đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș anarcho-review-the-age-of-empathy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:33:55. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Review: The Age of Empathy
Author: Anarcho
Date: April 25, 2012
Language: en
Topics: book review, empathy, mutual aid, evolution
Source: Retrieved on 24th April 2021 from https://anarchism.pageabode.com/?p=648

Anarcho

Review: The Age of Empathy

This is an excellent, if occasionally frustrating, book. Written by

leading Primatologist Frans de Waal, The Age of Empathy summarises the

research into the evolution of cooperation, social feelings and empathy.

If I were to sum it up in a few words it would be: “Kropotkin was

right.”

These were subjects close to Kropotkin’s heart and which, as de Waal

shows, he has been vindicated. Sadly, the scientific community did not

follow Kropotkin’s lead. Instead we got ideology and cultural

assumptions passing for science – as expressed by the embarrassment of a

nature alleged rooted in individualistic competition having so much

cooperation within it. That this was labelled a paradox rather a

refutation by many scientists shows the power of unstated and assumed

societal assumptions.

Now, a century after Mutual Aid was published, we are seeing the outcome

of research into how natural selection could produce morality. The book

describes its this in convincing detail and summarises (to quote de

Waal) much of the “exciting new research about the origins of altruism

and fairness in both ourselves and other animals.” (5) “Human empathy,”

he shows, “has the backing of a long evolutionary history” (x) and has

its basis in the cooperation required to survive in a hostile

environment. Thus we have inherited cooperative tendencies from our ape

ancestors, for “mutualism and reciprocity as the basis of cooperation”

places “chimps much closer to humans than to the social insects.” (180)

So the book’s title plays on two themes, namely that now is the time to

create more empathy within society and that empathy has been evolving

within mammals for millions of years: “Empathy is part of our evolution,

and not just a recent part, but an innate, age-old capacity.” (205) This

evolutionary heritage is reflected today, with research showing that we

“know an unfair distribution when we see one, and try to counteract it”

(186) and “we still have a psychology that feels most comfortable with

these outcomes.” (221) Thus:

“Empathy builds on proximity, similarity, and familiarity, which is

entirely logical given that it evolves to promote in-group cooperation.

Combined with our interest in social harmony, which requires a fair

distribution of resources, empathy put the human species on a path

towards small-scale societies that stress equality and solidarity.”

(221)

Unsurprisingly, de Waal discusses our evolutionary heritage and it will

make encouraging reading for libertarians. “We have,” he argues, “a

deeply ingrained sense of fairness, which derives from our long history

as egalitarians.” (159) Not only are we “born revolutionaries,” we

“emphasise sharing and suppress distinctions of wealth and power” and so

“tribal communities level the hierarchy” by “ridicule, gossip, and

disobedience” but also “more drastic measures.” (161) We have a

“distinctly subversive streak” (161) which mocks those seeking power

over others – and acts to stop them. Thus “empathy binds individuals

together and gives each a stack in the welfare of others” (223) and “the

true cradle of cooperation is the community.” (182)

Moreover, this cooperative and egalitarian legacy impacts on us today

and in spite of all erosive impacts of surviving under capitalism in

economic experiments, the majority “is altruistic, cooperative,

sensitive to fairness, and orientated towards community goals.” This

means that the “[t]raditional economic models don’t consider the human

sense of fairness, even though it demonstrably affects economic

decisions.” (162) Similarly, rather than being the aggressive animals of

popular culture, warfare “conflicts at the deepest level with our

humanity.” (220) This can be seen from the amount of propaganda required

to get a nation to go to war.

All this confirms anarchist theory. As de Waal suggests, and no

anarchist would disagree, the “firmest support for the common good comes

from enlightened self-interest: the realisation that we’re all better

off if we work together.” (223)

The book also addresses modern evolutionary theory, specifically the

much misunderstood notion of genetic “selfishness.” He discusses a

meeting with Richard Dawkins, author of The Selfish Gene, and notes the

common ground between them. He has “no problem calling genes ‘selfish’

so long as it’s understood that this says nothing about the actual

motives of humans and animals.” (40) This is Dawkins’ position (see the

preface to the 30^(th) anniversary edition of The Selfish Gene where he

acknowledges that some of the language used in the first edition was

confused and so misleading). So “selfish” genes do not preclude

cooperative and altruistic acts – quite the reverse, as cooperation (as

Kropotkin stressed) is how animals (and so their genes) best survive.

Talking of Kropotkin, de Waal explicitly mentions him and Mutual Aid

(32–3). He insists on calling someone who renounced his title “the

Russian prince,” but this can be forgiven as he summarises Kropotkin’s

argument that mutual aid benefits those who practice it: “If helping is

communal, he argued, all parties stand to gain.” (171–2) This means that

cooperation is “a crucial survival skill” and “cooperative groups of

animals (or humans) would outperform less cooperative ones.” (33) It

boils down to “the choice between the small rewards of individualism and

the large rewards of collective action.” (163) Cooperation is in our

best interests – as Kropotkin argued.

Sadly, de Waal suggests that Kropotkin “forgot to add” that “cooperation

is vulnerable to freeloaders” and suggests that he “corrected himself”

by arguing (in Conquest of Bread) a “few years after publication” of

Mutual Aid that the non-cooperative would be expelled from groups.

(171–2) However, while Conquest of Bread may have been published in

English after Mutual Aid, it was originally published in French before

it. Nor is Mutual Aid silent on the need for groups to act on

anti-social and non-cooperative behaviour as de Wall suggests (nor did

it deny competitive behaviour, another popular myth). Thus we find in

that work Kropotkin mentioning how animals penalise uncooperative

individuals (for example, “selfish” ants would be “treated as an enemy,

or worse”). In this way “natural selection continually must eliminate”

anti-social instincts – or, to quote de Waal, Kropotkin recognised that

a “measure of reciprocity” (174) is required for mutual aid to work and

so there is a need “to penalise those who fall short” (180–1) in order

to ensure cooperative behaviour benefits all.

So while it is obvious that de Waal is better acquainted with

Kropotkin’s work than most commenters on it, it is clear that he could

do with a closer read. If he did, then he would realise that to state

that “Mutual aid has become a standard ingredient of modern evolutionary

theories, albeit not exactly in the way Kropotkin formulated it” (33) is

incorrect. Kropotkin recognised the need to reward cooperative behaviour

and punish those who do not reciprocate in the same way as modern

evolutionary theories.

The book is keen to suggest that nature informs our ethical standards,

causing some to invoke “naturalistic fallacy” and dismiss the moral

relevance of empathy and altruism in non-human animals. What ethnical

conclusions can be drawn from scientific evidence? After all, if it is a

mistake to justify human selfishness on the basis of the alleged

competitive aspects of nature (as right-wing Social Darwinism does)

then, surely, it is just as bad to advocate altruism because animals

also cooperate.

Yet this ignores the fact that our sense of fairness and

right-and-wrong, our horror at certain behaviour, are a product of

evolution. As de Waal suggests, “[t]rying to set human cooperation apart

from the larger natural scheme
 hardly qualifies as an evolutionary

approach.” (182) Ultimately, if we do not derive “ought” from “is” where

do we derive it from? A Holy Book? Abstract thought untethered to

anything as trivial as evidence? As Kropotkin argued, if “the only

lesson Nature gives to man is one of evil” then a thinker “necessarily

has to admit the existence of some other, extra-natural, or

super-natural influence which inspires man with conceptions of ‘supreme

good’” which “nullifies” attempts “at explaining evolution by the action

of natural forces only.”

The question, then, is not whether we derive “ought” from “is” but

rather how do we justify the “is” we try and derive from nature. Here is

when our reason and our evolved sense of empathy and justice come in. We

analyse nature, see it as both competitive and cooperative and then,

based on our evolved sense of fairness and our evolving societal norms,

draw ethical conclusions. We can be horrified by the worse aspects of

the natural world precisely because our sense of justice has evolved as

part of it.

So this book is handy evidence to refute all those who rationalise their

own narrow perspectives (and social position) in terms of “nature.” This

is not justified by empirical evidence – nor Darwin’s work. The

competitive individualistic evolutionary perspective is highly

selective, indeed distorted. We are not condemned “by nature” to treat

each other badly, quite the reverse. In showing the evidence for this de

Waal is very convincing.

The Age of Empathy shows that the modern researcher (unknowingly,

usually) is following in Kropotkin’s footsteps. As Kropotkin put it in

the posthumously published Ethics, “Mutual Aid-Justice-Morality are thus

the consecutive steps of an ascending series” and that morality

“developed later than the others” (and so was “an unstable feeling and

the least imperative of the three”). Thus mutual aid came first and

ensured “the ground is prepared for the further and the more general

development of more refined relations.” This is an important point, both

because many confuse mutual aid with altruism and it shows that

Kropotkin recognised that ethical behaviour is not fixed in spite of it

having an evolutionary basis.

Marxists tend to reject the evidence that our behaviour reflects our

evolution as social animals. Instead they subscribe to the idea that

“human nature” is a social construct. To quote Marx: “M. Proudhon does

not know that the whole of history is nothing but a continual

transformation of human nature.” (The Poverty of Philosophy) To this day

there are some who think that this sentence by Marx nullifies millions

of years of evolution! And as de Waal suggests, “Marxism foundered on

the illusion of a culturally engineered human. It assumed that we are

born as a tabula rasa, a blank slate.” (202) So Marx’s position is

pre-Darwinian – and simply wrong. Sadly, it has been parroted by

Marxists ever since. The early Marx’s comments on species-character is

more fruitful a concept (particular with regards to alienation – for how

can you experience alienation if you don’t have something to be

alienated from?). For those interested in such analysis the work of

Erich Fromm is recommended.

The more sophisticated Marxist (like their Christian equivalent) will

not read these words literally but rather suggest that different

societies will promote different aspects of (our evolved) human nature.

Which is true, of course, but not what Marx asserted. As Noam Chomsky

(correctly) put it:

“Human nature is not totally fixed, but on any realistic scale

evolutionary processes are much too slow to affect it
 So within a

realistic time frame there is not going to be any change in human

nature. But human nature allows many different options and the choice

among those options can change, and it has. So there are striking

changes, even in our own lifetime, of what we accept as tolerable. Take

something like women’s rights: if you go back not so many years women

were basically regarded as property. That’s a sign of the expansion of

our moral spheres. So sure, human nature remains the same but a lot of

things can change.” (New Scientist no. 2856, 19 March 2012)

This echoes Kropotkin, who noted in Mutual Aid that “Man is a result of

both his inherited instincts and his education.” Looking around, it is

obvious that humans can, and do, ignore our evolved sense of empathy and

fairness. Some of us have developed whole ideologies (such as

economics!) to rationalise doing this (to ease our consciences).

Kropotkin recognised this very obvious fact, arguing in an article for

the anarchist press that “[w]hile the fundamental features of human

characters can only be mediated by a very slow evolution, the relative

amount of individualist and mutual aid spirit are among the most

changeable features of man. Both being equally products of an anterior

development, their relative amounts are seen to change in individuals

and even societies with a rapidity which would strike the sociologist if

only he paid attention to the subject, and analysed the corresponding

facts.” As de Waal suggests: “We may not be able to create a New Man,

we’re remarkably good at modifying the old one.” (210)

So recognising that ethics have an evolutionary basis is not to suggest

that ethical positions are unchanging. Far from it – as history shows,

different cultures have radically different notions of what is moral

(arranged marriages, slavery, wage-labour for example). Moreover, the

rationales for these practices have also changed (divine right,

religious authority, economic “science” to name just a few). Kropotkin

sketched these changing notions in Ethics. Human society evolves and

changes, reflecting changing economic, class and social relationships,

but within limits based upon an evolved sense of ethics – a “human

nature” which simply cannot be assumed away.

As Marx’s comment was directed at Proudhon, it must be noted that many

of his ideas seem to be confirmed by the research de Waal summarises so

ably. We seem to have a sense of fairness, justice even, and practice

reciprocity, all themes the Frenchman expounded upon (and Marx, perhaps

needless to say, mocked). His proclamation of anarchy in What is

Property? followed an interesting discussion of cooperation in animals

and humans. He noted that the “social instinct, in man and beast, exists

to a greater or less degree” and to “practise justice is to obey the

social instinct; to do an act of justice is to do a social act.” Thus

the “social instinct and the moral sense [man] shares with the brutes;

and when he thinks to become god-like by a few acts of charity, justice,

and devotion, he does not perceive that in so acting he simply obeys an

instinct wholly animal in its nature.” Unsurprisingly, Kropotkin

discusses Proudhon and his ideas on justice and ethics at some length in

Ethics.

The frustrating aspects of the book relate to the obvious societal

assumptions which creep in. It is somewhat ironic to see a scientist so

keen to refute the myths inflicted upon the animal world so readily

accept the myths of modern society – thus the USA is presented as the

land of liberty and Europe the land of equality (de Waal’s preference

seems to be somewhere in the middle – the North Atlantic not being the

best place to live!).

So de Waal does indulge in using metaphors which reflect the society he

is within and so he mentions “past exchanges” and “marketplace of

services.” (175) This is to be expected, given that scientists are

products of the society they live and work. Thus, as Daniel Todes has

recounted in Darwin Without Malthus: The Struggle for Existence in

Russian Evolutionary Thought, many Russian scientists recognised the

importance of Darwin’s work but also recognised the impact of British

society on its stress on individual competition. However, while expected

it cannot really be excused.

The problems with this can be seen when de Waal asks the question of

whether a “harder worker deserve to make more? This libertarian fairness

ideal is quintessentially American” (196–7) Yet genuine libertarians (as

opposed to the American propertarians) know that under capitalism those

who work hardest are usually the poorest and that those who “make more”

do so because other work for them. As such, genuine libertarians

acknowledge Proudhon’s analysis that property meant “another shall

perform the labour while [the proprietor] receives the product” and so

it was “the right to enjoy and dispose of another’s goods, – the fruit

of another’s labour.”

So while de Waal wishes to foster empathy, he does not ask whether this

requires changing our economic system at its base rather than trying to

change its outcomes. Yes, taxing the wealthy to reduce inequality is all

fine and well but surely the question should be asked why the rich are

richer (or, at least, why they have got so much richer over the last

30-odd years!). The unreflecting assumptions of capitalism can be seen

in de Waal but the scientific method of analysis is found in Proudhon

(indeed, the French anarchist calls in that work for a “scientific

socialism”!).

The quotes from Barak Obama and references to the current economic

crisis will also date the book (particularly as the ruling elite

unsurprisingly used the crisis caused by neo-liberalism to foster more

of that agenda rather than empathy). However, these are minor in

comparison to the wealth of information de Waal ably summarises on our

cooperative heritage.

And perhaps the notion life is competitive and nasty is simply because

of, not in spite of any lack of, our cooperative nature. After all,

newspapers report on events outside the norm – thus you get records of

fights, not the far more cooperative activity that marks everyday life.

Similarly with studies of animals, with the hours of cooperative living

being the backdrop to the “exciting” displays of alpha-male combat and,

as a result, unmentioned. In human terms, this can be seen from the

media which concentrates on the “interesting” stories rather than report

the mundane (but far more relevant) cooperative goings-on which dominant

everyday life. An extreme example can be seen in the run up to Franco’s

coup in Spain when a Conservative newspaper started to publish on its

front page all the murders, rapes and so on which were happening. There

was no actual increase in such crimes but public perception of them rose

– so promoting support for an authoritarian regime to solve this

apparent rise in lawlessness. Thus uncooperative is so noticeable

precisely because such acts are swamped by cooperative relations and so,

like islands in an ocean, stand out.

So de Waal’s work is of interest to anarchists and provide substantial

evidence to bolster our arguments on the importance of mutual aid as a

factor of evolution. It is refreshing to read a scientist proclaim that

we are born egalitarian revolutionaries. Yet while he is willing to

challenge the stereotypes and lazy-thinking as regards empathy and

cooperation within animals, de Waal shows no such scientific enquiry as

regards today’s social system. Still, this is a minor complaint about an

excellent book.

The Age of Empathy: Nature’s Lessons for a Kinder Society

Frans de Waal

Harmony Books

New York

2009