đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș lupus-dragonowl-against-identity-politics.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:00:27. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Against Identity Politics Author: Lupus Dragonowl Date: 2015 Language: en Topics: identity politics, oppression, essentialism, spectres, privilege, dropping-out, exodus, community, Maoism, AJODA, AJODA #76 Source: Retrieved from "Anarchy - A Journal For Desire Armed", No. 76, p. 29-51.
Identity Politicians (IPs) are a particular kind of leftist who use the
spectre[1] of an identity-category (gender, race, sexuality, etc) as a
lever to obtain power. In the sense discussed here, they should not be
considered coterminous either with groups of people oppressed by
identity categories, or even that subset who prioritise identity as a
key site of struggle. Not all women, Black people, People of Colour
(POC)[2], or members of other specifiable groups are IPs; not all
feminists, anti-racists, or even separatists are IPs. Racism, sexism and
other oppressions along identity axes are sociologically real, and not
every person involved in the struggle against such oppressions is an IP.
Intersectionality - the recognition of multiple forms or axes of
oppression, with complex interacting effects - is an effective
theoretical response to the problems of Identity Politics, but there
have clearly been difficulties putting it into practice. In
identity-linked movements, some people use intersectionality as a way to
avoid the idea of principal contradiction, although occasionally in
practice, people who claim to be intersectional end up treating one or
two oppressions as primary. Nevertheless, the fact that not all
identity-related theories or movements need to be treated as Identity
Politics does not mean that the influence of Identity Politicians is
trivial. The writers and activists discussed here not only exist, but
their ideas and practices are often insidious and unfortunately
widespread. Recognizing the importance and necessity of countering that
deleterious influence is my motivation for writing this essay.
It should here be emphasised that this is not a critique of all forms of
radical theory focused on racial or gender oppression. This critique of
IPs is by no means a critique of every position which focuses on a
particular type of oppression (such as gender or race). Indeed, aspects
of this critique are already present in a number of theorists who work
with identity. For instance, the iconic anti-colonial writer Frantz
Fanon argued that dualistic identities deform interpersonal relations
and reproduce colonial power. While the struggle against colonial power
is in fact an irreducible antagonism, and moves similar to those of IPs
are strategically useful to fight it, the ultimate goal is to overcome
such binaries in a future of the disalienated âwhole [hu] manâ (Wretched
of the Earth, 238-9). He even articulates an almost Stirnerianâ claim
that âthe real leap consists in introducing invention into existence ...
I am endlessly creating myselfâ (Black Skin, White Masks 204).
Similarly, in her later works, Gloria AnzaldĂșa argued that we are
citizens of the universe, sharing an identity at a cosmic or subatomic
level which is wider than any racial or social category (This Bridge We
Call Home, 558). She came to criticise IPs for putting up walls and
causing violence between groups (Interviews, 118). Neither of these
authors arrives at a Stirnerian position: Fanon moves towards humanism,
and AnzaldĂșa towards spiritual holism. However, their rejections of
fixed identities overlap and intersect with mine, and serve to counter
any suspicion that the rejection of Identity Politics entails a failure
to take patriarchy, colonialism, or racism seriously.
Some feminists and Black radicals do not deploy the reactive affects
discussed below, and instead seek to regenerate a force of becoming to
one degree or another (e.g. Mary Daly, Germaine Greer, Audre Lorde,
Edouard Glissant). Others, notably dependency theorists and
socialist-feminists, emphasise structural oppression, and struggle
primarily against macro-structures - destroying capitalism, modernity,
or the world-system - rather than focusing on the micro-politics of
privilege. None of these approaches falls within what is being critiqued
here. Academic approaches that draw on poststructuralism are also
distinct from Identity Politics, in that they typically reject the
primacy of any particular position. Academic theories related to
oppression and identity - for example, Queer Theory, Critical Race
Theory, Postcolonial Theory, and poststructuralist feminism - generally
reject the idea of principal contradiction. The popularity of Identity
Politics among radicals is partly due to the influence of academic work
on identity, but, in academic spaces, most strategies of IPs would be
rejected as essentialist (there are other issues of disagreement between
post-left anarchy and poststructuralism, and between post-left anarchy
and leftist types of structuralism, but these issues will not be covered
here).
What is being criticised here is a particular political style, rather
than a theoretical orientation - a style which labels as oppressive any
deviation from a particular political line, which resorts almost
immediately to public denunciation and exclusion, and which entails
analytical and categorical rigidity, with corresponding
boundary-policing. They can be distinguished from those whose approaches
pursue open-ended becomings through the deconstruction of
identity-categories (eg Heckert), which are minoritarian becomings
rather than minority identities.
IPs see one axis of oppression as primary - the principal
contradiction[3] They demand that everyone focus on this axis. If
someone fails to do so, IPs label them racist, sexist, white
supremacist, patriarchal, etc. Ditto if they refuse leadership by the
oppressed group (often meaning the IPs themselves), deviate from the
IPâs proposed political line, or criticise an IP. Such terms are
deployed only by a member of the correct group, and are used to silence
criticism - in the case of Patriarchy Haters, even the word violence is
monopolised; those who oppose them âdo not get to decide what counts as
violenceâ (Voline). The idea of a principal contradiction leads to
contempt for other issues and priorities. For instance, IPs in APOC, who
focus on race, argue that âbleating about gender and classâ is an
instance of âdiversionary tacticsâ to deflect from race (Anon, Open
Letter). Early CWS work treated issues other than racism as
âdistractionsâ (Dot Matrix), and Lorenzo Ervin demands that
âanti-racism/anti-colonialismâ be made âthe core concernâ of every
activist group (315). He also dismisses anything outside his own
agenda - from climate change to anti-fascism - as a âwhite rightsâ issue
(133, 290, 302).
This political style boundary-polices identities in a way which renders
them rigid and authoritarian. In many cases, fighting alleged racism or
sexism inside radical groups is seen as the most important issue in
radical politics - more important than fighting racism/sexism in the
wider society. Ervin calls white radicals the worst kinds of racists,
worse than hardcore conservatives (240, 272-3). Usually, these attacks
take the form of militant struggle from the Maoist milieu: public
denunciation and/or disruption, criticism/self-criticism, purging/
exclusion, and the policing of micro-oppressions within the movement or
scene; activists refuse to draw distinctions between allies and
sympathisers, active enemies, and anything in-between. Ostracism, âthe
ultimate form of social control,â âis very infrequently usedâ in
indigenous cultures (Peaceful Societies), but is used almost immediately
by IPs for the smallest perceived transgressions.
Ervinâs repeated tirades against white anarchists provide a textbook
case of this approach; his recent antics include labelling the entire
Anarchist Black Cross racist because, at their recent convention in
Denver, someone - at the request of Black political prisoner Jalil
Muntaqim - read aloud a racist letter by a prison guard. Roger Whiteâs
Post Colonial Anarchism exemplifies this too, as do the faction of APOC
who disrupted the Crimethlnc convergence in Philadelphia in 2009,
verbally abusing participants and damaging their belongings. Kill
Whitey, one ofthe cheerleaders for this attack, later extended the
disruptorsâ accusations ofâwhite supremacyâ to Food Not Bombs and other
anarchist groups, demanding that all such groups accept black
leadership. The attack by activists from the Qilombo social centre on
the CAL Press table at the Bay Area Anarchist Book Fair in 2014 is
another case; subsequent comments online by Qilombo supporters clearly
show the same rhetoric. Patriarchy Haters, the group which emerged from
the Patriarchy and the Movement event in Portland, represent a feminist
variant; their most notorious intervention was to shout down Kristian
Williams at an unrelated event for criticising their political style in
his article, The Politics of Denunciation.
From a Stirnerian anarchist perspective, at the root of the problem with
IPs is the spectre - the use of an identity-category as a transcendent,
abstract category which possesses and defines values. In Stirnerâs
theory, the problem of oppression is the problem that people value
spectres and the things which benefit spectres - instead of valuing the
things which they desire as a âunique one.â All categories, words,
concepts, can become spectres if they are allowed to possess and
dominate us - even those which refer to our properties or attributes
(59, 151). If people are defined as essentially and primarily
something - whether it be humanity, whiteness, blackness, masculinity,
femininity - this is always alienating, because the category is always
âhis essence and not he himself,â and therefore something alien (28),
which requires âmy valuelessnessâ (145). As a real person, each of us is
a processual being, an embodied self, located in a field of becoming.
From a Stirnerian perspective, systems of oppression such as racism and
patriarchy are oppressive impositions of a particular spectre. Systems
of oppression based on gender, race, and so on are sociologically real,
but ultimately rest on other people imposing a particular spectre -
treating another person not as a unique one, but as an instance of
femininity, or âjust another X.â Such systems entail valuing a
particular category to the exclusion of others, leading to violence
against those excluded.
However, the subordination of one spectre to another is not the base
level of the problem; the problem is that spectres do not liberate or
empower those who belong to the category they value, because those
belonging to the category are valued only as instances of the category,
not in their full, unrepresentable being. Hence, a right of humanity or
a white privilege is never my right or privilege, because my unique
being is not identical with humanity or whiteness. Even if I qualify as
human or white (by falling within the extensional set of each category),
there is some residue of uniqueness which is prohibited by the spectre.
Stirnerâs concept of the un-person expresses this clearly. An un-person
falls within the category human, but is deemed to deviate from the
essence, for instance by putting uniqueness before humanity. The
un-person is not liberated, but jailed or hospitalised. Indigenous
people always fell within the extensional set of humans, but were
historically exterminated or assimilated because they fell outside the
essence of what colonisers defined as having human value. The
hierarchising of representational categories is secondary to the initial
oppressive gesture of subordinating real becomings to abstract
categories.
By analogy, white or male privilege is the privilege of the spectre, not
of the extensional set. There is the spectre as a category, which
usually has a set of normatively defined characteristics (such as
masculinity, whiteness, humanity). And then there is the set of people
who are classified as part of the spectre, who may or may not have these
characteristics. A male white person becomes un-white or un-male when he
ceases to conform to dominant ideas about the category. We might say
that white privilege is not something which is owned by a person defined
as white; it is owned by an alien spectre (112), the category of
whiteness.
Spectres are connected to sovereignty, as theorised by Agamben. In
sovereignty, a political ruler has the power to decide which instances
of the extensional set conform to the essence of the spectre and are
accorded value - who is âpersonâ (qualified life) and who is âun-personâ
(bare life). This leads to âabyssal thought,â the devaluing of those who
fall outside dominant normativity (de Souza Santos). In Maoism and
Leninism, sovereignty operates in the form of vanguard ism or
substitutionism. The Party or leader defines the spectre and hence
claims to speak for all those covered by it - but such statements are
really political decisions rather than empirical claims. The IP, the
leader, claims to speak as and for POC, Black people, women, and so on -
but never for all those covered by the category. In a sneaky semantic
move, the moment the oppressed criticise the vanguard, they are no
longer the oppressed, but objectively have become allied with the
oppressors. An enemy of the IP becomes an enemy of the entire category â
the spectre.
IPs IMAGINE SPECTRES TO BE MATERIALLY REAL. Whereas Stirnerians insist
that becoming is unrepresentable, IPs follow Marxâs view that it can be
identified with an essence. For Stirner, binaries are artificial effects
of spectres; for Marxists, they are correct theoretical reflections of
binary structures within reality itself. The IPâs style is descended
from Maoism. Younger IPs are unlikely to have been directly influenced
by Maoism, but important elements of Maoist political grammar were
imported into earlier forms of Identity Politics and continue to
operate.
Maoists and IPs are strong structural determinists. This means that they
work with a model of social life in which macro-social structures
determine peopleâs identities and political outcomes. For instance,
Ervin says that any white radical has âmiddle class racial privileges...
and it does not matter about their personal beliefsâ (268). IPs deny
that people exist as unique individuals at all; people are simply
instances of spectres. As an APOC writer says, âItâs completely arrogant
and pretentious to think you are unique. You are just another white
personâ (Anon, Open Letter). People are taken to be effects of, and
reducible to, particular social structures: these structures determine
their material interests, which determine their unconscious investments,
which determine their beliefs and actions. Peopleâs real, unconscious
desires are always âracialized desiresâ stemming from âracialized,
classed, and gendered subjectivitiesâ (comments on Anon, Smack a White
Boy Part Two). In the case of privileged people, desires are not to be
liberated, but purified. In the case of oppressed people, what they
desire is automatically, instinctively right â provided it follows from
the spectre.
This approach depends on the conflation of the spectre (eg whiteness,
masculinity) and the extensional set it covers (eg white people, men).
Roger White asserts that âwhite, Christian men have held power and
privilegeâ - without distinguishing between the spectres, the elite, and
all members of the categories. And the founder of CWS writes of âthe
guilt that comes from being who I am: a white person of conscience in a
white supremacist societyâ (Dot Matrix).
All of these positions entail the view that we are our spectres. As
Williams argues, it classifies people as âparticular types of people who
are essentially those things,â and reduces oppressed as much as
abuser/oppressor to âpolitical symbols used by others to advance some
specific ideological line.â Normatively, anything which aids the
oppressed spectre is good; anything which harms it is bad. The same
action - silencing, violence, abuse, eviction - is praised in the former
case and condemned in the latter. A personâs intent is irrelevant; the
real significance comes from the effect, as defined in the IPâs frame.
Duplicating the historic role of the activist or militant (Vaneigem,
111; Anon, Give Up Activism), the IP makes her/himself indispensable as
an Expert on oppression, based on claimed knowledge of the spectre and
the correct response to it.
Such spectres are used to channel the anger of the excluded into
controlled political forms. Maoism is a power-politics of ruthless
control, but it is seductively appealing to marginalised people because
it contains a moment of empowerment. Especially when out of power,
Maoism encourages the expression of accumulated anger against real
oppressors such as landlords and government functionaries. This practice
is the origin of the culture of denunciation, and the reason why Black
and feminist groups in the â60s were attracted to Maoism. Once in power,
however, Maoists cannot continue to allow attacks on power-holders.
Instead they channel anger onto folk-devils, such as disempowered former
oppressors, in carefully managed denunciation campaigns (Perry and Li,
7). In the Euro-American context this method takes the form of moral
panics.
This contradictory role is also channelled theoretically. Maoists and
IPs deploy a contradictory fusion of two incompatible ontologies:
realism and perspectivism. Realists maintain that an external reality is
knowable through rational methods by anyone, whereas perspectivists
maintain that everyoneâs standpoint is culturally unique, and there is
no way to establish any standpoint as more true than others. Maoists/IPs
are ontological realists in identifying the principal contradiction and
depicting the actions of the privileged (which can be reduced to
externally knowable structures), but perspectivist in their treatment of
the standpoint of the oppressed: if a Black person says something is
racist, it is racist (comments on Jarach et al); if a woman alleges
abuse, the allegation is self-evidently true (comments on Black Orchid
Collective). This turns women and Black people into Experts, to be
unquestioningly listened to and obeyed - a position dehumanising for
them as well as others. In contrast, the real meaning of a white
personâs or a manâs actions is externally knowable, and intent is
irrelevant.
There is method in this madness. In Maoist theory, knowledge is a fusion
of experience, which comes from the masses, and rational theory, which
comes from the vanguard (Mao, On Practice). In practice, this meant that
knowledge emerging from mass meetings, denunciation campaigns,
speak-bitterness campaigns, and so on was systematised and reprocessed
by the Party into the Mass Line, which was presented as the unmediated
experience of the masses. Disagreements within the movement are
âresolved by the method of criticism and self-criticismâ (Mao, On
Contradiction). In practice this meant denunciation and
self-denunciation. During the Cultural Revolution, different Maoist
factions began denouncing each other as âobjectively
counter-revolutionary,â as part of a competition for resources. Elements
of both of these approaches can be seen in the actions of IPs, the
former as an insistence on leadership by members of a particular group
(Black, women, etc), the latter in the distribution of prestige to
allies based on conspicuous self-abasement and political performance.
Ultimately, denunciation, exclusion, border-policing, promoting us/them
binaries among the oppressed, and harping on principal contradictions
are the methods through which IPs/Maoists mould autonomy into political
power. Anarchism is a threat to Maoism, not because it denies oppression
or comes from privileged groups, but because it carries the
self-expression of the oppressed further.
References to liberation, autonomy, decolonisation, and so on
notwithstanding, in such perspectives, liberation necessarily means
liberation of a spectre, not of concrete people - not even of concrete
people categorised by a spectre (as women, Black people, POC, etc). By
implication, leadership or authoritarian rule by a member of the spectre
is unproblematic. It is still self-determination by the spectre - the
spectre itself remains autonomous, even if its members do not. This is
clear in Ribeiroâs essay Senzala or Quilombo: â[the quilombo] was no
communist societyâ but had a king; âthis is neither here nor [there] ...
[it had] freedom and self-determination.â It does not matter if an
autonomous zone is hierarchically structured, as long as the leaders are
POC.
To enforce this primacy of the spectre, IPs encourage massive
simplifications, reproducing the wider equivalence between stereotypes
and roles (Vaneigem, 134). Members of entire groups (white, male,
straight, middle-class) are deemed privileged. Privilege is often
alleged despite being a result of the actions of a third party (the
police, for example), rather than oneâs own. But it carries implications
that the privileged individual is somehow a direct oppressor of the
oppressed individual (Kill Whitey, in True Colors, refers to âwhite
peopleâ as the oppressor), that they are part of a small, isolated elite
(Ervin, 309), and that theyâve âgot it goodâ in an absolute sense (Anon,
Open Letter). Strategically, the focus is on the privileged person,
rather than the person who actually discriminates against or oppresses
the oppressed person. Such a person is to admit, identify with, unlearn,
or give up their privilege, as if it were an attribute they controlled,
rather than an attribute of a spectre, assigned and reinforced by
others.
In terms of political strategy, IPs declare that people should do what
the Expert defines as structurally responsible, rather than following
their desires. This encourages people to focus on their weaknesses or
internal conditioning, rather than their strengths or outer struggles
(Gelderloos), situating oppression mainly in individual activistsâ
psyches rather than the dominant social system. IPs insist movements
must have leaders, and these leaders must come from the oppressed group
(Dot Matrix, CWS; Ervin, 291). Spaces must implement extensive policies
of normative regulation and enclosure to meet criteria of safe space,
reflecting a âneed for protection and security that eclipses the desire
for freedomâ (Landstreicher, 12). Any refusal to do so is taken to be an
instance of racism/sexism within the radical movement - an instance
which is tied to occasional cases of insensitive or prejudiced comments
or actions to paint a misleading picture of a radical scene in which
oppressive behaviour is pervasive and out of control. Normative policing
through safe space policies often makes spaces less safe, by creating
risks of denunciation and purging which are greater than the risks of
micro-oppression (Anonymous Refused). Mixed movements are labelled not
as incidentally white/male, but as deliberately white supremacist and
patriarchal. The illusion is that exclusion creates inclusion; this
rests on the implication that the power to exclude is unproblematic,
provided it is vested in or exercised by the in-group. For anarchists,
the best way to help people feel safer is to recreate autonomous forms
of self-organized control over the basic economic and social conditions
of life, and to provide care and support within networks of affinity.
Without roots in material scarcity, spectres would lose their power to
wound.
To create a politics of sacrifice, people have to be taught they have no
inherent value, so they believe in and support the systems of
compensation associated with roles (Vaneigem,139). IPs convey this
message by defining privilege as an ineliminable attribute of identity
and encouraging guilt. Experiences of different groups - separated by
social categories - are taken to be incommensurable and incomparable,
whereas those of individuals in the same group are taken to be
equivalent or identical: incidents of alleged anarchist racism are
likened to slavery and genocide, but instances of police brutality
against black people and white protesters are absolutely incomparable
(Ribeiro). Objecting to IPsâ abuse is âentitlement,â which is always a
bad thing, since privileged people need to âknow their placeâ as docile
subordinates of the new rulers-to-be. In some cases they are also
expected to funnel resources to IPsâ groups, without anything in return,
all the while respecting the groupâs âautonomyâ to bad- mouth and
exclude them (Ervin, 291; Qilombo).
Despite their rhetorical radicalism, IPs, like all good Maoists, do not
challenge capitalism. On the contrary, Perlman argues that national
liberation movements - the inspiration for IPs - are actually means of
capitalist nation-building. Why is a supermarket packer not a manager,
or a security guard not the chief of police? Because of racism. âThereâs
no earthly reason for the descendants of the persecuted to remain
persecuted when nationalism offers them the prospect of becoming
persecutorsâ (Perlman). The point, however, is that they become
persecutors and not free beings. The overall system remains intact,
dominant, with the spectres reshuffled.
There is a common misunderstanding, going back to Marxâs critique of
Stirner and exhibited in Roger Whiteâs critique of Lawrence Jarach, that
anarchists believe that spectres are simply figments of the
imagination - âpretending [racist/sexist] discourse doesnât exist just
because you didnât create itâ (White). This means we can wish away
spectres. Stop believing in them, and they lose any power to oppress.
This is a mischaracterisation. While it is true that Stirner believes
that spectres lose their normative force when we disbelieve them, we can
also be oppressed by other people who continue to believe in and act on
spectres. Structural oppressions are sociologically real but are not
material in the Marxist sense. This simply means that oneâs own will is
pitted against the wills and beliefs of others - most of whom continue
to be possessed by spectres.
For anarchists such as Stirner, normative thought, or statism, is a
deeper structure of oppression which generates the various other axes.
Binary thinking is itself closely tied to European thought and the
underpinnings of patriarchy and colonisation. Eurocentric statism and
capitalism are bound-up with colonialism, modern thought, rationalism,
and the modern world-system, but at a deeper level, Europe was also
self-colonised first (Clastres, Perlman). While European countries
became the global imperial powers, the problem of imperialism and
ethnocide are inherent to all states (Clastres). The irony is that IPs
are in fact Eurocemtric, relying on European concepts such as rights and
strong binary oppositions Aragorn!, Non-European Anarchism, 10). On a
deeper level, to be anti-Eurocentric and anti-ethnocidal requires a
rejection of the state.
With their inversions of binaries, IPs seek to reproduce institutions of
hierarchical power. The alternative here is affinity: the attempt to
form connections, informal groups, and unions of egoists without these
groups being mediated by spectres. Creating unmediated intercourse
across socially operative hierarchies (race, gender, etc) is
complicated, but by no means impossible - nor necessarily more difficult
than creating unmediated intercourse between members of the same
category. Where radicalism works well, it manages to construct such
direct connections. As Landstreicher argues, â[t]he awareness each has
of the othersâ individuality creates a basis where decision and action
need not be separateâ (21). Relating to others as unique beings, as
non-disposable creatures valuable in themselves, makes possible
communication even in contexts of radical difference. Anarchic affinity
is undermined by the inability to challenge othersâ views, the
construction of oppressed people as Experts, and the idea of
incommensurability (Dot Matrix, CWS). This actually reinforces binary
thinking and relations of domination.
IPs start from a standpoint within the dominant system of spectres, and
encourage us to identify with our position within systems of oppression
(Gelderloos, 13). They require that âany person interested in radical
transformation relinquish the ability to define her/ himselfâ (Jarach,
5). Instead, people are to dissolve themselves into the pre-existing
social categories into which they are classified, both by the dominant
system and by IPs. As Jarach argues, âthey canât conceive of the
possibility that the elevation of any particular culturally constructed
marker into a significant value-laden category could lead to oppressionâ
(3). Indeed, they define the possibility out of existence: we really are
our categories; to oppress is to oppress a category; to liberate is to
liberate a category. And leadership of Experts is necessary, if the
extensional set are to be reduced to the spectre.
From a Stirnerian point of view, instead of starting from a
subject-position assigned by the regime of spectres and categories,
anarchists should start from a standpoint of being a unique individual
irreducible to any spectre or category (including those of uniqueness
and individuality). A Stirnerian recognises racism or sexism, not as
one's own privilege separating one from the other, but as an act of
normative repression against other unique ones, and an insult against
oneâs own uniqueness. The intensity of internal and external barriers to
free expression vary with context, but there is a basis for networking
together in the rejection of alienation and spectres. This is recognised
from non-Eurocentric perspectives; some indigenous scholars argue that
modern alienation is a kind of sickness, afflicting colonisers as well
as colonised - indeed, that the colonisers infected the colonised
because they were already sick (Duran and Duran, Burman). This position
meshes with the Stirnerian view that oppressor as well as oppressed is
possessed by spectres.
Anarchy does not necessarily stem from any identity at all. More often,
it comes from a standpoint outside the field of available identities -
as in Stirner's idea of a standpoint unique to each person (190-1).
Gelderloos argues that his own experience is that â[a]ll the identities
that society tried to stitch me into don't fit, and the fabric is
coarseâ (6), offering âan inheritance stripped of anything I valueâ (7).
Similarly, for another anonymous anarchist, âOur task is not to give up
some phantom privilege that has never really been our own, but to expose
and move beyond the artificial identities that smother our
individualityâ (Willful Disobedience).
Rather than expressing white male privilege, anarchy should be seen as a
form of ethnogenesis: the emergence of a subculture or counterculture
which, if able to continue on its line of flight (or détournement ),
would become a different culture entirely (New Travellers and,
historically, Irish Travellers are good examples). The emergence of new
cultures through ethnogenesis is well-documented, and often stems from
flight from state power (Scott), a process which begins with a choice to
differ from the majority of an existing group. In other words, forming a
counterculture is the first step in becoming non-white. Ethnogenesis is
a problem for essentialists because it entails fluidity in the very
formation of the structural basis; it frustrates border-policing. IPs
denounce both dropping-out and cultural hybridity, dismissing the latter
as cultural appropriation.
If oppression is the imposition of a structure in which people are
assigned to spectres - of which both privileged and oppressed spectre
are largely effects - then IPs actually entrench oppression by
locking-in the spectres and intensifying normativity. If one assumes
that hierarchical power is wrong because it prevents (non-white) people
from living joyously, in the flow of becoming of their own desires, then
the subordination of autonomy to the primary contradiction is not an
appropriate response. Anarchy goes further, because it opposes the
underlying structure of domination of unique ones and flows of becoming
by the order of spectres. IPs seek to abolish the privilege of a
particular spectre; ideally, anarchists seeks to abolish the normative
power of spectres in general - which necessarily also abolishes every
spectreâs privilege. Stirnerian anarchy goes beyond unlearning privilege
â the favouring of one spectre over another â to unlearning spectres â
learning not to be subordinate to spectres.
Affectively, the orientation of anarchy is to unmediated, active joy.
There is a level of immediate, free becoming which is deeper than the
hierarchy of spectres. Stirner theorises a kind of intense, joyous
exercise of capacities âwithout reservationsâ (171), giving âfree playâ
to oneâs capabilities (167), and playing âas freely as possibleâ (130).
Bonanno argues that capitalism denies us an experience of active (rather
than passive) joy, and counsels a âsearch for joy... through the search
for play,â driven by a âvital impulse that is always new, always in
movement.â In the excitement of play âlies the possibility to break with
the old world and identify with new aims and other values and needsâ
(15-16). Hakim Bey argues that insurrections and autonomous zones should
create peak experiences of extraordinary consciousness and intensity
(TAZ). Such peak experiences are âvalue-formative on the individual
level,â allowing a âtransformation of everyday lifeâ (Occult Assault).
Various anarchist practices, from the TAZ to rewilding, from joyous
insurrectionary struggle to dropping-out and living differently, are
means of recovering this level of becoming and immediacy.
In contrast, the dominant affects for IPs are wallowing in the loss of
immediacy and the inevitability of alienation (guilt, melancholy,
inadequacy), a kind of joyless anger. They reproduce a style of politics
which focuses on telling people âhow to behaveâ (Dot Matrix, CWS),
conditioning people into roles which reproduce the power of the
spectacle. IPs reproduce conventional morality and its structures of
ressentiment â negative affect (often including irrational, even
self-destructive, verbal or physical lashing out) towards others as an
expression of oneâs own powerlessness, in contrast to celebration of
one's power. I have lost my capacity to enjoy; you have stolen it; you
must be punished.
On the side of the supposedly empowered, Ervin encourages ruthlessness
and âcold-blooded efficiencyâ as key virtues (245), reproducing the
affective structur of managers, soldiers, and police. The practice of
calling-out frames whiteness, white supremacy, and patriarchy as
personal moral failures, even though the underlying theory frames them
as structural realities. The cultivation of individual guilt and blame
actually reproduces dominant Calvinist normativity (Gelderloos, 13), and
the development of elaborate group norms reinforces white middle-class
status orientations and etiquette.
For IPs, neither (those assigned as) privileged nor oppressed are able
to escape ressentiment and become empowered. The latter become angry,
rigid, and dependent on the spectre for their sense of power; the former
become docile, submissive, and incapable of autonomous action. With
intense joy forbidden, people become vulnerable to the mundane
manipulation of transitory pleasure and prestige. IPs create a âsystem
of rewards... to encourage complianceâ with leaders from marginalised
groups (Gelderloos, 12), reflecting the broader dynamic by which âskill
in playing and handling roles determines rank in the spectacular
hierarchyâ (Vaneigem, 131). For the former out-group, anger and
frustration with the dominant system are channelled onto other radicals,
which sustains continued submersion in systems of oppression by
providing a safety-valve for frustration, creating a substitute for a
less reliable substantive rebellion. It also renders the oppressed
dependent on the oppressors as either docile allies or targets of anger,
and often leads to a politics focused on demands for recognition from
those one also seeks autonomy from. The binary nature of the spectres
adopted by IPs preclude ever becoming autonomous from the supposed
oppressor, whom they paradoxically need to remain in place in order to
ground their own role as Experts. Hence the irony when Ribeiro says of
APOC âit is not about white people at allâ â at the end of an entire
article which is all about white people.
The structure of impotent anger, displaced aggression, and policing of
etiquette is most notable in the practice of calling-out or denouncing
other radicals â either for micro-oppressions (small comments or actions
which are insensitive or latently racist/sexist), or for political
disagreement categorised as racist/sexist. For instance, the CrimethInc
disruptors call for a âculture of calling people out on their shitâ
(Anon, Smack a White Boy Part Two). In general, calling-out involves a
crude, aggressive style; it carries a tone of I get to tell you what to
do, and you have to obey.
Negative effects of anti-oppression normativity are paradoxically felt
most strongly by the oppressed - poor whites, Black people, young
people, people with psychological problems, and newcomers to a
movement - who are less accustomed to self-policing their social
appearance, less able to do so, or less aware of the operative norms.
IPs thus close down radical groups into tightly bordered sects.
Gelderloos deems the emphasis on micro-oppressions a kind of purism
which seeks to banish deviance so as to create a monolithic
personality-type (18). In practice, what is being challenged is not the
personâs degree of complicity in regimes of oppression, but the extent
of their knowledge of the appropriate anti-oppressive terminology and
related normative codes.
Conceived as a struggle against the enactment of structural oppression,
calling-out confuses the individual with the spectre they are taken to
represent. It is understandable that oppressed people have a low
tolerance threshold for prejudice and insensitivity, but it is unhelpful
to glorify and encourage such reactions as politically valuable.
Aragorn! says that âI tend only to âcriticizeâ when I am willing to take
responsibility for the caring of the criticizedâ (Toward a Non-European
Anarchism, 6). This position is more attentive to the affective
consequences of calling-out, which, without suitable aftercare, leads to
guilt, despair, and apathy. Alternatives to calling-out include rational
debate, parody, ignoring provocations, trying to channel anger onto the
wider system, and discussing the incident one-to-one outside the
conflictual setting â also known as âcalling-in.â Some anarchists
advocate using nonviolent communication in such contexts (Heckert). In
classical indigenous cultures, harmful deviance is taken as a kind of
imbalance or sickness. They would seek to understand how a person has
come into imbalance, and to gently guide them back to the right path
(which is also the flourishing or becoming of their own personality).
Most anarchists are very reasonable if they are told precisely why
something is problematic.
IPs tend to react aggressively to any response to being called-out which
does not amount to unconditional apology. Usually, the responses are not
inherently objectionable. They deploy strategies of argumentative
rebuttal, mitigation by context or motive, etc, which are standard in
many conversational contexts. It is never entirely clear why these
predictable responses are deemed intolerable by IPs (the claim that they
seem to deny the otherâs perspective [Tekanji] seems spurious), but it
seems to be because they entail the absence of the desired affective
response of submission.
Landstreicher suggests that IPs turns us into âa bunch of shy, yet
inquisitorial mice tip-toeing around each other for fear of being
judged, and just as incapable of attacking the foundations of this
society as they are of relating to each otherâ (16). Instead, he urges
us to become âa certain sort of being ... capable of acting on our own
terms to realize our own desires and dreams,â in struggle against
domination (3). The point is âto transform ourselves into strong,
daring, self-willed, passionate rebelsâ (6). This strength and passion
is impeded by affects such as guilt, pity, and regret. We are aiming,
remember, for a state of full life without reservations.
IPs conceive of their angry, disruptive style of politics as a way to
express the authentic experience of being traumatised. But their
distribution of commensurability (absolute within a spectre, but utterly
absent outside it) entails downplaying the degree of specific traumas
suffered by concrete people. And while it is true that listening to and
believing a survivorâs story is crucial to healing, the sources and
symptoms of trauma are too diverse to be dealt with through homogenised
identities and prescriptive restrictions. Furthermore, the tactics of
calling-out and excluding deviants can themselves be traumatic or
triggering.
IPs often turn trauma into a source of power and identity, but marking
trauma as an identity is also a barrier to autonomy. It prevents us
reaching the level of immediacy and joy, keeping us in a field of
scarcity thinking. Itâs no coincidence that the most extreme regimes of
oppression (such as Gitmo, supermax segregation, concentration camps,
Native residential schools, and the âseasoningâ of slaves) are designed
to cause as much post-traumatic stress as possible. Trauma is also a
block on active becoming and on living life to the fullest. In
indigenous cultures, it is conceived as a sickness of the soul, in which
part of the self retreats from the world or loses its life-energy
(Burman; Duran and Duran).
Being open to people as unique individuals is the best way to respond to
these kinds of problems. The fact that someone else has needs
incompatible with oneâs own, or that they canât guess in advance what
common action or object might be personally unbearable, does not mean
they are oppressing someone.
One of the biggest disagreements between Stirnerian anarchists and IPs
is on the question of exodus. IPs (and most left anarchists) generally
condemn exodus as a privileged, middle-class strategy, instead favouring
submersion in existing communities of the oppressed. For instance, the
APOC disruptors claim that CrimethInc âencourage the culture of dropping
out of society, which makes the assumption that the reader/attendee has
that privilegeâ (Anon, Smack a White Boy Part Two). An anonymous Qilombo
supporter terms the anarchist scene a âsubcultural playpenâ and an
âall-white fantasy worldâ (comments on Jarach et al). Kill Whitey labels
dumpster-diving as privileged, condemning âwhite college kids and
middle-class punks hiding in drop-out cultureâ (Kill Whitey, Food Not
Bombs), while Ervin classifies criticism of the âstateâs ability to hold
back a free lifestyleâ as middle class (110). IPs allege that the entire
tactical repertoire of horizontalism is privileged, in contrast with
their preferred focus on community organising or intra-movement
struggle.
The grain of truth in this position is that tactics of escape, exodus,
and physical resistance carry different levels of difficulty and risk
for different people. Itâs easier to quit a job than to escape from
prison. Itâs easier to run from the police if one is physically fit. But
anyone can adopt a perspective of escape, and attempt to create lines of
flight from the system. While it may be easier for some than others,
nobody should be under a moral obligation to remain oppressed just to
avoid being different from others; any such obligation only reinforces
oppression.
There are far more people who squat, shoplift, or dumpster dive who are
from poor and marginal backgrounds; in the global South there are entire
strata living in squatted shantytowns, abstracting electricity, and
scavenging in rubbish tips. Historical practices such as the celebrated
quilombos show that dropping-out is a serious, and often successful,
strategy for the most oppressed.
James Scottâs work shows that peasants, slaves, and marginal groups use
various tactics of exodus to minimise their subservience to elite power.
Similarly, when highly oppressed groups become sufficiently angry, they
often use the most militant forms of protest - as we have seen in cases
like Paris 2005, London 2011, Los Angeles 1992, and so on. Poor people
also use all kinds of high-risk survival strategies, from undocumented
border-crossing to involvement in the drug trade. There is also evidence
that dropping-out worked to defeat aspects of capitalism in the 1970s
(Shukaitis).
Why, then, do IPs oppose exodus? I would hazard a guess that the real
underlying objection is not that poor people cannot drop out, but that
they should not: dropping-out contradicts the IPâs political agenda,
resting on strong spectres and identities within the existing frame.
Structural determinism precludes escape on principle. IPs celebrate
their current blockages, internalise their cage, and insist that the
cage is both inescapable and revolutionary. This is not a perspective of
escape â it is a perspective of entrapment in the guise of solidarity.
IPsâ emphasis on community really comes down to a fear of placelessness.
Their ideological vision of society requires that everyone have
definable positionalities: a conservative vision, but inverted. This
requires that categories remain dominant over lines of flight, escape,
and becoming. Hence the need to enforce a prohibition on exodus - a
prohibition which reveals their similarities with states and other
hierarchical systems, which similarly prohibit the withdrawal of
participation and restrict mobility. It is easy to see how the fear of
the uncontrollable and unknowable - and the parallel desire to order all
of reality into a fixed schema - lies beneath these discursive
strategies.
A lot of the objection to exodus comes down to a hatred of play.
Drop-outs are accused of turning poverty into a game, of saying someone
can be poor and have fun (Anon, Smack and White Boy Part Two). This may
just as well be said of important strands of peasant resistance such as
carnivalesque and folk culture. IPs flourish on a culture of deadly
seriousness and urgency, tied up with a celebration of trauma. Real
activism, after all, is hard work, sacrifice: I cant have fun, so you
shouldnât either. This entails denying pleasure to others whenever
possible. Of course, dropping out does lead to a kind of privilege - the
person who has escaped clearly has a better life than the person still
trapped in the system. This is equally true of quilombos, maroon
communities, pirate utopias, and so on. But is this really a case
against dropping-out?
Instead of seeking to escape the system, IPs place great emphasis on
serving the community, the people, the oppressed, or a particular
oppressed group. Ervin insists that the usefulness of revolutionaries
depends on whether they serve the community (136), as opposed to
âDeclasse punks with red Mohawksâ (276). White suggests that the âfirst
priority of resistanceâ is community consciousness raising. Ribeiro
argues that the âpeopleâ are failing to flock to existing anarchist
groups because they represent âa white, petty-bourgeois Anarchism that
cannot relate to the people,â an anarchism which is âindividualistic,
self-serving, [and] selfish.â A Qilombo supporter goes as far as to
argue that âinvolving oneself in the school systemâ is an âexcellent...
investment,â far superior to drop-out anarchism, while another posits a
âneed to emphasize community norms and practicesâ (Kurukshetra), and
Veranasi tells anarchists to get a job so as not to separate from the
oppressed (comments on Smack a White Boy Part Two). There is also a
wider accusation, particularly in Ervinâs work, that the allegedly bad
race, gender, or class politics of radical movements is the reason for
their continued failure (303, 310). This is the Maoist view that a tide
of latent energy is always waiting to be released, which is currently
fettered by the principal contradiction and inadequate leadership (Mao,
On Contradiction; Bouc, 137; Howe and Walker, 176; Gurley).
A collective proprietary attitude to geographical areas corresponds to
this political bias. White anarchists active in poor communities are
accused of failing to get community consent, disrespecting locals, and
gentrifying areas by inserting whiteness (Kill Whitey, Smack a White
Boy; Kurukshetra). Ervin suggests anarchists have no âright to beâ in a
Black area (282), Kill Whitey tells white radicals to âget the fuck out
of POC communitiesâ (True Colors); in effect, white radicals are banned
from Black areas in an inverted reproduction of segregation. This is a
double-bind, since anarchist events in rural locations are declared
inaccessible to poor people (Ervin, Racism in ABC; Veranasi, comments on
Smack a White Boy Part Two). This reflects a broader irresolvable
predicament: radicals are both told to be part of the people, and told
they cannot (since their perspective is incommensurable and their
privilege is ineliminable). The glorification of ghettos as autonomous
zones runs up against the reality of imposed racial segregation.
There is a strong tone of ressentiment in the position: I canât drop out
so you mustnât. If I was jailed and unable to escape from power, I would
take courage and hope from the fact that others are still able to do so.
The objection to separation tries to force radicals back into avoidable
systems of authoritarian domination, such as work and schooling, thus
reinforcing these institutions. IPs glorify escape from controlled
spaces, such as fleeing the senzala (slave quarters) to the quilombo
(autonomous zone). Yet in practice, they tell us never to flee the
senzala, but instead to work within it as overseers, conditioning
children into conformity, or as exploited, joyless workers. There is
nothing radical and empowering about getting a job. In a context of
generalised entrapment, to separate is not to alienate, but rather to
escape, to slip out of place, to flee dominant categories and those who
impose them.
Community politics is hamstrung by a major problem: the community are
not especially radical. The IP assumption that âthe peopleâ or âthe
communityâ has revolutionary instincts is an effect of its construction
as a spectre, not a result of observation of actual people. It also
embeds vanguardist assumptions that the role of radicals is to locate,
lead, and imbue these communities with revolutionary interests. The
orientation to liberate a spectre rather than concrete people is the
source of IPsâ hostility to individualism, personal freedom, and
supposed selfishness among radicals.
IPs also run up against the realities of contemporary capitalism. Today,
most of us do not belong to real, substantive communities. As
Landstreicher argues, âthe dominant forms of relating are economic,
based on the domination of survival over life ... Today, neither the
daily interactions of oneâs âcommunitiesâ (these strange, disconnected
âcommunitiesâ of family, school, work) nor the chance encounters (at the
market, on the bus, at some public event) have much chance of sparking a
real and intense interest in another, an impassioned curiosity to
discover who they are and what we might be able to create with themâ
(7). Bey argues that simply coming together is already a victory over
capitalism (Immediatism vs Capitalism), and the Situationists exposed
the emptiness of everyday life and the role of urban residential areas
as state-controlled warehouses for workers (Debord, sections 169-76).
Even where some kind of community life persists, it rarely entails a
unitary set of beliefs, demands, and interests, or even (outside of
certain subaltern social movements and indigenous groups) any kind of
collective power. In looking to âthe community,â IPs are seeking a
source of strength which is at once a product of the system, and thereby
constituted as weak. If they want dense, mutually supportive, socially
meaningful communities, then they - like the rest of us - will have to
build these communities, often from scratch, on the basis of affinity
and living-otherwise. When IPs speak for the community, they typically
do so as a vanguard, a representative, who substitutes for a community
which is absent in practice.
A short time ago, the new BBC class survey (Heyden) became a fad among
those activists who use social media. Nearly everyone who completed it
came out in a category called âemergent service workersâ (ESWs). The
survey has eight categories, and ESWs are the second-bottom category,
defined by low income and precarious work. They differ from the
worse-off precariat in only two ways - âsocial and cultural capital.â In
other words, the average anarchist is in the same position as the
poorest group, except that we have more education and stronger social
networks. ESWs are not some middle-class elite, hovering over the
authentic poor. The precariat make up only 15% of the population
according to the survey. ESWs are well below halfway. And the moment a
precarian becomes politicised, they tend to gain education and networks,
and become ESWs. So, realistically, anarchy is not a movement of
middle-class kids. It is a movement of politically conscious, socially
networked poor people.
IPs believe that anarchy is irrelevant to the community because
anarchists are privileged, and separate from the community. In fact,
anarchy seems irrelevant to the community because most people whoâve
been conditioned to live within such system-constructed communities have
internalised repressive, statist beliefs, and accept capitalist common
sense (the Gramscian notion of an incoherent everyday philosophy or
ideology prevalent among subaltern people, which embeds uncritical,
hegemonic, and reactionary beliefs). The idea that the oppressed are
just waiting for the right activist leadership, which is blocked by the
allegedly inherent racism/sexism in social movements, is a delusion.
Working in wider communities entails putting up with (and even
glorifying) a lot of common-sense ideologies, prejudices, and bigotry on
a scale far greater than anything within radical scenes. The real
problem is not organisation, or the correct line, or the right
leadership. The problem is whether people actually desire
revolution/insurrection. In fact, no revolutionary âpeopleâ exists,
because of what Stimer terms the police sentiments of actually existing
people (116).
The hypothesis that the community is more radical than so-called
privileged anarchists is simply false. Most anarchists already oppose
work, police, prisons, government, and so on whereas most community
members do not. It is not uncommon for anarchists fighting
gentrification, CCTV and other forms of the surveillance state, or
morality-policing to be pitted against other local residents. It might
be in poor peopleâs material interests to oppose dominant institutions,
but for the most part they donât. People who lack formal or informal
political education tend not to become anarchists because they tend to
remain stuck in capitalist common sense, dependent on the discourses
made available by the mainstream, and caught up in the pursuit of values
of individual advancement. Their supposed interests have little effect
in mitigating these influences. Any anarchist project directed at the
worse-off need to start from some kind of political education or
political de/resocialisation of the poor (not primarily of ourselves,
though most critical pedagogy is also reflexive and dialogical).
Otherwise, anarchists pursuing such projects will simply be overwhelmed
by the unreflexive common sense of those whose perspectives they
idealise.
The theme of urgency is closely connected to the community orientation.
IPs often posit immediately apparent realities, which are deemed
extra-theoretical and extra-political. Disagreement with the IPâs
perspective or actions is belittled as a âtopic ripe for a drunk PhDâ
(White) or âsome intellectualâs grad thesisâ(Weaver). The oppressed are
said to âknow oppressionâ from experience: âwe lost the need to
understand pain philosophically when we learned it physicallyâ
(Ribeiro). Ervin postures as having no particular expertise, except âa
decent supply of good common sense and street knowledgeâ (10), and urges
us to âtrust the best instincts of the peopleâ (119). Patriarchy Haters
condemn political debate as contrasting with real, life-or-death stakes
for them: âWe do not agree with people having a âpolitical argumentâ at
our expenseâ (Statement). They suggest that their positions come from
their âBODIES,â which are not âto be politicized, theorized, speculated
uponâ (Weaver).
IPs advance a framework in which theory distracts from reality. The
historical origin of this framework is the Maoist emphasis on
âexperienceâ (suitably processed by the party) as superior to âbook
learning,â and the corresponding âRed versus expertâ struggles of the
Cultural Revolution. The basic gesture is to split issues between the
real reality posited by IPs and associated with experience and the
principal contradiction, and a field deemed secondary or tertiary, and
therefore trivial. This grounds apparently obvious, self-evident claims
and is used to create a sense of urgency: IPs are doing real,
life-or-death politics, and everyone else is just messing around (notice
once again the prejudice against play). The function of this gesture is
to âdeclare certain questions off-limitsâ because âthe answer is already
knownâ (Williams). Arguments against IPsâ claims are often displaced
onto the issue of who has the right to decide, which is returned to the
question of spectres
Black radicals donât have to listen to white critics, male experts have
no right to expound on survivorsâ experiences, etc. This is a
category-error, to which the appropriate answer is: Iâve not exposed
your mistake because I think you need my permission - Iâve exposed your
mistake because it leads to oppression, bad politics, or
ineffectiveness. This strategy gives power to those who define which
issues are urgent. In fact, none of the cases discussed here were
anywhere near to being life-or-death situations. And paradoxically, to
heal from trauma, one needs to theorise and intellectualise it.
In fact, the idea of obvious experiences is fallacious. There is no
simple divide between reality/experience and thought/theory. Humans
process experiences through conceptual categories, and in many cases,
these categories affect the impact of an experience - or what,
subjectively, is experienced. People donât lack theories simply because
they are not formally educated or academically trained. Rather, everyone
has their own stock of theories and concepts through which they
unconsciously process the world, and without which the world would
simply be an incomprehensible mess of sense-impressions. Whenever
somebody claims that their own conceptions are real, or are unmediated
experience in contrast to othersâ mere ideas or opinions, they are
actually reifying and naturalising their own socially constructed
beliefs - usually beliefs based on capitalist common sense. There is no
such thing as direct, unmediated knowledge from experience (as distinct
from unmediated experience, which is felt as unrepresentable). In any
case, IPs create a regime of roles, which in Vaneigemâs terms, âexpress
lived experience, yet at the same time they reify itâ (131).
This does not mean that academic theories are always best. Academic
thought is often tied-up with corporate and state power (Dot Matrix,
Science As Capital). Everyday, local knowledges can also be effective
ways of theorising the world. But it is a mistake to reify them into
unmediated experiences which are somehow directly (and therefore more
objectively) true. It shuts down dialogue and reinforces the enclosure
of common sense. And in many cases, everyday common sense is also
extremely oppressive, accepting and imposing normativities complicit
with, and directly reinforcing, institutionalized forms of power. In
addition, many key terms in IPsâ discourse - structural oppression,
privilege, patriarchy, trauma, framing, supremacy, senzala, quilombo and
so on - are not everyday common sense terms, but imports from university
cultural studies texts or historical reading. Anti-intellectualism
handily insulates IPs from rebuttal, but does not make their poorly
based strategies any more effective.
From all of this, we must conclude that IPs are just another type of
leftist, promoting sacrifice and renunciation, posing as liberators of
the oppressed. IPs are seductive in the ways they have of identifying
and channelling the anger of the oppressed, the guilt of the
(relatively) privileged, experiences of trauma, and awareness of the
possibility of unintended oppression. But they channel these affects
into political power, using them to entrench the role of IPs as Experts.
This role requires that privilege/oppression be theorised as an
ineliminable original sin.
Against this prevalent form of disguised vanguardism, let us hold forth
the beacon of a world without spectres. Structural oppressions are
sociologically real, but their roots can be traced deeper, to the
structures of statism and representation. If we must theorise a primary
contradiction, then let it be the contradiction between ourselves - as
unique ones, forces of becoming, irreducible and unrepresentable
beings - and the entire regime of spectres and alienation. Let us
dispense with boundary policing, and instead nurture affinities across
social categories. It is in rediscovering the level of immanent,
abundant becoming, the joy of life, the flow of desire and direct
connection, that we destroy the power which spectres exercise over us.
Let us start always from this joy, share it with others when we can, and
use it as a weapon to break down common sense, to rebuild and redefine
community, to replace the graveyard of spectres with a world of life.
May the alien privileges of spectres and the alien oppressions they
engender never come between a unique one, a free being, and its immanent
becoming. @
Agamben, Giorgio (1998), Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life,
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
Anon. (2001), âGive Up Activism,â Do or Die 9, 160-66
http://www.eco-action.org/dod/no9/activism.htm
Anon. (2008), âAn Open Letter to White Progressives and Radicalsâ
http://news.infoshop.org/article. php?story=20080506232456151
Anon. (2009), âSmack a White Boy Part Two: Crimethlnc Evictionâ
http://news.infoshop.org/article. php?story=2009073l00325514
Anonymous Refused (2014), âFor Your Safety and Security'
http://anonymousrefused.tumblr.com/post/99047385737/for-your-safety-and-security
Anzaldua, G. (2000), Interviews/Entrevistas, New York: Psychology Press.
Anzaldua, G. (2013), This Bridge We Call Home: Radical Visions for
Transformation, New York: Routledge.
Aragorn! (2007), âA Non-European Anarchismâ
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/ara-gorn-a-non-european-anarchism.pdf
Aragorn! (2009), âToward a non European Anarchism or Why a movement is
the last thing that people of color needâ
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/aragorn-toward-a-non-european-anarchism-or-why-a-movement-is-the-last-thing-that-people-of-colo.pdf
Bey, Hakim (1991), T.A.Z. Part 3 http://hermetic.com/bey/taz3.html
Bey, Hakim (1992), âImmediatism versus Capitalismâ
http://hermetic.com/bey/radio_se.html
Bey, Hakim (no date), âThe Occult Assault on Institutionsâ
http://hermetic.com/bey/occultassault.html
Black Orchid Collective (2014), âBuilding Capacity for Complexityâ
https://blackorchidcollective.wordpress.com/
2013/03/14/building-capacity-for-complexity/
Bonanno, Alfredo (1977), Armed Joy.
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/alfredo-m-bonanno-armed-joy.pdf
Bouc, Alain (1977), Mao Tse-Tung: A Guide to his Thought, New York: St
Martinâs Press
Burman, Anders (2009), âColonialism in Context: An Aymara Reassessment
ofâColonialism,' âColoniality' and the âPostcolonial World,â' Kult 6,
117-29 http://postkolonial.dk/artikler/kult_6/BURMAN.pdf
Chan, Anita, Stanley Rosen and Jonathan Unger (1980), âStudents and
Class Warfare: The Social Roots of the Red Guard Conflict in Guangzhou,â
The China Quarterly 83, 397-446
Clastres, Pierre (1994/1974), âOfEthnocide,â in Archeology of Violence,
New York: Semiotext(e), 43-51
Debord, Guy (1977/1967), Society of the Spectacle, London: Rebel
Press/Dark Star
De Souza Santos, Boaventura (2007), Abyssal Thoughtâ
http://www.eurozine.com/articles/2007-06-29-santos-en.html
Dot Matrix (no date), âOn the Road with CWS,â Anarchy: Journal of Desire
Armed. http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/
dot-matrix-on-the-road-with-cws
Dot Matrix (2006), âScience is Capital: Fragments on Why Anthropology
Can't be Anarchist,â Anarchy: Journal of Desire Armed 61
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/dot-
matrix-science-is-capital.pdf
Duran, Eduardo and Bonnie Duran (1995),Native American Postcolonial
Psychology, New York: SUNY Press
Ervin, Lorenzo (2011), Anarchism and the Black Revolution: The Idea of
Black Autonomy, Denver: P&L/IWW
Ervin, Lorenzo (2014), âRacism at the North American Anarchist Black
Cross Conferenceâ http://www.ainfos.ca/en/ainfos30003.html
Fanon, F. (1963/2004), The Wretched of the Earth, New York: Grove.
https://warriorpublications.files.wordpress.com/
2013/01/wretched-of-the-earth-frantz-fanon.pdf
Fanon, F. (1952/2007), Black Skin, White Masks, New York: Grove.
Faun, Feral (no date), Feral Revolution and Other Essays
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/feralfaaun-essays.pdf
Gelderloos, Peter (2010), Lines in the Sandâ
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/peter-
gelderloos-lines-in-sand.pdf
Gurley, John G. (1970), âCapitalist and Maoist Economic Development,â
Bulletin of Concerned Asian Scholars 2
http://www.arkibongbayan.org/2011/
2011-05May20-KaBel3rdAniv/sosguidedoc/Capitalist%20and%20Maoist%20Economic%20Development.doc
Heckert, Jamie (2013), âAnarchy without Oppositionâ
http://www.occupywallstreet.net/story/anarchy-without-opposition
Herman, Judith (1997), Trauma and Recovery:The Aftermath of Violence,
New York: Basic
Heyden, Tom (2013), âClass calculator: Can I have no job and money and
still be middle class?â http://www.bbc.com/news/magazine-21953364
Howe, Christopher and Kenneth R. Walker (1977), âThe Economist,â in Dick
Wilson (ed), Mao Tse-Tung in the Scales of History, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 174-222
Jarach, Lawrence (2004), âPreliminary Theses for a Longer Discussion on
Essentialism and the Problem of Identity Politics,â Anarchy: Journal of
Desire Armed 58 (Fall)
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/lawrence-jarach-essentialism-and-the-problem-of-identity-politics.pdf
Jarach, Lawrence et al. (2014), âAn Open Letter to Bay Area Anarchistsâ
www.anarchistnews.org/node?page=48&%3Bpage=l99
Kill Whitey (2009), âSAWB2 [Smack a White Boy Part 2]: 15 Points of
Clarificationâ http://kilwaii.blogspot.nl/2009/08/
sawb2-15-points-factsquestionsclarifica .html
Kill Whitey (2009), âTrue Colors: An Open Reply to Food Not Bombs and
Those Who Defend Itâ
http://kilwaii.blogspot.nl/2009/08/true-colors-open-
reply-to-food-not.html
Kill Whitey (2009), âOpen Letter to Food Not Bombsâ
http://kilwaii.blogspot.nl/2009/07/open-letter-to-food-not-bombs-food-not.html
Kurukshetra (2014), âReflections on the âDecolonization and Anarchism'
Panel at the 2014 Bay Area Anarchist Bookfairâ
http://kurukshetral.wordpress.com/2014/04/03/
reflections-on-the-decolonization-and-anarchism-
panel-at-the-2014-bay-area-anarchist-bookfair/
Landstreicher, Wolfi (2005), âAgainst the Logic of Submissionâ
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/wolfi-landstreicher-against-the-logic-of-submission.pdf
Mao Zedong (1937), On
Contradictionhttps://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/mao/selected-works/volume-1/mswvl_l7.htm
Mao Zedong (1937), On
Practicehttps://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/mao/selected-works/volume-l/mswvl_16.htm
Marx, Karl (1845-6), The German Ideology, Chapter 3: Saint Max [Stirner]
https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1845/german-ideology/ch03.htm
Naparstek, Belleruth (2006), Invisible Heroes: Survivors of Trauma and
How they Heal, London: Piatkus.
Patriarchy Haters/Patriarchy and the Movement Organizers (2013),
âStatement on Patriarchy and the Movementâ
http://patriarchyandthemovement.wordpress.com/2013/03/07/statement-on-the-patriarchy-and-the-movement-event-portland-2282013/
Peaceful Societies (no date), âLadakhiâ
http://www.peacefulsocieties.org/Society/Ladakhis.html
Perry, Elizabeth and Li Xun (1997), Proletarian Power: Shanghai in the
Cultural Revolution, New York: Westview.
Petersen, Abby (2001), Contemporary Political Protest: Essays on
Political Militancy, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Qilombo (2014), âKeep Qilombo Openâ
http://qilombo.org/emergency-fundraiser-keep-qilombo-open/
Perlman, Fredy (1984), The Continuing Appeal of Nationalism
https://libcom.org/library/ continuing-appeal-nationalism-fredy-perlman
Ribeiro, Pedro (2005), âSenzala or Quilombo: Reflections on APOC and the
Fate of Black Anarchismâ
http://www.anarkismo.net/newswire.php?story_id=460
Scott, James C (2009), The Art of Not Being Governed: An Anarchist
History of Upland Southeast Asia, New Haven: Yale University Press
Shukaitis, S. (2006), âWhose Precarity is it Anyway?â Fifth Estate, vol.
41, no. 3
Stirner, Max (1845), The Ego and his Own
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/max-stimer-the-ego-and-his-own.pdf
Sullivan, Sian (2004), âWe are Heartbroken and Furious! (#2) Violence
and the (anti-)globalisation movement(s),â CSGR Working Paper No. 133/04
http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/1981/l/WRAP_Sullivan_wpl3304.pdf
Tekanji (2006), â'Check My What?â On privilege and what we can do about
itâ http://blog.shrub.com/archives/tekanji/2006-03-08_146
Vaneigem, Raoul (1994/1967), The Revolution of Everyday Life, London:
Rebel Press
Voline (2014), âRadical Irrationality and Authoritarianismâ
http://anarchistnews.org/content/radical-irrationality-and-authoritarianism
[currently inaccessible]
Weaver, Rebecca (2014), âThe Cult of the Male Expertâ
http://patriarchyhaters.wordpress.com/2014/05/23/the-
cult-of-the-male-expert-becca-weaver-explains-why-she-participated-in-the-protest-of-kristian-williams/
White, Roger (2005), âIdentity Politics and Essentialism, in Post
Colonial Anarchism: Essays on Race, Repression and Culture in
Communities of Color, 1999-2004
http://www.coloursofresistance.org/326/identity-politics-and-essentialism/
Willful Disobedience (Anon.) (2001), âA Question of Privilege,â Willful
Disobedience 2 (8), 7-8
http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/various-authors-willful-disobedience-volume-2-number-8.pdf
Williams, Kristian (2014), âThe Politics of Denunciationâ
http://towardfreedom.com/29-archives/activism/3455-the-politics-of-denunciation
[1] Ed. note: In Der Einzige... Stirner uses spuk; the English cognate
"spook," while a decent enough translation in 1907, is currently an
inappropriate (to say the least) option. We chose to use spectre
(especially and deliberately retaining the British spelling) for its
non-colloquial impact.
[2] Ed. note: There was a time when the term POC was inclusive of
everyone who so self-identified (regardless of the term exacerbating
certain unarticulated and unavoidable tensions about homogenizing the
distinct experiences of people from diverse ethnic backgrounds, as well
as the different ways those distinctions resulted in particular
experiences of racism); in the past few years, however, the analytical
category of Blackness/Anti-Blackness has become more popular in
post-colonial discourse, especially among academics and activists.
Michael P Jeffries writes that Anti-Blackness is "not simply about
hating or penalizing black people. It is about the debasement of black
humanity, utter indifference to black suffering, and the denial of black
people's right to exist." The recent twisting of "Black Lives Matter"
into "All Lives Matter" is a good example of how deeply the threat of a
recognized Black humanity runs in the US. Despite the increasingly
problematic term POC, we have retained it out of respect for the many
who continue to embrace it as a self-description.
[3] Ed. note: The fundamental aspect of tension/destructiveness of class
society; for traditional Marxists, itâs bourgeoisie-proletariat within
the framework of capitalism. When resolved through the teleological
process of dialectical materialism (The Revolutionâą), the resulting
synthesis is supposed to make the secondary (and tertiary, etc)
contradictions like sexism, racism, and other ostensibly trivial forms
of institutionalized oppression, melt away.