💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › petr-kropotkin-anarchist-morality.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:21:10. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchist Morality
Author: Pëtr Kropotkin
Date: 1897
Language: en
Topics: classical, ethics
Source: Retrieved on February 13th, 2009 from http://www.spunk.org/library/writers/kropotki/sp000066.txt

Pëtr Kropotkin

Anarchist Morality

Note For Anarchist Morality

This study of the origin and function of what we call “morality” was

written for pamphlet publication as a result of an amusing situation. An

anarchist who ran a store in England found that his comrades in the

movement regarded it as perfectly right to take his goods without paying

for them. “To each according to his need” seemed to them to justify

letting those who were best able foot the bills. Kropotkin was appealed

to, with the result that he not only condemned such doctrine, but was

moved to write the comrades this sermon.

Its conception of morality is based on the ideas set forth in Mutual Aid

and later developed in his Ethics. Here they are given special

application to “right and wrong” in the business of social living. The

job is done with fine feeling and with acute shafts at the shams of

current morality.

Kropotkin sees the source of all so-called moral ideas in primitive

superstitions. The real moral sense which guides our social behavior is

instinctive, based on the sympathy and unity inherent in group life.

Mutual aid is the condition of successful social living. The moral base

is therefore the good old golden rule “Do to others as you would have

others do to you in the same circumstances,” — which disposed of the

ethics of the shopkeeper’s anarchist customers.

This natural moral sense was perverted, Kropotkin says, by the

superstitions surrounding law, religion and authority, deliberately

cultivated by conquerors, exploiters and priests for their own benefit.

Morality has therefore become the instrument of ruling classes to

protect their privileges.

He defends the morality of killing for the benefit of mankind — as in

the assassination of tyrants — but never for self. Love and hate he

regards as greater social forces for controlling wrong-doing than

punishment, which he rejects as useless and evil. Account-book morality

— doing right only to receive a benefit — he scores roundly, urging

instead the satisfactions and joy of “sowing life around you” by giving

yourself to the uttermost to your fellow-men. Not of course to do them

good, in the spirit of philanthropy, but to be one with them, equal and

sharing.

I

The history of human thought recalls the swinging of a pendulum which

takes centuries to swing. After a long period of slumber comes a moment

of awakening. Then thought frees herself from the chains with which

those interested — rulers, lawyers, clerics — have carefully enwound

her.

She shatters the chains. She subjects to severe criticism all that has

been taught her, and lays bare the emptiness of the religious political,

legal, and social prejudices amid which she has vegetated. She starts

research in new paths, enriches our knowledge with new discoveries,

creates new sciences.

But the inveterate enemies of thought — the government, the lawgiver,

and the priest — soon recover from their defeat. By degrees they gather

together their scattered forces, and remodel their faith and their code

of laws to adapt them to the new needs. Then, profiting by the servility

of thought and of character, which they themselves have so effectually

cultivated; profiting, too, by the momentary disorganization of society,

taking advantage of the laziness of some, the greed of others, the best

hopes of many, they softly creep back to their work by first of all

taking possession of childhood through education.

A child’s spirit is weak. It is so easy to coerce it by fear. This they

do. They make the child timid, and then they talk to him of the torments

of hell. They conjure up before him the sufferings of the condemned, the

vengeance of an implacable god. The next minute they will be chattering

of the horrors of revolution, and using some excess of the

revolutionists to make the child “a friend of order.” The priest

accustoms the child to the idea of law, to make it obey better what he

calls the “divine law,” and the lawyer prates of divine law, that the

civil law may be the better obeyed.

And by that habit of submission, with which we are only too familiar,

the thought of the next generation retains this religious twist, which

is at once servile and authoritative, for authority and servility walk

ever hand in hand. During these slumbrous interludes, morals are rarely

discussed. Religious practices and judicial hypocrisy take their place.

People do not criticize, they let themselves be drawn by habit, or

indifference.They do not put themselves out for or against the

established morality. They do their best to make their actions appear to

accord with their professions.

All that was good, great, generous or independent in man, little by

little becomes moss-grown; rusts like a disused knife. A lie becomes a

virtue, a platitude a duty. To enrich oneself, to seize one’s

opportunities, to exhaust one’s intelligence, zeal and energy, no matter

how, become the watchwords of the comfortable classes, as well as of the

crowd of poor folk whose ideal is to appear bourgeois. Then the

degradation of the ruler and of the judge, of the clergy and of the more

or less comfortable classes becomes so revolting that the pendulum

begins to swing the other way.

Little by little, youth frees itself. It flings overboard its

prejudices, and it begins to criticize. Thought reawakens, at first

among the few; but insensibly the awakening reaches the majority. The

impulse is given, the revolution follows. And each time the question of

morality comes up again. “Why should I follow the principles of this

hypocritical morality?” asks the brain, released from religious terrors.

Why should any morality be obligatory?”

Then people try to account for the moral sentiment that they meet at

every turn without having explained it to themselves. And they will

never explain it so long as they believe it a privilege of human nature,

so long as they do not descend to animals, plants and rocks to

understand it. They seek the answer, however, in the science of the

hour.

And, if we may venture to say so, the more the basis of conventional

morality, or rather of the hypocrisy that fills its place is sapped, the

more the moral plane of society is raised. It is above all at such times

precisely when folks are criticizing and denying it, that moral

sentiment makes the most progress. It is then that it grows, that it is

raised and refined.

Years ago the youth of Russia were passionately agitated by this very

question. “I will be immoral!” a young nihilist came and said to his

friend, thus translating into action the thoughts that gave him no rest.

“I will be immoral, and why should I not? Because the Bible wills it?

But the Bible is only a collection of Babylonian and Hebrew traditions,

traditions collected and put together like the Homeric poems, or as is

being done still with Basque poems and Mongolian legends. Must I then go

back to the state of mind of the half-civilized peoples of the East?

“Must I be moral because Kant tells me of a categoric imperative, of a

mysterious command which comes to me from the depths of my own being and

bids me be moral? But why should this ‘categoric imperative’ exercise a

greater authority over my actions than that other imperative, which at

times may command me to get drunk. A word, nothing but a word, like the

words ‘Providence,’ or ‘Destiny,’ invented to conceal our ignorance.

“Or perhaps I am to be moral to oblige Bentham, who wants me to believe

that I shall be happier if I drown to save a passerby who has fallen

into the river than if I watched him drown?

“Or perhaps because such has been my education? Because my mother taught

me morality? Shall I then go and kneel down in a church, honor the

Queen, bow before the judge I know for a scoundrel, simply because our

mothers, our good ignorant mothers, have taught us such a pack of

nonsense? “I am prejudiced, — like everyone else. I will try to rid

myself of prejudice! Even though immorality be distasteful, I will yet

force myself to be immoral, as when I was a boy I forced myself to give

up fearing the dark, the churchyard, ghosts and dead people — all of

which I had been taught to fear.

“It will be immoral to snap a weapon abused by religion; I will do it,

were it only to protect against the hypocrisy imposed on us in the name

of a word to which the name morality has been given!”

Such was the way in which the youth of Russia reasoned when they broke

with old-world prejudices, and unfurled this banner of nihilist or

rather of anarchist philosophy: to bend the knee to no authority

whatsoever, however respected; to accept no principle so long as it is

unestablished by reason.

Need we add, that after pitching into the waste-paper basket the

teachings of their fathers, and burning all systems of morality, the

nihilist youth developed in their midst a nucleus of moral customs,

infinitely superior to anything that their fathers had practiced under

the control of the “Gospel,” of the “Conscience,” of the “Categoric

Imperative,” or of the “Recognized Advantage” of the utilitarian. But

before answering the question, “Why am I to be moral?” let us see if the

question is well put; let us analyze the motives of human action.

II

When our ancestors wished to account for what led men to act in one way

or another, they did so in a very simple fashion. Down to the present

day, certain catholic images may be seen that represent this

explanation. A man is going on his way, and without being in the least

aware of it, carries a devil on his left shoulder and an angel on his

right. The devil prompts him to do evil, the angel tries to keep him

back. And if the angel gets the best of it and the man remains virtuous,

three other angels catch him up and carry him to heaven. In this way

everything is explained wondrously well.

Old Russian nurses full of such lore will tell you never to put a child

to bed without unbuttoning the collar of its shirt. A warm spot at the

bottom of the neck should be left bare, where the guardian angel may

nestle. Otherwise the devil will worry the child even in its sleep.

These artless conceptions are passing away. But though the old words

disappear, the essential idea remains the same.

Well brought up folks no longer believe in the devil, but as their ideas

are no more rational than those of our nurses, they do but disguise

devil and angel under a pedantic wordiness honored with the name of

philosophy. They do not say “devil” nowadays, but “the flesh,” or “the

passions.” The“angel” is replaced by the words “conscience” or “soul,”

by “reflection of the thought of a divine creator” or “the Great

Architect,” as the Free-Masons say. But man’s action is still

represented as the result of a struggle between two hostile elements.

And a man is always considered virtuous just in the degree to which one

of these two elements — the soul or conscience — is victorious over the

other — the flesh or passions.

It is easy to understand the astonishment of our great-grandfathers when

the English philosophers, and later the Encyclopedists, began to affirm

in opposition to these primitive ideas that the devil and the angel had

nothing to do with human action, but that all acts of man, good or bad,

useful or baneful, arise from a single motive: the lust for pleasure.

The whole religious confraternity, and, above all, the numerous sects of

the pharisees shouted “immorality.” They covered the thinkers with

insult, they excommunicated them. And when later on in the course of the

century the same ideas were again taken up by Bentham, John Stuart Mill,

Tchernischevsky, and a host of others, and when these thinkers began to

affirm and prove that egoism, or the lust for pleasure, is the true

motive of all our actions, the maledictions redoubled. The books were

banned by a conspiracy of silence; the authors were treated as dunces.

And yet what can be more true than the assertion they made?

Here is a man who snatches its last mouthful of bread from a child.

Every one agrees in saying that he is a horrible egoist, that he is

guided solely by self-love.

But now here is another man, whom every one agrees to recognize as

virtuous. He shares his last bit of bread with the hungry, and strips

off his coat to clothe the naked. And the moralists, sticking to their

religious jargon, hasten to say that this man carries the love of his

neighbor to the point of self-abnegation, that he obeys a wholly

different passion from that of the egoist. And yet with a little

reflection we soon discover that however great the difference between

the two actions in their result for humanity, the motive has still been

the same. It is the quest of pleasure.

If the man who gives away his last shirt found no pleasure in doing so,

he would not do it. If he found pleasure in taking bread from a child,

he would do that but this is distasteful to him. He finds pleasure in

giving, and so he gives. If it were not inconvenient to cause confusion

by employing in a new sense words that have a recognized meaning, it

might be said that in both cases the men acted under the impulse of

their egoism. Some have actually said this, to give prominence to the

thought and precision to the idea by presenting it in a form that

strikes the imagination, and at the same time to destroy the myth which

asserts that these two acts have two different motives. They have the

same motive, the quest of pleasure, or the avoidance of pain, which

comes to the same thing.

Take for example the worst of scoundrels: a Thiers, who massacres

thirty-five thousand Parisians, or an assassin who butchers a whole

family in order that he may wallow in debauchery. They do it because for

the moment the desire of glory or of money gains in their minds the

upper hand of every other desire. Even pity and compassion are

extinguished for the moment by this other desire, this other thirst.

They act almost automatically to satisfy a craving of their nature. Or

again, putting aside the stronger passions, take the petty man who

deceives his friends, who lies at every step to get out of somebody the

price of a pot of beer, or from sheer love of brag, or from cunning.

Take the employer who cheats his workmen to buy jewels for his wife or

his mistress. Take any petty scoundrel you like. He again only obeys an

impulse. He seeks the satisfaction of a craving, or he seeks to escape

what would give him trouble.

We are almost ashamed to compare such petty scoundrels with one who

sacrifices his whole existence to free the oppressed, and like a Russian

nihilist mounts the scaffold. So vastly different for humanity are the

results of these two lives; so much do we feel ourselves drawn towards

the one and repelled by the other.

And yet were you to talk to such a martyr, to the woman who is about to

be hanged, even just as she nears the gallows, she would tell you that

she would not exchange either her life or her death for the life of the

petty scoundrel who lives on the money stolen from his work-people. In

her life, in the struggle against monstrous might, she finds her highest

joys. Everything else outside the struggle, all the little joys of the

bourgeois and his little troubles seem to her so contemptible, so

tiresome, so pitiable! “You do not live, you vegetate,” she would reply;

“I have lived.”

We are speaking of course of the deliberate, conscious acts of men,

reserving for the present what we have to say about that immense series

of unconscious, all but mechanical acts, which occupy so large a portion

of our life. In his deliberate, conscious acts man always seeks what

will give him pleasure.

One man gets drunk, and every day lowers himself to the condition of a

brute because he seeks in liquor the nervous excitement that he cannot

obtain from his own nervous system. Another does not get drunk; he takes

no liquor, even though he finds it pleasant, because he wants to keep

the freshness of his thoughts and the plentitude of his powers, that he

may be able to taste other pleasures which he prefers to drink. But how

does he act if not like the judge of good living who, after glancing at

the menu of an elaborate dinner rejects one dish that he likes very well

to eat his fill of another that he likes better.

When a woman deprives herself of her last piece of bread to give it to

the first comer, when she takes off her own scanty rags to cover another

woman who is cold, while she herself shivers on the deck of a vessel,

she does so because she would suffer infinitely more in seeing a hungry

man, or a woman starved with cold, than in shivering or feeling hungry

herself. She escapes a pain of which only those who have felt it know

the intensity.

When the Australian, quoted by Guyau, wasted away beneath the idea that

he has not yet revenged his kinsman’s death; when he grows thin and

pale, a prey to the consciousness of his cowardice, and does not return

to life till he has done the deed of vengeance, he performs this action,

a heroic one sometimes, to free himself of a feeling which possesses

him, to regain that inward peace which is the highest of pleasures.

When a troupe of monkeys has seen one of its members fall in consequence

of a hunter’s shot, and comes to besiege his tent and claim the body

despite the threatening gun; when at length the Elder of the band goes

right in, first threatens the hunter, then implores him, and finally by

his lamentations induces him to give up the corpse, which the groaning

troupe carry off into the forest, these monkeys obey a feeling of

compassion stronger than all considerations of personal security. This

feeling in them exceeds all others. Life itself loses its attraction for

them while they are not sure whether they can restore life to their

comrade or not. This feeling becomes so oppressive that the poor brutes

do everything to get rid of it.

When the ants rush by thousands into the flames of the burning ant-hill,

which that evil beast, man, has set on fire, and perish by hundreds to

rescue their larvae, they again obey a craving to save their offspring.

They risk everything for the sake of bringing away the larvae that they

have brought up with more care than many women bestow on their children.

To seek pleasure, to avoid pain, is the general line of action (some

would say law) of the organic world.

Without this quest of the agreeable, life itself would be impossible.

Organisms would disintegrate, life cease.

Thus whatever a man’s actions and line of conduct may be, he does what

he does in obedience to a craving of his nature. The most repulsive

actions, no less than actions which are indifferent or most attractive,

are all equally dictated by a need of the individual who performs them.

Let him act as he may, the individual acts as he does because he finds a

pleasure in it, or avoids, or thinks he avoids, a pain.

Here we have a well-established fact. Here we have the essence of what

has been called the egoistic theory.

Very well, are we any better off for having reached this general

conclusion?

Yes, certainly we are. We have conquered a truth and destroyed a

prejudice which lies at the root of all prejudices. All materialist

philosophy in its relation to man is implied in this conclusion. But

does it follow that all the actions of the individual are indifferent,

as some have hastened to conclude? This is what we have now to see.

III

We have seen that men’s actions (their deliberate and conscious actions,

for we will speak afterwards of unconscious habits) all have the same

origin. Those that are called virtuous and those that are designated as

vicious, great devotions and petty knaveries, acts that attract and acts

that repel, all spring from a common source. All are performed in answer

to some need of the individual’s nature. all have for their end the

quest of pleasure, the desire to avoid pain.

We have seen this in the last section, which is but a very succinct

summary of a mass of facts that might be brought forward in support of

this view. It is easy to understand how this explanation makes those

still imbued with religious principles cry out. It leaves no room for

the supernatural. It throws over the idea of an immortal soul. If man

only acts in obedience to the needs of his nature, if he is, so to say,

but a “conscious automaton,” what becomes of the immortal soul? What of

immortality, that last refuge of those who have known too few pleasures

and too many sufferings, and who dream of finding some compensation in

another world?

It is easy to understand how people who have grown up in prejudice and

with but little confidence in science, which has so often deceived them,

people who are led by feeling rather than thought, reject an explanation

which takes from them their last hope.

IV

Mosaic, Buddhist, Christian and Mussulman theologians have had recourse

to divine inspiration to distinguish between good and evil. They have

seen that man, be he savage or civilized, ignorant or learned, perverse

or kindly and honest, always knows if he is acting well or ill,

especially always knows if he is acting ill. And as they have found no

explanation of this general fact, they have put it down to divine

inspiration. Metaphysical philosophers, on their side, have told us of

conscience, of a mystic “imperative,” and, after all, have changed

nothing but the phrases.

But neither have known how to estimate the very simple and very striking

fact that animals living in societies are also able to distinguish

between good and evil, just as man does. Moreover, their conceptions of

good and evil are of the same nature as those of man. Among the best

developed representatives of each separate class, — fish, insects,

birds, mammals,— they are even identical.

Forel, that inimitable observer of ants, has shown by a mass of

observations and facts that when an ant who has her crop well filled

with honey meets other ants with empty stomachs, the latter immediately

ask her for food. And amongst these little insects it is the duty of the

satisfied ant to disgorge the honey that her hungry friends may also be

satisfied. Ask the ants if it would be right to refuse food to other

ants of the same anthill when one has had oneUs share. They will answer,

by actions impossible to mistake, that it would be extremely wrong. So

selfish an ant would be more harshly treated than enemies of another

species. If such a thing happens during a battle between two different

species, the ants would stop fighting to fall upon their selfish

comrade. This fact has been proved by experiments which exclude all

doubt.

Or again, ask the sparrows living in your garden if it is right not to

give notice to all the little society when some crumbs are thrown out,

so that all may come and share in the meal. Ask them if that hedge

sparrow has done right in stealing from his neighbor’s nest those straws

he had picked up, straws which the thief was too lazy to go and collect

himself. The sparrows will answer that he is very wrong, by flying at

the robber and pecking him.

Or ask the marmots if it is right for one to refuse access to his

underground storehouse to other marmots of the same colony. they will

answer that it is very wrong, by quarrelling in all sorts of ways with

the miser.

Finally, ask primitive man if it is right to take food in the tent of a

member of the tribe during his absence. He will answer that, if the man

could get his food for himself, it was very wrong. On the other hand, if

he was weary or in want, he ought to take food where he finds it; but in

such a case, he will do well to leave his cap or his knife, or even a

bit of knotted string, so that the absent hunter may know on his return

that a friend has been there, not a robber. Such a precaution will save

him the anxiety caused by the possible presence of a marauder near his

tent.

Thousands of similar facts might be quoted, whole books might be

written, to show how identical are the conceptions of good and evil

amongst men and the other animals. The ant, the bird, the marmot, the

savage have read neither Kant nor the fathers of the Church nor even

Moses. And yet all have the same idea of good and evil. And if you

reflect for a moment on what lies at the bottom of this idea, you will

see directly that what is considered good among ants, marmots, and

Christian or atheist moralists is that which is useful for the

preservation of the race; and that which is considered evil is that

which is hurtful for race preservation. Not for the individual, as

Bentham and Mill put it, but fair and good for the whole race.

The idea of good and evil has thus nothing to do with religion or a

mystic conscience. It is a natural need of animal races. And when

founders of religions, philosophers, and moralists tell us of divine or

metaphysical entities, they are only recasting what each ant, each

sparrow practices in its little society.

Is this useful to society? Then it is good. Is this hurtful? Then it is

bad.

This idea may be extremely restricted among inferior animals, it may be

enlarged among the more advanced animals; but its essence always remains

the same.

Among ants it does not extend beyond the anthill. All sociable customs,

all rules of good behavior are applicable only to the individuals in

that one anthill, not to any others. One anthill will not consider

another as belonging to the same family, unless under some exceptional

circumstances, such as a common distress falling upon both. In the same

way the sparrows in the Luxembourg Gardens in Paris, though they will

mutually aid one another in a striking manner, will fight to the death

with another sparrow from the Monge Square who may dare to venture into

the Luxembourg. And the savage will look upon a savage of another tribe

as a person to whom the usages of his own tribe do not apply. It is even

allowable to sell to him, and to sell is always to rob the buyer more or

less; buyer or seller, one or other is always “sold.” A Tchoutche would

think it a crime to sell to the members of his tribe: to them he gives

without any reckoning. And civilized man, when at last he understands

the relations between himself Ind the simplest Papuan, close relations,

though imperceptible at the first glance, will extend his principles of

solidarity to the whole human race, and even to the animals. The idea

enlarges, but its foundation remains the same.

On the other hand, the conception of good or evil varies according to

the degree of intelligence or of knowledge acquired. There is nothing

unchangeable about it. Primitive man may have thought it very right —

that is, useful to the race — to eat his aged parents when they became a

charge upon the community — a very heavy charge in the main. He may have

also thought it useful to the community to kill his new-born children,

and only keep two or three in each family, so that the mother could

suckle them until they were three years old and lavish more of her

tenderness upon them.

In our days ideas have changed, but the means of subsistence are no

longer what they were in the Stone Age. Civilized man is not in the

position of the savage family who have to choose between two evils:

either to eat the aged parents or else all to get insufficient

nourishment and soon find themselves unable to feed both the aged

parents and the young children. We must transport ourselves into those

ages, which we can scarcely call up in our mind, before we can

understand that in the circumstances then existing, half-savage man may

have reasoned rightly enough.

Ways of thinking may change. The estimate of what is useful or hurtful

to the race changes, but the foundation remains the same. And if we

wished to sum up the whole philosophy of the animal kingdom in a single

phrase, we should see that ants, birds, marmots, and men are agreed on

one point.

The morality which emerges from the observation of the whole animal

kingdom may be summed up in the words: “Do to others what you would have

them do to you in the same circumstances”.

And it adds: “Take note that this is merely a piece of advice; but this

advice is the fruit of the long experience of animals in society. And

among the great mass of social animals, man included, it has become

habitual to act on this principle. Indeed without this no society could

exist, no race could have vanquished the natural obstacles against which

it must struggle.”

Is it really this very simple principle which emerges from the

observation of social animals and human societies? Is it applicable? And

how does this principle pass into a habit and continually develop? This

is what we are now going to see.

V

The idea of good and evil exists within humanity itself. Man, whatever

degree of intellectual development he may have attained, however his

ideas may be obscured by prejudices and personal interest in general,

considers as good that which is useful to the society wherein he lives,

and as evil that which is hurtful to it.

But whence comes this conception, often so vague that it can scarcely be

distinguished from a feeling? There are millions and millions of human

beings who have never reflected about the human race. They know for the

most part only the clan or family, rarely the nation, still more rarely

mankind. How can it be that they should consider what is useful for the

human race as good, or even attain a feeling of solidarity with their

clan, in spite of all their narrow, selfish interests?

This fact has greatly occupied thinkers at all times, and it continues

to occupy them still. We are going in our turn to give our view of the

matter. But let us remark in passing that though the explanations of the

fact may vary, the fact itself remains none the less incontestable. And

should our explanation not be the true one, or should it be incomplete,

the fact with its consequences to humanity will still remain. We may not

be able fully to explain the origin of the planets revolving round the

sun, but the planets revolve none the less, and one of them carries us

with it in space.

We have already spoken of the religious explanation. If man

distinguishes between good and evil, say theologians, it is God who has

inspired him with this idea. Useful or hurtful is not for him to

inquire; he must merely obey the fiat of his creator. We will not stop

at this explanation, fruit of the ignorance and terrors of the savage.

We pass on.

Others have tried to explain the fact by law. It must have been law that

developed in man the sense of just and unjust, right and wrong. Our

readers may judge of this explanation for themselves. They know that law

has merely utilized the social feelings of man, to slip in, among the

moral precepts he accepts, various mandates useful to an exploiting

minority, to which his nature refuses obedience. Law has perverted the

feeling of justice instead of developing it. Again let us pass on.

Neither let us pause at the explanation of the Utilitarians. They will

have it that man acts morally from self-interest, and they forget his

feelings of solidarity with the whole race, which exist, whatever be

their origin. There is some truth in the Utilitarian explanation. But it

is not the whole truth. Therefore, let us go further.

It is again to the thinkers of the eighteenth century that we are

indebted for having guessed, in part at all events, the origin of the

moral sentiment.

In a fine work, The Theory of Moral Sentiment, left to slumber in

silence by religious prejudice, and indeed but little known even among

anti-religious thinkers, Adam Smith has laid his finger on the true

origin of the moral sentiment. He does not seek it in mystic religious

feelings; he finds it simply in the feeling of sympathy.

You see a man beat a child. You know that the beaten child suffers. Your

imagination causes you yourself to suffer the pain inflicted upon the

child; or perhaps its tears, its little suffering face tell you. And if

you are not a coward, you rush at the brute who is beating it and rescue

it from him.

This example by itself explains almost all the moral sentiments. The

more powerful your imagination, the better you can picture to yourself

what any being feels when it is made to suffer, and the more intense and

delicate will your moral sense be. The more you are drawn to put

yourself in the place of the other person, the more you feel the pain

inflicted upon him, the insult offered him, the injustice of which he is

a victim, the more will you be urged to act so that you may prevent the

pain, insult, or injustice. And the more you are accustomed by

circumstances, by those surrounding you, or by the intensity of your own

thought and your own imagination, to act as your thought and imagination

urge, the more will the moral sentiment grow in you, the more will it

become habitual.

This is what Adam Smith develops with a wealth of examples. He was young

when he wrote this book which is far superior to the work of his old age

upon political economy. Free from religious prejudice, he sought the

explanation of morality in a physical fact of human nature, and this is

why official and non-official theological prejudice has put the treatise

on the Black List for a century.

Adam Smith’s only mistake was not to have understood that this same

feeling of sympathy in its habitual stage exists among animals as well

as among men.

The feeling of solidarity is the leading characteristic of all animals

living in society. The eagle devours the sparrow, the wolf devours the

marmot. But the eagles and the wolves respectively aid each other in

hunting, the sparrow and the marmot unite among themselves against the

beasts and birds of prey so effectually that only the very clumsy ones

are caught. In all animal societies solidarity is a natural law of far

greater importance than that struggle for existence, the virtue of which

is sung by the ruling classes in every strain that may best serve to

stultify us.

When we study the animal world and try to explain to ourselves that

struggle for existence maintained by each living being against adverse

circumstances and against its enemies, we realize that the more the

principles of solidarity and equality are developed in an animal society

and have become habitual to it, the more chance has it of surviving and

coming triumphantly out of the struggle against hardships and foes. The

more thoroughly each member of the society feels his solidarity with

each other member of the society, the more completely are developed in

all of them those two qualities which are the main factors of all

progress: courage on the one hand, md on the other, free individual

initiative. And on the contrary, the more any animal society or little

group of animals loses this feeling of solidarity — which may chance as

the result of exceptional scarcity or else of exceptional plenty — the

more do the two other factors of progress courage and individual

initiative, diminish. In the end they disappear, and the society falls

into decay and sinks before its foes. Without mutual confidence no

struggle is possible; there is no courage, no initiative, no solidarity—

and no victory! Defeat is certain.

We can prove with a wealth of examples how in the animal and human

worlds the law of mutual aid is the law of progress, and how mutual aid

with the courage and individual initiative which follow from it secures

victory to the species most capable of practicing it. Now let us imagine

this feeling of solidarity acting during the millions of ages which have

succeeded one another since the first beginnings of animal life appeared

upon the globe. Let us imagine how this feeling little by little became

a habit, and was transmitted by heredity from the simplest microscopic

organism to its descendants — insects, birds, reptiles, mammals, man —

and we shall comprehend the origin of the moral sentiment, which is a

necessity to the animal like food or the organ for digesting it.

Without going further back and speaking of complex animals springing

from colonies of extremely simple little beings, here is the origin of

the moral sentiment. We have been obliged to be extremely brief in order

to compress this great question within the limits of a few pages, but

enough has already been said to show that there is nothing mysterious or

sentimental about it. Without this solidarity of the individual with the

species, the animal kingdom would never have developed or reached its

present perfection. The most advanced being upon the earth would still

be one of those tiny specks swimming in the water and scarcely

perceptible under a microscope. Would even this exist? For are not the

earliest aggregations of cellules themselves an instance of association

in the struggle?

VI

Thus by an unprejudiced observation of the animal kingdom, we reach the

conclusion that wherever society exists at all, this principle may be

found: Treat others as you would like them to treat you under similar

circumstances.

And when we study closely the evolution of the animal world, we discover

that the aforesaid principle, translated by the one word Solidarity, has

played an infinitely larger part in the development of the animal

kingdom than all the adaptations that have resulted from a struggle

between individuals to acquire personal advantages.

It is evident that in human societies a still greater degree of

solidarity is to be met with. Even the societies of monkeys highest in

the animal scale offer a striking example of practical solidarity, and

man has taken a step further in the same direction. This and this alone

has enabled him to preserve his puny race amid the obstacles cast by

nature in his way, and to develop his intelligence.

A careful observation of those primitive societies still remaining at

the level of the Stone Age shows to what a great extent the members of

the same community practice solidarity among themselves.

This is the reason why practical solidarity never ceases; not even

during the worst periods of history. Even when temporary circumstances

of domination, servitude, exploitation cause the principle to be

disowned, it still lives deep in the thoughts of the many, ready to

bring about a strong recoil against evil institutions, a revolution. If

it were otherwise society would perish. For the vast majority of animals

and men this feeling remains, and must remain an acquired habit, a

principle always present to the mind even when it is continually ignored

in action.

It is the whole evolution of the animal kingdom speaking in us. And this

evolution has lasted long, very long. It counts by hundreds of millions

of years.

Even if we wished to get rid of it we could not. It would be easier for

a man to accustom himself to walk on fours than to get rid of the moral

sentiment. It is anterior in — animal evolution to the upright posture

of man.

The moral sense is a natural faculty in us like the sense of smell or of

touch.

As for law and religion, which also have preached this principle, they

have simply filched it to cloak their own wares, their injunctions for

the benefit of the conqueror, the exploiter, the priest. Without this

principle of solidarity, the justice of which is so generally

recognized, how could they have laid hold on men’s minds? Each of them

covered themselves with it as with a garment; like authority which made

good its position by posing as the protector of the weak against the

strong. By flinging overboard law, religion and authority, mankind can

regain possession of the moral principle which has been taken from them.

Regain that they may criticize it, and purge it from the adulterations

wherewith priest, judge and ruler have poisoned it and are poisoning it

yet.

Besides this principle of treating others as one wishes to be treated

oneself, what is it but the very same principle as equality, the

fundamental principle of anarchism? And how can any one manage to

believe himself an anarchist unless he practices it?

We do not wish to be ruled. And by this very fact, do we not declare

that we ourselves wish to rule nobody? We do not wish to be deceived, we

wish always to be told nothing but the truth. And by this very fact, do

we not declare that we ourselves do not wish to deceive anybody, that we

promise to always tell the truth, nothing but the truth, the whole

truth? We do not wish to have the fruits of our labor stolen from us.

And by that very fact, do we not declare that we respect the fruits of

others’ labor?

By what right indeed can we demand that we should be treated in one

fashion, reserving it to ourselves to treat others in a fashion entirely

different? Our sense of equality revolts at such an idea.

Equality in mutual relations with the solidarity arising from it, this

is the most powerful weapon of the animal world in the struggle for

existence. And equality is equity. By proclaiming ourselves anarchists,

we proclaim beforehand that we disavow any way of treating others in

which we should not like them to treat us; that we will no longer

tolerate the inequality that has allowed some among us to use their

strength, their cunning or their ability after a fashion in which it

would annoy us to have such qualities used against ourselves. Equality

in all things, the synonym of equity, this is anarchism in very deed. It

is not only against the abstract trinity of law, religion, and authority

that we declare war. By becoming anarchists we declare war against all

this wave of deceit, cunning, exploitation, depravity, vice — in a word,

inequality — which they have poured into all our hearts. We declare war

against their way of acting, against their way of thinking. The

governed, the deceived, the exploited, the prostitute, wound above all

else our sense of equality. It is in the name of equality that we are

determined to have no more prostituted, exploited, deceived and governed

men and women.

Perhaps it may be said — it has been said sometimes “But if you think

that you must always treat others as you would be treated yourself, what

right have you to use force under any circumstances whatever? What right

have you to level a cannon at any barbarous or civilized invaders of

your country? What right have you to dispossess the exploiter? What

right to kill not only a tyrant but a mere viper?”

What right? What do you mean by that singular word, borrowed from the

law? Do you wish to know if I shall feel conscious of having acted well

in doing this? If those I esteem will think I have done well? Is this

what you ask? If so the answer is simple.

Yes, certainly! Because we ourselves should ask to be killed like

venomous beasts if we went to invade Burmese or Zulus who have done us

no harm. We should say to our son or our friend: “Kill me, if I ever

take part in the invasion!”

Yes, certainly! Because we ourselves should ask to be dispossessed, if

giving the lie to our principles, we seized upon an inheritance, did it

fall from on high, to use it for the exploitation of others.

Yes, certainly! Because any man with a heart asks beforehand that he may

be slain if ever he becomes venomous; that a dagger may be plunged into

his heart if ever he should take the place of a dethroned tyrant.

Ninety-nine men out of a hundred who have a wife and children would try

to commit suicide for fear they should do harm to those they love, if

they felt themselves going mad. Whenever a good-hearted man feels

himself becoming dangerous to those he loves, he wishes to die before he

is so.

Perovskaya and her comrades killed the Russian Czar. And all mankind,

despite the repugnance to the spilling of blood, despite the sympathy

for one who had allowed the serfs to be liberated, recognized their

right to do as they did. Why? Not because the act was generally

recognized as useful; two out of three still doubt if it were so. But

because it was felt that not for all the gold in the world would

Perovskaya and her comrades have consented to become tyrants themselves.

Even those who know nothing of the drama are certain that it was no

youthful bravado, no palace conspiracy, no attempt to gain power. It was

hatred of tyranny, even to the scorn of self, even to the death.

“These men and women,” it was said, “had conquered the right to kill”;

as it was said of Louise Michel, “She had the right to rob.” Or again,

“They have the right to steal,” in speaking of those terrorists who

lived on dry bread, and stole a million or two of the Kishineff

treasure.

Mankind has never refused the right to use force on those who have

conquered that right, be it exercised upon the barricades or in the

shadow of a cross-way. But if such an act is to produce a deep

impression upon men’s minds, the right must be conquered. Without this,

such an act whether useful or not will remain merely a brutal fact, of

no importance in the progress of ideas. People will see in it nothing

but a displacement of force, simply the substitution of one exploiter

for another.

VII

We have hitherto been speaking of the conscious, deliberate actions of

man, those performed intentionally. But side by side with our conscious

life we have an unconscious life which is very much wider. Yet we have

only to notice how we dress in the morning, trying to fasten a button

that we know we lost last night, or stretching out our hand to take

something that we ourselves have moved away, to obtain an idea of this

unconscious life and realize the enormous part it plays in our

existence.

It makes up three-fourths of our relations with others. Our ways of

speaking, smiling, frowning, getting heated or keeping cool in a

discussion, are unintentional, the result of habits, inherited from our

human or pre-human ancestors (only notice the likeness in expression

between an angry man and an angry beast), or else consciously or

unconsciously acquired.

Our manner of acting towards others thus tends to become habitual. To

treat others as he would wish to be treated himself becomes with man and

all sociable animals, simply a habit. So much so that a person does not

generally even ask himself how he must act under such and such

circumstances. It is only when the circumstances are exceptional, in

some complex case or under the impulse of strong passion that he

hesitates, and a struggle takes place between the various portions of

his brain — for the brain is a very complex organ, the various portions

of which act to a certain degree independently. When this happens, the

man substitutes himself in imagination for the person opposed to him; he

asks himself if he would like to be treated in such a way, and the

better he has identified himself with the person whose dignity or

interests he has been on the point of injuring, the more moral will his

decision be. Or maybe a friend steps in and says to him: “Fancy yourself

in his place; should you have suffered from being treated by him as he

has been treated by you? And this is enough.

Thus we only appeal to the principle of equality in moments of

hesitation, and in ninety-nine cases out of a hundred act morally from

habit. It must have been obvious that in all we have hitherto said, we

have not attempted to enjoin anything,we have only set forth the manner

in which things happen in the animal world and amongst mankind.

Formerly the church threatened men with hell to moralize them, and she

succeeded in demoralizing them instead. The judge threatens with

imprisonment, flogging, the gallows, in the name of those social

principles he has filched from society; and he demoralizes them. And yet

the very idea that the judge may disappear from the earth at the same

time as the priest causes authoritarians of every shade to cry out about

peril to society.

But we are not afraid to forego judges and their sentences. We forego

sanctions of all kinds, even obligations to morality. We are not afraid

to say: “Do what you will; act as you will”; because we are persuaded

that the great majority of mankind, in proportion to their degree of

enlightenment and the completeness with which they free themselves from

existing fetters will behave and act always in a direction useful to

society just as we are persuaded beforehand that a child will one day

walk on its two feet and not on all fours simply because it is born of

parents belonging to the genus Homo.

All we can do is to give advice. And again while giving it we add: “This

advice will be valueless if your own experience and observation do not

lead you to recognize that it is worth following.” When we see a youth

stooping and so contracting his chest and lungs we advise him to

straighten himself, hold up his head and open his chest. We advise him

to fill his lungs and take long breaths, because this will be his best

safeguard against consumption. But at the same time we teach him

physiology that he may understand the functions of his lungs, and

himself choose the posture he knows to be the best.

And this is all we can do in the case of morals. And this is all we can

do in the case of morals. We have only a right to give advice, to which

we add: “Follow it if it seems good to you.”

But while leaving to each the right to act as he thinks best; while

utterly denying the right of society to punish one in any way for any

anti-social act he may have committed, we do not forego our own capacity

to love what seems to us good and to hate what seems to us bad. Love and

hate; for only those who know how to hate know how to love. We keep this

capacity; and as this alone serves to maintain and develop the moral

sentiments in every animal society, so much the more will it be enough

for the human race.

We only ask one thing, to eliminate all that impedes the free

development of these two feelings in the present society, all that

perverts our judgment: — the State, the church, exploitation; judges,

priests, governments, exploiters.

Today when we see a Jack the Ripper murder one after another some of the

poorest and most miserable of women, our first feeling is one of hatred.

If we had met him the day when he murdered that woman who asked him to

pay her for her slum lodging, we should have put a bullet through his

head, without reflecting that the bullet might have been better bestowed

in the brain of the owner of that wretched den.

But when we recall to mind all the infamies which have brought him to

this; when we think of the darkness in which he prowls haunted by images

drawn from indecent books or thoughts suggested by stupid books, our

feeling is divided. And if some day we hear that Jack is in the hands of

some judge who has slain in cold blood a far greater number of men,

women and children than all the Jacks together; if we see him in the

hands of one of those deliberate maniacs then all our hatred of Jack the

Ripper will vanish. It will be transformed into hatred of a cowardly and

hypocritical society and its recognized representatives. All the

infamies of a Ripper disappear before that long series of infamies

committed in the name of law. It is these we hate.

At the present day our feelings are continually thus divided. We feel

that all of us are more or less, voluntarily or involuntarily, abettors

of this society. We do not dare to hate. Do we even dare to love? In a

society based on exploitation and servitude human nature is degraded.

But as servitude disappears we shall regain our rights. We shall feel

within ourselves strength to hate and to love, even in such complicated

cases as that we have just cited.

In our daily life we do already give free scope to our feelings of

sympathy or antipathy; we are doing so every moment. We all love moral

strength we all despise moral weakness and cowardice. Every moment our

words, looks, smiles express our joy in seeing actions useful to the

human race, those which we think good. Every moment our looks and words

show the repugnance we feel towards cowardice, deceit, intrigue, want of

moral courage. We betray our disgust, even when under the influence of a

worldly education we try to hide our contempt beneath those lying

appearances which will vanish as equal relations are established among

us.

This alone is enough to keep the conception of good and ill at a certain

level and to communicate it one to another.

It will be still more efficient when there is no longer judge or priest

in society, when moral principles have lost their obligatory character

and are considered merely as relations between equals.

Moreover, in proportion to the establishment of these relations, a

loftier moral conception will arise in society. It is this conception

which we are about to analyze.

VIII

Thus far our analysis has only set forth the simple principles of

equality. We have revolted and invited others to revolt against those

who assume the right to treat their fellows otherwise than they would be

treated themselves; against those who, not themselves wishing to be

deceived, exploited, prostituted or ill-used, yet behave thus to others.

Lying, and brutality are repulsive, we have said, not because they are

disapproved by codes of morality, but because such conduct revolts the

sense of equality in everyone to whom equality is not an empty word. And

above all does it revolt him who is a true anarchist in his way of

thinking and acting.

If nothing but this simple, natural, obvious principle were generally

applied in life, a very lofty morality would be the result; a morality

comprising all that moralists have taught.

The principle of equality sums up the teachings of moralists. But it

also contains something more. This something more is respect for the

individual. By proclaiming our morality of equality, or anarchism, we

refuse to assume a right which moralists have always taken upon

themselves to claim, that of mutilating the individual in the name of

some ideal. We do not recognize this right at all, for ourselves or

anyone else.

We recognize the full and complete liberty of the individual; we desire

for him plentitude of existence, the free development of all his

faculties. We wish to impose nothing upon him; thus returning to the

principle which Fourier placed in opposition to religious morality when

he said:

“Leave men absolutely free. Do not mutilate them as religions have done

enough and to spare. Do not fear even their passions. In a free society

these are not dangerous.”

Provided that you yourself do not abdicate your freedom, provided that

you yourself do not allow others to enslave you; and provided that to

the violent and anti-social passions of this or that person you oppose

your equally vigorous social passions, you have nothing to fear from

liberty.

We renounce the idea of mutilating the individual in the name of any

ideal whatsoever. All we reserve to ourselves is the frank expression of

our sympathies and antipathies towards what seems to us good or bad. A

man deceives his friends. It is his bent, his character to do so. Very

well, it is our character, our bent to despise liars. And as this is our

character, let us be frank. Do not let us rush and press him to our

bosom or cordially shake hands with him, as is sometimes done today. Let

us vigorously oppose our active passion to his.

This is all we have the right to do, this is all the duty we have to

perform to keep up the principle of equality in society. It is the

principle of equality in practice. But what of the murderer, the man who

debauches children? The murderer who kills from sheer thirst for blood

is excessively rare. He is a madman to be cured or avoided. As for the

debauchee, let us first of all look to it that society does not pervert

our children’s feelings, then we shall have little to fear from rakes.

All this it must be understood is not completely applicable until the

great sources of moral depravity — capitalism, religion, justice,

government — shall have ceased to exist. But the greater part of it may

be put in practice from this day forth. It is in practice already.

And yet if societies knew only this principle of equality; if each man

practiced merely the equity of a trader, taking care all day long not to

give others anything more than he was receiving from them, society would

die of it. The very principle of equality itself would disappear from

our relations. For, if it is to be maintained, something grander, more

lovely, more vigorous than mere equity must perpetually find a place in

life.

And this greater than justice is here.

Until now humanity has never been without large natures overflowing with

tenderness, with intelligence, with goodwill, and using their feeling,

their intellect, their active force in the service of the human race

without asking anything in return.

This fertility of mind, of feeling or of goodwill takes all possible

forms. It is in the passionate seeker after truth, who renounces all

other pleasures to throw his energy into the search for what he believes

true and right contrary to the affirmations of the ignoramuses around

him. It is in the inventor who lives from day to day forgetting even his

food, scarcely touching the bread with which perhaps some woman devoted

to him feeds him like a child, while he follows out the intention he

thinks destined to change the face of the world. It is in the ardent

revolutionist to whom the joys of art, of science, even of family life,

seem bitter, so long as they cannot be shared by all, and who works

despite misery and persecution for the regeneration of the world. It is

in the youth who, hearing of the atrocities of invasion, and taking

literally the heroic legends of patriotism, inscribes himself in a

volunteer corps and marches bravely through snow and hunger until he

falls beneath the bullets. It was in the Paris street arab, with his

quick intelligence and bright choice of aversions and sympathies, who

ran to the ramparts with his little brother, stood steady amid the rain

of shells, and died murmuring: “Long live the Commune!” It is in the man

who is revolted at the sight of a wrong without waiting to ask what will

be its result to himself, and when all backs are bent stands up to

unmask the iniquity and brand the exploiter, the petty despot of a

factory or great tyrant of an empire. Finally it is in all those

numberless acts of devotion less striking and therefore unknown and

almost always misprized, which may be continually observed, especially

among women, if we will take the trouble to open our eyes and notice

what lies at the very foundation of human life, and enables it to enfold

itself one way or another in spite of the exploitation and oppression it

undergoes.

Such men and women as these, some in obscurity, some within a larger

arena, creates the progress of mankind. And mankind is aware of it. This

is why it encompasses such lives with reverence, with myths. It adorns

them, makes them the subject of its stories, songs, romances. It adores

in them the courage, goodness, love and devotion which are lacking in

most of us. It transmits their memory to the young. It recalls even

those who have acted only in the narrow circle of home and friends, and

reveres their memory in family tradition.

Such men and women as these make true morality, the only morality worthy

the name. All the rest is merely equality in relations. Without their

courage, their devotion, humanity would remain besotted in the mire of

petty calculations. It is such men and women as these who prepare the

morality of the future, that which will come when our children have

ceased to reckon, and have grown up to the idea that the best use for

all energy, courage and love is to expend it where the need of such a

force is most strongly felt.

Such courage, such devotion has existed in every age. It is to be met

with among sociable animals. It is to be found among men, even during

the most degraded epochs.

And religions have always sought to appropriate it, to turn it into

current coin for their own benefit. In fact if religions are still

alive, it is because — ignorance apart— they have always appealed to

this very devotion and courage. And it is to this that revolutionists

appeal.

The moral sentiment of duty which each man has felt in his life, and

which it has been attempted to explain by every sort of mysticism, the

unconsciously anarchist Guyau says, “is nothing but a superabundance of

life, which demands to be exercised, to give itself; at the same time,

it is the consciousness of a power.”

All accumulated force creates a pressure upon the obstacles placed

before it. Power to act is duty to act. And moral “obligation” of which

so much has been said or written is reduced to the conception: the

condition of the maintenance of life is its expansion.

“The plant cannot prevent itself from flowering. Sometimes to flower

means to die. Never mind, the sap mounts the same,” concludes the young

anarchist philosopher.

It is the same with the human being when he is full of force and energy.

Force accumulates in him. He expands his life. He gives without

calculation, otherwise he could not live. If he must die like the flower

when it blooms, never mind. The sap rises, if sap there be.

Be strong. Overflow with emotional and intellectual energy, and you will

spread your intelligence, your love, your energy of action broadcast

among others! This is what all moral teaching comes to.

IX

That which mankind admires in a truly moral man is his energy, the

exuberance of life which urges him to give his intelligence, his

feeling, his action, asking nothing in return.

The strong thinker, the man overflowing with intellectual life,

naturally seeks to diffuse his ideas. There is no pleasure in thinking

unless the thought is communicated to others. It is only the mentally

poverty-stricken man, who after he has painfully hunted up some idea,

carefully hides it that later on he may label it with his own name. The

man of powerful intellect runs over with ideas; he scatters them by the

handful. He is wretched if he cannot share them with others, cannot

scatter them to the four winds, for in this is his life.

The same with regard to feeling. “We are not enough for ourselves: we

have more tears than our own sufferings claim, more capacity for joy

than our own existence can justify,” says Guyau, thus summing up the

whole question of morality in a few admirable lines, caught from nature.

The solitary being is wretched, restless, because he cannot share his

thoughts and feelings with others. When we feel some great pleasure, we

wish to let others know that we exist, we feel, we love, we live, we

struggle, we fight.

At the same time, we feel the need to exercise our will, our active

energy. To act, to work has become a need for the vast majority of

mankind. So much so that when absurd conditions divorce a man or woman

from useful work, they invent something to do, some futile and senseless

obligations whereby to open out a field for their active energy. They

invent a theory, a religion, a “social duty”— to persuade themselves

that they are doing something useful. When they dance, it is for a

charity. When they ruin themselves with expensive dresses, it is to keep

up the position of the aristocracy. When they do nothing, it is on

principle.

“We need to help our fellows, to lend a hand to the coach laboriously

dragged along by humanity; in any case, we buzz round it,” says Guyau.

This need of lending a hand is so great that it is found among all

sociable animals, however low in the scale. What is all the enormous

amount of activity spent uselessly in politics every day but an

expression of the need to lend a hand to the coach of humanity, or at

least to buzz around it .

Of course this “fecundity of will,” this thirst for action, when

accompanied by poverty of feeling and an intellect incapable of

creation, will produce nothing but a Napoleon I or a Bismarck, wiseacres

who try to force the world to progress backwards. While on the other

hand, mental fertility destitute of well developed sensibility will

bring forth such barren fruits as literary and scientific pedants who

only hinder the advance of knowledge. Finally, sensibility unguided by

large intelligence will produce such persons as the woman ready to

sacrifice everything for some brute of a man, upon whom she pours forth

all her love.

If life to be really fruitful, it must be so at once in intelligence, in

feeling and in will. This fertility in every direction is life; the only

thing worthy the name. For one moment of this life, those who have

obtained a glimpse of it give years of vegetative existence. Without

this overflowing life, a man is old before his time, an impotent being,

a plant that withers before it has ever flowered.

“Let us leave to latter-day corruption this life that is no life,” cries

youth, the true youth full of sap that longs to live and scatter life

around. Every time a society falls into decay, a thrust from such youth

as this shatters ancient economic, and political and moral forms to make

room for the upspringing of a new life. What matter if one or another

fall in the struggle! Still the sap rises. For youth to live is to

blossom whatever the consequences! It does not regret them.

But without speaking of the heroic periods of mankind, taking everyday

existence, is it life to live in disagreement with one’s ideal?

Now-a-days it is often said that men scoff at the ideal. And it is easy

to understand why. The word has so often been used to cheat the

simple-hearted that a reaction is inevitable and healthy. We too should

like to replace the word “ideal,” so often blotted and stained, by a new

word more in conformity with new ideas. But whatever the word, the fact

remains; every human being has his ideal. Bismarck had his — however

strange — government of blood and iron. Even every philistine has his

ideal, however low. But besides these, there is the human being who has

conceived a loftier ideal. The life of a beast cannot satisfy him.

Servility, lying, bad faith, intrigue, inequality in human relations

fill him with loathing. How can he in his turn become servile, be a

liar, and intriguer, lord it over others? He catches a glimpse of how

lovely life might be if better relations existed among men; he feels in

himself the power to succeed in establishing these better relations with

those he may meet on his way. He conceives what is called an ideal.

Whence comes this ideal? How is it fashioned by heredity on one side and

the impressions of life on the other? We know not. At most we could tell

the story of it more or less truly in our own biographies. But it is an

actual fact — variable, progressive, open to outside influences but

always living. It is a largely unconscious feeling of what would give

the greatest amount of vitality, of the joy of life.

Life is vigorous, fertile. rich in sensation only on condition of

answering to this feeling of the ideal. Act against this feeling, and

you feel your life bent back on itself. It is no longer at one, it loses

its vigor. Be untrue often to your ideal and you will end by paralyzing

your will, your active energy. Soon you will no longer regain the vigor,

the spontaneity of decision you formerly knew. You are a broken man.

Nothing mysterious in all this, once you look upon a human being as a

compound of nervous and cerebral centers acting independently. Waver

between the various feelings striving within you, and you will soon end

by breaking the harmony of the organism; you will be a sick person

without will. The intensity of your life will decrease. In vain will you

seek for compromises. Never more will you be the complete, strong,

vigorous being you were when your acts were in accordance with the ideal

conceptions of your brain.

There are epochs in which the moral conception changes entirely. A man

perceives that what he had considered moral is the deepest immorality.

In some instances it is a custom, a venerated tradition, that is

fundamentally immoral. In others we find a moral system framed in the

interests of a single class. We cast them overboard and raise the cry

“Down with morality!” It becomes a duty to act “immorally.”

Let us welcome such epochs for they are epochs of criticism. They are an

infallible sign that thought is working in society. A higher morality

has begun to be wrought out.

What this morality will be we have sought to formulate, taking as our

basis the study of man and animal.

We have seen the kind of morality which is even now shaping itself in

the ideas of the masses and of the thinkers. This morality will issue no

commands. It will refuse once and for all to model individuals according

to an abstract idea, as it will refuse to mutilate them by religion, law

or government. It will leave to the individual man full and perfect

liberty. It will be but a simple record of facts, a science. And this

science will say to man: “If you are not conscious of strength within

you, if your energies are only just sufficient to maintain a colorless,

monotonous life, without strong impressions, without deep joys, but also

without deep sorrows, well then, keep to the simple principles of a just

equality. In relations of equality you will find probably the maximum of

happiness possible to your feeble energies.

“But if you feel within you the strength of youth, if you wish to live,

if you wish to enjoy a perfect, full and overflowing life — that is,

know the highest pleasure which a living being can desire — be strong,

be great, be vigorous in all you do.

“Sow life around you. Take heed that if you deceive, lie, intrigue,

cheat, you thereby demean yourself. belittle yourself, confess your own

weakness beforehand, play the part of the slave of the harem who feels

himself the inferior of his master. Do this if it so pleases you, but

know that humanity will regard you as petty, contemptible and feeble,

and treat you as such. Having no evidence of your strength, it will act

towards you as one worthy of pity — and pity only. Do not blame humanity

if of your own accord you thus paralyze your energies. Be strong on the

other hand, and once you have seen unrighteousness and recognized it as

such — inequity in life, a lie in science, or suffering inflicted by

another — rise in revolt against the iniquity, the lie or the injustice.

“Struggle! To struggle is to live, and the fiercer the struggle the

intenser the life. Then you will have lived; and a few hours of such

life are worth years spent vegetating.

“Struggle so that all may live this rich, overflowing life. And be sure

that in this struggle you will find a joy greater than anything else can

give.”

This is all that the science of morality can tell you. Yours is the

choice.