in dozens, or even in

pairs. The only individual, then, whom it is safe to presume as a reader

for poetry is the poet himself. But if he is obliged to advertise his

poetry to himself, it is perhaps a sign that the poem is being asked to

stand for a poetic intelligence wanting in the poet in proportion to the

degree claimed for it in the poem: the poem is not self-determined, but

merely the poet's personal implement of self-determination.

Another form of survival possible to the poetic intelligence, and one

involving no definite break with the Zeitgeist (the family name of the

concrete intelligence), is for it to submit itself to a test of physical

endurance, that is, to produce a long poem. Contemporary efforts to make

the poetic absolute consist in sheer structural impressiveness have been

numerous. For example, Edith Sitwell's Sleeping Beauty, Aldous Huxley's

Leda, W. J. Turner's Paris and Helen, John Masefield's Reynard the Fox,

Alfred Noyes' The Torchbearers, Conrad Aiken's Pilgrimage of Festus, Roy

Campbell's The Flaming Terrapin, V. Sackville-West's The Land, William

Ellery Leonard's Two Lives or Edwin Arlington Robinson's Tristram can

account for their length in no other way.

Nature

Of the various escapes from the Zeitgeist open to poetry the

nature-escape offers the fewest obstacles. For, as to childhood, certain

privileges are granted to the nature-feeling, chiefly the privilege of

immaturity. Nature is that part of the universe which is at man's mercy

and is spared by him so long as it acknowledges his lordship. Man's

all-conquering mass-intelligence even permits nature to appear

humanized, to make the drama between innocence and intelligence more

vivid: nature is the world-as-universe's humorous indulgence of its own

contemporaneous childhood. For this reason the nature-mode arouses less

opposition in an environment hostile to poetry than other forms of

romantic escape. But innocence, of which nature is the quaint symbol,

presupposes that still quainter sophistication, irony. The irony of the

nature-mode in a latter-day atmosphere is the mature handwriting in

which innocence is written down; innocence cannot be put on record as

such without an intellectual bias in its favour. The nature-mode avows

intelligence even in forswearing intelligence: innocence is a conscious

means of direct escape from the Zeitgeist or of demure flattery of it,

of indirect escape.

The countryside element in late eighteenth-century poetry was inspired

by the panic into which certain poets were thrown when they suddenly

found poetry on its death-bed; they staggered to Nature's breast and,

giving her a philosophicodeistic piece to speak, begged her to use all

her eloquence to hold off the grim adversary. And though Goldsmith was

“ignorant” and Collins, Gray and Cowper only slightly more “reasonable,”

Johnson never damned them completely. They gave the age an opportunity

of justifying its intellectual refinements by comparison with a

contemporaneous infancy—the nature of the countryside being the stupid

foil to the intelligence of the coffeehouse. The nature of

twentieth-century poetry is the mouse which the lion spares to show how

savage he really is.

But however demure and submissive the nature-mode may appear, it is, in

its affected innocence, closer to active rebellion than any other form

of poetic escape: it is capable at any moment of romantic controversy,

of becoming the weapon of a new Zeitgeist against the old—a brief flush

of triumph, then dissolution, even at the hands of the new Zeitgeist.

Such, for instance, was the history of the late eighteenth-century

nature-movement that took off from Cooper's Hill and ended in myth, far

from home, among the Isles of Greece. It had had, or had seemed to have,

the choice of connecting itself retrospectively with a formal

uncontroversial nature-tradition or of converting nature into an

imagination which would be able to overthrow the autocratic, adult

regime of reason. In reality it had no choice but controversy. Close as

was the Cooper's Hill tradition, Sir John Denham was but an isolated

anachronism, a minor eighteenth-century nature-writer and moralist born

a century too soon. Milton was the closest classical figure who might

have constituted a literary inheritance, but his “nature” was a vulgar

conglomeration of bookish references. Besides these, all else was dim,

covered by the crooked shadow of the age of Pope. Pope himself made use

of the nature-mode, like many of his contemporaries, as a formalistic

reaction against the eccentric Elizabethan pastoral and its free

personal use of the classical pastoral, as by Spenser, Fletcher and

Browne; against the naturalness of the Elizabethan nature in general. In

the hands of writers like Pope and Ambrose Philips the pastoral became

an instrument of conformity with the Zeitgeist, a flattery of modernism:

though Pope professed Virgil as his model and Philips, Spenser, the

result was much the same in both. Their object was to stand Cooper's

Hill between the eighteenth century and the barbaric Elizabethans,

surmounted by the stern form of Milton (in the folds of whose robe were

concealed so many of the gems he had taken from these barbarians

because, presumably, they were too good for them). All that the literary

past could furnish, therefore, to the storm about to break was

provocation. Cooper's Hill may be regarded as the provocation to Keats'

little hill of nonsense, as Milton may be regarded as the provocation to

Blake's religious romanticism.

Militant romanticism is three parts defiance, one part constructive

innovation. Begun as a reaction against prevailing literary snobbisms,

it gives birth to new snobbisms, temporarily more tyrannical because

they are emotional rather than intellectual snobbisms: that is, they do

not merely conform to their Zeitgeist, they are part of it. It is

therefore destructive of literary traditions, having to break down some

to get at others which have been blocked—as Keats had to tear down two

whole centuries to get at the Elizabethan pastoral-writers; but socially

constructive, since the Zeitgeist is but a gigantic social movement; and

so eventually a constructive literary influence. For while the actual

productions of a romantic movement soon become absurd and lose literary

significance, it, in turn, through its social modernism, makes a great

many superannuated literary superstitions look absurd. The effect of the

Industrial Revolution, for instance, on romanticism was not only to

provide it with new subjects (literally so in the novel, as in Shirley,

Sybil and John Halifax, Gentleman), but also to create a new modern

feeling which the romantic movement helped to convey to literature.

Early nineteenth-century political humanitarianism, again, had a more

important influence on literature than the literary works of the

romantic movement itself. It replaced eighteenth-century social

definitions, which had existed in purely literary terms, with new social

definitions in political terms and thus temporarily deprived literature,

poetry in particular, of its social usefulness.

The amazing critical banalities of Wordsworth, the remote metaphysical

propositions of Coleridge, the socio-political doctrines of Shelley are

all part of an attempt to give poetry an eternal poetic usefulness. But

the contemporary man still overshadowed the poet who only happened to be

a contemporary man. The balance of influence was still with the

Zeitgeist. The difference, however, between the characteristic

eighteenth-century Zeitgeist and the characteristic early

nineteenth-century Zeitgeist is that one was a dead weight around the

neck of the poet, turning him into a literary drudge to society, the

other a form of mass-hypnotism in which the poet had at least the

illusion of freedom and voluntary participation in his time. Both were

immoral; the latter, however, had the merit of allowing the poet to

forget the mass-source of this hypnotism and to treat it as the

first-hand inspiration of the poetic intelligence. The only difference

that this made was, perhaps, in providing a less inhibited, if more

foolish race of poets. Keats, for example, was far more inhibited than

Shelley because he engaged consciously in literature and in literature

alone. He would undoubtedly have been more comfortable in the eighteenth

century: he was a better literary poet than Shelley (and than any other

poet of his time); though not a better poet.

The application of this history to the contemporary problem of the

nature-mode, to which it must return, may be slight. One thing appears

certain, that the nature-mode is not threatening to break loose into

militant romanticism. It flashes upon us that we are not the twentieth

century in the sense in which the eighteenth century, say, seemed to

have been the eighteenth century; that upon the assumption of a coherent

and peculiar Zeitgeist we have invented certain modes of escape from it,

and certain modes of coming to terms with it; and that the only result

is the increased vagueness of the Zeitgeist. Shall we give the

nature-mode a push in order to have, some time soon, a romantic movement

and a new modern feeling? Or shall we be classical in order to make the

Zeitgeist talk more clearly?

Oh, Zeitgeist, had we but a Borrow or a Melville to apostrophize thee in

the shameless manner of the 1840's! Thou art verily a sore weight and a

millstone about our necks, and we have not offended the little ones. As

a matter of fact, we are the little ones. Where art thou, Zeitgeist,

that we may hang the millstone about thy neck and cast thee into the

sea? The Zeitgeist is silent. Can it be possible that after all there is

no Zeitgeist?

IV: Poetic Reality and Critical Unreality

The critical problem, then, is not so much a matter of the proper

subjects or style-modes by which to ensure the integrity of poetry, as

the determining of where the true reality of the poem lies, whether in

the gross contemporary mind of which the poet is supposed to be

possessed, or in the non-contemporary poetic mind—for poetic must mean

non-contemporary if contemporary is understood as anything more than a

historically descriptive phrase, if it is used, for example, to describe

the mind as shaped by contemporary influences. If the distinction

between these two minds is carefully drawn, it will be seen that, in

times when the poetic mind has been under the dictatorship of the

contemporary mind, the poem has had only contemporary reality; as in the

eighteenth century, when the poem had a false poetic reality because the

social dictatorship was disguised in the literary dictatorship, and as

in the Victorian period, when the poem had a more obvious contemporary

reality. In the early nineteenth century the poem had a mixed reality;

the contemporary mind, in its caprice and inventiveness, imitating the

poetic mind.

If we observe what happens when the poem is confined to one type of

reality, to that of the contemporary mind, as in the eighteenth-century

satire, or to that of the poetic mind, as in the romantic abuse of the

poetic absolute, it appears that both of these are but half-realities

and that the true reality of the poem must have a double force: a

positive truth, from its origin in the poetic mind, and a negative

truthfulness, from the fact that it is not made unreal when brought into

contact with the contemporary mind, that is, with contemporary

knowledge. When the contemporary mind, or the concrete intelligence, or

whatever we please to call it, is seen to be no more, no less, than

accumulated knowledge-material, it will be realized how grotesque it is

that this should supply the creative origin, and hence the first reality

of the poem, leaving to the poetic mind the secondary service of

interpretation.

But the slaves of this knowledge-material can imagine no state of

activity which shall not be dependent on it; they cannot understand that

the poet can have experience of it as an independent mind reducing

authoritative mass to unauthoritative ideas; that once the mass of

intelligent matter is recognized as a mass of ideas about matter, every

man is potentially his own scientist, though not his own poet, since

only the poet is fully capable, in this way, of being his own scientist.

Therefore, if the poet shows independence, if he is, indeed, not a mere

mouthpiece of the contemporary mind, it is assumed by the

knowledge-slaves that he cannot have an informed mind; and everything he

writes is taken with a grain of scientific salt. This snobbism, which

naturally appeals to criticism, because it seems another indulgence by

which poetry may manage to survive, in turn drives poets who stand in

fear of the knowledge-hierarchy to profess only the single reality of

the poetic mind—what we may call the apologetic absolute. The result is

poetry whose only subject is the psychology of the poet and whose final

value is scientific; which is as it should be, since the snobbism

responsible for it tries to treat poetry as if it were a science.

Poetry of this kind thus finally comes to justify itself by an analogy

with mechanical reality. France and America provide numerous examples of

it. In America industry itself may be said to have an imagination and so

to furnish an instructive parallel to the creative mind faced with the

problem of employing itself. If it cannot have poems which shall have a

place in the world, perhaps it can have poems which shall have a place

in themselves, which shall end where they begin; if it cannot have

poetry, perhaps it can have purity. The machine is a practical symbol of

automatism and may be said to create itself as the psychological poem

does, to be its own product. Instead of possessing a life, such a poem

possesses a mechanism, a fixed emotional routine that may be called

absolute because its effect never varies. In France the analogical

element is provided to poetry by the mechanical principle of other arts,

by painting, principally by music. The aesthetic purity of the poem is

made to consist in its behaving like a machine, in imitating its making

and in maintaining an absence of meaning except as a non-conscious cause

and instrument of a conscious effect. The history of this theory lies

between Poe, in whom it was an amateur's attempt to defend the

independence of the poem on the grounds of its mere pleasure-reality,

and Paul Valéry and other musico-poeticians, who further develop the

pleasure-reality theory by transferring the centre of the poem from its

origin in the poet to its conclusion in the reader. Invention is

converted into reaction, poetry into criticism. The pure poem is arrived

at by subtracting the poem from itself. Only its limits remain, its

points of origin and of communication. The rest is a time and space

necessity between them, the place, presumably, which the poetic mind

leaves to be filled in by the contemporary mind; the myth, once more,

which the contemporary mind is supposed to suggest to the poetic mind,

but now a blank myth, since the contemporary mind believes itself to

have arrived at the all-in-all, that what is not itself is merely its

shadow.

If, in spite of the present surquidry of the contemporary mind and the

accidie with which the poetic mind is afflicted, it were possible to

conceive of the production of a true poem, to what should we look for

evidences of its reality? To those inner circumstances which make up the

poetic mind and which the poem is the means of externalizing, as the

poetic mind is the means of externalizing the poem, which hitherto

existed only unto itself. In this mutuality lies the real clue to the

double reality of the poem, its truth as a poem, its truthfulness as a

demonstration of the poet's mind. For we have now come to the point

where it is permissible to talk of the poetic mind as the poet's mind,

and of the poet's mind as the only contemporary mind possible in the

poem, its incidental reality. The poem itself is supreme, above persons;

judging rather than judged; keeping criticism at a respectful distance;

it is even able to make a reader of its author. It comes to be because

an individual mind is clear enough to perceive it and then to become its

instrument. Criticism can only have authority over the poem if the

poet's mind was from the start not sufficiently clear, sufficiently free

of criticism; if it obeyed an existing, that is, a past order of

reality, rather than a present order of reality, that is, the order of

the things which do not yet exist. How shall this true poem be

recognized? By those tests of reality it imposes on the reader; perhaps,

then, only by the strength of the hostility it arises and the extent of

its unpopularity even with the minority cults, or by its modest

contentment with itself and the obscurity to which it is consigned.

False poems, as distinguished from weak poems, are those written to

respond to tests of reality imposed by the contemporary mind and are

therefore able to satisfy them better than any true one. The creative

history of the false poem is the age, the author sensible of the age and

the set of outer circumstances involved in his delicate adjustment to

the age at a particular moment, in a particular place. Nothing remains

beyond this, no life, no element, as in the true poem, untranslatable

except in the terms provided by the poem itself. In the true poem these

terms form a measurement that hitherto did not exist, and the test of

the poem's reality is: to what degree is it a new dimension of reality?

Indeed, in the true poem poetry is the science of reality, so-called

science, itself the myth—the corpus of knowledge to which poetry has for

centuries been an inspired drudge, turning it into the sensible material

of a religious mysticism, a gross and flabby self-worship. Poetry, in

other words, has been the divine solvent converting knowledge into

truth, until knowledge, mad with its own modernity, declared itself the

sole source of truth. But if knowledge can dismiss poetry, can it

dismiss the poet? If the poetic mind was once the source of truth for

knowledge, does it cease to have truth because the corpus of knowledge

finds it no longer useful? In its primitive period of usefulness to

knowledge it was a superior knowing; itself truth, knowledge its

truthfulness: the true poem was at once truth and myth (truthfulness),

knowing and knowledge, reality and test of reality. But if knowledge is,

so to speak, composing its own monster-poem, has the poem as such

necessarily disappeared? Can minds and their perceptions be erased by a

piece of self-investigated india-rubber?

The word poem itself is an ever new meaning of an ever new combination

of doing and making as one act, with a third inference of being

perpetuating these in dynamic form. The only difference between a poem

and a person is that in a poem being is the final state, in a person the

preliminary state. These two kinds of realities, that of the person,

that of the poem, stand at one end and the other of the poet's mind,

which is but progressive experience made into a recurrent sequence

circulating between one kind of reality and the other without destroying

one reality in the other.

T. S. Eliot observed some time ago that “the conditions which may be

considered to be unfavourable to the writing of good poetry are

unfavourable to the writing of good criticism.”^(=> #calibre_link-21 20

) This implies that the reality of poetry is externally, not internally

derived. But though “conditions” may be unfavourably disposed to good

poetry, they cannot affect the writing of good poetry if there are poets

who insist on writing it. They can, however, affect the writing of such

poetry as is actually created by external contemporary conditions;

poetry, in fact, that is not poetry at all but the by-product of a

period's spiritual indecision. But such poetry is not a manifestation of

the poetic mind but of certain unhappy formations in the contemporary

mind acting as individuals whose task it is to present the signs of the

times rather than poetry.

We have, then, in a period when the Zeitgeist, the Old Man of the Sea,

is working particular mischief, a number of Sinbads drifting at large

whose fate it is to be at the mercy of his humours. They may either be

washed astride a breakwater (when their balancing gestures are called

criticism) or dashed over the sea wall into the Sacred Grove, where they

try to feel at home in spite of the Old Man on their back (when their

balancing gestures are called poetry).

When such contemporary formations are converted into creative or

critical personalities by Zeitgeist humours, a subtle strangeness will,

of course, be perceived in them. First something scarcely discernible,

except for the feeling of embarrassment it conveys—a faint, but distinct

foreign accent; next that dissociation or snobbism which a newly

converted Catholic feels toward the born Catholic, or the cabinet-maker

who has learned his trade at a school toward one who has inherited it

from his father. It is the self-conscious earnestness of an alien doing

his best to become acclimatized to his adopted country. Without that

natural endowment which makes the creative faculty indifferent to moral

justifications of itself (its moral justification being best presented

in a work), the chief preoccupation of the factitious creative

personality is with the moral values, or the legitimacy, of literature.

A blend is thus made of the creative and critical operations, resulting

in much interesting self-revelation (“good criticism”), but in too much

dull self-concealment in poetry, which comes to be the martyrdom of

lack-of-confidence-in-self. Mr. Eliot's axiom, therefore, which was

composed long before he was completely floored by the Zeitgeist, must be

brought up-to-date in this way: “The conditions which may be considered

favourable to the writing of good criticism may be considered favourable

to the writing of good criticism.” For in such language poetry is but an

incident of criticism. Mr. Eliot wrote several years ago: “Every form of

genuine criticism is directed toward creation. The historical or the

philosophical critic of poetry is criticising poetry in order to create

a history or a philosophy; the poetic critic is criticising poetry in

order to create poetry.”^(=> #calibre_link-22 21

) In a review of two books by two distinguished contemporary

personalities, Mr. Herbert Read and M. Ramon Fernandez, in the October,

1926, issue of the New Criterion (a community of contemporary

personalities), Mr. Eliot goes still further: “The significance of the

term critic has varied indefinitely; in our time the most vigorous

critical minds are philosophical minds, are, in short, creative of

values.”^(=> #calibre_link-23 22

)

Further characteristics of this snobbism, besides its preoccupations

with the moral values of literature, are its emphasis on personal

pedigree, learning and literary internationalism. The review referred to

above is so generous in examples of these that I cannot refrain from

using it as a text, nor indeed this entire number of the New Criterion,

which includes an essay by M. Fernandez himself beginning, “It is

pleasant for a French critic to write for the cultivated public on the

other side of the Channel”; a poem by Mr. Read himself, The Lament of

Saint Denis with a motto From the Institutes of Johann Lorenz von

Mosheim, translated by Archibald Maclaine (1764) and three foot-notes:

Inferno xxviii. 121–2, Paradiso: x. 94, and BoĂ«thius: De Consolatione,

II., vi., the learned if not the moral justifications for such lines as

And then a faint rumour in the night

An approaching murmur of enemies

Their hearts were suddenly loud in their still bodies

Fluttering wildly within those livid tunicles of flesh

(poor Mr. Read, likewise floored by the Zeitgeist, who in his less

contemporaneous days could write less ambitiously but more

authentically:

Judas was right

In a mental sort of way;

For he betrayed another and so

With purpose was self-justified.

But I delivered my body to fear—

I was a bloodier fool than he.);^(=> #calibre_link-24 23

)

and a poem by Mr. Eliot himself, Fragment of a Prologue, with two

mottoes, one from the Choephoroi, the other from St. John of the Cross,

the poem itself being a kind of epilogue to Ulysses, or Ulysses in the

Waste Land.

But the review itself is even more illuminating, especially as to the

love of pedigree, learning and literary internationalism: “Mr. Read and

M. Fernandez provide an excellent example of this invalidation of the

ancient classification” (critical and creative) because, the next

sentence continues, “They are of the same generation, of the same order

of culture; their education is as nearly the same as that of men of

different race and nationality can be. . . . Both were primarily

students of literature, and animated by the desire to find a meaning and

justification for literature. Mr. Read has the advantage of being

European and English; M. Fernandez that of being European and American

(he was born in Mexico). . . . Both are critics with international

learning and international standards.” All this to prove the

invalidation of that “ancient” classification.

It is improper to advance that criticism and poetry spring from the same

kind of personal impulse, unless it is made equally clear that they must

diverge at an early stage toward their respective positions. Criticism

and creation do not face the same way, but face each other, criticism

forgoing creation in order to be able to describe it. This purpose

demands learning in criticism, because it is thus the author not of one

poem, let us say, but of the history of one poem and another and another

(since when face to face with one poem the critic sees many others as

well); but it does not mean that criticism may be substituted for

creation, as would follow if that “ancient classification” were really

invalidated. The novel perhaps shows the danger of such a substitution

more clearly than any other kind of writing, being avowedly critical

rather than creative, historical rather than poetic: it is a description

of poetic reality by contemporary reality. Wherever the novel tries to

create poetic values, it becomes false art, as with Proust, Joyce,

Virginia Woolf and such American poetic novelists as Waldo Frank and

Sherwood Anderson. For, while the novel may suggest them or describe

them, it needs to be emphasized dogmatically that there are no true

creative values but poetic values—values which can be final without

reference to their contemporary setting. (This does not apply to the

poetical novel, to Borrow or Melville, poetical referring only to the

character of the style, not to the creative intention of the novel.) The

novel may be eminently true, or truthful, but it is not truth; and no

novelist who held his work in proper respect would claim it to be truth

except in this relative sense of truthful. If Mr. Eliot were not so

comfortably relaxing against the novel, “a capital point for every

contemporary mind (sic)”^(=> #calibre_link-25 24

) (to start from), evidently because it can be perverted to bring about

“this invalidation of the ancient classification,” he would perhaps

reject Proust with Mr. Read and M. Fernandez not so much because Proust

was wanting in the moral element as because he falsified the

novel—composing it synthetically of those infinitesimal morsels of

poetic reality by which the connoisseur's palate has had to appear

uniformly stimulated throughout that long, long from-egg-to-apple

dinner.

Proust recalls the snobbism of literary inter-nationalism, which has

provided Charles Scott-Moncrieff, George Moore and Ezra Pound among

others, with continuous employment. Any serious indictment of it would

only assist in prolonging the sufferings of the silent populations whose

palates were long ago exhausted by foreign banqueting but who go on

because the connoisseurs go on, who go on because they are at the head

of the table and cannot escape. Excepting rare instances of personal

sympathy with a foreign language arising out of associations, of

circumstance or temperament; excepting also such a unique case of

internationalism as that of America and England, where one is but a

historical layer of the other; any persistent cultivation of a

contemporary foreign literature is a snobbism inspired, apart from its

association with a general programme of literary snobbism, by a romantic

purpose to find relief from one dull literary scene in another—a form of

literary pornography. Nothing could be more alien to Mr. Eliot's

temperament, for example, than the sentiment and temperament expressed

in: “la littĂ©rature est impossible. Il faut en sorter” which he quotes

from Jean Cocteau's letter to Jacques Maritain on poetry and religion.

“International standards” of literature are a degraded critical

Esperanto and, like Esperanto, comprehensible only to Esperantists.

What unites littérateurs (the successors of the critics and creators of

“the ancient classification”) in this generation is, in fact, not

standards of taste or positive intellectual sympathy, but the feeling of

panic occasioned by the setting adrift of literature by the

time-universe. The reason why contemporary critics are so interested in

inquiring into the nature of the function of literature is not, as Mr.

Eliot suggests, because they do not wish “to take for granted a whole

universe,” but because a whole universe has given literature its

dismissal papers.^(=> #calibre_link-26 25

) Naturally endowed creative writers may protect themselves from the

present Zeitgeist or remain entirely unaffected by it. But those

sensitive spots in the contemporary mind to be identified as

littérateurs can neither avoid nor revoke the Zeitgeist nor yet cancel

themselves, since they are so organically of the Zeitgeist; and are thus

obliged to make a religion of their own posthumousness, a religion so

serious that Mr. Eliot himself calls it “an athleticism, a training, of

the soul as severe and ascetic as the training of the body of a

runner.”^(=> #calibre_link-27 26

) The asceticism on which it is based is the deprivation of the universe

which science has forced on literature; and the moral values implied are

the coward's promise to keep up his courage though all is lost.

The most redeeming and yet most unfortunate characteristic of this

snob-criticism is its seriousness. Unfortunate because by contrast with

the complete frivolousness or inaneness of all other contemporary

critical writing it is the only criticism that demands any respect from

the independent writer; and in this way likely to make him, in spite of

his independence, ingenuously shy of it, and of expressing his normal

reactions to the awful gloom that it has cast over the whole literary

scene. Such is the science of overwhelming by pomp. Even the London

Mercury would not if it could quiz the New Criterion, but would on the

contrary feel flattered to be counted amongst its colleagues.

The final effect of this snobbism is the deliberate cultivation of a

modernity, a calculated and therefore more “classical” quality (“We

live”) than mere crude romantic contemporaneousness (“I'm glad I'm

alive” or “I'm sorry I'm alive”). “A poem which was never modern will

not pass into that curious state of suspended animation by means of

which the poems we call classic are preserved active to the palate,”

said Edgell Rickword, Editor of the Calendar of Modern Letters, lately

next to the New Criterion the most serious community of contemporary

personalities.^(=> #calibre_link-28 27

) Thus poetic modernism, advertised by its own uplift, reaches the

poetry societies of the provinces, who by now have used up all their war

and post-war subjects and are grateful for a change. “At an evening of

the Bournemouth Poetry Society,” reports the Bournemouth Echo, “held at

Eight Bells, Christchurch, poetry enthusiasts (one came all the way from

Broadstone) were well rewarded by a remarkably live and able paper by

Mrs. Leslie Goodwin on ‘Further Aspects of Modern Poetry.’ Mrs. Goodwin

called attention to the unappreciated importance of the Left Wing or

extreme Modernist Group, who have new ideas as to what is appropriate

and beautiful.” For the Old Man of the Sea must have his joke.

“Modern,” however, is not a contemporary invention: it must not be

forgotten that the littérateurs of the characteristic eighteenth century

were likewise modernists and likewise invalidated “the ancient

classification.” Their poetry and criticism, although not born of the

same impulse, were written from the same point of view, which gave them

a mutual consistency if not a reciprocal power. Criticism became, then

also, a moral measurement: arbitrary judgments for arbitrary poetic

practices. Poetry was a critical convenience, criticism a poetic

convenience; the offspring of this union between them had that inbred

half-reality which is characteristic of present-day manifestations of

the contemporary mind in criticism and poetry. The period was a

“literary” period. It had been fitting, for example, for Milton some

time before, to dedicate Samson Agonistes to a campaign against what he

called the corrupt gratification of the people with “comic stuff,” and

to a classical conception and treatment of tragedy. It was fitting for

Whitman, long after, to justify Leaves of Grass by an exactly contrary

critical attitude: “that the real test applicable to a book is entirely

outside literary tests.”^(=> #calibre_link-29 28

) For, though both disregarded the meaning of poetic intention, one

accepted the authority of literature, the other that of life and

humanity. The authority of eighteenth-century literature was neither of

these, but a working compromise between them. Literature was the

rationalizing apparatus that added logic to morality; life, the literary

demonstration. This code expressed the temper of the age faithfully:

snobbism, or conformity of behaviour to a degree where nothing happened

at all, where important poetry was prevented from happening. Such

literary sterility caused a reaction in the next century, frenzied

fertility resulting in an unpedigreed stock. Although a fresh creative

basis was found, the preceding century furnished its literary ancestry,

which could be revolted against but not cast out of the blood. So poetry

was for a time a romantic misfit, until new critical values could be

found to match the new poetical values. In Keats we find many Pope-ish

echoes; as we find many nineteenth-century echoes in the poetry of Miss

Sitwell. Torn between her inherited Wordsworthianisms and

Tennysonianisms and her acquired Pope-isms, her poetry no less than

Keats' bears the marks of a conflict. Her nineteenth- century-isms (as

Keats' eighteenth-century-isms) it is possible to indulge because they

were inherited; likewise her Gallicisms, as a decorative relief to

these. But why should Miss Sitwell, with an abundantly endowed creative

faculty, find it necessary to praise The Rape of the Lock as a beautiful

example “of the fusion of subject matter and

style”?^(=> #calibre_link-30 29

) If not because prevailing critical snobbisms force the independent

creative faculty to strengthen its pedigree with artificial critical

values which, in turn, act as a kind of protective snobbism (as

Elizabethanisms did for Keats).

Nineteenth-century poetry, after a brief period of sentimental debate,

failed to develop any real critical values. Instead, it borrowed its

titles from the idea of progress, the philosophical demiurge of the

century, thus only changing one social god for another without the

disguise this time of a literary mask. The popular mode of mysticism

resulting from this religiosity was the intelligence—not the intellect.

The reason why the intellect is held anti-religious is that it is an

individual property rather than a social one and is therefore less

likely to accept as final the generalizations of the prevailing

community system of faith. Contemporary criticism is endeavouring to

elevate the mass-intelligence by making it behave like an independent

intellect, the effect of which is to rob the term intellectual integrity

of all significance. While “contemporary” eighteenth-century poetry

cannot be said to have had great intellectual integrity, it did make an

honest compromise between the general intelligence and the individual

intellect by postulating wit as the common raw material of literature.

However wit may be abused by being made to serve moral ends, it is in

itself an intellectual competence which is bound to protect itself in

some way against the uses to which it is put. Wit may indeed be called

the subject-matter of the best of eighteenth-century poetry, as human

wisdom forms the subject-matter of the worst of nineteenth-century

poetry.

In the earlier period there was at least wit to act as a basis, however

artificial, of critical values. In the later there was only a standard

of philosophical satisfaction demanding an unrestrained flattering of

every possible variety of human activity: poetry being the spiritual

sign of practical prosperity and advance, the personified muse of

optimism. For this later tendency Wordsworth's critical commonplaces

were principally responsible; which even modern writers find it

impossible to reject on the proper ground. Miss Sitwell, for example,

thinks that it is time to discard the Wordsworthian tradition, not

because it is fundamentally false, but only because it has grown dull in

the course of its development. It is time to leave “the peasant and

words suitable to the peasant.” That is, what poetry needs is a general

correction of taste, not an independence in which creative values have a

lack of conformity according to the variety of poetic minds (the use of

poetic mind as a critical abstraction is likely to make us forget that

it is a rather than the poetic mind). It is a telling piece of

well-meaning literary snobbism to call Wordsworth a peasant poet.

Wordsworth, like Miss Sitwell, wanted to “interest mankind” in the

proper way, “to correct the present state of the public taste in this

country.” “Humble and rustic life was generally chosen” because it made

a more fluid philosophical language for poetry: the peasant flavour is

only a literary manner, as that part of Miss Sitwell's own poetry which

is dedicated to taste is but the exploitation of a literary manner.

Wordsworth's poetry is no more fit for reading by peasants than Miss

Sitwell's is by princesses. Both have the view that poetry is a careful

annotation of life. To Wordsworth, poetry is “the spontaneous overflow

of powerful feelings”; to Miss Sitwell, it brings “new and heightened

consciousness to life.”^(=> #calibre_link-31 30

) Both have a purpose to deal with what she calls the “common movement

of life,” only “the modern poet has a different stylisation.”

Wordsworth, under the false mask of taste, made moral enlargements on

trivial subjects. The modern poet who, like Miss Sitwell, is not

overwhelmed by the world or made an instrument of the Zeitgeist, but who

in spite of his contempt for its blustering demonstration of power

clings to it out of an inherited and old-fashioned sense of duty, wastes

himself on that sentimental, self-sacrificing office which Miss Sitwell

calls “showing the world in all its triviality.”

So that present modernism is not even literary in the eighteenth-century

sense but a complex of pietist snobberies and sentimentalities.

V: Poetry and Progress

In spite of “the invalidation of that ancient classification” (between

the critic and the creator), to quote T. S. Eliot once more,

contemporary criticism shows certain survivals of the humble advisory or

research functions of criticism in the past: it continues to make a few

naive medical recommendations. On the one hand, we find the new universe

of science, the successor of the old politico-philosophistical universe,

forcing literature to retire or to show good cause why it should not or

to temporize in elaborate leave-takings. On the other, we find science

hopefully recommended as a new poetical subject. Even so presumably

modern a type as the intelluptuous Aldous Huxley still clings to the

superstition of subject-matter and, while regretting “the deplorable

traditionalism of subject-matter that weighs so heavily upon so much of

contemporary poetry,” reaffirms Wordsworthianism by suggesting new

subject-matter. Overlooking the fact that subject- matter has always

exhausted rather than nourished creative energy, he names science as the

proper modern subject for poetry and Laforgue as a poet who made real

poetry out of science, “science's only lyrist.”^(=> #calibre_link-32 31

) Now Laforgue is, as a matter of fact, one of the most non-subject of

poets. He did, indeed, attempt to make poetry a discursive record of

pure sensation—comme parlĂ©. His Complaintes are a series of satires on

subjects, an anthology of phraseologies; and science can only mean to

poetry one more phraseology. His intention was to give poetry complete

ideological freedom from subjects, to record sensation in its natural

sense-terms, in its immediate, or contemporary, associations, without

resorting to literary classification. Such poetry makes use of science

to help it invent special vocabularies, but it does not use science as a

subject. It would indeed be, in the scientist's opinion, romantically

unscientific. It is not “scientific” to speak of the sun as white as

tap-room spittle, or to speak of the moon as having its ears stopped

with cotton. It is merely the effort of an intellectually

non-intellectual intellect to describe contemporary emotions with

contemporary sophistication but with a classical affectation of

innocence. Such is the Anti-Reason of Paul Valéry and such is that

vocabularistic whimsicality or quaintness by which poets like E. E.

Cummings and Edith Sitwell inoculate themselves against the Zeitgeist—a

protective measure against the practical mentalism of their period with

which poets are always afraid of becoming emotionally infected.

Expressionism—and all super-realist movements may be classified as

expressionistic—is another typical recommendation, a starvation diet as

a protest against the tyranny of the material universe, a denial of the

potency of inorganic matter. Technically, expressionism admits no

distinction between the word and the poetic mind. The word, not the

mind, becomes the centre of poetic life. It acts without memory, without

equipment; it is completely unqualified, capable of expressing anything

it chooses at the moment to express. This autonomous quality of words

may justify itself in the academic nursery prose of Gertrude Stein, but

it is futile in poetry because, though words must be pure in poetry,

they cannot be blank. Expressionism therefore may have been valuable as

a temporary rest-and-diet cure, but in general it resulted in creative

depression. For as it is difficult for an invalid to resist technical

preoccupation with himself, so expressionism encouraged morbid egotism

and imbecile healthiness. Instead of transferring the creative centre

from the poetic mind to words, it should have concentrated on the

rehabilitation of the poetic mind, with words as the physical incident

of this mind. Words in themselves are as false a distinction as is the

body in itself apart from the mind.

Expressionism was merely one complete illustration of this unholy

alliance in which the Zeitgeist kills and criticism cures. It passed,

and the Zeitgeist is still killing, criticism still curing. The

expressionist objected to the destruction of the personal self in a

world becoming more and more material and externalized. So he shut out

the visible world and invented an abstract self to replace that self

which is only a product of the external world—the Zeitgeist-self.

Expressionism, or some similar movement of “objective” subjectivity, is

therefore likely to flourish when the Zeitgeist is patently destructive

rather than constructive, as in war- and post-war Germany. But the

expressionist is one thing, expressionism is another. The expressionist

is a personal victim, expressionism a critical device of the Zeitgeist

for allowing its victim to extinguish itself.

The pragmatic reality of the Zeitgeist and its criticism must be

assumed, as must that of anything by which the weakness of one set of

minds prevails over the weakness of another. All that can be said for

critics who serve the Zeitgeist is that some, the most stupid, know not

what they do. The critics who know what they do never stoop to critical

recommendation but consecrate their intelligence to the complete service

of the Zeitgeist. Poetry must not be assisted, it must conform. If it

cannot conform it must cease to exist, since it can only exist by a

kindly dispensation from the Zeitgeist. Zeitgeist intelligence, as it is

possessed by criticism, thus returns poetry to its primitive ritualistic

function of community revelation. In other words, it is the generalized

voice of social sentiment: as an independent personal attribute it is,

in fact, non-existent. It ceases to employ subject-matter not because it

has renounced its job as an inspired research-worker on matter that

philosophy, history and science could take no further, but because it

has been denied subjectivity and once and for all universalized; given,

instead of subject-matter in various stages of indigestion, the whole

self-digested substance of contemporary learning and asked to humble

itself before it in reverent self-revilement. First of all, of course,

searching itself to see if it is sufficiently pure, that is, if it has

really acknowledged itself a worm in its god's sight: in which

purification criticism condescends to assist by what is called

discovering to literature its function.

Science, then, as a critical recommendation for poetry is as irrelevant

as an attack on science for impeding the progress of poetry. For science

as agent of a period's mass-vanity is one thing and science as a small

historical item is another; and most contemporary views of science

overlook the second sense in favour of the first. Only the first is,

indeed, apparent, since science cannot afford to allow the second to

appear: never has it been more reckless, more blind, more disorganized,

more meaningless than at the present moment, never, therefore, more in

need of being accepted as truth instead of as a small though

authoritative corner of human knowledge. The best way to hide confusion

and flippancy is to declare a new life or age, to proclaim a Zeitgeist.

Poetry as creative truth is thus made to apologize for itself because,

being a personal attribute, it seems irregular and behind the times. The

advance of time as a universal force superior to persons left the time

of the individual far behind long ago. Intelligence, the historical

fallacy, is the philosophical means by which the individual makes his

literal time catch up with the figurative synthetic time of the totality

of matter. Advanced contemporary poetry is thus breathless with

scholarship—the Waste Land, a poem of four hundred and thirty-three

lines, has one learned reference to every eight of these; but it is not

breathless with intellect—there is no sign of intellect per se in the

Waste Land. For as soon as an independent mental act needs to

substantiate itself historically it ceases to be independent and it

ceases to be intellect. It is only rather evasively intelligent.

Such is the time-fear and such is the timidity of personal illusion

against gross illusion, or of common sense as individual wisdom against

the doctrinaire Common Sense of the knowledge-superstition. So does the

quantity of learning separate itself from its source and so does the

independence of the mind become the source of its own subjection. What

is being fed to poetry now is the dregs of what poetry itself has

produced, and produced long ago. Or, let us not say poetry, since it is

a word spoiled by self-abuse. More specifically: science or any similar

fetish of the concrete intelligence is a mere by-the-way of the

suggestive intelligence, or intellect, a digression that becomes more

and more irrelevant and wanting in meaning as it treats itself as a

whole instead of as an enlarged incident of the suggestive intelligence.

The nearer it seems to approach a whole, the more vain, the more blind

it will become, the nearer it is approaching collapse. Modern warfare is

only a small aspect of the decay of science, “scientific” spiritualism

another. Sooner or later, sooner than expected, science will confound

itself with its own successes and remain only an old-fashioned household

word. Its present prestige is due chiefly to its imperfection: when

every cure has been found for everything and every device for doing

everything has been invented and all the Florence Nightingale-sentiment

showered on scientists has been used up, it will be clear how much

sidetracked poetry went into the making of science. And poetry, as the

suggestive intelligence, will probably then make some new suggestion for

human energy at a loss as to how to employ itself; and will be once more

put in its place until this digression, in turn, wears itself out.

Meanwhile, however, science and its accessories are the new life and

poetry is the old, which must either acknowledge itself as dead or

consent to have itself kept alive by gland extracts, Viennese

rejuvenation treatments and radium, as a testimony of the power and

grace of science. There have been isolated and faint protests from poets

against Zeitgeist superstition, but in the main poets and especially

critics have grasped the possibilities of contemporary success in

Zeitgeist vanity and dedicated poetry to a display of its own

helplessness and to a vulgar flattery of the contemporary god, learned

matter. But how low in spirits and how full of humility! The only

joy-in-life left to contemporary Zeitgeist poetry is a little

half-hearted obscenity; and even obscenity must apologize for itself

with learning.

To propose that contemporary learning retards the synthesis always

implicit in poetry, to point out that it is science which is slow, and

not poetry, would confess a view of the nature of poetry incompatible

with the self—deprecating sophistication of present Zeitgeist poetry and

criticism; and immediately ally one with that sentimental adoration of

poetry common to clergymen, poetry societies, editors of weekly literary

reviews, anthologists, anthology readers, university professors,

business men, doctors and modern lyrical poets. To say, with Francis

Thompson, that poetry is always a hundred years in advance of science

would seem equally trivial, because Francis Thompson is not a

respectable literary reference, although his extravagance in paying

homage to an ancient dogmatic institution was more dignified than the

extravagance of contemporary poetry and criticism in paying homage to an

ephemeral, dogmatic Zeitgeist.^(=> #calibre_link-33 32

) In truth, advance is an unfortunate word: poetry does not advance

except in the sense that other things, such as science, are behind it.

There is no progress of poetry any more than there is a progress of

time. There is a progress of matter, but this is a permanent progress of

corruption.

Indeed, any attempt to look to a personal rather than to an academic

dignity in poetry will be set down to critical romanticism. Why

any-thing is less true than otherwise if it can be set down to critical

romanticism must remain a mystery. For snob-critics make a practice of

annulling the value of any statement detrimental to them by giving it a

name which relieves them of the obligation of replying to it directly.

(The late T. E. Hulme tried to rescue the artist from historical

difficulties by combining art and philosophy into a dry theory of

historical objectivity. Instead of delivering him up to time he brought

time inside the bounds of the creative system that he outlined. He

advocated a discipline that would control both time and the creator

through the impersonal severity, the absoluteness, in which artistic

forms might be conceived. The product of this “objective” objectivity is

therefore pure, hard, non-sympathetic. It is not intelligent: that is,

it is not materialistically interpretative, but material. It is not

emotional: that is, it is not imaginatively imitative but

unimaginatively representational. It is a non-human object. But such a

system results only in criticism, not in works. It expresses an attitude

toward time, protests against extraneous elements which have crept into

art, states the conflict between art and civilization, between creative

isolation and vulgarized originality. It shows the creator defeated by

progress taking refuge in a petulant barbarism.)^(=> #calibre_link-34 33

)

Social sentiment is the general source, conscious or unconscious, of the

“subjects” of poetry. Contemporary social interests may even, as at

present, deprive poetry of an old stock of subjects and, instead of

providing a new stock, require that the inspiration of poetry shall be

even its own poverty, its humble renouncement of worldliness after it

has been frustrated by worldliness. What causes a change, then, in the

official inspiration of poetry is usually not a revolt on the part of

poetry itself against the tyranny of social sentiment, but the

absorption of poetry by a new social sentiment, which uses it as an

aggressive weapon against the old. The extravagant modernism of poetry

at any particular moment is due not to its independent defiance of

superannuated social sentiment but to its excessive slavishness and

adaptability, by which it anticipates, and thus seems to invent, an

impending social sentiment about to make itself historically effective.

Literature, poetry in particular, is in this way an instrument for

dramatizing the historical conflict between an old social sentiment and

a new. It performs the work of transition which might otherwise be

accomplished with greater violence. Spiritual violence in poetry makes

the least tangible sort of wreckage, because the formal cathartic

process is considered natural to it and disintegrating forces in it

easily simulate catharsis; also because the superstition of form imposes

on it an artificial urbanity. It is difficult, besides, for the vanity

which so often goes with poetic powers to resist the occasions for

theatricality which the Zeitgeist drama provides.

So it is fitting that Mr. Edwin Muir should call a book dealing with the

work of characteristic writers of to-day

Transition,^(=> #calibre_link-35 34

) a descriptive term having to do with social sentiment rather than with

literary criticism; and that he should fail with those writers to whom

the Zeitgeist is not a literary clue, just where, in fact, literary

criticism is demanded. But the distinction between literary criticism

and social sentiment (Zeitgeist sentiment), between unconditioned poetry

and conditioned poetry, becomes vague when the snobbism of progress,

disguised as literary modernism, obscures the anarchic nature of

creative activity and tries to justify it to its time by showing that it

is an effect of history. In this normalizing and levelling of literature

to its age, any poet who does not seem to conform to the historical laws

of his age is rejected by social sentiment disguised as literary

criticism. Poetry is required to proceed not from an individual sense of

life but from a social sense of literature: it must emphasize the social

rather than the individual origin of creation. It must, that is, be a

vehicle of prophecy of the most brutally servile kind.

The revolt against nineteenth-century subjects was the sign that a new

social sentiment was preparing to displace the old, using literature as

a destroying agency, as it had been used as a constructive agency in the

beginnings of the Victorian period. (The sensitiveness of the creative

mind is thus seen as an accursed talent, since by it the poet may become

so open to influences that he ceases to create and is, instead, merely a

historical barometer; in periods of change the public-utility character

of creation is likely to overshadow completely its private character.)

The Victorian period consolidated a great many different sets of values

already loosely equated—economic values, religious values, moral values,

aesthetic values, and so forth. Social values were the general mean of

all these. Then material development began to demand a more flexible

social sentiment, a more “broad-minded” interpretation and

differentiation of values. Literature made the first efforts at formal

differentiation by attempting to separate moral values from aesthetic

values.

The effect of playing this historical role was to make literature

digress first into pure sociology, continuing in this century in such

anachronisms as Butler, Shaw, Wells, Galsworthy and finally D. H.

Lawrence (an instance of contemporary Rousseauism); then into an

anti-social orgy of third-rate decadence—both of these resulting from

the differentiation of moral and aesthetic values. The virtue, however,

of both literary sociology and literary decadence is that sooner or

later they must write themselves out. The former lasted longer because

it is more congenial to the Anglo-Saxon temperament, the latter died out

soon after it was contracted from French decadence. In the English

’nineties there was no decadence anywhere except in literature. In

France, on the other hand, there is always decadence, it is the great

national genius and source of life. The French have, indeed, a natural

aptitude for decadence; it is in them a sign of health. The underlying

theme of all French literature, romantic and classical alike, is

Decline, and all French writers of excellence must begin by falling in

love with Decline. This is why French criticism has no difficulty in

reconciling contradictory literary movements, since they are all in

agreement on at least one point.

So it is pitiful to think of Arthur Symons, a feeble English decadent,

making brotherly advances to such healthy French decadents as Baudelaire

and Laforgue. The sociologists, though here and there slightly infected

with decadence, were for the most part healthy, cheerful and good.

William Morris and Edward Carpenter were the early poetical writers of

the sociological movement, whose literature soon, however, lost its

poetical tinge and became propagandist, journalistic, scientific,

philosophical or witty. Doughty was perhaps the writer who paid least

attention to contemporary social sentiment. Even Hardy was contaminated,

on one side by historical mysticism, rural economy and the divorce laws,

on the other by the same decadent, sentimental suicidism which made

Barrie, because he was Scotch, simply a pretty writer. The decadents

were divided into two classes, the sad people, the bad people. Among the

sad people were Thomson, Dowson, Davidson, Middleton and O'Shaughnessy,

who may all be described in the adjective invented by Max Beerbohm for

Enoch Soames: dim. The bad people were the unmentionables who collapsed,

too weak for vice, at the feet of the Zeitgeist.

Though literary sociology survived literary decadence, it soon merged

with non-literary forces; and though literature continued as one of the

minor branches of social intelligence, poetry as idiosyncratic creation

officially disappeared. What literature did persist was unimportant, as

there was now no historical reason for its being otherwise. In the

Victorian period literature had been an instrument of hypocrisy. When a

more liberal rationalism succeeded Victorian rationalism, literature

became merely an instrument for confessing hypocrisy, especially poetic

hypocrisy. One doubtful result of this was that the quality of poetry

went into other kinds of writing and effected a great revival of wit in

the sophisticated novel and essay. Sentimental reactions to the passing

of poetry then occurred, without the attendance of criticism, in great

variety—Georgianism, Imagism, Vers Librism, lyricism, all too wanting in

originality or direction to survive their own enthusiasm. At last

criticism was awakened by the voice of the new Zeitgeist, which was one

in which the only social excuse that could be found for poetry was in

its renunciation of its non-tribal, personal attributes. But as the new

universe in which this perfunctory occupation had been found for poetry

had no real need even for a formal act of renunciation by it, criticism,

in evoking a new social sentiment, was asking for a hypocrisy in poetry

more inexcusable than Victorian hypocrisy, which was at least the result

of a real social need. Worse still, not only was poetry called upon to

exchange private poetic reality for public contemporary reality, but

even the contemporary reality of the time-universe was received

second-hand. For the time-universe having haughtily dismissed poetry,

criticism was obliged to invent an analogical universe, a sort of

scholastic image before which poetry could perform its prostrations.

As in any time there exist a number of unclassified minds capable of

much but wanting in personal differentiation, such an equivocal

definition of poetry opens up for them an unlimited opportunity for

converting want of person into ritualistic impersonality. In this manner

does the disintegration of poetry as a thing of poets make poets of

minds that had otherwise been nameless thought-mechanisms. The

mechanistic side of contemporary Zeitgeist poetry is shown in its

complete lack of form in any organic sense—though it maintains an

automatic convention of formality. It is obliged to forswear all

personal reality (unless it can be classified as “psychological”), to

submerge itself in contemporary realism, to employ a learned ritual in

which contemporary data are left unpoetized, that is, as in their final

stage of truth. This definition of poetry is further observed by

reviving previous literary rites, though rejecting the various

historical realisms with which they were connected for the present

realism: uniting the historical past and the historical present in one

expanded social sentiment, an authoritative snobbism against creative

personal eccentricity. The official seriousness and dignity of this

sentiment acting as literary criticism is likely to obscure the fact

that it is but the old snobbism of non-poets (literary poets) against

poets (non-literary poets).

VI: The Higher Snobbism

The true relations between society and poetry are concealed by a number

of reciprocal snobbisms which maintain an armed peace between them. It

is the strength of snobbisms to be never at war with one another. The

original snobbism in these relations obviously came from society. The

poet was a man apart, foolish but tribally useful, and regarded with

that half-fear and half-contempt which the executive or active members

of a community tend always to have for the divining or reflective

members. If we imagine the poet in an extremely unsuspicious attitude

toward his official rĂŽle, we can see him as being probably without a

retaliative or protective snobbism. But as society comes to depend less

and less on the poet, as he is supplanted by patriotism, formal learning

and other instruments of community self-reliance, his official dignity

turns into a mere decorative social survival. Society loses fear of him,

retaining only tender contempt. And the poet himself therefore

emphasizes more and more the eccentric personal character of poetry and

sets up a counter-snobbism, a pride in weakness and eccentricity, which

plays on certain ancient superstitions about poetry that still survive.

The formal corpus of these superstitions by which poetry remains a minor

religion to society is criticism. Society represents practicality,

against which poetry protects itself by cultivating an atmosphere of

unpracticality. For society spares what is unpractical if it is made

poetical. And the poet keeps up his illusion of self-respect under a

cloak of salvaged history and legend, a Joseph's coat, a patchwork quilt

of fact and fancy that grows a little shabbier from generation to

generation, from age to age. Keats so fancied himself in the priestly

Joseph's coat that he sacrificed himself to ambition, writing according

to a layman's idea of how a poet should write, catering to society's

snobbism toward poetry and to poetry's protective snobbism toward

society. Many another independent genius has been led astray by the same

flamboyant appeal.

Here within the ranks of poetry itself a reaction occurs against its

increasing effeminacy and, without discarding their ancient

prerogatives, poets enter into friendly competition with society in the

manly arts. But this remains a subordinate snobbism, the signs of growth

of shame and of decay. The whole snobbism by which poetry first came to

terms with society is a gross snobbism still obtaining where poetry and

society have not yet caught up with the Zeitgeist, or sometimes even

continuing, from literary habit, where they have. Although the

knowledge-display in advanced contemporary poetry has other more

important explanations, it is to a small degree a survival of the

superstitious practice of allusion, the Golden Bough supplanting the

Historical Library of Diodorus Siculus, the Bestiaries, Ovid and so

forth.

The next step is the breaking away, from the professionalism of the

gross snobbism, of individual poets or groups of poets; whose

counter-snobbism to the gross snobbism is their amateurishness, and to

society a snobbism against its acquiescence in the gross snobbism. These

amateurs protect themselves by exquisiteness: Pre-Raphaelite

exquisiteness is a genuine example of non-professionalism in the

Victorian period, Pater-Ruskin exquisiteness (to be counted as poetry

because it was “poetical”) a spurious one, being Victorianism in exotic

trappings. In the end the gross snobbism generally reabsorbs the amateur

snobbism by means of criticism.

Soon, however, society reaches a stage of such self-importance that it

feels it beneath its dignity to carry on any longer its tender play with

poetry. It abandons its snobbism of tolerance towards poetry and, except

that small portion of contemporary society which remains slightly in

arrear of the date, drops it out altogether. Poetry in the old sense

nevertheless continues to live, principally on memories, still wielding

its anachronistic gross snobbism against an imaginary snobbism of

society, still relying on criticism to make it socially effective.

In theory, poetry has officially passed. A new universe without poetry

might be expected. But instead a new criticism arises to proclaim poetry

because there is no poetry, a criticism which shares the new universe's

atavistic hunger for poetry. A poetry results that has a paradoxical

reality, the contemporary reality which denies poetry's rights to

existence, as having only a private personal reality or an official

unreality—both equally unreal when viewed historically. This new poetry,

born of the new criticism, attempts to placate the Zeitgeist by

abandoning all the superstitions by which the old poetry prolonged its

life, and by using against itself all the snobbisms that have ever been

held toward poetry, including the last conclusive one, that there is no

more poetry—all forming the higher snobbism, poetry's snobbishness

toward itself. For creation it substitutes a philosophical life in the

Zeitgeist; for inspiration, criticism—the anti-poetic metaphysics of

this life. Criticism and creation thus at last become single in act and

in effect, immediately responding to social sentiment without

intervening reflections or ecstasies. We are returned once more to the

fitness of Mr. Eliot's observation on “the invalidation of that ancient

classification” (between critic and creator).^(=> #calibre_link-36 35

)

But although poetry in the old sense has theoretically passed, the

personal idiosyncrasy that makes the poet cannot pass. Poetry

quantitatively viewed is a social product; and one kind of social

product may be superseded by another. But poetic power can only come

from individuals and can only be superseded by itself in individuals.

There are poets and there are authors of a social product, who are not

poets. Contemporary thought tends to make all contemporary poetry a mere

social product, handing over the task of invention to the higher

snobbism. It unclasses the poet proper because his work might or might

not form part of the social product. The ideal author of the social

product is a correct citizen of his age. If the poet proper happens to

have contemporary taste as well as poetic power he innocently becomes a

spokesman for the higher snobbism.

Miss Sitwell, for example, unconsciously explains what the higher

snobbism is really pining for: the respectable freedom of

eighteenth-century literary Whiggery, where poetry could refine social

sentiment without being forced to be poetry, where it could be

professional without allying itself to the gross snobbism of romantic

professionalism and where a minor criticism, at one with a minor poetry,

could act as a social check against the poetry of a vulgar major

criticism, against the gross snobbism. The higher snobbism is, in fact,

in agreement with the new anti-poetic universe only in that it wishes to

disconnect itself from the gross snobbism: even to disown poetry and

substitute letters, in which poetry and criticism may be united if the

contemporary intelligence is accepted as the philosophical life

inspiring both. The higher snobbism is even willing to recommence a

corrected poetic tradition, with the poet deprived of all those powers

and privileges which in the beginning laid the foundations of the gross

snobbism. If the poet is, it says, deprived of all the social importance

granted him for being a poet, he will lose vulgarity; he will be part of

a process, not a process in himself. He will not be a blustering,

despised genius but a haughty, respected mechanic of contemporary

thought.

Poetic power may even, as in Miss Sitwell's case, substitute taste for

itself in order to be protected from the higher snobbism; it transfers

itself from the tradition of personalities to the tradition of periods.

This unnatural emphasis on periods rather than on poets has the effect

of exaggerating the significance of poets who count for next to nothing

in the tradition of personalities. What real sympathy can exist between

the kangaroo Sitwell and the duck Beddoes? Yet Miss Sitwell is drawn to

him: he is as close as she can come in the nineteenth century to her

chosen literary past. He was one of the few eighteenth-century men of

the first half of the nineteenth century; that is, he got as close to

the eighteenth century as an early nineteenth-century character could.

The closest he could get to the eighteenth century was the late

Elizabethan drama, which he wrote like an eighteenth-century writer.

Like Miss Sitwell he saw the problem of poetry as a problem of taste

rather than of personality, the continuance of poetry as the continuance

of the right tradition. He therefore picked up the Elizabethan drama

where the eighteenth century left off with it—the eighteenth century

never went much further in it than Shakespeare's lesser comedies and

histories. Miss Sitwell finds herself an associate of Beddoes in

literary heraldry; he is a fellow modernist carrying on with her, to

quote Miss Sitwell, “the great tradition leading from the Elizabethans”

in such lines as

Old Adam, the carrion crow,

The old crow of Cairo;

slightly misquoted (or modernized?) by Miss Sitwell as

Adam, that old carrion-crow

Of Cairo.^(=> #calibre_link-37 36

)

By thus naming herself with gentlemen rather than geniuses she puts

herself beyond the suspicion of the higher snobbism; she makes herself a

subject of the minor criticism, the criticism of breeding, rather than

of the major criticism, the criticism of personality. Personality, Miss

Sitwell would agree, is the glory of the commoner, and every charwoman a

subject of the major criticism. In the contemporary situation the poet

has to be either a Beddoes or an elevated charwoman: he boasts either a

sense of literature (of time) or a sense of life—if the latter, he is an

ostracized vulgarian of character.

The weakest point in the higher snobbism (and its criticism) is that in

attacking the gross snobbism (and its criticism) it loses all sense of

differentiation. Not only must a poet choose categorically between being

a higher snob or a gross snob, because the minor criticism makes only

these two large critical generations; but in its desire to destroy the

gross snobs of contemporary literature it condescends to excuse certain

poets of the past of gross snobbism, also certain contemporary poets who

profess the gross snobbism, but as in the past—to excuse anyone, that

is, who may be used against contemporary gross snobbism.

The minor criticism can therefore tolerate Dr. Bridges and Mr. Kipling

better than it can some one who is a gross snob and a modern as well or

some one who is a modern and, though not a gross snob, still not a

higher one. It is only a matter of time until the higher snobbism adopts

Tennyson, to take him away, as everything it can lay its hands on, from

the gross snobbism. Thus Miss Sitwell, in attacking Mr. Alfred Noyes,

Mr. J. G. Squire and Mr. Edward Shanks and the whole Yellow Press of

poetry, falls back into the arms of Wordsworth. For she has, for the

moment, in her hatred of contemporary gross snobbism, forgotten or

forgiven it in the past. Because, as she learns from De Quincey,

Wordsworth “was abominated and insulted until 1821, when he was

fifty-one years of age, and barely tolerated for another ten years,

until he was sixty-one,” Miss Sitwell for the moment sees him as one of

the higher snobs.^(=> #calibre_link-38 37

) He appears to her to have been a victim, a victim, she concludes, of

the gross snobbism and of the major criticism. This of the Wordsworth

who so hastily retracted his adolescent Jacobinism; that “poly-hedric

Peter” damned by Shelley, a higher snob in comparison with him, in all

his sides; who accepted homage from that London “Where small talk dies

in agonies”; whose drift from the first was “To be a kind of moral

eunuch”; whom the Reviews

who heaped abuse

On Peter while he wrote for freedom,

So soon as in his song they spy

The folly which soothes tyranny,

Praise him, for those who feed ’em.^(=> #calibre_link-39 38

)

(“Praise him”—W.'s poetry cordially praised in Blackwood's, 1817); of

whom even Keats in 1818 dared to write: “It may be said that we ought to

read our contemporaries. . . . But, for the sake of a few imaginative or

domestic passages, are we to be bullied into a certain philosophy

engendered in the whims of an Egotist?”; whom Keats disliked for his

great-poet snobbism toward him, his conservatism, his flattery of

influential persons, his dressing up to dine in a stiff collar “I am

sorry that Wordsworth has left a bad impression wherever he visited in

town by his egotism, vanity and bigotry”; yet whom Keats continued to

consider a literary king; who in 1813 was appointed Stamp-Distributor

for Westmoreland by the Regent, in 1815 published his first collective

edition, by 1817 was taking part in “immortal dinners”; who became J.P.

for Westmoreland in 1819 and was kindly entertained in 1820 at both

universities. All this occurred during a period in which Miss Sitwell

considers Wordsworth to have been “abominated and insulted,” apparently

by the Yellow Press of major criticism. The abomination, as a matter of

fact, came from Keats, Shelley, Coleridge and other exponents of the

gross snobbism in which, it appears, there are degrees of honour and of

sense of calling. In her anxiety to make her case against the Yellow

Press fool-proof Miss Sitwell mistook Wordsworth for her kind of snob,

which is doing a monstrous injustice both to herself and to the higher

snobbism.

Literature, whose authority lay in the special privileges granted it by

society, had nothing to fall back on when society, finding literature no

longer socially useful, withdrew these privileges. It had no separate

confidence, no sense of life as an individual resource: life had been

delivered to literature en masse in each age as contemporary philosophy.

Direct communication with life without the intervention of society had

been gradually disappearing since the Elizabethans, so that literature,

when it lost caste, could be neither disdainfully indifferent nor openly

aggressive; it had to agree and yet not agree, surrender and yet not

surrender—to survive by brilliant equivocation. The poet who did not

wish to come to blows with the Zeitgeist had no other alternative than

to become a snob. The snob is one who defeats circumstances which are

against him by not committing himself; one who adopts a strategical

position which he does not have to defend because its strategy is so

obscure that it is not attacked.

If, then, in spite of everything, literature was to go on at all, it had

to be wilfully modern; it had to coincide with its age not by the

accidents of personal authorship but by a calculated critical method.

Aristotelianism brought up-to-date could therefore settle the problem of

contemporary reality for literature better than any new philosophical

solution. In revised Aristotelianism, or neo-realism, reality is the

final, determining cause and substance that invents all attitudes to it.

A poem, as expressing a quality of final reality, is thus little more

than automatic effect and the creative mind merely a post-event position

of reality. The author of a poem is consequently without personal

reality, or responsibility—another important article in snobbist belief.

In such an aesthetic the prevailing system of knowledge becomes the

self-knowing Reason. Science is the modernized Self of reality (T. S.

Eliot's thomistic God); not Baconian science, which was merely a human

method of knowledge, but science as sophisticated substance superior to

time and space qualifications, which are the marks of nonsensical,

poetical facetiousness in humanity. Advanced contemporary poetry is, as

may be verified, facetious, poetical and full of sophisticated nonsense:

poetic snobbism is directed chiefly against the humanity, the

infantilism, of the poetic mind. And poetry excuses itself by giving

itself this ironic title: “The Private Life of the Atom, A Dream

Fantasy.” Poetry must, that is, be a joke at its own expense, a mature

exercise in juvenility. It must no longer live in the time when

Life went a-maying

With Nature, Hope and Poesy.^(=> #calibre_link-40 39

)

It must rather approach that informed but idiotic bird-wittedness which

is the chief charm of the nursery-rhyme. Mr. Eliot's Waste Land is the

great twentieth-century nursery rhyme. And, like the nursery rhyme, this

poetry dispenses with that burden of continuity and sentimental

intelligibility implied in an audience. The poet renounces his

citizenship in gross humanity and joins that dim social class which

lives in the genteel retirement of a few superior critical journals. The

only way out for a poet who does not wish to avail himself of the social

privileges of his calling, or yet abide in the public maytime

reservations still set aside for poets by the modern world out of an

inherited sentiment, or yet submerge himself mystically in gross

humanity, is to disguise himself as a buffoon; so that his contempt of

the complicated snobbisms which paralyse all normal poetic instincts and

his own casual cultivation of these instincts may pass for simpleness

and he be left to his own devices.

It is easy enough to show historically how such a snobbism has arisen.

It is not quite so obvious where the snobs come from, how they are

provided. Does the snobbism make the snobs, or the snobs the snobbism?

Are the snobs natural snobs or have they been converted to snobbism by

contemporary pressure? I think it may be safely ventured that the

snobbism was implicit in the Zeitgeist, but that it became an effective

snobbism because social development at the same time discharged a class

which found this snobbism a useful refuge from historical necessity. The

disintegration of the aristocracy left a great many human loose ends who

formerly would have been happy as patrons of literature or as gentle

amateurs. Deprived of class rank they are now able to keep class rank by

the practice of literature. Likewise the farm-boy who formerly achieved

gentility by becoming a priest or a scholar now achieves it by

practising the higher snobbism in poetry and criticism. The attraction

of the higher snobbism as a social aristocracy is naturally felt by the

poet who, living in an environment hostile to poetry, sees it also as an

intellectual aristocracy holding out to him the promise of freedom from

a vulgar age and of consolation in a congenial society. And so have many

spirits bold and true been led astray and driven to belie themselves.

For less than any-thing is the higher snobbism an atmosphere congenial

to poetry. It is, more than anything, the complete eighteenth century

increased in all its manners, most of all increased in Frenchness.

After Frenchness it is increased most of all in Classicism. These

arrivistes, by regarding the universe as completed in effect and by

covering it with a thin coat of historicity, have achieved an immediate

aesthetic absolute. If the end has been reached, then every act is

posthumous and has a posthumous finality; and it becomes the function of

literature to prolong this finality indefinitely. The age is

philosophically conclusion on the brink of conclusion. The serenity of

classicism has always derived from an underlying historical

posthumousness, as the turbulence of romanticism from an underlying

pre-natalism.

Only one thing stands in the way of perfect posthumousness, a slow and

irregular population-mass which is always arriving late, and so

interfering with the higher snobbism's complete view of finality, even

forcing the higher snobbism to make a few mistakes in calculation. If

everything could be classically classified as science, the literary

expression of finality would be simple enough, for science is so far

advanced into itself that it is already in its literary stage. But

unfortunately certain elements of contemporary life, such as politics,

remain backward and stubbornly human. It is just here that the higher

snobbism is likely to commit regrettable errors of judgment, being

equipped to interpret nothing but finality, and to be wholly unable to

make an intelligent choice between one relative fact and

another—between, say, Communism and Fascism. Yet for the most part, the

contemporary and snob succeeds in keeping himself away from the

population-mass, which is not the Zeitgeist but the dregs of many

Zeitgeists; from anything, in fact, which looks like sentimental

rescue-work of the floating wreckage of time. As far as possible he

wants to rid himself of the pathetic errors of personality and make the

creative operation a pure critical reflex, free of error. Now nothing

can be free of error unless it is entirely negative; Ulysses is in this

way a great snob-work because it is a synthesis of as many negative

forces as could be assembled in a given time-limit. In poetic form the

result of removing subjective determination is a minimum of originality

and a maximum of freakishness. A great quantity of false aesthetic

material may thus be disposed of and the values generally used to

animate such material permanently discredited. But when this snobbism,

this fear of error, has done its work, what is left? Does there remain

any ground for independent creative activity, for a positive poetic

life? In the modernized quantitative cosmos of the Western mind, in this

blight of perfection, where is there room for new errors? There is room

for nothing but an empty philosophical absolute, whose hypothetical

reality the negative, qualitative cosmos of criticism derives from the

quantitative cosmos.

This is the dreary situation which the higher snobbism has brought about

by expelling error from art. For with error went works in the sense of

personal authorship, since works were imperfect because of authorship;

and for works criticism had therefore to substitute philosophy.

Criticism is left with nothing to talk about but its prejudices; and so

it becomes more dogmatic, more formalistic, more obscure and more free

from error from day to day. Even the poetry written by the higher

snobbism can only be, by its very perfection, a form of criticism

composed by the whole snobbist machine, a philosophical but not an

aesthetic act. And even as criticism it must fail because it borrows its

aesthetic terms from philosophy, the logical enemy of any creative

principle, since it is opposed to any really real absolute. Philosophy

is the religion that fills the critical senses with illusions of

purified reality when ordinary human reality is, for one reason or

another, under a cloud. It is therefore the principal consolation of the

contemporary and snob and allies him with that long and aristocratic

line of literary defeatists who have always protected poetry from the

facts and errors of life by allowing criticism to substitute poetics for

persons. What the higher snobbism wants above all things is consistency.

Theoretically it can get consistency by conforming to the Zeitgeist,

which has in this age so separated itself from the human population-mass

and advanced so far beyond it that it is free of those imperfections

which spring up in any system when it begins to be humanly assimilated.

Never, in fact, has philosophical reality (for the Zeitgeist, or

contemporary reality, is only philosophical reality) been further

removed than at present from human reality, which for this reason seems

more inconsistent than ever. The more systematic philosophical reality

becomes, the greater the breach between it and human reality; the more

inconsistent, in fact, it becomes itself. The illusion of consistency in

philosophical reality is due to its inhumanity, and its perfection is

merely a proof of its irrelevance. To be humanly consistent and

philosophically consistent in a single stroke one would have to conform

to neither human nor philosophical reality; one would have to be, in

other words, an irregular genius capable of an act of creative

consistency from which both realities could be simultaneously derived.

This would mean the brutal victory of the person over numbers and their

abstraction. But the higher snobbism spurns victory; it considers the

person a sentimental vulgarity; and it does not want to have anything to

do with numbers except through the mediation of philosophy, which deals

only in perfected social abstractions of incomplete, sluggish humanity.

And here it rests.

The person in poetry began to lose standing because the poetic faculty

came to be identified with a set of poetical sensations which may be

summarized as sentimentality. So much of the private personal data

involved in the making of poetry had been vulgarized and divulged by the

influx of confused and high-strung democratic elements, that the

gentlemen of poetry disclaimed the poetic faculty in order to avoid

writing unladylike poetry: the ribaldry of Eliot, Cummings and Joyce are

instances of this conscientious effort on the part of gentlemen-authors

to avoid the temptations to sentimentality inherent in the poetic

faculty; this effort, that is, to be ladies. Suppressed ribaldry in

gentlemen-authors, as in Miss Marianne Moore and Miss Edith Sitwell,

generally means that the temptations to sentimentality have been yielded

to, though without vulgarity: in Miss Moore's poetry by putting

sentimental poetic subjects under a cold shower of prose-language and

prose-technique, in Miss Sitwell's by abducting sentimentality to that

strange still-life land of metallic fruits and decorous kitchen-gardens

in which it would be difficult for anything to be vulgar.

But not only did poetry reach a stage where it was impossible to write

with taste without observing a large number of critical taboos; the

language of criticism itself had become so vulgarized that its dearest,

most cherished property rights in its key-words, such as Imagination,

Beauty, Truth, Feeling, became meaningless. Criticism had therefore to

withdraw itself from this vulgarized poetry and this vulgarized language

of criticism, which had originally been taken over from philosophy.

Gentleman-criticism and gentleman-poetry now worked hand in hand,

criticism refreshing itself once more in the fount of philosophy, poetry

learning at the feet of criticism a new code of thoroughly censored

behaviour by which it became an impeccable though obscure intellectual

observance. The fount of philosophy at which criticism refreshed itself

was the Zeitgeist, the philosophical aggregate of the age. But the

Zeitgeist is never an exact historical equivalent of the age, in some

ages less so than in others; the less so as knowledge-material becomes

more and more systematized. The Zeitgeist of the early nineteenth

century was an approximate historical equivalent of its age because

contemporary knowledge-material was disorganized and therefore humanly

realistic. There was one whole fixed Zeitgeist throughout the Middle

Ages because of epistemological over-organization and rigidity; the

geographical succession of Renaissance Zeitgeists and their human

relevance was due to the breakdown of this very rigidity. There is as

much difference between the human relevance of the present Zeitgeist and

that of the Platonic Zeitgeist as between the distance of the Phaedrus,

let us say, from the average person of 360 B.C. and the distance of the

Theory of Relativity from the average person of 1927.

The present Zeitgeist is, indeed, a Renaissance Zeitgeist with an

abnormally low degree of human relevance as a philosophical aggregate.

Nor would it be pertinent to object that this cannot be so, since

philosophy as such has disappeared. Philosophy seems to have disappeared

only because knowledge has become more philosophical, more systematized:

the Zeitgeist is nearly entirely without human relevance. Its

irrelevance, in fact, means that in a human sense it is without system,

that it has a forced systematism to disguise its internal inconsistency.

Actually any system of knowledge at a given moment has as much

inconsistency as there is inconsistency in humanity at that moment;

which is just why a system of knowledge is a philosophical tyranny and a

historical falsehood. If, however, the Phaedrus and the Theory of

Relativity were treated as independent human acts, consistent in

themselves but of human inconsistency, then they could exercise no more

tyranny than could a fine, elaborate poem. Instead, because they are

presented as systems, neither Platonism nor modern science ever become

effectively real, as a poem can, but merely literary, as Platonism

survives in vague Truth-and-Beauty terminology, and as science, which

becomes literary very quickly, reaches humanity in electrical devices,

cancer cures and radio-entertainments, which are purely literary

manifestations of science.

What, then, is the code which contemporary criticism, bathing in the

perennial and ever-changing fount of philosophy, the Zeitgeist, delivers

for the benefit of that impeccable though obscure intellectual

observance? Can it be that the social backing of contemporary poetic

gentlemanliness is only, after all, a gloomy medley of scholastic

anthropology, spaded Freudianism, Baroque Baedeckerism, sentimental

anti-quarianism, slum-and-boudoir philology, mystical Bradleyanism,

tortoise-shell spectacled natural history, topee'd comparative religion

and Arrow-collared Aristotelianism?—Aristotelianism first and last,

because it is the most dogmatic, tight-laced ethical system ever devised

outside of a tribal religion, and without the human passion and error of

a religion, a literary substitute for Christian asceticism; and because

romanticizations of it have never reached the vulgar population-mass, as

with Platonism?

As criticism has gone so far beyond erratic humanity and the perceptive

intelligence into pure, automatic Being and Knowing, it is natural that

the first article of that obscure intellectual observance should be a

renunciation of pathetic personality, a profession of lack of faith in

self and of distrust in the human mind. To this extreme was it necessary

to go to justify the expulsion of those words, subjects, attitudes and

sensations which had fallen into literary disrepute. Granted the

provocation, in what way, however, is the poetic faculty to be carried

safely through a Zeitgeist which not only denies the reality of poetry

but with which criticism allies itself as well in denying the reality of

the poet? Obviously the poetic faculty cannot get through the Zeitgeist

unless some poet or other carries it through on his back. But can he

carry it through if he makes a formal deposition of disbelief in the

human mind? Can he afford to disregard the Zeitgeist and carry the

poetic faculty through without making such a deposition, when to

withhold it means social disgrace, that is, critical ostracism? Can he

behave in a way not becoming to the Zeitgeist and get through the

Zeitgeist? Can he get through at all if he does behave in a becoming

way? A poet deficient in the poetic faculty may make as noble a

deposition of distrust in the human mind as one abundantly supplied with

it. Perhaps the only way to get through the Zeitgeist is to acknowledge

it and let it hurry on, leaving the poetic faculty behind to make

continuous refutations of poetic Adventism. To help pass away the time,

while this is happening, the poet with the poetic faculty strapped on

his back may play the buffoon, call criticism “nuncle” and cajole it

into a historical accuracy in the dating of poetry, pointing out, with

his bladder-stick, that it must allow biographical corrections of the

Zeitgeist, as man is permitted to improve on Time, since if Time were

left to itself there would be no to-morrow.

Note

The preceding essay is a long-term view of the relations of the poet

with the world he lives in. The following essay is a short-term view of

a single generation of poetry by itself and of its internal problems and

tendencies. No close correlation has therefore been made between them,

and none should be; although they will be found to agree in their

general implications.

*

Jean Cocteau, “Lettre à Jacques Maritain.”—Author

2

T. E. Hulme, the New Barbarism, and Gertrude Stein

I

The most obvious thing about contemporary poetry is that it is

“difficult.” It first of all appears difficult in the reading; so great

a distance separates the contemporary poet from the contemporary reader

that the only contemporary reader possible seems to be the poet himself.

It then appears that the difficulty is perhaps in the writing rather

than in the reading. The reader's difficulties are a reflection of those

which the contemporary poet has to face if he wishes to write as a

contemporary—to be included in the generation to which, by birth and

personal sympathy, he historically belongs. They determine the external

character of the text because they belong to its internal

character.^(=> #calibre_link-43 1

)

Now in general date or time is an arbitrary convenience adopted to

distinguish in the memory one day, one hour from the other. To the

reader, the poet, or the night-watchman it is simply an artificial

system of classification. We do not feel different on waking up to-day,

because to-day is to-day, from what we felt on waking up yesterday. We

have to make the mental effort of registering in our waking

consciousness that to-day is to-day; it is indeed this mental effort

that increases our age. No one really feels older than he felt

yesterday; second-childhood, for instance, is merely the cessation of

the mental effort required to mark down sunrise and sunset as time.

As the poet, if a true poet, is one by nature and not by effort, he must

be seen as writing as unconsciously (in regard to time, at any rate) as

his ordinary reader lives. The relation of his poetry to Poetry and to

the time in which it is written is the problem of criticism; and if this

problem enters into the actual writing of his poetry it must do so by

being superimposed upon it. A new and even alien element is in this case

added to his poetry—the historical effort. His reader must not only make

the effort demanded by the difference between his own way of existing

unconsciously and the poet's way of existing unconsciously—he must not

only consciously compare his own unconsciousness with the poet's

unconsciousness; he must make the same historical effort that the poet

makes. He must make the poet's creative difficulties his own critical

difficulties. This is why, in a generation of poetry so significantly

marked by such a historical effort, the plain reader is inclined to be

more sympathetic with the poetry of a past period than with that of his

own period: by belonging to the past, past poetry makes the historical

effort for him.

If contemporary poetry is for various reasons written with this effort,

there is no escape for the reader but to make the effort himself;

otherwise he must be content to wait until contemporary poetry has

become history, until, presumably, his generation is dead. Or, if he has

sufficient receptivity and historical awareness of the present, he need

not make a special effort in his reading. He is a contemporary reader

before he reads. He is armed with his criticism.

Indeed, in some ways it seems more reasonable for the reader to make the

historical effort than for the poet, as it is more a part of the

consuming side of poetry than of the creative side. But the facts are

otherwise. Poetry has been the victim of increasing pressure and

isolation. It has been obliged to specialize and over-specialize in

itself. It has been narrowed down by the specialization of human

time-activities to a point where it seems only another human

time-activity, where it becomes, in other words, an art in the most

formal interpretation of the word. The poet therefore has forced upon

him the whole burden of the criticism of poetry. He has forced upon him

a historical consciousness far more acute than that, say, of the

travelling bard of the Beowulf period or of the professional poet of an

imperially or religiously phrased society. Such poets merely met certain

demands laid upon them by an environment in which they were generously

included. The modernist poet has no such easy social adjustment to make:

it is doubtful whether he is included at all in the complicated social

pattern. As a result he is more at the service of the public situation

of poetry, which is a perilous one, than of his private poetic

endowments. He may, in a few rare cases, by a sort of historical

absent-mindedness, happen to write by pure nature, without historical or

professional effort. But on the whole it is probable that he will be

affected, and forgivably affected, by the pressure and influence of a

commercial society on poetry. He will be too conscious of the forced

professionalization of poetry to resist the temptation to justify it

professionally. But if he admits that it is only one of the numerous

time-activities of its period, an activity parallel to music or

painting, as other time-activities, or to radiology, aerostatics, the

cinema, modern tennis or morbid psychology, he must see it in its

contemporary setting as a very small patch on the time-chart, a bare

dot. The only way that this dot, this poetry-patch, can be given depth

is by being given historical depth. Then its local reality and

significance can be made to lie not so much in its general importance as

an expression of this particular period or age (for obviously as an

expression of this age it is no more than a dot on a hysterically

overcrowded chart) as in its particular importance in the general

tradition of poetry.

The tradition of poetry, or, we had better now say, the tradition of the

art of poetry, is therefore the formal organization which the modernist

poet finds himself serving as an affiliated member. He must not only, if

he accepts this view of the situation of poetry (whether out of

conviction or necessity), have a personal capacity for poetry—this is

merely his apprenticeship-certificate. He must have beyond this a

master's sense of the historical experience of poetry, of its functions,

its usefulness, its present fitness and possibilities. He must have a

science of the “values” of poetry; a scale of good and bad or true and

false or lasting and ephemeral; a theory of a tradition of poetry in

which successive period-poetries are subjected to historical judgment

either favourably or unfavourably, and in which his own period-poetry is

carefully adjusted to satisfy the values which the tradition is believed

to have evolved. Furthermore, since this tradition is supposed to

represent a logical historical development, its values, if observed, are

considered sufficient to produce the proper poetic expression of the

age. The adjustments which the poet has to make are no longer direct,

unconscious adjustments to his social environment, but critical

adjustments to a special tradition: his contact with his own period is

indirect, through the past, the past seen narrowly as the literature of

the past narrowing down to the literature, more particularly the poetry,

of the present.

So it comes about that the modernist poet tends to have an exaggerated,

even an abnormal preoccupation with criticism: largely forced upon him,

as has been noted, by the defensive position into which poetry is put by

modern life. A professional conscience dawns on the poet; as when the

prestige of any organization is curtailed—of the army, or the navy, for

example—a greater internal discipline, a stricter morality and a more

careful evaluation of tactics result. The organization becomes

self-critical, severe, sophisticated; strenuously up-to-date and of its

generation; the critic of itself in the past. In poetry the negative

side of this discipline shows itself in the avoidance of all the wrongly

conceived habits of the past. Poetry becomes so educated in itself that

it knows or seems to know at last how it should be written and written

at the very moment. The more its tradition is limited and purified of

elements like religion, science, psychology, philosophy or sociology,

which once existed in it as loose sentiments, the more technically

expert in them it grows; and in itself, by imitative sympathy. It looks

indeed as if the poetry of the period could be written by historical

effort alone; as if poetry has become so civilized, so all-aware, that

in its most advanced stage it is on the brink of a new primitive stage.

It seems about to begin again as from the beginning but drawing on the

experience of its tradition.

In practice, however, this new stage is only implied, not realized, in

contemporary poetry. True, there is more experimenting and greater

strictness in the construction of the poem, and a greater consciousness

of what a poem should not be. But so far this consciousness has remained

a negative influence: it is a professional, critical self-consciousness,

not a creative one. And how should it be creative? Creative

self-consciousness is a contradiction in terms; for it is clear that

poets do not begin to write by effort but by nature. It might seem,

however, that such an atmosphere, if it did not actually produce poets,

would at least make it easier for those who were poets by nature to

write well, by removing all temptations to write badly, and by creating

a feeling of tolerance toward a possible new poetry. But it is if

anything more difficult than usual to write either well or badly in an

atmosphere charged with discussion and self-consciousness about the

“values” of poetry and about how poetry should be written in conformity

with the period. Such an atmosphere forces the historical effort upon

the poet. It confounds the problems of criticism with the problems of

writing. It hampers the poet with the poetry of all poets who have ever

written, who may be writing at the moment, or who will ever write. It

invents—and this is the most serious drawback—a group poetic mind which

is at the elbow of the individual poet whenever he engages in

composition. This contemporary climate is as much responsible for the

“difficulty” of modernist poetry as the fact that well-written poetry is

always difficult and that the criticism responsible for this climate

demands that contemporary poetry should be well written. So the reasons

why there should be a new poetry prove to be the very ones why there is

not a new poetry but only a disturbed, a self-critical, a tightly

written, a strongly corrective poetry; why we shall probably find

ourselves to have had, after the novelties have been absorbed by

tradition, not a new age of poetry, in which new resources have been

opened up for the poetic mind, but merely another generation of poets, a

generation that has already begun to pass.

For however opposed this generation may have been to certain tendencies

in the poetic tradition, it has been bound over from the very beginning

to the idea of a tradition, and of a correct tradition. The passion for

correctness has led it to many strange caprices; to an admiration for

the eighteenth century in English poetry as the most correct literary

period of modern times; to a bias in favour of the most foppishly

correct classical writers; to such odd niceties and pains and punctilios

that it is not extravagant to suggest to the contemporary reader that

the poetry peculiar to his generation is perhaps the most correct poetry

that has ever been written in the English language. So intense has this

process been, so thorough and hurried at the same time, that it has made

poetry a narrower time-activity from within than it has been made, even,

from without. The generation is already over before its time, having

counted itself out and swallowed itself up by its very efficiency—a true

“lost generation,”^(=> #calibre_link-44 2

) as Gertrude Stein has called it and as it is fond of calling itself.

Already its most correct writer, T. S. Eliot, has become a classic over

the heads of the plain reader. The plain reader who would now first read

the poetry of his time must read it as already passed into tradition.

Although he will find a high degree of application necessary for the

actual word-by-word reading of the various works, he is spared that more

elaborate effort of criticism which deals with works as potential

classics. The whole problem of taste, that is, has been taken care of

for him by the poets themselves, who have written their poems with such

precision and far-sightedness that “acceptance” as such has been made

superfluous. Creation and critical judgment being made one act, a work

has no future history with readers; it is ended when it is ended.

In practice, then, there is no such thing as a new poetry; only a short

and very concentrated period, already nearly over, of carefully

disciplined and self-conscious poetry. It is almost just to say that at

the present moment there is no poetry but rather an embarrassing pause

after an arduous and erudite stock-taking. The next stage is not clear.

But it is not impossible that when the embarrassment has passed there

will be a resumption of less foppish, less strained, more critically

unconscious poetic methods of writing, purified, however, by the period

of historical effort behind it. At any rate for the time being we have

nothing better than this pause and in it an opportunity of understanding

what has taken place. We might almost say that poetry temporarily turned

into philosophy, entangled itself in many introspective absurdities that

had nothing to do with poetry, became pretentiously scholastic and

dogmatic in its theory; but that all this was perhaps unfortunately

necessary before a position could be reached in which poetry might be

normal without being vulgar, and deal naturally with truth without being

trite.

Such an embarrassed lull having fallen in poetry, the result of minute

searching and conscientiousness, the abstract nature of poetry

eventually becomes more important to the poet than the immediate

personal workings of poetry in him. His introspectiveness, which up to a

certain technical point might make his poetry clearer and more careful,

when carried beyond this point makes the writing of poetry altogether

impossible by turning it into a pursuit of theory and the poet into a

scientific investigator. So the philosophical phase of poetic modernism

is a laboratory phase, a complex interrelation of metaphysics and

psychology blighting the creative processes wherever they become

involved in it. This can be well-illustrated by comparing the highly

organized nature of T. S. Eliot's criticism in its present stage with

the gradual disintegration of his poetry since the Waste

Land.^(=> #calibre_link-45 3

) The absolute sense of authorship has been lost and the poet finds

himself counting only as he can be related to the historical period to

which he accidentally belongs. The time-element is made the law of

composition and any work which cannot be readily interpreted in terms of

its period-significance cannot be said to have any critical value—which

at the moment is the one admissible value by which poetry can become

current. The only good in this critical obsession is that, while it may

cause many temporary extravagances and suppressions, by stirring up a

historical consciousness of poetry it may make the world in general more

conscious of poetry in a specialized sense and more intimate with its

processes. In the end the emphasis on up-to-dateness and the

time-element in poetry may only mean a greater concentration in both the

reader and the poet on poetry as an ever immediate reality confirmed

afresh and independently in each new work rather than as a continuously

sustained tradition: confirmed personally rather than professionally.

II

There are discoverable reasons why the time-element came to have such

importance in contemporary poetry and criticism. Literature in the past

had been forced to recognize barbaric definitions of time which might be

foreign to the nature of literature but were imposed by local

convenience: the poet accepted authorized “ideas” of God or Immortality

or State and invented within these limits. He used, that is, the formal

human language of his time. The language and the time were barbaric

because they were gross dogmatic conventions resulting from the

fear-inspired consolidation of humanity. Humanity is a consolidation

against the terror of numbers, each unknown, which would reign if

humanity were not consolidated as humanity. When humanity is so

consolidated it becomes a stabilized and known mass, a weapon against

any non-human unknown. Of the various ways in which humanity may be

consolidated—by some symbol of individual similarity, whether of

religious beliefs or government, or by the observance of common social

taboos— contemporaneousness, the idea of the numbers sharing in one

time, is the most unifying sentiment. Poetry was obliged to acquiesce in

this sentiment because language is the most tangible sign of local

uniformity: the poet had to accept his medium from humanity at large, to

allow it, indeed, to invent his medium for him. If organic changes took

place in the language, they were not caused by any inventive caprice in

him or because he shifted, and his medium with him, in adjusting himself

to time. Humanity shifted, as a whole, perhaps, in making some slight

adjustment within itself, and language with it; and this might be called

a manifestation of barbaric time. But the poet had no particular

consciousness or responsibility of time. He was in this respect free of

the historical effort which is forced on the present-day poet. The

historical effort was assigned to all as a mass and to none in

particular.

The barbaric tendency expresses itself in mass, the civilized tendency

in specialization. When the necessity for consolidated mass passes, mass

breaks up into smaller units; it substitutes civilization for

consolidation. The tendency to consolidate does not necessarily,

however, antedate the tendency to specialize. The barbaric tendency

might reasonably be inculcated in an individualistic society, out of

common fear and compulsion. At all events, European barbarism comes

finally to be replaced by humanism: humanity viewed as a quality in the

individual rather than in the mass—as personality. Instead of one gross

composite time we have as many times going on at once as there are

individual expressions of dissimilar personality going on at once. Or,

to look at it differently, time has become so relative that the

individual need not be necessarily conscious of it. The poet in a

barbaric period is free from historical effort because time is absolute,

he has no power over it; and he is free from historical effort in a

civilized period because time is so strictly personal a measurement that

he has complete power over it.

The disintegrating effect of civilization is not only felt in the

development of personality. As the abstract idea of humanity is broken

up into concrete personal existences and the conception of time changes

accordingly, so the categories developed by barbarism to express the

underlying principle of the solidarity of humanity are now used to

express the non-cohesiveness of humanity. The language that once served

the conformity of human interests now serves their diversity. Each

category becomes specialized into a study of itself and each discovers,

in terms appropriate to it, its own theory of the relativity of time.

Each category becomes a separate time-activity. In a barbaric society

religion does not occupy one mental compartment, philosophy another,

science another, painting another, poetry another, and so on. But

religion is everything and everything is religion, philosophy is

everything and everything is philosophy, and so on. In a civilized

society religion is a sentiment, philosophy a speculation, science a

pursuit of knowledge, painting and poetry arts.

The arts have the most difficult problem to face in a specializing

civilization because when converted into separate activities they retain

something of their original force. They continue to have to do

principally with being and making and being and making is everything and

everything is being and making. When, however, they try to treat

themselves as specialized departments of study and at the same time to

continue to be the subjects of their study, to remain the kind of

activity they have been from the beginning, an impossibility is struck

upon. And yet this impossibility is the basis of the civilized

conception of such activities as arts, art being apparently a term

applied to intellectual activities which are something more than studies

of themselves.

In an art, it seems, two powers are concerned, the original power which

is the subject of the art—the being and making—and the power to study

this power; both powers being presumably one and the same. In an

ordinary category like science, where there is nothing but the study,

all that is involved is a laborious registering of changes which are

continually taking place in the study. The study is the minute

observation of the tradition and the deriving from this observation of

the time or pace which is peculiar to this tradition. Religion is such

an observation of a tradition, a sensitive registering of the changes

which observation itself brings about in the study.

But in an art, in poetry let us say, there is the study, in which

changes are always taking place (else there could be no study, for this

is the meaning of study, which is not repetition), and there is the

other power, which is pure from the beginning and in which no changes

can take place without the destruction of the art as a category.

Science, though a single tradition, is a different thing in Einstein's

time from what it was in Archimedes' time; and the tradition permits of

its being this radically different thing. Poetry, however, is not a

different thing in T. S. Eliot's time from what it was in Euripides'

time; if it were, neither Euripides nor Eliot could be defined as poets

and the tradition would be non-existent. How, then, is the poetic

tradition to move in time and yet poetry itself to remain unchanged; and

how is this further impossibility to be overcome, that the study, which

is the continuousness of the tradition, or the object of the art, cannot

go on at the same time as the being and making which are the subject of

the art?

Up to a certain stage in its history as a civilized category, poetry

escapes from these impossibilities and maintains itself as an art by

formally dividing itself into a composing half and a studying half, the

former limited to workmanship, the latter to criticism. The poet as a

workman being naturally free from the time-sense and the historical

effort, criticism devotes itself to the cultivation of a poetic

time-sense and to its imposition on the poet. Poetry has a relative

civilized time, then, only while the pressure of criticism on the

workman-poet is so light that he has his own relative time and not that

of poetry as a whole. It is when poetry is forced to over-specialize and

professionalize itself as a category and workmanship and criticism are

narrowed down to a single process, that the falsity of the

categorization of poetry either in a barbaric or civilized sense becomes

plain. For when this happens poetry must get its consolidated time-sense

from criticism rather than from workmanship: workmanship is as various

and contradictory as the number of workmen. What Mr. Eliot calls “the

invalidation of that ancient classification,”^(=> #calibre_link-46 4

) the disappearance, that is, of the distinction between critical and

creative, is in reality the domination of creation by criticism. If

creation were to dominate criticism, criticism would disappear. While

criticism and creation exist side by side with only a loose partnership

between them, creation is for the most part carefree, it has a general

but not disturbing intelligence of the tradition of poetry and tolerates

criticism as a harmless and even an occasionally useful parasite.

Underneath the bustle and clutter of historical interpretations,

underneath the disguise of a category—poetry can be free to be what it

has always been, an entity which can lend itself to the absolute

entirety of barbaric humanity or to the relative entirety of civilized

personality, but which remains fundamentally independent of and

unaffected by historical changes; its purpose being not to express

history, humanity or personality, but itself.

When poetry reaches the stage in its history as a civilized category

where criticism, or the studying-half, dominates the workmanship-half,

and the unsuitability of poetry as a specialized art makes both

criticism and workmanship very difficult, it is actually in danger of

being destroyed as a tradition unless some time-sense is introduced into

it, by no matter how artificial an effort. No one seems to realize that

the destruction of poetry as a tradition would not destroy poetry

itself. Those who are not poets do not, because to see poetry as such an

independent force requires that one should be a poet. And those who are

poets are tempted to encourage the idea of the traditional

professionality of poetry because it confers a group-dignity and power

that protects their personal sensitiveness. Consequently there is no

debate about the necessity of preserving the tradition; and it is

criticism which assumes responsibility for the collective unity of the

art of poetry.

The time-sense by which such unity can be consciously maintained must

be, it is evident, a mass, or barbaric, time-sense and not a

personalized, or civilized, one. Thus when all other categories,

particularly those generally classified as scientific, are developing

minutely relative time-senses, poetry (and painting as well) attempts to

stabilize itself by evoking an absolute time-sense. This new

intellectual barbarism must, of course, differ from a natural historical

barbarism. In the latter, mass-time and mass-humanity are real and

automatically fixed and absolute, so that the poet is free of any

conscious effort to construe his time. In the former there is no

mass-time or mass-humanity, time and humanity are personal

sentimentalities; so that the concept of absoluteness by which poetry as

a whole may have some historical coherence must first be consciously

postulated before the poet can claim any meaning for his work. In

consequence the meaning and the making of a poem become two separate

elements. Meaning is the substance of criticism, and a general, common

problem. Making in its most limited sense is the substance of

workmanship and tends, as in most modernist poetry, to grow more and

more particularized and technical. Criticism now actually precedes

workmanship.

To support such a theory of barbaric absoluteness poetry must ally

itself with a special metaphysic of poetry. It must even, in

self-defence, believe that the new barbarism is a natural and not a

forced stage in the tradition, must even believe that, because a

conscious stage, it is a superior, in fact a final one. It must make the

present period not so much the next one of a series as a resume of

periods. Its obligatory concern with the general meanings of poetry and

the maintenance of a formal metaphysic of poetry tempt it to assume the

position formerly belonging to philosophy. In defining the poetic

absolute a hierarchy or graduated order of values is established,

converting poetry into a dogmatic science pledged to the refinement of

these values. The personal creative side of poetry is overshadowed by

the professional traditional side.

The effect of this scientific attitude may eventually be to give the

poem itself greater distinctness; in contemporary poetry there have been

many efforts to present the poem as a thing in itself, a definite object

produced by a conscientious craftsman. Its general immediate influence

has been to put an unnatural burden of faultlessness on the poem. The

modernist poem probably suffers more than it benefits from the attention

which contemporary criticism grants it. If on the one hand it has

acquired a new sort of conspicuousness, it has been forced, on the other

hand, to have a greater regularity than would otherwise have been

necessary.

An absolute which shall give the poem a regularity more certain than the

accidental regularity that it has in a civilized, more relatively stated

aspect of the tradition can at present be only an absolute in theory—it

begins as an idea not a fact. It cannot be a virtual absolute because,

however regular the poem itself should be if the poet adheres to this

theory, the necessity of adhering to a theory remains an ineradicable

flaw. It is possible and interesting to observe that at such and such a

historic period an absolute conception of humanity, time and art

prevailed and that a peculiarly fixed kind of perfection in art, as in

Egyptian art, developed from this conception. Such a general observation

is history; if particularly applied, as to poetry, it is criticism. But

if criticism is made something more than observation, if it develops

such a preference for the barbaric absolute, say, that it attempts to

give this to poetry artificially, by historical effort, then it is

creating not poetry but history. Critically conceived poetry at the

present time is historical rather than poetic. Historical inventiveness

of this kind is, as we shall see, fundamentally

Bergsonian.^(=> #calibre_link-47 5

) It is as if all individual consciousnesses were expected to be able at

will to submerge themselves completely in a single race-consciousness

and for a protracted period evolve with great intensity and at great

strides, without variation, digression or error. All separate poetic

faculties, that is, are supposed to merge into a single professional

group-faculty of which each poet is separately possessed. The poetic

production as a whole, where such an effort is made, would have great

theoretical simplicity because criticism had conceived and directed it

as a whole; but equally, great practical complexity, since individual

poetic faculties cannot submerge themselves at will in an absolute

faculty except by such intricacies of theory as complicate the whole the

more theoretically simple it is.

It is not surprising, therefore, that poetry has for the moment assumed

the position formerly occupied by philosophy. Philosophy is pure history

and pure criticism. It observes, and from its observations it creates

something which pretends to be neither actual history nor actual poetry.

Its purpose is to generalize from particulars and to simplify its

generalities with the idea of discovering a code of perfection. The end

of all philosophies, however much they have seemed to contradict one

another, has been to define the absolute. Committed to a belief in the

reality of the generalities by which they arrived at this absolute, they

have, moreover, been bound to minimize the reality of variation,

digression or error. Caprice is never more than a foot-note subject in

any philosophy; its conclusions must obviously be only those which

humanity can arrive at as a single-minded, barbaric whole. This

systematic conformity of pure philosophy is, described in historical

language, classicism.

So it has happened that when the absolutist conception of humanity was

succeeded by the relativist conception of personality (humanism), pure

philosophy disappeared. Since the Renaissance caprice has governed the

forms which human thought and conduct have taken; and caprice is

romanticism. Not only this, but thought and conduct have found a common

ground in which they are united and of equal potency—Imagination; and

Imagination is romanticism. In classicism the distinctions between

thought and conduct are strictly drawn, and philosophy must observe

these distinctions in order to protect the idea of perfection: once they

are allowed to disappear, imperfection or error or caprice is admitted

as a fundamental generality. Since the Renaissance, then, formal

philosophy has grown more and more feeble, as Time, the generality

capable of most uniformity, has grown more and more diversified and

relative. Philosophy, when narrowed down by the large-scale

diversification of civilized humanity into a minor category or

time-activity, could obviously not develop itself as such, could not

acquiesce in its own relativity without contradicting itself.

The only chance of reviving its old authority was, if some category like

poetry, which originally had first-class, general significance in a

barbaric order, should in being civilized be weakened as a category;

should consequently need assistance in re-establishing its professional

standing. In an individualized time-combination, poetry or any

previously standardized tradition becomes, up to a certain point, more

and more non-professional. Then this very non-professionalism itself is

loosely professionalized. We have stereotyped individuality instead of

stereotyped uniformity, or the standardization of specialization. It is

in such circumstances that poetry feels tempted to take specialization

literally and to dignify itself by turning its haphazard professionalism

into a formal, authoritative professionalism. It accepts the specialized

denomination art, but within the limits set by this denomination it

enforces its own peculiar generalities—generalities which imply a system

of the absolute and therefore the entire machinery and vocabulary of

“pure” philosophy.

III

The new poetic barbarism could be felt in poetry in a disorganized way

as an intellectual necessity and even conscientiously carried out as a

programme by individual poets, though in a still more disorganized way.

But it was important that it should have its philosopher and that he

should be, besides, a person disappointed in the course taken by

philosophy since the Renaissance—in the decline of “pure” philosophy.

The pressure exerted on poetry to interpret itself by a conscious

historical effort as a coherent tradition drove it to organize itself

temporally. Its sole contemporary object became an expression of the age

which would not only justify itself professionally but redefine time for

it in an absolute way. Thus a hunger was created in the generation on

which the pressure fell for some doctrinaire statement of this

philosophization of poetry, and a readiness to make a modern Aristotle

of the person who could do something toward satisfying the hunger. Such

a person was provided in the late T. E. Hulme, who died before he had

developed a well-defined system of aesthetics, but who left enough

fragments to be accepted by a generation starved for respectable

philosophico-literary dogma.^(=> #calibre_link-48 6

) It is significant that his philosophy was founded on a view of the

absolute which was more religious than philosophical, and more proper to

art than to religion. In searching for a way to purify philosophy, he

could find nothing better than the need which art—painting or sculpture

or poetry—had to be philosophically organized and corrected. All his

statements about the nature of pure philosophy will be found to apply

more accurately to art than to philosophy.

Hulme's absolute was a strictly barbaric concept: anti-humanism,

anti-Renaissance, anti-civilization. In his division of reality into its

prime zones or categories he derided any idea of relativity among them.

His absolute implied what he called a principle of discontinuity, and it

is amusing to find that he named these categories in such a way that no

communication could seem plausible between them. They were the inorganic

world, the organic world and the world of religious and ethical values.

It is clear how he arrived at them. For they are the categories into

which evolutionary time naturally falls if progressive historical

continuity is assumed: first the world of apparently final, static,

unformulated matter, then that of growing, or changing matter (the human

world), then the world of forms created by this growth—the world, we

might say, of formulated matter, really final and static. Now let these

categories stand but remove the conception of time in process which

invented them and we have the same categories, their definition

unchanged, but discontinuous. All objectionable notions of time and

relativity will then appear to have proceeded from the second category.

In the first is a seeming absolute, the brutal absolute of mere

primitiveness, in the third is a true absolute possessing all those

attributes by cultivation which in the first belong by crudeness. Time

is absolute in the first because it is so completely absent as to be

uniform. In the third it is absolute because the uniformity is aesthetic

and creates the absoluteness of time. The two complementary factors in

this creation are the exercise and the submission of the will. Therefore

this third category, which is really the field of aesthetics, is called

the world of religious and ethical values. The second is not even

properly speaking a category, it is the whole imperfect and vacillating

human intelligence, a kind of freak of nature, which has the vanity to

attempt to find in itself a subjective mock-Divine. Nor is the first

category, properly speaking, a category, but only a rough unrealized

statement of the third. Only one true general category does, in fact,

exist, the single barbaric absolute in which religion, ethics, and art

combine to objectify and fix the temporal phases through which the human

intelligence, out of imperfection and caprice, passes.

Such a dogmatic interpretation of history—(I have only extended Hulme's

fundamental propositions)—for it is an interpretation of history

although it does not adopt the conventionally historical view—can

obviously be of great value to a particular tradition which, like

poetry, has been placed in a position of self-defence and made to feel

the need of systematizing itself. It can be especially valuable because,

by discrediting the idea of history as necessary continuity of time in

which all human personalities or groups of personalities share variously

and freely, and by making it a discontinuous principle, it suggests that

there is an inevitable order in it to which the human intelligence may

be held generally responsible. The productions of an age cannot answer

for themselves by declaring “We are these several productions and the

age exists through our variety and contemporaneity.” They are, on the

contrary, incidental to the age and a corroboration of it. The age is

not an expression of the relativity of the various activities going on

in it, but these activities express it and their relativity is due to

its absoluteness; it is not a short period or piece of time but all

time—the world indeed of religious and ethical values—attested to and

worshipped by a number of individual times. It is a curious fact that

whenever such barbaric ideology as this has prevailed the age has been

so compact that it has not had “periods.” It has appeared final and

eternal and prolonged itself artificially and even destroyed itself by

prolonging itself. Mediaevalism, for example, was a protracted absolute

and unvaried throughout by minor periods or by any relative sense of

time.

Once poetry through its criticism becomes aware that the personal

authority of the poet in a relative, civilized time-scheme is reduced to

the small accidental share he has in it, then such a view of time as a

belief in an absolute affords must naturally appeal to poets as a

conscious contemporary body. It is beside the point that such a body

would be an artificial one, that poetry considered as a specialized

activity reduces to the poet, not to the co-ordinated production of

poets (while science does not reduce to the scientist). The fact is that

the appearance of inevitable co-ordination is forced upon poetry and

that it seems to lose authority unless it imposes co-ordination. Poetry

cannot be left to its fate with the poet, whose proportionate authority

is now as infinitesimal as the constituents of the atom. The only way to

give poetry formal authority is through some philosophical system like

the one that Hulme roughly suggested.

Hulme's ideas have by now been absorbed by sensitive contemporary

criticism and indeed inspire, however remotely, most contemporary poetry

consciously written as part of a co-ordinated period-production: “he

appears as the forerunner of a new attitude of mind, which should be the

twentieth-century mind,” was the New Criterion's summary of his

significance.^(=> #calibre_link-49 7

) Hulme himself wrote a few poems, and it is interesting that they all

come vaguely under the period-classification popular in his time:

Imagism. But he adopted it only tentatively: it was just one possible

form. In painting and sculpture he saw more definite possibilities,

because they were historically freer. Neither of them had to face the

problem which literature faced in entering upon a new stage. There were

no such intrinsic changes wrought in colour and stone by decades of

humanism as were wrought in language. All that sculpture and painting

had to do was to escape from the works of humanism and revert to

preferred barbaric modes, creating modern forms as if in primitive

times—forms primitive, obedient to the conventions they accepted,

therefore final, absolute, abstract. For poetry the problem was not so

simple. It could not, it seemed, submit itself so facilely to an as-if:

its expressive medium, language, had been intrinsically affected not

only by the works in which it had been used but also by all the

non-poetic uses of which language is capable.

This difference between poetry and the regular arts points to a variance

in poetry and suggests the probable falsity of such philosophical

generalizations on art as Hulme made. In his desire to coordinate and

correctly generalize, he fell into the familiar philosophical confusion,

the confusion of analogy. Art, for instance, is a philosophical term

invented for the convenience of classification, not a term that poetry

would naturally invent for itself, though painting and sculpture very

well might for themselves. To the philosopher, however, the most

accurate term is the most general rather than the most particular; and

so to Hulme a common co-ordination of the “arts” seemed possible and

necessary. Analogy is always false, but it is the strongest

philosophical instrument of co-ordination. Since poetry as an art is not

sufficiently regular, not sufficiently professional, it is to be made so

by becoming more sculptural or more pictorial, by having grafted on it

the values and methods of more professional arts.

While, then, by the use of analogy and other philosophical

generalizations, a co-ordination and a simplification might be made in

poetic theory and a satisfactory understanding of the poetic absolute

and abstract poetic form reached, still language itself demanded

purification; and this was a most complicated and difficult problem. It

demanded first to be allowed to become disorganized until so loose

grammatically that it could be reorganized as if afresh, without regard

to how words and their combinations had been sympathetically affected by

usage. It had to be as instrumentally pure as colour or stone. Words

themselves would be reduced by this process to their least historical

value. They would be cleansed of stale associations in order that they

might be used primitively and abstractly. The purer they were the more

eternally immediate and present they would be. In this way they could

express the absolute at the same time as they were expressing the age.

Gertrude Stein's use of words may be looked on as such a purification.

Her language is primitive and abstract. It is so primitive, indeed, that

criticism has felt obliged to repudiate her work as a romantic vulgar

barbarism, an expression of the personal crudeness of a mechanical age

rather than a refined historical effort to restore a lost absolute to a

group of co-ordinated creators. T. S. Eliot has said of Miss Stein's

work that “it is not improving, it is not amusing, it is not

interesting, it is not good for one's mind. But its rhythms have a

peculiar hypnotic power not met with before. It has a kinship with the

saxophone. If this is the future, then the future is, as it very likely

is, of the barbarians. But this is the future in which we ought not to

be interested.”^(=> #calibre_link-50 8

) Mr. Eliot was for the moment speaking from the civilized viewpoint: it

seemed suddenly impossible to reconcile the crudities of any barbarism,

however new, with the advanced historical state of the poetic mind and

with the professional dignity of poetry which the new barbarism was

invented to restore. A sincere attempt to do so was at once vulgar and

obscure, like the work of Miss Stein. So except for such whole-hog

literalness as hers modernist poetry has lacked the co-ordination to

which modernist criticism subscribes; it has not had a controlling ism

or school. This want would have been welcome if it had not meant an

irreconcilability between criticism and workmanship which has made the

latter a wasted performance.

Although Hulme has been Aristotelianized by the generation of modernist

poets just passing, he arrived at art only through the failure of

philosophy, and his theories of art must be derived from his criticism

of philosophy. Philosophy had failed historically to keep “pure,” to be

“entirely objective and scientific.” Philosophy was corrupted by the

personal element. The personal element should have been carefully

separated from the scientific element. The philosopher is the scientist

of the absolute, but he unfortunately possesses an imperfect romancing

human intelligence which confounds his study of the absolute with crude

dreams and desires—the emotional, religious element. Philosophy can only

be kept pure by cutting away the second element and making it an object

of study, or rather of light philosophical curiosity. For it is this

same intelligence or personalized humanity which in art upsets the

absolute with caprice. The absolute is fixed; caprice is fictional.

Recognize that the activities of the human intelligence are fictional,

and fictional and relative become synonymous terms. How are we to

determine what belongs to the absolute category, “the world of religious

and ethical values,” and what to the organic (the human, historical)

category? By the principle of discontinuity. Decide that humanity is

incapable of perfection, and perfection becomes dissociated from it, and

the absolute is then absolute because it is discontinuous with organic

humanity.

Now it might seem easier to enforce this distinction in philosophy than

in art. But since all philosophy considers itself “pure” it is not

likely to recognize the corrupting humanistic element when it appears;

for this disguises itself in the same scientific language with which

philosophy defines the absolute. Art, on the other hand, has grown more

and more frankly humanistic and romantic—it rejoices in the fact that

its values are fictional. Art, therefore, would not, like philosophy,

resist the charge that it has allowed itself to be seduced by fictional

values. It might even, if it were made to feel that its integrity was in

danger, accept the formulas of a hypothetically pure philosophy in order

to make its fiction substantial. It might tie itself to an absolute in

order to make its fiction philosophically respectable. The fact that it

owned to a fiction would merely mean that it lacked the arrogance

natural to philosophy, which owns only to an absolute.

All this must have been felt by Hulme in his deprecation of the course

philosophy had taken since the Renaissance and in his restatement of the

absolute in terms of art rather than of philosophy. He did not, for

instance, attack romanticism from the philosophical but from the

literary point of view. The weaknesses of his generalizations are

consequently more obvious than they would have been had his statement

remained strictly philosophical. For philosophical statements are so

general that they exclude illustrations and thus remain uncontrovertible

until some one has the courage to challenge their consistency as

generalizations, without resorting to illustrations. Furthermore, the

literary statement never has the dogmatism of the philosophical

statement: the philosopher speaks as for the Cosmic, the critic for a

craft or himself or for those who may personally agree with him. Had

Hulme been speaking as a philosopher he would not have attacked

romanticism, he would have destroyed it, and he would have been

unanswerable. It would have been impossible to point out that the idea

of perfection dwelling in a non-human absolute is as romantic as the

ideal of its dwelling in variable humanity; or that, since he could not

admit perfection except in dissociation from humanity, he had merely

invented the principle of discontinuity in order to invent from it the

non-human absolute. By the way that philosophy defines itself it is

protected from being revealed as a fiction. Hulme did not make a

philosophy but a criticism of philosophy, and this was making a fiction.

It is fiction to say, as this criticism does, that if the human

intelligence recognizes an absolute and, of course, its own

imperfection, and so shuts out from its fictional activities the “human

plane,” it must realize that its fiction will have a wholly “tragic

significance” and will express the “futility of existence.” It is

romantic to say, while denouncing as romantic the meanings which the

creative mind gives to its fictions, that these can only be valid if

they confess their meaninglessness. Is not a belief in the lack of

meaning in organic existence merely a new meaning that art is to adopt

for the sake of the prestige given it by the metaphysics from which it

is drawn?

Whether or not Hulme formally inaugurated the new barbarism in

contemporary criticism is a fine and irrelevant point of history.

Certainly a general degradation of the person was taking place in poetry

at the time that he was writing—the first disorganized step toward

professionalization and co-ordination. Poetry felt forced to objectify

itself and to do this successfully it had to enter upon a philosophical

career. Hulme's ardent neo-realism, or anti-humanism, supplied the

doctrine necessary for this career. (His doctrine, a disappointment with

philosophy, was itself in need of being legitimized and made positive by

an application to practical aesthetics.) If poetry was to make its new

career barbarically uniform, it had first of all to set about

methodically exterminating the person. As there is nothing more absolute

than the person and as there are therefore as many absolutes as distinct

persons, the only way to get uniformity was to impose a single objective

absolute, an abstract, regularly waved sea defeating eccentric

individual configuration by the uninterrupted rhythm of its gross and

monotonous detail.

The philosophical side of poetry's new career was simple. It defined the

absolute, quoted the philosophers, dreamt of objectivity and spread its

lap for the golden apples of art which it hoped would now drop out of

its neo-realistic heaven. But no golden apples came, only glass marbles

for criticism to play with while waiting for golden apples. The golden

apples never came and criticism went on collecting more and more glass

marbles. The reason why there have been no golden apples is that

workmanship has not been able to take advantage of the serene privileges

of the absolute. It has had to keep busy degrading the person and

casting out from written and proposed verse all the romantic egotistical

absolutes with which the tradition of poetry has ever been decorated. So

literary criticism, as with Hulme, turns to admire other arts, such as

painting, which are technically more capable of professional formality

and period-uniformity.

The view that periods are or should be coherent time-lengths follows

from a belief in an invariable, inferred absolute. Humanity itself is

not absolute, but it has the privilege of dramatizing the absolute in

time. If it could be physically as well as ethically or religiously

(dramatically) uniform, it would have one single intact time-length.

Personal time would be absent and require the same effort to be

conceived as absolute time itself is by a physically variable humanity.

It would, indeed, not affect the inherent absoluteness of time, it would

merely make numerical repetitions of it. With a variable humanity,

however, conforming to an ethically absolute time, personal time is a

numerical variation, not a numerical repetition of it. And because

absolute time can only be dramatically executed through personal time,

it can be only relatively absolute: its absoluteness has to be inferred

by comparison.

When humanity or a co-ordinated representative portion of humanity

attempts to observe the absolute as strictly as possible in whatever

form it is officially recognized at the time, and to compare its own

relativeness with it continually, then we have a coherent time-length;

we have classicism. When humanity falls in love with its own

relativeness and ceases to compare its variability with an absolute,

then we have romanticism. An unexaggerated romantic period is a

collection of the remarkable and independent individuals who were alive

in that period and of “forces” so distinctly varied that they are nearly

recognizable as people—perhaps numerically representative of the less

remarkable and independent individuals of the period. An exaggerated

romantic period is one in which variation has assumed so great a

significance that the period seems composed by one or two dominant

personalities. The Napoleonic period was an exaggerated romantic period;

so much so that every highly specialized personality seemed

Napoleonic—the shadow of Napoleonism fell, in Europe, across the entire

first half of the nineteenth century.

The antithesis of exaggerated romanticism is exaggerated classicism,

which opposes impersonal to personal uniformity. Contemporary literary

classicism is bent on enforcing a coherent time-length which shall rob

personal variations of significance, and on connecting this time-length

sympathetically with former classical periods, in order to make it as

relatively absolute as possible. So it dismisses the Renaissance and

joins itself directly to Mediaevalism; so it dismisses Darwinism as

having given romantic significance to biological variation.

What impresses one most in tracing the new barbarism from its

theoretical phase to its contact with actual creation is that here is a

complicated machinery which, when set in motion and concentrated on what

are its expressed ends, is capable of only the crudest mechanical

gestures. Its subtleties become pomposities, its contributions to the

cause that it has created, trivialities. Criticism has a great deal to

say about criticism, which means that it is highly philosophical. But as

it has very little that is relevant and helpful to say about poetry

itself—not as a philosophical abstraction but as poems—criticism

becomes, in practice, highly philosophical nonsense. Although it objects

to the romantic disorganization in which there is not beauty but

“beauties,” it has no absolute canon of beauty to offer to the poetry

which it is attempting to inspire but a primitive satire of beauties and

a counsel to suppress the obvious because the obvious is often

romantically (personally), therefore sentimentally beautiful. Although

it insists that a fixed dogmatic beauty leaves the poet more free to

achieve perfection, yet it has nothing better to offer than a few

elementary suggestions and clues such as that “golden lad” is a

beautiful classical phrase and “golden youth” a beautiful romantic

phrase (Hulme). “The thing has got so bad now that a poem which is all

dry and hard, a properly classical poem, would not be considered poetry

at all. . . . They cannot see that accurate description is a legitimate

object of verse.”^(=> #calibre_link-51 9

) Hulme did not stop just here, but however far he went (and this was

not far) he could not get away from his battle with the past and help

the present, although the present was his professed objective. Nor did

he seem to realize the waste and absurdity of asking a forward-looking

twentieth-century generation to arm itself against an early

nineteenth-century bogey or against the Renaissance bogey itself.

We scarcely realize how crude a reference-word “classical” really is. If

we consider its usage, even by an apparently careful writer like Hulme,

we find it is nothing more than a term to apply to works designed with

the intention that they shall become classics, and to those which have

succeeded in this intention. If, moreover, we examine this intention, we

discover that it is servilely concerned with technique and decency, but

little with meaning, personal intensity or experimentation. Many of the

difficulties of contemporary verse are indeed due to the attempt to

reconcile the classical desideratum “dry and hard” with the necessity to

experiment in order to fix beauty as criticism seems unable to fix

it—experiment of course leading to romanticism. Romanticism, on the

contrary, is not so concerned with technique or decency; it is more

freakish, more ambitious, more amateurish. Because it is amateurish it

is more serious: genuine amateurishness is a mixing of the making of a

thing with the significance of its making. In exaggerated romanticism

the significance of the making is more important than the problem of the

making itself; it is the object of each individual exercise. In

exaggerated classicism the professional sense is so dominant that the

significance of the making is considered settled for the craft as a

whole: there can be no making unless it is settled. Therefore in

exaggerated romanticism we find an abnormal emphasis on perspective as

in exaggerated classicism an abnormal absence of it. This abnormal

absence of it, this forced naivety, is obedience to a discipline whose

object is to prevent the use of form for speculation. The concentration

of form on form means in classical terminology “abstract” or “pure”

form. Speculation with form can also become, in romantic art, forced

naivety—what Hulme wished to attack in Ruskinian seriousness.

The opposition is not, as Hulme cavalierly made it, of sophisticated

levity to idiot-headed seriousness, or of fancy to imagination, but of a

heavy, rigid, originally dull seriousness to a rather ingenuous,

sometimes successful, often droll, though perhaps eventually dull

seriousness. “Wonder must cease to be wonder,” complained Hulme: but in

the beginning, while there is wonder, there is always the chance of a

surprise success in romanticism. In classicism, which sets out with a

formal, defined intention, there is never the chance of success in this

sense. If romantic freakishness generally quiets down to triteness and

is for this reason dull, classical freakishness, of which there are so

many contemporary specimens, is fixed and eternal from the outset and

thus eternally dull. It cannot even be undermined by the influence it

exercises because it is made with a kind of bigotry that immediately

imposes itself rather than influences. A romantic movement must have an

end, Hulme said, a discovery by a bigoted classicist full of

significance: “movement” meaning the history and influence of romantic

works, rather than the making of original romantic works themselves. A

classicist, it is to be remarked, in attacking romanticism always

attacks the end-products of a romantic movement, and the most feeble of

these; as Hulme chooses to attack romanticism through Ruskinian

seriousness rather than through the best of Keats, whom he admired; as

he attacks humanism and the Renaissance at points where they break down.

The conglomerativeness of romanticism makes it possible to attack it as

a whole in this way through an assailable part, while the romanticist

wishing to attack classicism must attack it as an integrated whole, with

the result that it generally remains unattacked because the task seems

too formidable.

Let me set down the most ingenuous expression of the romantic point of

view that I can at the moment find. It is by William Kiddier, from a

little book, one of a series, called “The Profanity of

Paint.”^(=> #calibre_link-52 10

) First on colour, the medium of painting: “Colour is the soul of

things! . . . I believe colour belongs to the fairies; it never comes

quite within our grasp. It is borne upon the air, its chariot is the

morning dew, and its paths the sunbeams. I have come to regard colour as

a spiritual thing changing for ever, as all spiritual things do.” Then

on what we might call “The first principle”: “Everything in the work

should, in some special degree, contribute to the first idea. Nothing

should be introduced for the sake of variety. . . . of a truth, trees

can only be painted by the sympathetic hand, one that can make a simple

group of all around him, selecting only those that, by their forms,

shall contribute to the artistic sense relation. . . . Time counts for

nothing. The trunk has been the work of centuries; and the season

present brings forth the shoot; yea! a thousand years have gone between

and both are in relation!” Now as this statement stands, we can say that

it illustrates certain general characteristics of romanticism. The

medium itself is related to a meaning, or spiritualized. Art is not the

definite formation of form but human aspiration working through form,

therefore tending to indefiniteness. Relation is apparently only an

ambitious word for perspective. Contribution to a first idea is only

romantic distortion of the elements of a picture to create a meaning. It

does not imply in the artist a reverence for the absolute; for then his

picture would have Meaning, but not a meaning in the human sense. If

time counts for nothing to Mr. Kiddier, it is because he believes in

continuity. It is eternal because human life to him is eternal, not

because a discontinuity exists between “life” and the world of religious

and ethical values which makes the time of the latter absolute, of the

former relative.

Now let me set down the least ingenuous expression of the classical or

barbaric point of view that I can at the moment find. It is by Ezra

Pound, on the work of the sculptor Gaudier-Brzeska. Mr. Pound admires

his work, we learn, because it is anti-Hellenic its chief formative

influences were from archaic Greek, the Oceanic, the Egyptian, the

Assyrian, the African, the Chinese—from strictly barbaric sources, in

other words. He says, speaking of Gaudier's “The Dancer”:

This is almost a thesis of his ideas upon the use of pure form. We have

the triangle and circle assented, labled almost, upon the face and right

breast. Into these so-called “abstractions” life flows, the circle moves

and elongates into the oval, it increases and takes volume in the

sphere, or hemisphere of the breast. The triangle moves toward organism,

it becomes a spherical triangle. . . . These two developed motifs work

as themes in a fugue. We have the whole series of spherical triangles,

as in the arm over the head, all combining and culminating in the great

sweep of the back of the shoulders, as fine as any surface in all

sculpture. The “abstract” or mathematical bareness of the triangle and

circle are fully incarnate, made flesh, full of vitality and energy. The

whole form series ends, passes into stasis with the circular base or

platform.^(=> #calibre_link-53 11

)

Mr. Pound quotes Gaudier-Brzeska himself: “Sculptural feeling is the

appreciation of masses in relation. Sculptural ability is the defining

of these masses by planes.” Mr. Pound continues: “The sculptor must add

to the power of imagining form-combination the physical energy required

to cut this into the unyielding medium. He must have vividness of

perception, he must have this untiringness, he must beyond that be able

to retain his main idea unwaveringly during the time (weeks or months)

of the carving.” This statement may likewise be taken as a

characteristic expression of classicism. We have an emphasis on the

medium as material. The “main idea” is the proper and painstaking

adjustment of the material to itself, its gradual assumption of definite

form. The artist could not have the concentration necessary for this

task, it is implied, if he did not exlude from it meaning in the human,

relative sense. His work has an absolute quality, an “abstractness,” to

the degree to which he can exclude a meaning, to the degree to which his

work exists in the world of religious and ethical value rather than in

the world of biological striving. His forms would lack finality if they

strove. There is no talk of spirituality, of everness, of sunbeams or of

seasons bringing forth shoot. There is undoubtedly a fundamental first

principle, but this is apparently so fundamental and so fixed that it is

unnecessary and even forbidden to introduce it as the subject of a work.

It is the point from which the artist begins rather than the one at

which he aims.

Such seems to be the irreconcilability of these two statements as the

expressions of two opposed ways of interpreting and applying the

creative capacities. If, however, we examine them as two statements

showing a difference of personal temperament in their authors, this hard

and fast irreconcilability between romanticism and classicism

disappears, and we see them both as somewhat arbitrary distinctions

based on the temperamental variations likely to occur in people dealing

with what is virtually the same process. Both temperaments may even be

found to exist side by side in the same period. Mr. Kiddier is

historically a modest contemporary of Mr. Pound's; and what, after all,

does Mr. Kiddier say that Mr. Pound does not? He says that colour is the

important thing in painting and that it is a very difficult and subtle

medium. To say that it belongs to the fairies is only an extravagant and

harmless way of saying that man has trouble in mastering it. To call

colour a spiritual thing is merely an extravagant way of saying that, to

use it properly, the artist must have high qualities, such as “insight,

poignancy, retentiveness, plus the energy”—Mr. Pound's own list of the

essentials in the “making of permanent sculpture.” If Mr. Kiddier

insists on a first idea, Mr. Pound insists on a main one. The artistic

sense relation which for the former should show in the association of

trees in a picture is, true enough, defined as a kind of emotional

sympathy in the artist rather than as a necessary relationship between

the “motifs” employed. But is this not merely a tenderer, more ingenuous

version of Mr. Pound's own ingenuous enough remarks about the “complete

thesis of principles” which the perfect statue apparently attains? Mr.

Kiddier, when he comes to Time, obviously lets his extravagance get

control of him; there is a lack of respectability of a sort in this,

unredeemed by any uniqueness of thought or expression. But it should not

be overlooked, in Mr. Kiddier's defence, that it is part of his

ingenuousness to pretend neither to respectability nor uniqueness; while

Mr. Pound makes the uniqueness of his views respectable by quoting half

a dozen barbarisms as his authorities, and his respectability unique by

the use of a very limited language supposed to express literally the

concrete problems of the artist. Romantic language such as Mr. Kiddier's

soon becomes trite after the surprise of its first use wears off;

language such as Mr. Pound uses (Id do not wish, of course, to suggest

that either Mr. Kiddier or Mr. Pound invented their language) soon

becomes jargon, which means not only trite but senseless—for it is so

limited that when it loses its literal sense its metaphorical sense

(such as the application to poetry of terms invented for sculpture)

becomes purely academic. We shall grow weary (if we have not already) of

talk of circles, triangles, spheres, form, planes, stasis and masses

sooner than talk of trees put in motion by the wind, fairies, sunbeams,

seasons and the passing of centuries.

Shorn of its jargon, is there anything that Mr. Pound says which is not

in Mr. Kiddier's philosophy? He says that the artist makes the

mechanical exercises of his art breathe out life, that everything must

be in relation (Mr. Kiddier's word), that the sculptor can make flesh

out of stone as the colour-artist gets significant vibrations out of

paint. His elaborate explanation of the technical merit of “The Dancer”

is really a pedantic evasion of such words as “spirituality” about which

Mr. Kiddier, if asked describe this statue, would in his ingenuousness

not be squeamish. “The whole form-series ends, passes into statis with

the circular base or platform” is merely the basic “sameness” or

peacefulness of Mr. Kiddier's philosophy of art into which variety shall

not be introduced for its own sake.^(=> #calibre_link-54 12

) A romanticist would paraphrase Gaudier-Brzeska: “The sculptor must

feel his subject as a whole and understand it minutely in its parts

without allowing its soul to escape. More than this, he must be able to

feel and understand with stone as well as with his heart and

mind.”^(=> #calibre_link-55 13

) Whatever conviction this definition loses by its sentimentality, it

gains by its applicability to more than one kind of sculpture—the

romantic definition is always less strictly romantic than it would be if

romanticism were a “movement” in the sense generally ascribed to it.

That the language of classicism cannot be so easily applied to romantic

works as that of romanticism to classical works would seem to show that

it is classicism indeed which is always a movement doomed to have an

end, and romanticism a vague name, sentimentally used on both sides, to

describe the general human movement of art; if derogatively, to attack

the vulgarity and incompetence in this movement.

The differences between the classical attitude and the romantic

attitude, when considered as temperamental reactions to the same thing,

seem to centre in the question of extravagance. The romanticist is not

afraid of extravagance. He is so earnest that the danger of excess does

not occur to him. The classicist is most of all afraid of extravagance.

He has a self-conscious lack of confidence which prevents him from being

earnest because he is aware of the danger of excess. This earnestness in

the romanticist easily leads to vulgarity, this self-consciousness in

the classicist, to snobbery. The reason why Hulme opposed fancy to the

imagination was that he had a snobbish feeling against the imagination

from its being associated with many vulgarities, not from any real

objection to imagination itself: for fancy to him was merely an

improved, more technical, narrower imagination. “Abstract” is another

“classical” word that has come to have a thoroughly snobbish

connotation. It generally means: lacking in sentimental allusions to

fairies, trees, spirituality, time, spring. Likewise “mathematical” and

“geometric” prove themselves to mean lacking in vulgar humanity, having

non-vital realism. The classical artist is a snob against himself. He

therefore separates his art from his nature and thus art from nature.

This is the history of discontinuity and the abstraction of art. Art, in

Hulme's words, is created to satisfy a desire. The desire appears to be,

in theory, the desire for art itself; to create a discontinuity in man

by isolating art from nature. So art is not the creation of a fiction,

but a very gloomy feeling in man about his own nature. Why this is not a

romantic attitude—for the romantic includes some very gloomy feelings,

indeed, about the nature of man—is that the romantic gloomy feelings do

not seem to be gloomy or pessimistic enough. Romantic gloom, of course,

can be extravagantly depressing or hysterical. But gloom for the

classicist is not final, abstract or mathematical unless it is just

gloom, without being either depressing or hysterical. Absolute gloom is

so gloomy that it does not have to be gloomy: if gloom is gloomy it

becomes vulgarized. Classical art is therefore created to satisfy a

desire for gloom which is really, however, a snobbish feeling about

romantic gloom.

IV

It has been seen that contemporary criticism, the philosophical portion

of contemporary poetic activity, has attempted to bring about some order

in the views commonly held about poetry. By doing this it has hoped to

bring about an order in the actual writing of poetry. The only order

there has been in poetry for the last hundred and thirty-five years has

been a superficial uniformity due to a confused sympathy of sentiment

and imagery in the language in which it was written. But there has been

no fundamental professional sense of the eighteenth-century sort. The

mental background has been anarchic and amateurish. When contemporary

criticism expresses its respect for the eighteenth century it is, of

course, praising its professional sense. It is impossible to believe

that it is praising eighteenth-century poetry as such, in which the

sentiment of professional uniformity lacked the energy that might have

been supplied to it by anarchy and amateurishness.

The problem of the present-day poet, therefore, who feels himself

responsible to the problem raised by criticism, is a very difficult one.

He must react against the unprofessional and superficial uniformity

which romanticism brought about—he must maintain a professional

independence of sentiment and imagery—and at the same time avoid anarchy

and amateurishness. He must resign from the emotional brotherhood which

poetry formed from a loose romantic social sense and attach himself to

the organized metaphysics of poetry professionalized in the narrowest

possible social sense as an art-and-craft.

We may say that the problem will be to a large extent solved by the

poet's originality and the discipline that should go with it if it is to

be effective originality. And it is true that the successes in

contemporary poetry have been those which have been able to combine

originality and discipline. But in general the burden of responsibility

has been with originality; discipline has been distorted, teased and

distracted by the lack, in criticism, of immediate suggestiveness, a

failure which is aggravated by the dogmatic character of its theorizing.

Criticism assumes all the prerogatives which belong to creation without

assuming any of its concrete responsibilities. It limits its share in

these responsibilities to a negative and irresponsible taste and

envelops itself in a forbidding cloud of snobbery.

Criticism says: “Art refers to an absolute. It must recognize a first

principle. Every work must imply this first principle.” “What,” is the

creative question, “is the first principle? A work cannot imply it by

interrogation; that would be romantic.” But the first principle is not

stated. It seems part of the consistency of the system that it shall not

be stated. It must be derived from the system in such a way that its

finality shall not be impaired by its relation to contemporary history.

The age itself must invent a provisional first principle, the corporeal

representative of the absolute. The absolute cannot be absolute and

appear in person. Art is ideal action. It does not so much create

“things” as reveal “things” with the things it creates. Its purpose is

“to pierce through the veil placed between us and reality” (Hulme) with

the work, not to lodge reality in the work

itself.^(=> #calibre_link-56 14

) The work is a kind of beautiful behaviour, but the beauty of this

behaviour must not be made to inhere in the work, for this would mean a

confusion of standards. Beauty must be inferred, its sameness verified.

Variety is in the instrumentality of art, not in its meaning. Its

meaning is so same that it can only be “expressed,” it cannot be

immediately present. The belief in the possibility of its being

immediately present is a perverted romantic notion.

Thus the absolute, beauty, the first principle, remain persistently

elusive unless supplied by the “age.” The critical energy of the poet is

supposed to be more concretely responsible than the creative energy of

criticism: half the energy of the poet, if not more, is to be consumed

in making the age yield its version of the first principle. This version

is known as a “theme.” If the theme is absent it is through the combined

fault of the poet and the age. The poet should have the power of

identifying himself with the temporal extent of his age, of realizing

his proper theme; and the age should lend itself to this identification.

If this happy union is not effected, criticism takes the attitude that

it is very significant that it has not been effected, that it is indeed

too bad and that the poet will have to do the next best thing, that is,

write about this very significant and deplorable handicap. “The

dissociation” (of vision and subject), says Allen Tate in his Foreword

to a volume of poems by Hart Crane, “appears decisively for the first

time in Baudelaire.”^(=> #calibre_link-57 15

) Theme-ishness, Mr. Tate wishes to suggest, wore itself out. This is

not to be interpreted as a reflection on the theme-ishness of the

absolute, but apparently on history, which has not been able to sustain

the succession of themes, and on poets, who have, because of history,

been forced to desert this succession. Nor does it contradict the

unexpressed first principle or the theoretical necessity for a theme.

“For while Mr. Eliot might have written a more ambitiously unified

poem,” Mr. Tate further says, “the unity would have been false;

tradition as unity is not contemporary.” Tradition, he means, is unity,

and contemporary criticism is busy saying this; but contemporary poetry

is not unity because it is busy proving how distressing the absence of

unity is and also paying the penalty for the sins of romanticism, which

disregarded tradition as unity and so in its anarchic enthusiasm

developed no unity but a feeble universalization of poetic language.

“For,” he goes on to say in a few sentences, “the comprehensiveness and

lucidity of any poetry, the capacity for poetry being assumed as proved,

are in direct proportion to the availability of a comprehensive and

perfectly articulated given theme.” This theme being temporarily absent

(Mr. Tate does not say who should have articulated the theme. Not the

poet, since the theme is given? Nor history, since this would imply a

critical function which Mr. Tate would surely not admit in history? The

only deduction possible is that criticism, for no discoverable reason,

has decided to be coy), “the important contemporary poet has the rapidly

diminishing privilege of reorganizing the subjects of the past,” Mr.

Tate concludes.

T. S. Eliot composed such a résumé in The Waste Land. James Joyce

attempted the same sort of thing in a more destructive way in his long

progressive use of period literary styles in Ulysses. Gertrude Stein,

lacking the sophistication of either of these, refused to be baffled by

criticism's haughty coyness and, taking the absolute and beauty and the

first principle quite literally, saw no reason, all these things being

so, why we should not have a theme, why indeed we cannot assume “a

perfectly articulated given theme.” If everybody assumed this perfectly

articulated given theme (and no one has yet shown satisfactorily why,

fortified by such a criticism, we should not), everybody would

understand Gertrude Stein. By combining the functions of critic and poet

and taking everything around her very literally and many things for

granted which others have not been naive enough to take so, she has done

what every one else has been ashamed to do. No one but Miss Stein has

been willing to be as ordinary as simple, as primitive, as stupid, as

barbaric as successful barbarism demands.

Does no one but Miss Stein realize that to be abstract, mathematical,

thematic, anti-Hellenic, anti-Renaissancist, anti-romantic, we must be

barbaric? What has happened? We have had enough triangles, circles,

spheres and hemispheres to satisfy any barbaric geometric craving, and

yet it is certain that triangles, circles, spheres, and hemispheres have

passed: the London Times recently criticized a young artist's work which

was of a geometric type as “old-fashioned.” If the geometric type (which

Hulme opposed to the vital type) has passed (as it has) it must be

because it was romantic (a romantic movement must have an end) and

because it was surprised and defeated by its own romanticism.

We have seen how near the surface romanticism lurked in Mr. Pound's

philosophy. We discover Hulme's absolute, too, to have been a

pessimist's deification of pessimism, a sentimental abstraction of

despair. Hulme's romanticism is finally and completely confessed in his

attachment to Bergson. Bergson's attraction is that in rescuing the

fundamentally romantic idea of evolution from its idealization,

evolutionary progress, he invented an elaborate, pleasurable and dreamy

way for the modern classicist to be barbaric. By interpreting evolution

as an intensive instead of an extensive process he kept the movement and

variations of evolution but eliminated the objectionable enlargement of

significance with which humanity generally accompanies its movement and

variations. By calling the true intelligence of this process intuitive

rather than intellectual he discredited the civilized personality of the

human mind: he made intelligence a principle instead of a faculty. By

defining the time-world as an absolute duration which continuously

interpenetrated itself and thus continuously produced new forms, he

suggested a movement in the absolute without attacking its absoluteness;

he made romanticism seem classical, and, above all, kept an important

place for originality in this system without displacing discipline.

The devotion of the modern classicist to originality is the most serious

flaw in his metaphysical technique. As a result of his romantic weakness

for it, discipline is perverted. Yet he cannot abandon originality,

however it perverts discipline, because he despises and wishes to

suppress the vulgar undisciplined originality of ordinary humanity. So

his classicism is designed to represent ordinary humanity only

theoretically, which means that it really represents those who have

extraordinary power or superiority over ordinary humanity. This flaw was

very obvious in Hulme's idea of the nature of the artist's vision. To

Hulme, the artist saw something that no one else saw, he directly

communicated “individuality and the freshness of things”: the only

suggestion of classicism in this being the peculiar emphasis on

“things.”^(=> #calibre_link-58 16

) Speaking again of the artist, he said: “It is because he realizes the

inadequacy of the usual that he is obliged to invent.” Direct

communication, it is further implied, is hindered by the long romantic

history of society: democratic communism of speech has destroyed the

priesthood of the artist to the absolute. The modern classicist, to

believe in the absolute, must believe in communism, but in autocratic

communism: communism permitting of originality in the autocrat. The

representative authority of the artist comes, it appears, from his

superiority: he is the autocrat of originality.

A discrepancy multiplies. How is originality to remain consistent with

the classicism of the new barbarism when every increase in originality

seems, as in modernist poetry, a movement in the direction of

romanticism, a widening of the breach between criticism and workmanship?

“The artist must discover,” criticism would reply, “classical

originality: he must invent an original type.” For a time it seemed as

if the geometric type was the sought-for original type. But it failed as

an experiment in original classicism because it was only a sophisticated

imitation, or rather caricature, of perhaps the most ordinary type of

art in the past. And it is hard to see, indeed, how the pursuit of an

original type can get any farther than a caricature of the ordinary. The

possibilities might seem greater in literature, where it has been

permissible for human personality to contribute to this desired

combination of originality and conventionality. But here, too, the

creative limit seems to be reached in caricature; in Joyce's Leopold

Blum and in Eliot's Prufrock and other “low types,” originality proves

to be, after all, only an attack on a degenerated ordinary. Ordinary and

original therefore cannot be used by classicism as reconcilable terms;

or rather their use as such reveals the contradiction in their use.

The “direct communication” by which originality is to be transmitted

contains a further contradiction. Directness of communication means

immediate ideal intelligibility. But since language has been degraded by

its experiences, much of the originality will have to be employed in

attacking the ordinary language of communication: direct communication,

like the original type, will be able to go no farther than an obscure

caricature of ordinary language, as in the dialogue in Mr. Eliot's

Fragment of a Prologue.^(=> #calibre_link-59 17

) And caricature is indirect, erratic, romantic. The poetry of Edith

Sitwell is but one instance in contemporary poetry of the romantic

caricature of language which contemporary classicism has fostered.

Another aspect of the same general flaw is the incompatibility of the

“things” which are supposed to be revealed in the direct communication

(“things” in which apparently the first principle inheres) with the

talent of the artist to see things “as no one else sees them.” The

barbaric absolute, the divine source of “things,” wherever it has

prevailed naturally, has always been marked by a penetrating

obviousness. The Pyramids are penetratingly obvious: they nearly make

absoluteness synonymous with obviousness.

Creative originality can only be consistent with barbaric communism if

it is not superior creative originality. The only kind of originality

which can see “things” “as no one else sees them” for barbaric

mass-humanity, for human ordinariness, is mass-originality: some

mystical, large-scale process in which the artist is chosen as a seeing

instrument without his ordinariness being destroyed. He may be regarded

by his tribe as divinely inspired to communicate directly, but inspired

in ordinariness. The ideal barbaric artist is superior in ordinariness

rather than in originality. For a long time the new barbarism has been

wasting itself on disguised romantics while Gertrude Stein quietly has

gone on practising a coherent barbarism under its very nose without

encouragement or recognition. Her only crime has been that she has

followed directions and disciplined away discrepancies. She has been

able to do this because she is completely without originality. Everybody

is unable to understand her and thinks that this is because she is too

original or is trying too hard to be original. But she is only divinely

inspired in ordinariness. She uses language automatically to record

pure, ultimate obviousness. She makes it capable of direct communication

not by caricaturing language in its present stage-attacking decadence

with decadence—but by purging it of its discredited experiences. None of

the words Miss Stein uses have ever had any experience. They are no

older than her use of them, and she is herself no older than her age

conceived barbarically.

Put it there in there there where they have it

Put it there in there there and they halve it

Put it there in there there and they have it

Put it there in there there and they halve it^(=> #calibre_link-60 18

)

None of these words, it can be seen, has ever had any history before

this. The design that Miss Stein makes of them is literally abstract and

mathematical because they are etymologically transparent and

commonplace, mechanical but not eccentric. If they possess originality

it is the originality of gross automatism. Their author is a large-scale

mystic, she is the darling priest of cultured infantilism to her age—if

her age but knew it.

Nothing changes from generation to generation except the thing seen, and

that makes a composition.^(=> #calibre_link-61 19

)

Her admission that there are generations does not contradict her belief

in an unvarying first principle. Times does not vary, only the sense of

time.

Automatically with the acceptance of the time-sense comes the

recognition of the beauty and once the beauty is accepted the beauty

never fails anyone.^(=> #calibre_link-62 20

)

Beauty has no history, time has no history; only the time-sense has

history. When the time-sense acclaims a beauty which was not at first

recognized, the finality of this beauty is at once established, it is as

though it had never been denied. All beauty is equally final. The reason

why the time-sense if realized reveals the finality or classicalness of

beauty is that it is the feeling of beginning, of primitiveness and

freshness which is each age's or generation's version of time.

Beginning again and again and again explaining composition and time is a

natural thing.

It is understood by this time that everything is the same except

composition and time, composition and the time of the composition and

the time in the composition.^(=> #calibre_link-63 21

)

Originality of vision, then, is invented not by the artist but by the

collective time-sense. The artist does not see “things” “as no one else

sees them.” He sees those objective “things” in which the absolute is

repeatedly verified, personalized and represented by the age. He sees

concretely and expressively what every one else who is possessed of the

time-sense has an unexpressed intuition of: the time-sense may not be

generally and particularly universal; but this does not make the

artist's vision, even his originality of vision, less collective or less

universal.

The composition is the thing seen by every one living in the living they

are doing, they are the composing of the composition that at the time

they are living is the composition of the time in which they are living.

It is that that makes living a thing they are doing. Nothing else is

different, of that almost any one can be certain. The time when and the

time of and the time in that composition is the natural phenomena of

that composition and of that perhaps every one can be

certain.^(=> #calibre_link-64 22

)

All this Gertrude Stein has understood and executed logically because of

the perfect simplicity of her mind. Believing implicitly in an absolute,

she has not been bothered to doubt the bodily presence of a first

principle in her own time. Since she is alive and everybody around her

seems to be alive, why of course there is an acting first principle,

there is composition. This acting first principle provides a “perfectly

articulated given theme” because there is time, and everybody, and the

beginning again and again and again, and composition. In her primitive

good-humour she does not find it necessary to trouble to define the

theme. The theme is to be inferred from the composition. The composition

is clear because the language means nothing but what it means in her

using of it. The composition is final because it is “a more and more

continuous present including more and more using of everything and

continuing more and more beginning and beginning and

beginning.”^(=> #calibre_link-65 23

) She creates this atmosphere of continuousness principally by her

progressive use of the tenses of verbs, by an intense and unflagging

repetitiousness and by an artificially assumed and regulated

child-mentality: the child's time-sense is so vivid that an occurrence

is always consecutive to itself, it goes on and on, it has been going on

and on, it will be going on and on; a child does perhaps feel the

passage of time, does to a certain extent feel itself older than it was

yesterday because yesterday was already to-morrow even while it was

being yesterday.

Alfred as I was saying was in Gossols when he was a very young one and

when he was a little older than a young one. Sometimes then later he saw

a little sometimes of Olga the sister of the first governess the

Herslands had had in their Gossols living staying with them. Sometimes

the Wyman fairily made up to him. This is the way he had all these in

him this that I am now beginning describing. This is now beginning to be

a history of him, a history of Alfred Hersland of all the being and all

the living in him.^(=> #calibre_link-66 24

)

This is how Gertrude Stein wrote in 1906 and this is how she was still

writing in 1926. Writing by always beginning again and again and again

keeps everything different and everything the same. It creates duration

but makes it absolute by preventing anything from happening in the

duration.

And after that what changes what changes after that, after that what

changes and what changes after that and after that and what changes and

after that and what changes after that.^(=> #calibre_link-67 25

)

The composition has a theme because it has no theme. The words are a

self-pursuing, tail-swallowing series and are therefore thoroughly

abstract. They achieve what Hulme called, but could not properly

envisage, a “perpendicular,” an escape from the human horizontal

plane.^(=> #calibre_link-68 26

) They contain no references, no meanings, no caricatures, no jokes, no

despairs. They are so automatic that it is even inexact to speak of Miss

Stein as their author: they create one another. The only possible

explanation of lines like the following is that one word or combination

of words creates the next.

As long as head as short as said as short as said as long as

head.^(=> #calibre_link-69 27

)

. . . . .

A little away

And a little away.

Everything away.

Everything and away.

Everything and away.

Away everything away.^(=> #calibre_link-70 28

)

This is repetition and continuousness and beginning again and again and

again.

Nothing that has been said here should be understood as disrespectful to

Gertrude Stein. What has been said has been said in praise and not in

contempt. She has courage, clarity, sincerity, simplicity. She has

created a human mean in language, a mathematical equation of

ordinariness, which leaves one with a tender respect for that changing

and unchanging slowness that is humanity and Gertrude Stein.

Humanity—one learns this from Gertrude Stein but not from contemporary

poetry—is fundamentally a nice person; and so is Gertrude Stein.

Having, in her recent essay Composition As Explanation, explained

composition and composed explanation and made language serve critical

and creative aims at the same time, she then proceeds to speak of

romanticism as no other contemporary critic with a classical bias has

been able to do; she speaks of it as a role which composition may play

when it is being the same thing that it is when it plays the rĂŽle of

classicism.

Everything is the same except composition and as the composition is

different and always going to be different everything is not the

same.^(=> #calibre_link-71 29

)

We may draw from this a definition of classicism: it is the sameness of

the differentness of composition. The definition of romanticism means

only a shift of emphasis, and Miss Stein does this for us.

Romanticism is then when everything being alike everything is naturally

simply different, and romanticism.^(=> #calibre_link-72 30

)

Romanticism is the differentness of the sameness of composition.

After all this, there is that, there has been that that there is a

composition and that nothing changes except composition the composition

and the time of and the time in the composition.^(=> #calibre_link-73 31

)

The time in the composition is its sameness and its differentness, its

classicism and its romanticism. If the composition is to have

lastingness it must return to the sameness. If the composition is to

have life it must begin again and again and again with the

differentness. Such seems to be Miss Stein's philosophy of history in

art. But as the composition is something which goes on and on in a

continuous present and using of everything and beginning again and again

and again, it does not seem to matter which comes first, romanticism or

classicism, or whether a work or attitude is attributed to one or to the

other or whether, indeed, it is ever necessary to refer to either.

Both, however, have a certain strategical usefulness. Classicism is a

historical formula invented by criticism for any period of history whose

art can be looked on as a whole. It is very strictly a term for the past

and for the past only. However good a work may seem, it cannot be

properly called classical unless it can be associated with other things

called classical. The word classical carries with it the weight of all

works that have ever been called classical. The impressiveness of a

“classic” is in the implication that it belongs in the company of other

great works and, regardless of its time, really dates from long ago,

from the time when the past was so solid that everything was classical.

Everything up to a certain point in history, the Renaissance say, was

classical, even the Hellenic, which has really only lost respectability

because of its Renaissance and post-Renaissance influence. This is the

ironical force of “a modern classic.” Classicism is what Miss Stein

means by “distribution and equilibration.”

But when “distribution and equilibration” is urged or attempted while

the composition is in process, when criticism recommends a

contemporaneous classicism, then it is really being the criticism of the

future, looking back on its own period (since classicism can only refer

to the past) and attempting to order its own period backwards. This is

why a division between modernist composition and modernist criticism is

inevitable. The criticism is talking backwards. The composition, because

its time is a continuous present, is talking forwards. Criticism drops a

perpendicular at the point where the continuous horizontal of

composition begins again with the contemporary time-sense. The point

where the perpendicular meets the horizontal is unreal in the

perpendicular, because past and therefore refuted by the presentness of

the point on the horizontal.

Romanticism has a broader usefulness. Referring to differentness rather

than sameness, it is a word for the present rather than for the past:

the farther works are in the past the more same they seem, the nearer to

the present, the more different. Romanticism is more useful if only by

the greater of number of works to which it may refer, also because it

characterizes without definitely classifying—“romanticism, which was not

a confusion but an extrication” as Gertrude Stein says. Afterwards comes

the distribution and equilibration, “there must be time that is

distributed and equilibrated.” Thus every period afterwards is in a way

classical. But, while the composition is going on, it is not same, it is

different, it is “an extrication.” Contemporary composition which may be

in sympathy with the classicism of contemporary criticism must

nevertheless in practice react against it; composition cannot go on if

it tries to be self-consciously same. It must be different if only

because it must have different authors. Gertrude Stein, an ideal “same”

author for a classical period, is nevertheless many different authors in

one. She might seem more intelligible if it were possible to read her as

many authors.

3

The Facts in the Case of Monsieur Poe

Poe stock goes up and up; and what with Close-up's and Appreciations and

Gups, Tips, Hints, Revelations, Communications, Studies, Essays,

Beauties, Congratulations, Intimations, Discoveries, Embroideries,

Theories, Comparisons, Editions, Diapasons, literary criticism has now

another yard of rope with which to hang itself. Poe has come to be, at

first slowly, then with increasing rapidity, one of the “good names.” He

may be evoked by advanced criticism when references run down; there is

an alliance of reciprocal favours between Poe and advanced criticism.

There is an alliance between Poe and less advanced criticism because he

has passed the required exhumation period and may be personally

reclaimed through those poems and tales by which he has always been dear

to the hearts of parlour reciters and editors of short-story classics.

He has been found to rhyme with Rimbaud. He has been found to yield a

thesis subject. He has added to the vocabulary and the voraciousness of

amateur psychologists of the abnormal. He is an example of persecuted

genius, wayward genius, practical genius, supreme artifice in art,

supreme art in artifice, narcotics, metaphysics, dream-life, love-life,

and fate. Much of the stimulus for this enthusiasm has been furnished by

the publication of hitherto unaccessible documents. Contemporary

criticism, however, is very little interested in correcting and

stabilizing the Poe legend. The popularity of Poe is due rather to his

usefulness to criticism than to criticism's usefulness to him. There is

an arrogance, a restlessness, a high pitch in the name which gives an

air of irrefutability to critical jargon. Nor does literal

investigation, when it occurs, yield anything more than the theory of

the investigator, since the subject, being cloudy but shallow, does not

complicate its usefulness as a laboratory specimen by unsuspected depth

or richness.^(=> #calibre_link-348 1

)

For Poe was too much of a mystery-man to himself to remain a mystery-man

to others. His life, like his poems, had an immediate journalistic

communicability, a mean public confidentialness. It gives little cause

for speculation on motives, misconstructions, secrecies—Poe is a

biographical failure if for no other reason than that he is too obvious.

A Poe cult can have no science, it can have only sentiment, and is

therefore completely humourless, as humourless indeed as Poe was

himself. A few trivial instances of this sentiment from “a monograph now

in preparation” and printed in one of the many Poe articles to be found

in the index of any current American (or English or French) periodical

will perhaps suggest the extent to which the cheap-jack figure of Poe

has hypnotized the good sense of contemporary letters. “Poe later became

estranged from Hirst when that worthy parodied two lines of ‘The Haunted

Palace’ thus:

Never nigger shook a shin-bone

In a dance-house half so fair.

Poe was particularly sensitive to such breaches of good taste.” The

lines parodied will be found to read:

Never seraph spread a pinion

Over fabric half so fair!^(=> #calibre_link-349 2

)

It is easy to understand that Poe was sensitive in the matter of parody;

but it seems impossible that the worst good taste could have resisted

the invitation to parody in these foolish lines. Again, the same writer

excuses Poe's irascible nerves on the ground that “poor Poe,” as “a

reviewer of current books, could not escape reading what came from the

press, and the literary output of that day was in most instances

unconscionably trashy.” Very true. But it did not occur to the author of

this article that some of this unconscionable trash was contributed by

the pen of Edgar Allan Poe. If “Poe must have gasped at such figures as:

My love, good night! let slumber steep

In poppy juice those melting eyes . . .

may we not be permitted to gasp at such figures as:

The very roses' odours

Died in the arms of the adoring airs.^(=> #calibre_link-350 3

)

“Strangely enough,” says the same writer, “it is quite impossible to

determine whether it was friendship or fear which held Poe in restraint

whenever he noticed publicly the occasional writings of Mr. English.” He

defends Poe by advancing the theory that Poe wrote “tongue in cheek,

keeping, however, always within a safe limit, so as not openly to offend

one who seems to have had some strange control over him.” Poe himself

says that he always wrote of English in “the most unmistakable irony.”

But if it is recalled that Poe over and over again found beauties in

verse not better than English's, and often worse—especially in the work

of contemporary poetesses, likewise that Poe had at his command only the

bluntest, heaviest kind of sarcasm, it will be seen that Poe was neither

behaving strangely nor “writing tongue in cheek”—a performance of which

Poe was constitutionally incapable. He was merely exercising his usual

critical policy, a form of lively, self-protective opportunism. Most of

the illustrations in Poe's critical writings are from the works of

fellow-editors and fellow-journalists, most of them absurd, as absurd as

the verse of that absurd period so consistently was—including Poe's. A

real perspective of Poe's “verse” can be had only by considering it in

relation to its contemporaneous fellow-verse, in emulation of which it

was written—the verse, say, of Neal, Pinkney, Willis, Longfellow. It was

not better, it was only more flashy. By his vulgar capacity for

measuring the limits of “popular taste” (his favourite slogan) he soon

outclassed Longfellow, a more genuine if more tame talent specializing

in the same effects as himself. Contrary to the impression given by

Poe's numerous defenders, his reputation has never been neglected. Poe

never neglected it himself during his lifetime. With the mystery tales,

which naturally reached “popular taste” sooner, as a background, and the

melancholy autobiographical tone of the name as a literary headline, it

has never been neglected since.

Looking over the history of his reputation to the opening of the

twentieth century, we find him favourably and fully represented in the

major anthologies published during that time: for example, in Griswold's

Poets and Poetry of America published during his lifetime; in Dana's

Household Book of Poetry, published eight years after his death; in

Bryant's Library of Poetry and Song, published in 1870; and in Stedman's

1900 American Anthology in which the editor says, “He gave a saving

grace of melody and illusion to French classicism, to English didactics,

to the romance of Europe from Italy to Scandinavia.” He was a schoolroom

classic long before he became one of the watchwords of advanced

criticism; and the romantic ill-fame of his personal life, wholly out of

proportion to the facts, which read neither wickedly nor impressively,

increased, if anything, the legend which Poe himself seems to have

invented.

The typical publisher's notice of a new Poe volume generally reads as

follows:

A Publication of Startling Content

EDGAR ALLAN POE—THE MAN

With a Foreword by . . . known as the “greatest living authority on Poe”

NOW THE TRUTH IS KNOWN

Since Poe's death, seventy-seven years ago, a sympathetic following has

had to accept statements of Poe's indulgences. This monumental work is a

defence, substantiated by conclusive evidence, of the character of

America's greatest literary genius.

More than Sixty-Five Per Cent. New Material, letters, records, documents

and illustrations are here published for the first time. Poe, the man of

mystery, is revealed in a standard, final biography, the only complete,

illustrated life of him “whose imperishable fame is in all lands.”

Two Volumes. 1,649 Pages. 500 Illustrations.

Even more than as “America's greatest literary genius” Poe stands as a

symbol of “the American grain” (to use a phrase of Dr. William Carlos

Williams') to those to whom Americanism means not precisely patriotism,

but a certain dashing intellectual concept.^(=> #calibre_link-351 4

) Mr. H. L. Mencken, for example, who, like Dr. Williams, is an exemplar

of Americanism in the large and luxurious sense, is not exactly

patriotic; but a worshipper of Poe. Poe to Dr. Williams is not, as he

must be to some extent to Mr. Mencken and as he was to the Reverend

Rufus Wilmot Griswold, the descendant, however wayward, of a respectable

Baltimore family; he is “a new De Soto,” an American pioneer clearing

away old-world clutter by “the plainness of his reasoning upon

elementary grammatical, syntactical and prosodic

grounds.”^(=> #calibre_link-352 5

) Some of the old-world clutter Poe thought worthy of preserving from

destruction and immortalizing along with new-world clutter that he did

not have the courage to clear away (the poetry of Mr. Cranch, Mrs.

Welby, Mr. Pinkney, etc.) was the poetry of Lord Byron, Thomas Moore,

Alfred Tennyson, Thomas Hood, etc. He even patronized Longfellow, Bryant

and Lowell until he began to feel that he was being snubbed by them.

Then Longfellow became Professor Longfellow and Mr. L. is challenged to

a sparring match. It is difficult not to sympathize with Lowell, who

wrote:

Here comes Poe with his Raven, like Barnaby Rudge

Three fifths of him genius, and two fifth sheer fudge;

Who talks like a book of iambs and pentameters;

In a way to make all men of common sense damn meters;

Who has written some things for the best of their kind;

But somehow the heart seems squeezed out by the

mind.^(=> #calibre_link-353 6

)

Indeed, Mr. L. has shown himself, if anything, too tolerant.

Three-fifths of him sheer fudge and two-fifths sheer fudge would have

been more accurate. But Mr. L. was a contemporary and a gentleman.

Another element of Poe's “originality,” according to Dr. Williams, is

his “native vigour,” his rejection of “colonial imitation.” Poe said, on

this subject: “Because it suited us to construct an engine in the first

instance, it has been denied that we could compose an epic in the

second. . . . But this is purest insanity.” And again “We have snapped

asunder the leading-strings of our British Grandmama, and, better still,

we have survived the first hours of our novel freedom, the first

licentious hours of hobbledehoy braggadocio and swagger.” The only

hobbledehoy braggadocio and swagger to be found in early

nineteenth-century American literature is in Poe; and then it is not

anti-British, but anti-Mr. Lowell, anti-Professor Longfellow, anti-Mr.

English or anti-anyone who could be construed in any sense as anti-Poe.

Dr. Williams, moreover, is not apparently aware that literary

independence was the favourite polite topic of the American Victorian

essayist. Even the objectionable Mr. Lowell, in his essay On a Certain

Condescension in Foreigners, wrote:

But whatever we might do or leave undone, we were not genteel, and it

was uncomfortable to be continually reminded that, though we should

boast that we were the great West till we were black in the face, it did

not bring us an inch nearer to the world's West-End. That sacred

enclosure of respectability was tabooed to us. The Holy Alliance did not

inscribe us on its visiting list. The Old World of wigs and orders and

liveries would shop with us, but we must ring at the area-bell and not

venture to awaken the more august clamors of the knocker. Our manners,

it must be granted, had none of those graces that stamp the caste of

Vere de Vere, in whatever museum of British antiquities they may be

hidden. In short, we were vulgar.^(=> #calibre_link-354 7

)

Dr. Williams might be enlightened by similar passages in Emerson and

other Victorians. “Lowell and Bryant,” continues Dr. Williams, “were

concerned with literature, Poe with the soul.” This of the Poe whose

energy was consumed before its due time in journalistic pettifoggery,

what Dr. Williams calls Poe's “slaughter of banality.” Poe's banal

slaughter of banality. Dr. Williams reaches the climax of his enthusiasm

in finding in him a foreshadowing of Gertrude Stein: “Sometimes he used

words so playfully his sentences seem to fly away from sense.”

Now Doubt—now Pain

Come never again,

For her soul gives me sigh for sigh,

And all day long

Shines, bright and strong,

Astarte within the sky,

While ever to her dear Eulalie upturns her matron eye—

While ever to her young Eulalie upturns her violet

eye.^(=> #calibre_link-355 8

)

No, this is Poe, not Miss Stein. But Dr. Williams is perhaps referring

to Poe's prose?

It was in no placid temper, I say, that the metaphysician drew up his

chair to its customary station by the hearth. Many circumstances of a

perplexing nature had occurred during the day to disturb the serenity of

his meditations. In attempting des Ɠeufs à la Princesse, he had

unfortunately perpetrated an omelette Ă  la Reine; the discovery of a

principle of ethics had been frustrated by the overturning of a stew;

and last, not least, he had been thwarted in one of those admirable

bargains which he at all times took such special delight in bringing to

a successful termination. But in the chafing of his mind at these

unaccountable vicissitudes, there did not fail to be mingled some degree

of that nervous anxiety which the fury of a boisterous night is so well

calculated to produce. Whistling to his more immediate vicinity the

large water-dog we have spoken of before, and settling himself uneasily

in his chair, he could not help casting a wary and unquiet eye toward

those distant recesses of the apartment whose inexorable shadows not

even the red fire-light itself could more than partially succeed in

overcoming. Having completed a scrutiny whose exact purpose was perhaps

unintelligible to himself, he drew close to his seat a small table

covered with books and papers, and soon became absorbed in the task of

retouching a voluminous manuscript, intended for publication on the

morrow.^(=> #calibre_link-356 9

)

Or

And it is the greater number of spondees in the Greek than in the

English—in the ancient than in the modern tongue—which has caused it to

fall out that while these eminent scholars were groping for a Greek

hexameter, which is a spondaic rhythm varied now and then by dactyls,

they merely stumbled, to the lasting scandal of scholarship, over

something which, on account of its long-leggedness, we may as well term

a Feltonian hexameter, and which is a dactylic rhythm, interrupted,

rarely, by artificial spondees which are no spondees at all, and which

are curiously thrown in by the heels at all kinds of improper and

impertinent points.^(=> #calibre_link-357 10

)

—Such is the language (to disregard the inaccuracy of the content of the

second quotation) which, to Dr. Williams (and others), seems “to fall

back continuously to a bare surface exhausted by having reached no perch

in tradition.”^(=> #calibre_link-358 11

)—“Seldom a long or sensuous sentence. . . . Thought, thought, mass . .

. ”—“There is nothing offensively ‘learned’ there, nothing contemptuous,

even in the witty tricks with bogus Latin which he plays on his

illiterate public, which by its power, in turn, permits him an

originality, allows him, even when he is satiric, an authenticity—since

he is not seeking to destroy but to assert, candidly, and to defend his

own.”—“His greatness is in that he turned his back and faced inland, to

originality, with the identical gesture of a Boone.”—“And for that

reason he is unrecognized.” For what reason, and by whom? By his

illiterate public, and because he tried to palm off bogus Latin on them?

Poe stayed against the thin edge, driven to be heard by the battering

racket about him to a distant screaming—the pure essence of his

locality.

The best poem is To One in Paradise.

A few lines of this poem should be reproduced:

For, alas! alas! with me

The light of Life is o'er!

“No more—no more—no more—”

(Such language holds the solemn sea

To the sands upon the shore)

Shall bloom the thunder-blasted tree

Or the stricken eagle soar!^(=> #calibre_link-359 12

)

An inhibition composed of uneven parts of snobbism and loyalty generally

inspires modern Poe enthusiasts to quote Poe in his less famous

achievements. In Dr. Williams it is three parts loyalty to prefer To One

in Paradise, one of the worst of Poe's poems, to the Raven, the best of

the worst (and all were worst); and the lesser tales to the “popular,

perfect” Gold-Bug and the Murders in the Rue Morgue, which are

undoubtedly the best. T. S. Eliot's singling out of the Assignation

should, in justice to Mr. Eliot, be assigned to the three parts

snobbism.^(=> #calibre_link-360 13

)

Concerning “the pure essence of his locality”—it is gratifying to find

Poe avoiding the temptation to exploit theatrical American subjects. But

what is “the sullen, volcanic inevitability of the place” to be found in

Poe? Presumably the essence of this locality should permeate his poems.

What is, then, the locality “so coldly nebulous” in his essays, that

“luminosity that comes of a dissociation from anything else than the

thought and ideals? America's first originality of place in literature

was, it seems, of Guy de Vere's and Israfel's, of Lenore's and Annabel's

in worlds of moon, in haunted palaces, of Eulalies and other girls with

eyes of purple tints and pearls, of chambers where the embers were

glittering and shining like the cushion's velvet lining, like the velvet

violet lining, of filmy Thules where an Eidolon covered green isles and

the lakes of Eden and uncovered the drowsy hells in the dells, dells,

dells, dells, dells, dells, dells.

About Poe there is

No supernatural mystery-

No extraordinary eccentricity of fate—^(=> #calibre_link-361 14

)

One must agree with Dr. Williams in his conclusions. There is no

supernatural mystery because Poe was plain and significant—significant

because—and this is the only amendment to be made to Dr. Williams'

generalization—he was plainly insignificant.

Many apologies may be made for Poe on the ground that, if his sins are

the sins of journalism, he was, however, forced into journalism by

economic necessity. But Poe never behaved like a man forced into

journalism; rather like a man born to journalism and to the least

competent and least dignified aspects of journalism. The spirit of

journalism vitiated his poems, his formal criticism. It even marred his

prose fiction, whose nature admitted of the exercise of a journalistic

sense. For Poe was a slipshod, insincere detective: the spring of

imaginative invention in him was not disinterested, accurate curiosity,

but a desire to produce a certain kind of effect in a reader estimated

as having the mean intelligence of the masses. If the sole object of a

work is to produce a predetermined effect, then it is bound to be

attended by vagueness rather than by particularity. The false atmosphere

of Poe's poems are caused by the same devotion to effect as is displayed

in the tales. They are both literary rush-orders.

Casting aside all inhibitions of either snobbism or loyalty let us see

how Poe, in his two most “popular, perfect” tales, conspicuously betrays

himself by revealing this vagueness to be not so much a conscious

creative device as a deficiency in mental quality, in fineness. Both of

these, indeed—they are the Gold-Bug and the Murders in the Rue

Morgue—affect and seem to demand an effect of great accuracy. But as it

is only the effect of accuracy which is demanded and not accuracy

itself, inaccuracies and discrepancies appear, covered only by the haste

of composition and the indulgence of the unexacting reader, who is taken

for granted. Can it be thought that these inaccuracies and discrepancies

were purposely introduced as an aid to the effect of accuracy? There

might be some reason for believing this if Poe had not repeatedly

represented himself as a connoisseur of detail. Poe addressed the

popular taste; but he defended himself against a hypothetical enquiring

criticism.

The main point on which the Rue Morgue mystery hangs is that it was

impossible to discover how the murderer (the ape) got in and out of the

room, which was on the fourth story of an old house. The neighbours were

at the door and the only ways out were two windows and a chimney. The

chimney was too narrow and both windows were closed. Poe tells us that

what happened was that the ape came in at one of the two windows by

climbing up a lightning-rod. The window was open, yet a large unwieldy

bedstead obscured the lower portion, pressed close against it. The only

way to open the window from the inside was to stand on the bed and slide

the hand down behind the head-board, there pressing a secret spring; a

spring so secret that the police had not observed its counterpart in the

other window of the room (which was, however, securely shut by a nail

hammered through the window-frame). A most improbable arrangement, all

round, especially as concerns the existence of such a mechanism in an

old, shabby house and on the fourth story. The ape reached the window

from the lightning-rod, which was five and a half feet away, by a

shutter three and a half feet broad which could shut like a door to

cover the whole window and was now lying flat against the wall. He

grasped the “trellis-work” on the upper part of the shutter and swung

himself into the room, landing unobserved directly on the head of the

bed. This is impossible. Poe at one point suggests that it was a

double-sashed window: he speaks of the “lower sash.” But does not say,

whether only the lower sash moved, or both sashes, or whether the two

sashes were really one single piece. If only the lower sash moved, then

the ape, grasping the shutter and kicking himself backwards (frontways

is impossible) into the room, would have been obstructed by the upper

half of the window from landing directly on the head of the bed, which

was pressed close against the window. If only the lower half moved, then

it was only the lower half that was open. If, however, the upper sash

moved too, the ape, on climbing out and shutting the window behind him,

as he is said to have done, could not have fastened this upper sash by

the secret “catch” which was at the bottom of the window and therefore

controlling the lower sash. The window would have remained open.

At another point Poe describes “the window” as “dropping upon his exit”

and becoming fastened automatically by the catch. This suggests that the

window may have been in one piece, hinged at the top with the catch at

the bottom, opening upwards and outwards (not inwards because of the bed

being in the way). In this case the shutters could not have swung beyond

halfway; they would have collided with the window, and again the ape

could not have got in. The exact constitution of the window, one of the

leading elements of the mystery, remains obscure. There are numerous

other falsities in this story: the failure of anyone to find the

sailor's pigtail ribbon lying beside the corpse until the detective

picked it up a day or so later; the subsequent movements of the ape,

which was not seen by anyone in Paris throughout the excitement; the

time-factor of the murders.

The Gold-Bug similarly does not work out in many points. If the

difference of two and a half inches between the two eye-holes of the

skull, through one of which the weighted line was to be dropped, made a

difference of “several yards” in the final calculation of the buried

treasure's position, how was it that the main branch forking from the

tree “at a height of some sixty or seventy feet” had not grown enough in

the hundred and thirty odd years that had elapsed since the death of

Captain Kidd to throw out the measurement by a quarter of a mile? Poe

carefully makes the limb growing from the branch dead in order to

obscure this: but even supposing the bough to have died the year that

the skull was nailed to it, and to have hung dead for all that time,

would the branch have stopped growing too? And what natural historic

monstrosity was this gold bug, anyhow, of a species totally new, alive

and excessively heavy? What part has it in a supposedly rationalistic

story?

Such are the methods generally used by Poe, the covering of one

obscurity with another, the heaping of aggressive scorn on his puppet

police or on his puppet critics and the establishment of a forced

confidence in himself by his knowledge of the workings of trick

mechanisms and by superfluous quotations from Latin and French. The work

and the person of Edgar Allan Poe did not need a sentimental revival or

the publication of new material in order to be seen in their proper

light. He has been no mystery and nothing pertinent to an understanding

of Poe has ever been suppressed, because Poe himself suppressed nothing.

He published more than enough to reveal the quality of his mind and of

his personality; and he was never obscure. The mystery is not Poe, but

how Poe, with all the evidence we have had from the beginning, ever came

to be a legitimate literary subject at all with serious readers and

still more serious critics. The only solution to be advanced is that the

readers are serious and the critics still more serious, but that they

cannot have read Poe. The only explanation, indeed, for Poe is that

nobody has ever read him. Otherwise it is inconceivable that even the

most serious reader and the still more serious critic should be taken in

by him.

The steps, however, by which Poe came to occupy this singular position

are not difficult to trace. First, that national vanity and academic

snobbism in French literary criticism which assumes the burden of making

writers of other nations popular to these nations; the constant need in

French poetry for new theory by which to live; and the character of

Poe's literary criticism, which was not a mature, applied criticism (a

mature criticism is never any good to any poetry but its own) but an

irrational, noisy rhetoric well suited to bolster up weak literary

theorizing. Next, that the uplift of Poe was in another respect

accomplished outside the limits of English literary criticism: by

students of abnormal psychology to whom Poe furnished an example of

eccentric genius rather by his reputed personal habits than by the

character of his poetry or of his criticism. Finally, from critical

cowardice, came the adoption of Poe by professional criticism itself and

by all camps of this criticism. It is another question, who has ever

read Poe; that he has managed, as everybody's darling, to pass through

the ranks and, arriving in a new day, to raise the standard of Al Aaraaf

side by side with that of The Waste Land is at least incontestable.

It is first of all important to remove the diĂŠresis from Poe's name and

at the same time the sentimental diĂŠresis that dots Poe's life in the

eyes of those critics to whom criticism is a form of biographical

sympathy. It is certain from the tone of all of Poe's comments on his

life, if from nothing else, that his secret and unsatisfied ambition was

to be a great autobiographer. Tear away the romance with which the

French have surrounded the spelling of his name and the facts of his

life; the romantic origin traceable to his Celtic background, where Poe

is likewise Poë (and who has not a romantic origin hidden away in his

blood somewhere?); and there is left a mediocre but vulgar talent,

placed in the less immediate foreground of public attention, seeking to

distinguish itself through affected refinements. His morbid

preoccupation with autobiographical melodrama prevented Poe from

enjoying a serene success even in the minor literary fields for which he

was perhaps fitted.

Of his apparently uneventful childish school life in England Poe later

wrote in an artificial vein of De Quincey melancholia (“the sad

experience of my schoolboy days”); he was never at any time without a

Mme de Warens. And whether or not he invented an opportunity for helping

the Greeks against “their Turkish tyrants,” he was at any rate guilty of

many personal Byronisms,^(=> #calibre_link-362 15

) such as Byron collars, an overbearing manner and his swim “from

Ludlam's wharf to Warwick (six miles) in a hot June sun, against one of

the strongest tides ever known in the river.” (“The writer,” he says in

a letter, “seems to compare my swim with that of Lord Byron. . . . Any

swimmer ‘in the falls’ in my days would have swum the Hellespont, and

thought nothing of the matter.”) The Goethe-Rousseau-Byron-De Quincey

autobiographical romanticism with which he later scented his early life

was mainly retrospective fiction. He had a dutiful though indifferent

foster-father, a sentimental, doting foster-mother, child-loves,

early-loves, education, an allowance he considered illiberal and a

desire to run away—in other words an exceedingly normal and comfortable

early history as early histories go. But partly from inherited dramatic

instincts—both his parents had been actors—and partly from the

intoxication of authorship in a febrile brain, he was pleased to invent

for himself a heroism and a pathos. The pathos carried him through life,

the heroism through literature. His life, from his own lips, conveyed

passion in conflict with the enemies of passion, mysterious destiny and

that atmosphere of spiritual brooding which makes ambition forgivable as

the whimsical tail of genius. Unfortunately for Poe, English is a poor

language for atmosphere, it is too plain, too suspicious: as a Rimbaud

or a Verlaine he was only sham French. Even as a Byron he lacked the

easy swagger and generosity of mood proper to truly elevated vulgarity.

His literary ambitiousness suggests comparison with Keats. But Keats did

not calculate success. He had a haughty enthusiasm for himself,

something just a degree beyond vanity, that prevented him from aiming.

Poe aimed. He conducted his career like a business-man, he invested in

himself. Otherwise miscalculations of taste and sense need not

necessarily have meant failure. As it was, one false move would lose

him. And as he was all false moves, he had to spend his energy in making

them seem consistent with one another, and so to come out right.

Undoubtedly every poet, or every person who has ever written poems, has

at some time thought of himself as a candidate for fame and thus caused

temporary exaggerations in his person and work. Where such exaggerations

are due to innocent enthusiasm, they are merely romantic lapses and do

not permanently damage the respect, or personal virtue, which should

attach to character that is to be remembered. But Poe was consistent and

crafty in his exaggerations and therefore unforgivable There is an

unclean taint in his personal relationships, which were intense but not

serious; in the astuteness with which he devoted himself to athletics,

adventure, soldiering and being unhappy—an astuteness without rapture;

in the pity with which he always spoke of himself; in the swollen

self-consciousness of his prefaces and of the Marginalia. It was not

even a monstrous taint, but a small, comtemptible, paranoic one. Poe has

been a popular subject of psychological criticism, which is fond of

denning genius in terms of abnormality. It is true he had an abnormal

passion for greatness, but for greatness of reputation, not greatness of

work.

Paranoia, then, was not an unconscious element of Poe's poetic genius,

but a wilfully created fiction of persecution and a publicity method.

Mr. Allan was an ideal poet's guardian. At the worst, his attitude to

Poe may be called “sensible.” His idea of his duty to him was to provide

him with stable “future prospects.” Considering the sentimental intimacy

existing between Poe and his wife, he can be forgiven for wanting in

affection for him, even for reacting against him if this intimacy was as

effusive as all Poe's future ones with women. The illusion of

persecution, it may be said, has been common in poets—in Shelley, for

example. But in the first place Shelley's family was actively hostile to

him; in the second place Shelley had a genuine sense of universal

persecution, the obsession of mankind in pain. The weakness of Poe's

romantic pessimism is that it concerned no one but himself, and himself

in small matters. The difficulties of his life are those of a pushing

talent, not of a tragic genius.

With women, especially with older women, Poe's favourite rĂŽle was that

of the unhappy and persecuted youth of genius. This inclination for

older rather than younger women was a persistent one. It was undoubtedly

on Mrs. Clemm's account that he married Virginia: Mrs. Clemm informally

succeeded Mr. Allan as guardian when the latter's interest and sense of

duty to Poe weakened and when, finally, he entirely neglected him in his

will. So Poe combined sentiment and patronage. The fact is, Poe did not

like men and did not get on with them. He needed the companionship of

women because they pitied him and because their pity did no damage to

his dignity—it was merely their tribute to his nobility. Virginia, who

as a little girl had carried his love letters, as his wife never

interfered with any of Poe's sentimental romances. To her they were

“poetical episodes in which the impassioned romance of his temperament

impelled him to indulge.” Unfortunately most of the objects of Poe's

“impassioned romances” did not make suitable heroines of Sentiment; they

were respectable women, on too small a scale for the grande passion,

exercising their maternal instinct and their poetical female fancy on an

affected and rather ridiculous young man. However sympathique Poe may

have been to his poetesses and early and late loves, it is impossible to

see him otherwise than as a vain and foolish aspirant, whose real

misfortunes, even, seem unreal because he sympathized too much with

himself.

Two years after he left West Point Poe won a prize given by The Saturday

Morning Visiter for the best short story submitted in a competition.

Through the publicity gained by this success he made many influential

friends and connections with current magazines. In two years he became

the editor of the Southern Literary Messenger. Before he was

twenty-three Poe had published three volumes of poems, the first when he

was eighteen. In the preface to this he claims most of them to have been

written before the completion of his fourteenth year; and its style

reveals, indeed, the self-appointed child of genius making his first

disdainful bow to the public.

They were not of course intended for publication; why they are now

published concerns no one but himself. . . . In “Tamerlane” he has

endeavoured to expose the folly of even risking the best feelings of the

heart at the shrine of Ambition. . . . There are many faults . . . which

he flatters himself he could, with little trouble, have corrected, but

unlike many of his predecessors, has been too fond of his early

productions to amend them in his old age.

He will not say that he is indifferent to the success of these Poems—it

might stimulate him to other attempts—but he can safely say that failure

will not influence him in a resolution already adopted. This is

challenging criticism—let it be so. “Nos haec novimus esse

nihil.”^(=> #calibre_link-363 16

)

The theme of nearly all of these early poems of Poe's is thwarted Power.

The “cold reality of waking life” Poe knew before he had awakened, by

temperamental premonition: he was born saying “I have been happy, Tho'

in a dream.” Tamerlane is his Childe Harold. In the 1829 edition he

shortened the poem, but made it, if anything, even more unabashed than

the excited but rather ingenuous original.

An examination of Byron's first literary confession, his preface to

Hours of Idleness, will best show the class into which Poe's adolescent

snobbery falls. This preface is preceded by quotations from Horace,

Homer and Dryden and continues as follows:

TO THE RIGHT HONOURABLE

FREDERICK, EARL OF CARLISLE

KNIGHT OF THE GARTER ETC. ETC.,

THE SECOND EDITION OF THESE POEMS IS INSCRIBED

BY HIS

OBLIGED AND AFFECTIONATE KINSMAN

THE AUTHOR

In submitting to the public eye the following collection, I have not

only to combat the difficulties writers of verse generally encounter,

but may incur the charge of presumption for obtruding myself on the

world, when, without doubt, I might be, at my age, more usefully

employed.

These productions are the fruits of the lighter hours of a young man who

has lately completed his nineteenth year. As they bear the internal

evidence of a boyish mind, this is perhaps unnecessary information. . .

. I am sensible that the partial and frequently injudicial admiration of

a social circle is not the criterion by which poetical genius is to be

estimated. . . . Poetry, however, is not my primary vocation; to divert

the dull moments of indisposition, or the monotony of a vacant hour,

urged me ‘to this sin’: little can be expected of so unpromising a muse.

[Here follows a sardonic reference to the ‘genuine’ bards.]

With slight hopes, and some fears, I publish this first and last

attempt. . . . The opinion of Dr. Johnson, on the Poems of a noble

relation of mine,

*

‘that when a man of rank appeared in the character of an author, he

deserved to have his merit handsomely allowed,’ can have little weight

with verbal, and still less with periodical censors; but were it

otherwise, I should be loth to avail myself of the privilege, and would

rather incur the bitterest censure of anonymous criticism, than triumph

in honours granted solely to a title.^(=> #calibre_link-365 17

)

Poe's second publication of poems owned the conspicuously suppressed

authorship of the first “By a Bostonian” and offered the gratuitous

information that this was “suppressed through circumstances of a private

nature.” The first was without dedication, the second bore two

dedications, a formal literary dedication

Who drinks the deepest?—here's to him.—

Cleveland;

and a personal dedication of Tamerlane to John Neal, Editor of the

Yankee, the first of the long suite of editors and persons of literary

influences whom Poe so frantically pursued during his whole lifetime. To

the theme of the first volume, thwarted power, this volume added the

minor vein of renunciatory solitude.

Poe's third volume, formally dedicated to the U.S. Corps of Cadets, was

published in the same year that he obtained his dismissal from the West

Point Military Academy. The literary quotation on the title page this

time reads “Tout le monde a Raison.—Rochefoucault.” It is accompanied by

an elaborate preface in the form of a letter to Mr.—. It includes an

ingenious defence of a poet's good opinion of his own work; an

impassioned refutation of the Lake School as making poetry so removed

from popular understanding as to rob it of pleasure; a special trouncing

of Wordsworth; a partial pleading for Coleridge; and a formal definition

of poetry in reference to science, romance, music and prose. This is a

specimen of Poe's prefatorial manner: “Think of poetry, dear B—Think of

poetry and then think of—Dr. Samuel Johnson! Think of all that is airy

and fairy-like, and then of all that is hideous and unwieldy: think of

his huge bulk, the Elephant! and then—and then think of the Tempest—the

Midsummer Night's Dream—Prospero—Oberon—and Titania!” It is clear from

these early writings that Poe's professional arrogance and violence must

not be laid to alcoholism. The more we learn about Poe, the more

grateful we are for his alcoholism. It was apparently the one thing that

could restrain Poe from himself: the idea of a sober Poe is intolerable.

The impression to be got from everything written by Poe is that it was

meant to be read immediately, that its design was a spontaneous and

gratifying effect; that is, his creative direction was always

journalistic. Indeed Poe wasted the best part of his energy in editing

and writing for magazines and in trying to found one of his own. It is

Poe's passion for journalism that prevented him from ever reaching

maturity in his art and in his criticism; and the literary uses to which

he put journalism that prevented him from attaining any dignity as a

journalist.

The constant agitation in which Poe is found, his unashamed solicitation

of approval, his rash exercise of critical vanity in place of critical

judgment, all this makes the picture of an Effort conniving at too great

an Aim and therefore driven to practice certain violences and delusions

on itself. The intensity of Poe's campaign for greatness is shown by the

way in which a portion of posterity has succumbed to it. Poe had a

terrible suspicion of success in others; everywhere he looked he seemed

to see a need for self-justification. The result was the pompous and

childish disdain with which he wrote of the Literati: “Some honest

opinions about authorial merits and demerits, with occasional words of

Personality”; and the note of false ease and self-confidence in which he

couched his more regular compositions.

The Marginalia in particular (originally newspaper book-chat) give

evidence of Poe's nervousness, his desire to achieve a natural manner

through journalism. In these, by writing as casually as he knew how, he

hoped to prove himself at home in literature. The futile sarcasm of

these notes, their showiness in strained and overworked literary

references, expose his greatest weakness, his inability to be off-hand.

His desire in them was to exercise wit and opinion without the restraint

imposed by more formal journalistic channels, to enjoy in public the

privilege of private ranting. They are full of examples of the

perversion of taste by journalism: his attachment to journalism itself

(“I will not be sure that men at present think more profoundly than half

a century ago, but beyond question they think with more rapidity, with

more skill, with more tact, with more of method and less of excrescence

in the thought. Besides all this they have a vast increase in the

thinking material, they have more facts, more to think about. For this

reason they are disposed to put the greatest amount of thought in the

smallest compass and disperse it with the utmost attainable rapidity.

Hence the journalism of the age; hence, in especial, magazines. Too many

we cannot have, as a general proposition.”); his tribute to Thomas Moore

(this was just before Moore had “gone out”) and Tennyson, “the greatest

of poets”; his disproportionate interest in Dickens and the criticism of

Dickens; technical appreciations of Longfellow; an ill-tempered and

uneasy weakness for Ossian, echoing his condemnation of Wordsworth, in

an early preface, for his “absurdity” in attempting to prove the

worthlessness of these poems (“But worse still:”—to quote from this

preface—“that he [Wordsworth] may beat down every argument in favour of

these poems, he triumphantly drags forward a passage, in his abomination

of which he expects the reader to sympathize. It is the beginning of the

epic poem ‘Temora.’ ‘The blue waves of Ullin roll in light; the green

hills are covered with day; trees shake their dusky heads in the

breeze.’ And this—this gorgeous, yet simple imagery—where all is alive

and panting with immortality—than which earth has nothing more grand,

nor paradise more beautiful—this William Wordsworth, the author of

‘Peter Bell,’ has selected to dignify with his supreme contempt”).

Much of Poe's critical irritability was undoubtedly due to his private

awareness of his errors of taste. Obviously sentiment and taste were in

conflict in him and he formed his judgments by allowing sentiment to

rule taste; without, however, being willing to admit the total defeat of

taste. The truth is that Poe had an equal capacity for the right and the

wrong in literature, but a morbid perversity by which he could not

resist the temptation to his pride to go wrong. And in defending his

errors Poe defended his sentiment, never his taste. He is never at rest,

he is continually visualizing himself as the protagonist of a drama in

which he is the defender of an unpopular but noble sentiment, or

inventing “good ideas for a Magazine paper,” whether it is to show how

“a modest young gentleman” gets the better in an argument of “a flippant

pretender to universal acquirement” or how a particular poem attained

its ultimate point of completion. “Why such a paper has never been given

to the world, I am much at a loss to say—but perhaps the authorial

vanity has more to do with the omission than any one other cause.” And

so Poe sets about to write such a paper on the construction of The Raven

to flout popular superstitions about authorial vanity and the

mysteriousness with which the processes of creation are supposed to be

surrounded, describing a poetic method for The Raven most likely to

antagonize popular superstition.^(=> #calibre_link-366 18

) This mechanical recipe-method, by the way, is apparently contrary to

the actual facts of the case. For according to the two stories of its

composition circulated by unprejudiced personal gossip, more acceptable

than Poe's too neat, too glib mathematical scheme for the poem (unless

Poe meant his own story to be understood as a critical joke, which is

unlikely), the poem was either “dashed off” one evening after a long

walk at Poe's most gloomy period, when Virginia was on her deathbed and

the family starving, or its composition covered a longer period, being

written in instalments, passed round among his friends over and over

again for criticism, altered, rewritten, juggled into shape: whichever

of these two may be true, nevertheless constructed along any but

systematic lines.

Poe's egotism was so extremely sensitive that it was always expressed as

a defence of his offensiveness, not of his greatness: he had a

superstitious faith in opposition and therefore a martyr's love of

insult. When accused of madness he could make no definite reply but a

categorical defence of madness: “The question is not yet settled whether

madness is or is not the loftiest intelligence, whether much that is

glorious, whether all that is profound, does not spring from diseases of

thought—from moods of mind exalted at the expense of the general

intellect.” In this manner Poe laid the foundations for the myth of

genius via abnormality by which he was subsequently ennobled in literary

history. “Why, to be frank,” he says in the Gold-Bug, “I felt somewhat

annoyed by your evident suspicions touching my sanity, and so resolved

to punish you quietly, in my own way, by a little bit of sober

mystification.” In the preface of the 1845 edition of his poems,

dedicated to Elizabeth Barrett Barret, “the noblest of her sex,” appears

just such another scornful statement of a principle he knew would be

inacceptable to the critical public. In defending himself from this

public he removes all possibility of critical sympathy by defining his

poetry as a passion, not as a purpose (a way of stating his indifference

“to the paltry commendations of mankind” calculated to prove most

obnoxious to mankind), and by concluding with the sweeping

generalization that “the passions must be held in reverence.” He behaved

as if, his case being hopeless with criticism, he was free to yield to

his temperament and use the manner of a private diary.

But Poe's personal arrogance about his work is one matter and the work

another and his critical writing still another. The private diarist is

protecting himself from failure by haughtily anticipating failure. The

author of the work is protecting himself from failure by making neat

calculations on the side in the science of popular taste. The critic is

protecting himself from the possible vulgar success of the author by

trying to establish that vulgar success can also be literary success. So

the critic and the private diarist are reconciled, since the failure of

the diarist meant, of course, only vulgar failure. The vulgar success of

Poe's poems was elevated into formal literary success in two ways. They

have obviously that lack of distinction and that facility of sentiment

which are the two requirements for acceptable magazine verse—poetry,

that is, which neither has nor desires a passport to criticism. But

since these magazine successes, these little recitation classics, are

the result of a design, a journalist's careful measurement of how far

surface-emotions of the reader may be taken, the design in itself is

criticism. Poe thus made criticism of his poems and poems of his

criticism, and they have conferred on each other a mutual distinction,

in both cases an acquired one. The second formal corroboration of the

vulgar success of Poe's poems is of an accidental nature: that by their

technical musicalness and sense-combining effects they happen to appeal

to those pianoforte experimentalists in French poetry who are always

trying to achieve the surface purity which music and painting, for

example, are thought to have. Perhaps more than half of Poe's literary

respectability is just such back-door respectability.

His criticism, indeed, cannot be estimated except as part of his

personal system. It is constantly cancelling itself in anti-climaxes; as

the generalities of ambition in Poe's temperament are never matched by

particular potentialities. His campaign against the long poem, for

example, is really only a denunciation of its commercial unreadableness.

The interest-value of the poem is at the bottom of all of Poe's critical

writing. The contemporary success of a poem is its selling-power; and in

his criticism he could discuss this interest-value without violating the

professed indifference to success of the private diarist. All of his

suppressed anxiety to please comes out in his essays in the guise of

critical theory. And as music is the art which concerns itself most with

the problem of co-ordinating its technique with the impressionability of

the audience, it becomes the analogy on which his construction of the

poem is based. His poetic absolute, therefore—“the poem written solely

for the poem's sake”—reveals itself as the duty of a poem to give

nothing but pleasure; pleasure being further qualified as the “thrill”

which poetry communicates by the taint of sadness, the finger-mark of

Beauty. Beauty was exemplified in the works of Willis, Longfellow,

Bryant, Edward C. Pinkney, Byron, Thomas Moore (who not so far back had

visited America and condoled with those Americans who were moved by his

pity to confide in him their disappointment

that the powerful stream

Of America's empire should pass like a dream,

Without leaving one relic of genius . . . ),^(=> #calibre_link-367 19

)

Thomas Hood, Tennyson.

We can get a truer picture of Poe as a critical mind by comparing him

with Shelley, another sentimental theorist, rather than by looking at

him through the eyes of that advanced criticism which, perhaps because

of its subservience to French literary tastes, has condescendingly

opened the pearly gates to him. Both Poe and Shelley fixed on Love as

the underlying human principle of poetic Beauty. Shelley's explanation

of this principle is:

Poetry lifts the veil from the hidden beauty of the world, and makes

familiar objects be as if they were not familiar; it reproduces all that

it represents, and the impersonations clothed in its Elysian light stand

thenceforward in the minds of those who have once contemplated them, as

memorials of that gentle and exalted content which extends itself over

all thoughts and actions with which it coexists. The great secret of

morals is love; or a going out of our nature, and an identification of

ourselves with the beautiful which exists in thought, action, or person,

not our own. A man, to be greatly good, must imagine intensely and

comprehensively; he must put himself in the place of another and of many

others; the pains and pleasures of his species must become his own. The

great instrument of moral good is the imagination; and poetry ministers

to the effect by acting upon the cause. Poetry enlarges the

circumference of the imagination by replenishing it with thoughts of

ever new delight, which have the power of attracting and assimilating to

their own nature all other thoughts, and which form new intervals and

interstices whose void forever craves fresh

food.^(=> #calibre_link-368 20

)

And Poe's:

—Love—the true, the divine Eros—the Uranian, as distinguished from the

Dionaean Venus—is unquestionably the purest and truest of all poetic

themes . . . we shall reach, however, more immediately a distinct

conception of what true Poetry is, by mere reference to a few of the

simple elements which induce in the Poet himself the true poetical

effect. He recognizes the ambrosia which nourishes his soul, in the

bright orbs that shine in Heaven—in the volutes of the flower—in the

clustering of low shrubberies—in the waving of the grain-fields—in the

slanting of tall Eastern trees—in the blue distance of mountains—in the

grouping of clouds—in the twinkling of half-hidden brooks—in the

gleaming of silver rivers—in the repose of sequestered lakes—in the

star-mirroring depths of lonely wells. He perceives it in the songs of

birds—in the harp of Aeolus—in the sighing of the night-wind—in the

repining voice of the forest—in the surf that complains to the shore—in

the fresh breath of the woods—in the scent of the violet-in the

voluptuous perfume of the hyacinth—in the suggestive odour that comes to

him, at eventide, from far-distant, undiscovered islands, over dim

oceans, illimitable and unexplored. He owns it in all noble thoughts—in

all unworldly motives—in all holy impulses—in all chivalrous, generous,

and self-sacrificing deeds. He feels it in the beauty of woman—in the

grace of her step—in the lustre of her eye—in her sigh—in the harmony of

the rustling of her robes. He deeply feels it in her winning

endearments—in her burning enthusiasms—in her gentle charities—in her

meek and devotional endurances—but above all—ah, far above all—he kneels

to it—he worships it in the faith, in the purity, in the strength, in

the altogether divine majesty—of her love.^(=> #calibre_link-369 21

)

The essay from which this is taken closes with a mock-antique poem in

illustration of this principle, “The Song of the Cavalier” by William

Motherwell, who was Editor of the Paisley Advertiser and later of the

Glasgow Courier, a fellow-journalist.

Then mounte! then mounte, brave gallants, all, And don your helms

amaine!” etc.^(=> #calibre_link-370 22

)

Let the advanced critic now, to whom Poe is a tribal watchword and

Shelley an outcast because he was not literary, swallow this and see

whether he can keep it down. Shelley had too earnest a social sense and

his poetry suffers from his sympathies. But it is not difficult to keep

Shelley down: he does harm to no advocate's dignity. If Shelley had not

been over-affected by the ugliness of human society he would have been

great—Shelley was momently too unhappy to be great. And perhaps this is

as it should be, if he meant to preserve a sort of non-literary human

integrity: there is always a certain meanness in greatness. Whatever may

have happened to Shelley's poetry, Shelley himself remained true; while

Keats, of whom Poe is a cheaper edition, grew too literary to be true.

Poe, that is, is cockney, though he never realized this, masquerading as

true because he thought himself unhappy—Poe always had a tear in his

pocket, as Keats a sigh in his handkerchief. They are both, however,

seen as upholders of a Taste which Shelley is thought to have violated,

because neither of them had power to do more than put forward their

personal claims to fame.

“I prefer commencing with the consideration of an effect,” boasts Poe,

having once decided that “a” poem must be written which shall “suit at

once the popular and the critical taste”—we are given no clue as to

which is which.^(=> #calibre_link-371 23

) Deeply conscious of the fact that his own limitations forced him to

oppose virtuosity to genius, Poe was always brazenly on the defensive in

discussing poetic technique. Real poetry (poetry that was a passion not

a purpose!), he convinced himself, was always written by rhythm and

rote. Indeed an “interesting magazine paper might be written by any

author who would . . . ” etc. It was a shame-complex that drove Poe to

the exhibitionism of his analysis of the Raven—of which he was probably,

because of its history, most ashamed. The recipe for the ideal poem to

be deduced from this analysis is:

1. A one-sitting length (about 100 lines).

2. Elevation and excitement.

3. Universal appeal.

4. Beauty (not Truth or Passion)—“Truth demands a precision, and Passion

a homeliness, which are absolutely antagonistic to that Beauty which, I

maintain, is the excitement, or pleasurable elevation, of the soul.”

5. Melancholy—“Melancholy is the most legitimate of all poetical tones.”

6. “Artistic poignancy”—“points, in the theatrical sense”—in the Raven

the refrain, in various combinations, performs this function.

7. Finding the refrain—take o and r and it is “absolutely impossible to

overlook the word ‘Nevermore’”!

8. Now find “a pretext” for using the refrain. “A parrot”? No, “a

Raven—it is infinitely more in keeping with the tone.”

9. Choosing the subject—“‘Of all melancholy topics, what, according to

the universal understanding of mankind, is the most melancholy?’

Death—was the obvious reply.”

10. Getting together the scenery—“‘And when,’ I said, ‘is this most

melancholy of topics most poetical? When it most closely allies itself

to Beauty: the death, then, of a beautiful woman is, unquestionably, the

most poetical topic in the world—and equally is it beyond doubt that the

lips best suited for such topic are those of a bereaved lover.’”

With these few simple precautions, the rest is easy, “the ominous

reputation of the fowl” will carry it through. Of course, write the

first stanza last, and work backward until the hundred (or hundred and

eight) lines are used up, “enfeebling” them as the beginning is neared

to preserve the “climacteric effect” of the last. And of course, a

little originality in rhythm and metre. Then put the lover in a room, “a

close circumscription of space” to make all cosy, and let in the fowl,

who alights on a bust of Pallas, “chosen, first, as most in keeping with

the scholarship of the lover, and, secondly, for the sonorousness of the

word Pallas itself. With an “indulgence, to the extreme, of

self-torture” and an eye to the “artistical eye” and a few minor

considerations having chiefly to do with sauce, the poem is done to a

turn.

Such is the philosophy of composition and such the theorist who has

contributed so much to the science of modern French verse. Recently

Valéry's translator, Mr. Malcolm Cowley, quoted from his translation of

Variété the following:

What critics call a realization, or a successful rendering, is really a

problem of efficiency . . . in which the only factors are the nature of

the material and the mentality of the public. Edgar Allan Poe . . . has

clearly established his appeal to the reader on the basis of psychology

and probable effect.

The most important ingredient of literary composition is the idea of the

most probable reader. . . . The change of century, which means a change

of reader, is comparable to an alteration in the text

itself.^(=> #calibre_link-372 24

)

Adding himself the never-failing analogy: “The poem is conceivably, the

pearl certainly, the result of an unhealthy condition. But this has

nothing whatever to do with their own effects.” The poem, by excessive

analogy—criticism's last resort—with pictures, symphonies, pearls and

other consumable products, ceases to be production. What Valéry calls

“the problem of efficiency” is the elimination of production.

Consumption is production. Demand is supply. Poet is public. Poet is a

dud.

Even Mr. Eliot sandwiches Poe between Donne and Mallarmé as a

metaphysical poet, treating the problem of Poe's effects and his methods

of achieving them with apparent seriousness.^(=> #calibre_link-373 25

) (Poe is to be tolerated in this position if only to separate Donne

from Mallarmé.) Yet Poe's contributions to the theory of verse amounted

to no more than a bombastic attack on the prosodists, to prove that the

alternation of syllables in verse was not regular; a theory that all

life began with the spondee; and all that false technical association of

verse with music (“verse, an inferior or less capable

music”^(=> #calibre_link-374 26

)) which is found to be of service and self-gratification to criticism

when the life-blood of poetry has run low and criticism is looking for a

“science” by which it may be restored.

And who are Poe's references or authorities in his indignant rationale

of verse? Mr. N. P. Willis, author of “such lines” as

That binds him to a woman's delicate love—

“but one of the innumerable instances he has given of keen sensibility

in all those matters of taste which may be classed under the general

head of fanciful embellishment; Mr. Horne (of England), the author of

‘Orion,’ one of the noblest epics in any language”; Edgar Allan Poe, in

“Al Aaraaf, a boyish poem written by myself when a boy” in which occur

“two consecutive equivalent feet”—“I cannot say I have ever known the

adventure made” (except here)—equivalent, “that is to say, feet the sum

of whose syllabic time is equal to the sum of the syllabic times of the

distinctive feet”; “one of the finest poets, Mr. Christopher Pease

Branch,^(=> #calibre_link-375 27

) who begins a very beautiful poem thus”:

Many are the thoughts that come to me

In my lonely musing:

Mrs. Welby, author of “a little poem of great beauty” containing a

“variable foot”:

I have a little stepson of only three years old.

Miss Mary A. S. Aldrich, author of “quite a pretty specimen of verse”:

The water lily sleeps in pride

Down in the depths of the azure lake.

One would like to pity Poe, if possible, as he wished, but his appeals

for pity were so undignified that it is scarcely dignified to pity him.

One would like to sympathize with him in his outspoken and fierce

attacks on contemporary criticism and pedantry—there is no doubt Poe

lived in one of the worst of times for literature. But they have a bad

grace and an overweeningness that harm the attacker rather than the

attacked. His wit was warped and thinned out by petty ambitioning; and

whatever our feelings may be about the North American Review as it was

in Poe's time, we are not amused when Poe suggests that it be thrown to

the pigs.

Poe was only satiric when he lost his temper, and as he was continually

losing his temper he could not be satiric with much conviction. He was

always losing his temper because he was always looking for the ideal

public. The ideal public was one which could immediately appreciate his

work, which was ideal for the ideal public. He knew what the ideal

public was, but it was apparently as slow as it was ideal. It was not

the false sales public, nor the clique public. It was, it seems, that

“not-too-acute reader,” as he called him in his review of Barnaby Rudge,

that “excitable, undisciplined and childlike popular mind which most

keenly feels the original,” as he called him in his review of Twice Told

Tales. The fault, indeed, he had to find with Hawthorne was that he was

not original, only “peculiar,” that is, he did not make use of that

technique of which effect is the sole object and in which new and

“pleasurable” emotions are aroused through the mechanism of mystery.

Poe, in his praise of originality, excluded those who “limited the

literary to the metaphysical originality.” (How does this tally with Mr.

Eliot's classification of Poe as metaphysical?) Metaphysical

originality, Poe claimed, offended the masses because, by seeking

absolute novelty of combination, it resembled instruction.—“True

originality . . . combines with the pleasurable effect of apparent

novelty, a real egotistic delight.” Hawthorne, by his charm and

fancifulness, shared in this true originality, but in a lesser degree,

not so much because his allegory was false as because it was “removed

from the popular intellect, from the popular sentiment, and from the

popular taste.” Allegory was too close to truthfulness—it cannot be too

strongly emphasized that to Poe the essence of composition was

fictitiousness designed to produce an effect. This is why he evoked

music in support and this is why he glorified the mystery-story and the

mystery-poem—the petty journalist's contribution to the problem of

reconciling the rough reading masses to the fine writers. The poem and

the tale were to him the two complementary acts of creation, the poem

being obliged to use “artificialities” of rhythm to bring out “the idea

of the Beautiful” which were “an inseparable bar” to “Truth,” the tale

being able to make use of elements “(the ratiocinative, the sarcastic or

the humorous) which are not only antagonistical to the nature of the

poem, but absolutely forbidden by one of its most peculiar and

indispensable adjuncts; we allude, of course, to rhythm.”

It is a sad picture, a gloomy and sentimental hack, seeing plagiarism of

himself everywhere because his own poor capacities for melodrama

naturally produced the same results as other poor capacities; plotting

mystery tales, plotting mystery poems, solving conjuror's tricks;

constructing feeble ladyships and creaking phantoms; triumphantly

checking the plot errors in long, dull Victorian serial stories;

thinking up “good ideas” for Magazine articles. The solution seems to be

to leave him to the romantic esteem of the French, who are so eminently

qualified to sympathize with (ah!) “les beaux cris de passion sincùre,

les beaux Ă©lans d'amour,”^(=> #calibre_link-376 28

) as his French translator, M. Gabriel Mourey, calls them; to receive in

tender immortality the many who were Poe's only loves and to place him

among the candidates for pity in whom their own literary history is so

rich. “Baudelaire, MallarmĂ©, Hennequin, Rollinat, vous-mĂȘme d'autres

encore . . . ”^(=> #calibre_link-377 29

) (Rimbaud and Verlaine we might add) “on a tant fait en France pour y

acclimater Edgar Poe que ses compatriotes affirment que l'auteur du

Corbeau Ă©tait francais,” wrote John H. Ingram, Poe's most inspired

advocate to Poe's French translator.^(=> #calibre_link-378 30

) One leading clue to Poe's French reputation seems to be that “Poe

aimait la France et son admirable littérature et ne parlait qu'avec

respect des chefs-d'Ɠuvre qu'elle a produits; jamais sa plume caustique

ne serait essayer à diminuer sa gloire.”^(=> #calibre_link-379 31

) Another is that by the antagonism his personality left behind him, he

could be used as an effective scourge against the “philistins.” Poe's

chief adaptability to the French temper, however, must lie in the

infinite advantage any inferior work has when translated into French, a

language whose large sonorousness and refined daintiness supplies to

Poe's poems just that element of musical “fugitiveness” which the

English language is more strict in refusing to yield.

“ProphĂšte” dis-je, “crĂ©ature du mal!—ProphĂšte cependant, oiseau ou

dĂ©mon !—

Soit le Tentateur t'ait mandĂ© ou soit que la TempĂȘte t'ait rejetĂ© sur ce

rivage,

Désolé, mais indompté, sur cette terre déserte enchantée.

Sur ce foyer hautĂ© par l'Horreur—dis-moi, vraiment, je t'implore—

Y a-t-il, -y a-t-il un baume dans Galaad? Dis-moi—dis-mois, je

t'implore!”

Fit le Corbeau: “Jamais plus.”^(=> #calibre_link-380 32

)

A few internal rhymes may, of course, be lost in the translation, but

Poe would undoubtedly have remedied this deficiency if he had written

the poem originally in French himself.

One mystery remains, the popularity of Poe with that portion of critical

opinion which should, by all sense and taste, disregard him most. Why,

indeed, should Mr. Eliot share with the French their particular

admiration for the tale called the Assignation? Because of the poetical

motto from Henry King's (Bishop of Chichester) Exequy On The Death Of

His Wife, and because Mr. Eliot has more than a weakness for poetical

mottoes? Because of the Venetian setting and because Venice is

romantically situated in the international cosmography of Mr. Eliot's

mind? Because of the literary references to Socrates, Michelangelo,

Chapman and others included in a tale often and a half pages, and

because Mr. Eliot has more than a weakness for literary references? He

cannot surely be serious in advancing that Poe makes the most artificial

melodrama seem real, with this tale in particular—one of the most

nonsensical—as evidence? Is it to be suggested that this partiality for

Poe is a confession of that love of “magnificent meditation,” that

morbid taste for desolation and ill-fatedness which is more appropriate

to the boyish, melodramatic enthusiasm of the penny dreadfuls than to

advanced contemporary poetry and criticism—unless these are willing to

confess to internal melodrama, as they apparently are not?

*

Frederick Howard, fifth Earl of Carlisle, author of fugitive pieces and

two tragedies, was born 1748, and died in 1826.—Author

Editors' Notes

Chapter 1 Poetry and the Literary Universe

1

. The opening chapter of Contemporaries and Snobs presents the main

argument of the book, and was never published elsewhere. Riding likely

wrote much of it in 1926 and 1927, in response to a few works of recent

criticism, including Edith Sitwell's Poetry and Criticism (London:

Hogarth Press, 1925); Edwin Muir's Transition: Essays on Contemporary

Literature (London: Hogarth Press, 1926); the October 1926 issue of

Eliot's journal, the New Criterion; and Allen Tate's “Poetry and the

Absolute,” which Riding read in draft form [Laura (Riding) Jackson and

Schuyler B. Jackson collection, #4608, Division of Rare and Manuscript

Collections, Cornell University Library, Series IX, Box 100, folder 3]

though it later appeared in the January 1927 issue of The Sewanee

Review. After Leonard and Virginia Woolf declined to publish

Contemporaries at Hogarth Press, Riding offered this opening essay to

Wyndham Lewis for publication in his journal, The Enemy, but Lewis also

turned it down [Friedmann, Elizabeth. A Mannered Grace: The Life of

Laura Riding Jackson (New York: Persea, 2005), 114–116].

2

. Arthur Rimbaud, letter to Paul Demeny, May 15, 1871. In this letter

appears the famous statement, “Car je est un autre” (“I is an other/I am

an other”). The impact of this statement on the development of modernist

impersonality cannot be underestimated. Rimbaud attempts to explain how

the poet distances himself from the subject, how language takes

precedence over ego:

Je dis qu'il faut ĂȘtre voyant, se faire voyant.

Le PoÚte se fait voyant par un long, immense et raisonné dérÚglement de

tous les sens. Tous les formes d'amour, de souffrance, de folie; il

cherche lui-mĂȘme, il Ă©puise en lui tous les poisons, pour n'en garder

que les quintessences. Ineffable torture oĂč il a besoin de toute la foi,

de toute la force surhumaine, ou il devient entre tous le grand malade,

le grand criminel, le grand maudit—et le suprĂȘme Savant!

I say that one must be a seer, make oneself a seer.

The Poet makes himself a seer by an immense, slow, and intentional

disordering of all the senses. All the forms of love, suffering, and

insanity; he searches himself, he rids himself of all poisons and keeps

only the quintessence. An ineffable and torturous process for which he

needs complete faith, superhuman strength, and from it he becomes the

diseased, the criminal, the damned—and the supreme scholar!

3

. Percy Bysshe Shelley, “A Defense of Poetry” (1821).

4

. Albert Einstein's Relativity: The Special and General Theory was first

published in German in 1916 and translated into English by Robert W.

Lawson in 1920 (New York: Henry Holt).

5

. T. S. Eliot, “Gerontion” (1920).

6

. T. S. Eliot, The Waste Land (1922). These lines of the poem borrow

from Charles Baudelaire's “The Seven Old Men,” from Les Fleurs du Mal

(1857).

7

. See Edwin Muir, Transition: Essays on Contemporary Literature (London:

Hogarth Press, 1926), particularly “Introductory: The Zeit Geist” and

the chapters on T. S. Eliot, Edith Sitwell, and Robert Graves, and Edwin

Muir's Chorus of the Newly Dead (London: Hogarth Press, 1926).

8

. Riding is perhaps misremembering Dryden's claim, in the introduction

to Annus Mirabilis (1667) that “the composition of all poems is, or

ought to be, of wit.”

9

. John Lyly, Euphues: The Anatomy of Wit (1578). The full sentence

reads, “Englishmen desire to heare finer speech than the language will

allow.”

10

. Samuel Johnson, “The Life of Cowley,” Lives of the Poets (1779–81).

11

. “The Life of Cowley.” The full sentence reads, “But Pope's account of

wit is undoubtedly erroneous: he depresses it below its natural dignity,

and reduces it from strength of thought to happiness of language.”

12

. Riding came to know Ransom when she was a member of the Fugitive group

in the early 1920s. By the time Contemporaries was published, Ransom had

published three volumes of poetry: Poems about God (1919), Chills and

Fever (1924), and Two Gentlemen in Bonds (1927).

13

. Erasmus Darwin, The Botanic Garden (1791).

14

. Riding likely drew her title for this section from Allen Tate's

“Poetry and the Absolute.” Tate sent Riding this essay in typescript

[Laura (Riding) Jackson and Schuyler B. Jackson collection, #4608,

Division of Rare and Manuscript Collections, Cornell University Library,

Series IX, Box 100, folder 3], and it later appeared in The Sewanee

Review 35.1 (January 1927): 41–52. In “The Poetic Absolute,” Riding

argues against Tate's attempt to provide a philosophical basis for a

poetic “absolute.”

15

. Riding met and befriended Hart Crane in New York in 1925. She

ceaselessly championed his poetry; her review of Crane's White Buildings

appeared in transition in January 1928 (“A Note on White Buildings,”

transition 10, 139–141).

16

. Arthur Rimbaud, letter to Paul Demeny, May 15, 1871. See note 2.

17

. Paul Valéry, Variété II (Paris: Gallimard, 1929), 28. The full passage

reads:

L'homme des foules est poĂšte, conteur, ou quelque ivrogne de l'esprit.

Il se noie dans la quantité des ùmes ambulantes; il s'enivre d'absorber

un nombre inépuisable de visages et de regards, et de ressentir au fil

de la rue fluide le vertige du passage de l'infinité des individus.

The man of the crowd is a poet, a storyteller, or a kind of drunken

spirit. He drowns himself in a sea of restless souls; he becomes drunk

soaking in an unending sea of faces and looks and, in the wake of the

moving streets, experiences vertigo from becoming part of this infinity

of individuals.

18

. Jean Cocteau, “Lettre à Jacques Maritain.” See Jacques and Raïssa

Maritain, Oeuvres complĂštes, Volume 3 (Atlanta: International Book

Center of Atlanta, 1985), 692. The full passage reads:

J'apprendrai que le besoin de changer en art n'est pas autre chose que

celui de chercher une place fraĂźche sur l'oreiller. Posez la main sure

une fraĂźcheur, elle cesse vite de l'ĂȘtre; le neuf est une fraĂźcher. Le

besoin de neuf est le besoin de fraĂźcheur. Dieu est la seule fraĂźcheur

qui ne se rechauffe pas.

J'apprendrai Ă  fabriquer les poĂšmes (le mot est de La Fontaine) et pour

le reste Ă  laisser faire Dieu.

I will learn that, in art, the need to change is nothing other than the

desire to find a cool place on the pillow to rest one's head. Place the

hand on this cool spot, and it quickly ceases to be so; newness is this

coolness and freshness. The need to be new is the need for this

freshness. God is the only cool spot that never warms to the touch.

I will learn to make poems (the word is from La Fontaine) and leave the

rest to God.

19

. Cocteau, “Lettre à Jacques Maritain.” The quote reads: “Imagine, my

dear Jacques, the joy of a language free from Rimbaud (right now more

cumbersome than Hugo) and from the superstition of Maldoror. All youth

could breathe again.”

20

. “A Brief Treatise on the Criticism of Poetry,” Chapbook 2.9 (March

1920): 1.

21

. “A Brief Treatise on the Criticism of Poetry,” Chapbook 2.9 (March

1920): 3.

22

. “Books of the Quarter” [review of Herbert Read, Reason and

Romanticism: Essays in Literary Criticism (Faber & Gwyer) and Ramon

Fernandez, Messages (Paris: Gallimard)] New Criterion 4.4 (October

1926): 751.

23

. Naked Warriors (London: Art and Letters, 1919). The lines read, “Judas

no doubt was right / In a mental sort of way: / For he betrayed another

and so / With purpose was self-justified.”

24

. “Books of the Quarter,” 751.

25

. “Books of the Quarter,” 751. The full quotation reads: “Both [Herbert

Read and Ramon Fernandez], instead of taking for granted the place and

function of literature—and therefore taking for granted a whole

universe—are occupied with the inquiry into this function, and therefore

with the inquiry into the whole moral world, fundamentally, with

entities and values.”

26

. “Books of the Quarter,” 751–2. Eliot writes that “we have from these

two writers [Herbert Read and Ramon Fernandez] almost incorrigible

testimony to the actual lack of value of Proust, or more exactly, to his

value simply as a milestone, as a point of demarcation between a

generation for whom the dissolution of value had in itself a positive

value, and the generation for which the recognition of value is of

utmost importance, a generation which is beginning to turn its attention

to an athleticism, a training, of the soul as severe and ascetic as the

training of the body of a runner.”

27

. C. H. Rickword, “Scrutinies (5): Bernard Shaw,” Calendar of Modern

Letters 1.6 (September 1925): 50–54.

28

. “Final Confessions—Literary Tests,” Specimen Days (1892).

29

. Poetry and Criticism (London: Hogarth Press, 1925), 16. Interestingly,

Sitwell draws on the concept of “texture” elaborated by “my friend Mr.

Robert Graves” to praise Pope's The Rape of the Lock (15).

30

. Poetry and Criticism, 17.

31

. “The Subject-Matter of Poetry,” The Chapbook, 9 (March 1920): 11–16.

32

. Riding is perhaps thinking here of the following lines from Francis

Thompson's Shelley: An Essay (1909): “It is this gift of not merely

embodying but apprehending everything in figure which co-operates

towards creating his rarest characteristics, so almost preternaturally

developed in no other poet, namely, his well-known power to condense the

most hydrogenic abstraction. Science can now educe threads of such

exquisite tenuity that only the feet of the tiniest infant-spiders can

ascend them; but up the filmiest insubstantiality Shelley runs with

agile ease. To him, in truth, nothing is abstract.”

33

. Riding's parenthetical on Hulme here prefigures her broader treatment

of Hulme in Chapter 2. (See chap. 2, n. 6.)

34

. Transition: Essays on Contemporary Literature (London: Hogarth Press,

1926). See also note 7.

35

. “Books of the Quarter,” 751.

36

. Poetry and Criticism, 23. For Sitwell, Beddoes' “Song” (1851)

represents the “nearest approach” to “making abstract poems in words as

the modernist poet has.”

37

. Poetry and Criticism, 7–9.

38

. Percy Bysshe Shelley, “Peter Bell the Third” (written 1819, published

1839).

39

. Samuel Taylor Coleridge, “Youth and Age” (1828).

Chapter 2 T. E. Hulme, the New Barbarism, and Gertrude Stein

1

. Riding most likely composed this chapter in response to T. S. Eliot's

1927 review, titled “Charleston, Hey! Hey!,” in which he deemed Gertrude

Stein's writing an “ominous” harbinger of a “barbarian” future (see n. 8

below). An earlier (and shorter) version of this chapter appeared under

the same title in transition 3 (June 1927): 153–168. Robert Graves and

Riding also reworked some of this material as the “Conclusion” to A

Survey of Modernist Poetry (London: William Heinemann, 1927).

2

. This phrase became widely known after the publication of Ernest

Hemingway's The Sun Also Rises (1926). In that volume, Hemingway credits

Stein with the phrase.

3

. After the publication of The Waste Land in 1922, Eliot published The

Hollow Men (1925), “Doris's Dream Songs, I–III” (parts of which were

reprinted in Poems 1909–1935), and parts of what would later become

Sweeney Agonistes (1932).

4

. “Books of the Quarter,” New Criterion 4.4 (October 1926), 751.

5

. Riding joins Wyndham Lewis in denouncing modernist poetry as

Bergsonian. In Time and Western Man (1927), Lewis outlines the

“psychology of the time-snob” modernist, who glorifies

“life-in-the-moment, with no reference . . . to absolute or universal

value.” Lewis also discusses modernists' desire to “return to the Past,”

in the form of the child or the primitive. Riding's critical terms are

similar to Lewis's, but she reverses his dismissal of Gertrude Stein's

Composition as Explanation. See Wyndham Lewis, Time & Western Man [1927]

(Santa Rosa: Black Sparrow Press, 1993), 11, 14, 35, 59–63.

6

. Most of T. E. Hulme's essays on poetry, sculpture, painting,

philosophy, and politics initially appeared in The New Age journal

during the years before and during World War I. After Hulme's death in

the war, Herbert Read collected selections from his writings and

notebooks and published them as Speculations: Essays on Humanism and the

Philosophy of Art, ed. Herbert Read (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner

& Co., 1924).

7

. Eliot, “Commentary,” Criterion II (April 1924): 231.

8

. “Charleston, Hey! Hey!,” Nation & Athenaeum, 40:17 (29 January 1927):

595.

9

. “Romanticism and Classicism,” Speculations, 126.

10

. The Profanity of Paint (London: A. C. Fifield, 1916).

11

. Gaudier-Brzeska: A Memoir (London: John Lane, 1916), 137–138.

12

. Gaudier-Brzeska, 138.

13

. This quotation represents Riding's translation of two lines from

Gaudier-Brzeska's manifesto into William Kiddier's non-objectifying

prose. The lines from Gaudier-Brzeska's manifesto—which originally

appeared in the first issue of BLAST (1914)—read, “Sculptural feeling is

the appreciation of masses in relation. Sculptural ability is the

defining of these masses by planes.” Gaudier-Brzeska, 138.

14

. “Bergson's Theory of Art,” in Speculations, 147.

15

. White Buildings (New York: Boni & Liveright, 1926). In his

introduction to White Buildings, Allen Tate suggests that the

“separation of vision and subject” in modern poetry arises because “the

poet no longer apprehends his world as a Whole” (xi).

16

. “Bergson's Theory of Art,” 163.

17

. Eliot's “Fragment of a Prologue”—which later became the first part of

Sweeney Agonistes (1932)—appeared in the Criterion 4.4 (October 1926):

713.

18

. See Gertrude Stein's 1926 portrait “Jean Cocteau” in Portraits and

Prayers (New York: Random House, 1934), 81.

19

. See Gertrude Stein, Composition As Explanation in A Stein Reader, ed.

Ulla Dydo (Evanston: Northwestern UP, 1993), 495. In the section that

follows, Riding cites repeatedly from Stein's Composition as

Explanation, which was first published in Dial 81, no. 4 (October 1926),

then delivered as a lecture at Oxford University in June 1926, and

finally published in book form by Leonard and Virginia Woolf's Hogarth

Press in November of the same year. Riding relies on Stein's sense of

the continuous present throughout Chapter 2 of Contemporaries,

particularly when describing the “time sense” in contemporary poetry,

and as she attempts to explain Stein's “barbarism” in terms of her

radical deconstruction of language, best demonstrated in Composition As

Explanation.

20

. Composition As Explanation, 497.

21

. Composition As Explanation, 499–500.

22

. Composition As Explanation, 497.

23

. Composition As Explanation, 501.

24

. Gertrude Stein, The Making of Americans (Dijon: Contact Editions,

1925). Though Stein began writing The Making of Americans as early as

1903, and finished the manuscript in 1911, it did not appear in print

until 1925 and was reviewed by Edith Sitwell for The Criterion in 1926,

a review Riding certainly would have read.

25

. Composition As Explanation, 499.

26

. Herbert Read, ed., Speculations: Essays on Humanism and the Philosophy

of Art (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., 1924), 34.

27

. Stein, What Are Masterpieces? (Los Angeles: Conference Press, 1940),

57.

28

. Stein, “Jean Cocteau,” 84.

29

. Composition As Explanation, 500.

30

. Composition As Explanation, 501.

31

. Composition As Explanation, 502.

Chapter 3 The Facts in the Case of Monsieur Poe

1

. “The Facts in the Case of Monsieur Poe” likewise appeared in altered

form previous to its inclusion in Contemporaries, first as a lecture

before the Oxford English Club in March of 1927, then as an essay

entitled “Jamais Plus” that appeared in the October 1927 issue of

transition (139–56). Elizabeth Friedmann indicates that Riding's lecture

at Oxford was presented as a preview of a chapter from Contemporaries,

“in which she explained how the myth of Edgar Allan Poe's genius became

so widely held and long maintained. She portrayed the icon of the French

symbolists not as America's greatest literary genius but as a

self-publicizing hack journalist who wrote ‘literary rush orders’ to

produce a predetermined effect.” See A Mannered Grace: The Life of Laura

(Riding) Jackson, 103.

2

. Riding draws these unattributed quotations from Yale Professor Carl

Schrieber's article “A Close-Up of Poe” that appeared in the Saturday

Review of Literature 3.11 (October 9, 1926): 165–67.

3

. Edgar Allan Poe, “To Helen” (1831).

4

. “Edgar Allan Poe,” In the American Grain (New York: New Directions,

1956 [1925]), 216–34.

5

. “Edgar Allan Poe,” 216.

6

. James Russell Lowell, “Fable for Critics” (1848).

7

. On a Certain Condescension in Foreigners (1914).

8

. Poe, “Eulalie” (1845).

9

. Poe, Bon-Bon (1850).

10

. Poe, “The Rationale of Verse” (1848).

11

. “Edgar Allan Poe,” 216–34.

12

. Poe, “To One in Paradise” (1834).

13

. Riding most likely refers to Eliot's “Note sur MallarmĂ© et Poe,” La

Nouvelle RĂ©vue Française 14 (November 1, 1926), 524–26.

14

. “Edgar Allan Poe,” 222.

15

. Riding cites a letter from Poe to T. W. White, April 30, 1835. The

full sentence reads: “I noticed the allusion in the Doom. The writer

seems to compare my swim with that of Lord Byron, whereas there can be

no comparison between them.”

16

. From the preface to Poe's Tamerlane and Other Poems (1827).

17

. From the preface to (George Gordon) Lord Byron's Hours of Idleness

(1807), his first collection of poems.

18

. Riding refers to Poe's 1846 essay, “The Philosophy of Composition,”

which elaborates a strict formula for poetic composition, using “The

Raven” as an ideal example.

19

. Thomas Moore, “To the Boston Frigate, On Leaving Halifax for England”

(1804).

20

. A Defense of Poetry (1821).

21

. The Poetic Principle (1850).

22

. William Motherwell, “The Cavalier's Song” (1841).

23

. “The Philosophy of Composition” (1846).

24

. See Malcolm Cowley's preface to his translation of Paul Valéry's

Variété (New York: Harcourt, Brace & Co., 1927).

25

. “Note sur MallarmĂ© et Poe,” 524–26.

26

. “The Philosophy of Composition” (1846).

27

. A typographical error—Riding refers here to American writer and

artist, Christopher Pearse Cranch (1813–1892).

28

. “The beautiful cries of real passion, the elegance of love . . . ”

comes from the preface to Edgar Allan Poe, Poésies ComplÚtes, trans.

Gabriel Mourey (Paris: Mercure de France, 1910), 1.

29

. “Baudelaire, MallarmĂ©, Hennequin, Rollinat, yourself and others. . . .

” PoĂ©sies ComplĂštes, 5.

30

. “We have done so much in France to acclimate Edgar Poe that his

compatriots insist that the author of ‘The Raven’ was French.” John H.

Ingram, letter to Gabriel Mourey, as quoted in the preface to Mourey's

translation of Poe. Poésies ComplÚtes, 5.

31

. “Poe loved France and its admirable literature and only spoke with

respect of the masterpieces that it produced; his caustic pen would

never try to diminish its glory.” PoĂ©sies ComplĂštes, 6.

32

. From Mourey's 1910 French translation of Edgar Allan Poe's “The Raven”

(1845). Poésies ComplÚtes, 21. The stanza in English reads:

“Prophet!” said I, “thing of evil!—prophet still, if bird or devil!

Whether Tempter sent, or whether tempest tossed thee here ashore,

Desolate, yet all undaunted, on this desert land enchanted—

On this home by Horror haunted,—tell me truly, I implore—

Is there—is there balm in Giliad?—tell me—tell me, I implore!”

Quoth the Raven, “Nevermore.”

Chronological Bibliography

As Laura Riding

The Close Chaplet. London: Hogarth Press, 1926.

[with Robert Graves]. A Survery of Modernist Poetry. London: Heinemann,

1927. Reprint, New York: Haskell House, 1969. Reprint, Manchester:

Carcanet, 2002.

Voltaire: A Biographical Fantasy. London: Hogarth Press, 1927.

Anarchism Is Not Enough. London: Jonathan Cape, 1928. Reprint, Berkeley:

University of California Press, 2001.

Contemporaries and Snobs. New York: Doubleday, Duran, & Co., 1928.

Reprint, St. Clair Shore: Scholarly Press, 1971.

A Pamphlet Against Anthologies. New York: Doubleday, Duran, & Co., 1928.

Reprint, New York: AMS, 1970. Reprint, Manchester: Carcanet, 2002.

Experts Are Puzzled. London: Jonathan Cape, 1930.

Four Unposted Letters to Catherine. Paris: Hours, 1930. Reprint, New

York: Persea, 1993.

Poems: A Joking Word. London: Jonathan Cape, 1930.

Though Gently. Deya: Seizin Press, 1930.

Twenty Poems Less. Paris: Hours, 1930.

Laura and Francisca. Deya: Seizin Press, 1931.

Everybody's Letters. London: Barker, 1933.

The Life of the Dead. London: Barker, 1933.

Poet: A Lying Word. London: Barker, 1933.

Americans. Los Angeles: Primavera, 1934.

[with George Ellidge]. 14A. London: Barker, 1934.

Progress of Stories. London: Constable, 1935. Reprint, New York: Dial,

1982. Reprint, New York: Persea, 1994.

The Second Leaf (broadside). Deya: Seizin Press, 1935.

[Madeleine Vara, pseud.] Convalescent Conversations. Deya: Seizen Press,

1936.

[Edited with Robert Graves.] Epilogue I. London: Constable, 1936.

———. Epilogue II. London: Constable, 1936.

———. Epilogue III. London: Constable, 1937.

A Trojan Ending. London: Constable, 1937. Reprint, Manchester: Carcanet,

1984.

Collected Poems. London: Cassell; New York: Random House, 1938.

The Covenant of Literal Morality. London: Seizin Press, 1938.

The World and Ourselves. London: Chatto & Windus, 1938.

Lives of Wives. New York: Random House, 1939. Reprint, Los Angeles: Sun

and Moon, 1995. Reprint, Los Angeles: Sun and Moon, 2000.

Selected Poems in Five Sets. New York: Persea, 1993.

As Laura (Riding) Jackson

The Telling. London: Athlowe, 1972; New York: Harper & Row, 1973.

Reprint, Manchester: Fyfield Books, 2005.

“What, If Not a Poem, Poems?” Denver Quarterly 9.2 (1974): 1–13.

“Dr. Grove and the Future of the English Dictionaries.” Denver Quarterly

10.1 (spring 1975). Reprinted in Rational Meaning.

“On Ambiguity.” Modern Language Quarterly 36.1 (March 1975): 102–106.

Reprinted in Rational Meaning.

“Bertrand Russell, and Others: The Idea of the Master-Mind.” Antaeus

21/22 (spring–summer 1976): 125–35.

“It Has Taken Too Long: From the Writings of Laura (Riding) Jackson.”

Chelsea 35 (1976): entire issue.

Description of Life. New York: Oliphant, 1980.

The Poems of Laura Riding: A New Edition of the 1938 Collection. New

York: Persea, 1980.

Some Communications of Broad Reference. Northridge: Lord John, 1983.

“Engaging the Impossible.” Sulfur 10 (1984): 4–35.

“As to a Certain Poem & Poetry” (“Lamenting the Terms of Modern

Praise”). Chelsea 47 (1988): 3–5.

First Awakenings: The Early Poems of Laura Riding. New York: Persea,

1992.

The Word “Woman” and Other Related Writings. Edited by Elizabeth

Friedmann and Alan J. Clark. New York: Persea, 1993.

“About the Fugitives and Myself.” The Carolina Quarterly 47.3 (summer

1995): 73–87.

“The Promise of Words.” London Review of Books 7 (September 1995):

23–24.

[with Schuyler B. Jackson]. Rational Meaning: A New Foundation for the

Definition of Words. Edited by William Harmon. Introduction by Charles

Bernstein. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1997.

The Sufficient Difference: A Centenary Celebration of Laura (Riding)

Jackson. Edited by Elizabeth Friedmann. New York: Chelsea Associates,

2000.

[with Robert Graves]. Essays from Epilogue 1935–1937. Manchester:

Carcanet, 2001.

The Poems of Laura Riding: A Newly Revised Edition of the 1938/1980

Collection. New York: Persea, 2001.

Laura Riding, Gertrude Stein, Jane Bowles. Warsaw: Wydaje Biblioteka

Narodowa, 2003.

“Literature and the Right.” Delmar 10 (2004): 69-81.

Under the Mind's Watch: Concerning Issues of Language, Literature, Life

of Contemporary Bearing. Edited by John Nolan and Alan J. Clark. Bern:

Peter Lang, 2004.

The Laura (Riding) Jackson Reader. Edited by Elizabeth Freidmann. New

York: Persea, 2005.

The Failure of Poetry, the Promise of Language (Poets on Poetry). Ann

Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2007.

On the Continuing of the Continuing. London: Wyeswood Press, 2008.

[with Jan Erik Bouman]. As Many Questions As Answers. Den Haag: Bureau

Claxon, 2010.

The Person I Am: The Literary Memoirs of Laura (Riding) Jackson, Volume

One. Edited by John Nolan and Carol Ann Friedmann. Nottingham: Trent

Editions, 2011.

The Person I Am: The Literary Memoirs of Laura (Riding) Jackson, Volume

Two. Edited by John Nolan and Carol Ann Friedmann. Nottingham: Trent

Editions, 2011.

Index of Names

Aiken, Conrad,

18

Aldrich, Mary A. S.,

109

Allan, John,

98

Anderson, Sherwood,

27

Archimedes,

58

Aristotle,

44

,

49

,

62

,

66

Barrett, Elizabeth Barrett (Elizabeth Barrett Browning),

103

Barrie, J. M.,

38

Baudelaire,

9

(cited in Waste Land)

37

,

77

,

111

,

114n6

,

120n29

Beddoes, Thomas Lovell,

42

,

117n36

Beerbohm, Max,

38

Beowulf,

52

Bergson, Henri,

78

,

118

Blake, William,

19

Bonaparte, Napoleon,

69

Boone, Daniel,

92

Borrow, George,

21

,

27

Bradley, F. H.,

49

Branch, Christopher Pease,

89

,

109

,

120n27

Bridges, Robert,

43

Brontë, Charlotte,

20

Browne, Thomas,

19

Bryant, William Cullen,

88

,

89

,

90

,

104

Butler, Samuel,

37

Byron, George Gordon Lord,

10

,

89

,

97

,

99

,

120n17

Campbell, Roy,

18

Carpenter, Edward,

37

Chapman, George,

111

Chaucer, Geoffrey,

2

Clemm, Virginia,

98

Cocteau, Jean,

15

–

16

,

27

,

115nn18–19

,

118n18

,

119n28

Coleridge, Samuel Taylor,

20

,

44

,

101

,

117n39

Collins, William,

19

Cowley, Abraham,

11

,

114nn10–11

Cowley, Malcolm,

108

,

120n24

Cowper, William,

xxiii

,

19

Craik, Dinah,

20

Cranch, Christopher Pearse,

89

. See Branch, Christoper Pease

Crane, Hart,

x

,

xi

,

xvi

,

14

,

77

,

115n15

Cummings, E. E.,

xi

,

14

,

32

,

48

Cunard, Nancy,

13

Dana, Charles A.,

88

Darwin, Erasmus,

12

,

114n13

Darwin, Charles,

69

Davidson, John,

38

Denham, Sir John,

19

DeQuincey, Thomas,

43

,

96

–

97

Dickens, Charles,

102

,

110

Diodorus Siculus,

40

Disraeli, Benjamin,

20

Donne, John,

3

,

11

,

16

,

108

Doughty, Charles Montagu,

37

Dowson, Ernest,

38

Dryden, John,

3

,

11

,

99

,

114n8

Einstein, Albert,

48

–

49

,

58

,

114n4

Eliot, T. S.,

x

–

xiii

,

xv

–

xvii

,

xix

,

xxi

,

xxiii

,

8

–

10

,

24

–

28

,

31

,

41

,

44

–

45

,

48

,

55

–

56

,

58

–

59

,

66

,

77

–

80

,

93

,

108

,

110

–

112

,

113n1

,

114nn5–6

,

116n26

,

117n1

,

117n3

,

118n7

,

118n17

,

120n130

Emerson, Ralph Waldo,

90

Euripides,

58

Fernandez, M. Ramon,

25

–

27

,

116n22

,

116nn25–26

Fielding, Henry,

12

Fletcher, John,

19

Frank, Waldo,

27

Freud, Sigmund,

49

Galsworthy, John,

37

Gaudier-Brzeska, Henri,

xv

,

72

–

74

,

118nn11–13

Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von,

10

,

97

Goldsmith, Oliver,

19

Goodwin, Leslie,

xii

,

29

Graves, Robert,

xii

–

xiii

,

xv

,

xviii

,

xxi

,

xxiii

,

9

,

114n7

,

116n29

,

117n1

Gray, Thomas,

19

Greene, Robert,

2

Griswold, Rufus Wilmot (Reverend),

88

–

89

Hardy, Thomas,

37

Hawthorne, Nathaniel,

110

Hennequin, Émile,

111

,

120n29

Homer,

99

Hood, Thomas,

89

,

105

Horace,

99

Horne, Richard Henry,

109

Howard, Frederick,

100

Hulme, T. E.,

x

,

xi

,

xiii

,

xv

,

35

,

51

,

63

–

71

,

75

–

76

,

78

–

79

,

83

,

117n33

,

117

–

18n6

Huxley, Aldous,

18

,

31

Ingram, John H.,

111

,

120n30

Johnson, Samuel

2

,

11

,

19

,

100

–

101

,

114n10

Joyce, James

xi

,

xv

,

xvii

,

12

,

27

,

48

,

78

–

79

Keats, John,

19

–

20

,

29

–

30

,

39

,

43

–

44

,

71

,

97

,

106

Kiddier, William,

71

–

74

,

118n13

King, Henry,

111

Kipling, Rudyard,

43

Laforgue, Jules,

31

,

37

Lamartine, Alfonse de,

10

Lawrence, D. H.,

37

Leonard, William Ellery,

18

Lodge, Thomas,

2

Longfellow, Henry Wadsworth,

88

–

90

,

102

–

103

Lowell, James Russell,

89

–

90

,

119n6

Mallarmé, Stéphane,

108

,

111

,

120n13

,

120n25

,

120n29

Maritain, Jacques,

16

,

28

,

115nn18–19

Masefield, John,

18

Melville, Herman,

21

,

27

Mencken, H. L.,

89

Michelangelo,

111

Middleton, Richard,

38

Milton, John,

19

,

29

Moore, George,

27

Moore, Marianne,

xi

,

14

,

48

Moore, Thomas,

89

,

102

,

104

,

120n19

Morris, William,

37

Motherwell, William

106

,

120n22

Mourey, Gabriel,

111

,

120n28

,

120n30

,

120n32

Muir, Edwin,

xv

,

9

,

26

,

113n1

,

114n7

Neal, John,

88

,

100

Nightingale, Florence,

34

Noyes, Alfred,

18

,

43

O'Shaughnessy, Arthur,

38

Ossian,

102

Ovid,

40

Pater, Walter,

40

Peele, George,

2

Philips, Ambrose,

19

Pinkney, Edward C.,

88

–

89

,

104

Plato,

48

–

49

Poe, Edgar Allan,

v

,

xi

,

16

,

22

,

86

–

112

,

119nn1–5

,

119nn8–11

,

120nn12–16

,

120n25

,

120n28

,

120nn30–32

Pope, Alexander,

3

,

4

,

11

,

19

,

29

,

114n11

,

116n29

Pound, Ezra,

xi

,

xv

,

xvi

,

27

,

72

–

74

,

78

Proust, Marcel,

27

,

116n29

Ransom, John Crowe,

x

,

xi

,

12

,

114n12

Read, Herbert,

x

,

25

–

27

,

116n22

,

116nn25–26

,

117

–

18n6

,

119n26

Rickword, Edgell,

x

,

27

,

116n27

Rimbaud, Arthur,

xv

,

4

,

14

,

16

,

86

,

97

,

111

,

113n2

,

115n16

,

115n19

Robinson, Edwin Arlington,

18

Rochefoucault, François de la,

100

Rollinat, Maurice,

111

,

120n29

Rousseau, Jean Jacques,

37

,

97

Ruskin, John,

40

,

71

Sackville-West, Vita,

18

Sassoon, Siegfried,

12

Scott-Moncrieff, Charles,

27

Shakespeare, William,

xi

,

2

–

3

,

42

Shanks, Edward,

43

Shelley, Percy Bysshe,

5

–

6

,

20

,

43

–

44

,

98

,

105

–

7

,

114n3

,

116n32

,

117n38

Sidney, Sir Philip,

2

Sitwell, Edith,

xi

,

xv

,

9

,

15

,

18

,

29

–

32

,

41

–

44

,

48

,

80

,

113n1

,

114n7

,

116n29

,

117n36

,

119n24

Soames, Enoch,

38

Socrates,

111

Spenser, Edmund,

2

,

19

Squire, J. C.,

43

Stedman, Edmund Clarence,

88

Stein, Gertrude,

ix

–

xi

,

xiii

,

xviii

–

xxii

,

32

,

51

,

55

,

66

,

78

,

80

–

85

,

91

,

117nn1–2

,

117n5

118nn18–22

,

119nn23–25

,

119nn27–31

Symons, Arthur,

37

Tate, Allen,

x

,

xi

,

xv

,

77

–

78

,

113n1

,

114

–

15n14

,

118n15

Tennyson, Alfred Lord,

7

,

10

,

29

,

43

,

89

,

102

,

105

Thompson, Francis,

35

,

116n32

Thomson, James [Bysshe Vanolis],

38

Turner, W. J.,

18

Valéry, Paul,

6

,

15

,

22

,

32

,

108

,

115n17

,

120n24

Verlaine, Paul,

97

,

111

Virgil,

19

Warens, Françoise-Louise de,

96

Welby, Amelia,

89

,

109

Wells, H. G.,

37

Whitman, Walt,

29

Williams, William Carlos,

89

–

93

Willis, Nathaniel Parker,

88

,

10

,

109

Woolf, Virginia,

xi

,

27

,

113n1

,

118n19

Wordsworth, William,

xi

,

20

,

29

–

31

,

43

–

44

,

101

–

2