💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › noam-chomsky-philosophers-and-public-philosophy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:58:50. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Philosophers and Public Philosophy.
Author: Noam Chomsky
Date: October 1968
Language: en
Topics: philosophy, ethics
Source: Retrieved on 8th June 2021 from https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/pdf/10.1086/291699
Notes: Published in Ethics, 79(1), 1–9. doi:10.1086/291699

Noam Chomsky

Philosophers and Public Philosophy.

This paper was read at the May, 1968, meetings of the Western Division

of the American Philosophical Association, in a symposium on this topic.

It was not originally intended for publication and therefore

incorporates some material from other writings that are now in press, in

a collection of essays entitled American Power and the New Mandarins

(New York: Pantheon Books, forthcoming).

When the paper was given, I had no specific model in mind of the work

that a philosopher might do, entirely within the framework of his

professional activities, on issues of the sort discussed here. One has

since appeared, namely, the very thoughtful essay by Ronald Dworkin on

“Civil Disobedience,” New York Review of Books, June 6, 1968.

---

FOR a number of reasons, I have found it extraordinarily difficult to

write about this topic. Perhaps it would help set the stage for a

discussion if I were to begin by mentioning some of these, even though

to do so, I will have to digress somewhat. The first problem is that I

am approaching the topic of the symposium from several premises which

themselves require argument and justification, although this is not the

place to elaborate them. My response to this topic must naturally be

based on a certain interpretation of the context in which questions of

public policy arise in the United States at this particular historical

moment, an interpretation which obviously cannot fail to be

controversial but which, within the framework of this symposium, I

cannot develop but can only formulate as a basis for my own discussion

of the topic. One premise is that the country faces a serious crisis and

that, because of our international role, our crisis is a world crisis as

well. Increasingly, the United States has become both the agent of

repression and-to use Howard Zinn’s phrase-“the white-gloved financier

of counter-revolution” throughout the world.[1] It is, by any objective

standard that I can imagine, the most aggressive country in the world,

the greatest threat to world peace, and without parallel as a source of

violence. In part, this violence is quite overt-I need say little about

our behavior in Vietnam. In part it is more subtle, the violence of the

status quo, the muted endless terror that we have imposed on vast areas

that are under our control or susceptible to our influence. Americans

are no more likely to accept such a judgment than were citizens of Japan

or Germany thirty years ago. However, an objective analysis seems to me

to permit no other evaluation. If we consider governments maintained in

power by force or overthrown through subversion or intrigue, or the

willingness to use the most awesome killing machine in history to

enforce our rule, or the means employed -saturation bombing, free-strike

zones, napalm and anti-personnel weapons, chemical warfarethere seems to

me no other conclusion: we are simply without a rival today as an agent

of international criminal violence.

There is, furthermore, a serious domestic crisis. Again, I need not

speak of the problems of racism and poverty, which are all too obvious.

What deserves some comment, however, is the callousness with which we

react to the evident in the growing opposition to the war in Vietnam. It

is no secret to anyone that the war is highly unpopular. It is also no

secret that the opposition to the war is based primarily on its cost. It

is a “pragmatic opposition,” motivated by calculations of cost and

utility. Many of those who are now most vociferous in expressing their

opposition to the war announce-in fact proclaimthat their opposition

would cease if our effort to control and organize Vietnamese society

were to prove successful. In that case, in the words of one such

spokesman, we would “all be saluting the wisdom and statesmanship of the

American government” (Arthur Schlesinger), even though, as he is the

first to point out, we are turning Vietnam into “a land of ruin and

wreck.”[2] This pragmatic opposition holds that we should “take our

stand” where the prospects for success are greater, that Vietnam is a

lost cause, and, for this reason, that our efforts there should be

modified or abandoned.

I do not want to debate the issue here but only to formulate a second

premise from which my discussion of the topic of this meeting will

begin: namely, that this quite pervasive pragmatic attitude toward the

war in Vietnam is a sign of moral degeneration so severe that talk of

using the normal channels of protest and dissent becomes meaningless and

that various forms of resistance provide the most significant course of

political action open to a concerned citizen.

Nothing supports this judgement more clearly, in my opinion, than the

recent change in the domestic political climate, dramatized by the

President’s announcement that he will not seek reelection. The political

commentators would have it that this event demonstrates that our

political system is, after all, healthy and functioning. Confronted with

the collapse of its war plans, an international economic crisis, and

threatening internal conflicts, the Administration has, in effect,

resignedto put it in parliamentary terms. This shows the health of our

democratic system. By such standards, an even more viable democratic

system was that of Fascist Japan thirty years ago, where more than a

dozen cabinets fell under not-dissimilar circumstances. What would have

demonstrated the health of our system would have been a change of policy

based on the realization that the policy was wrong, not that it was

failing-a realization that success in such a policy would have been a

tragedy. Nothing could be more remote from the American political

consciousness. It is held, rather, that it is the peculiar genius of the

American politics of accommodation to exclude moral considerations. How

natural, then, and how good that only pragmatic considerations of cost

and utility should determine whether we devastate another country, drive

its people from their villages, and carry out the experiments with

“material and human resources control” that so delight the “pacification

theorist.”

Three times in a generation American technology has laid waste a

helpless Asian country. This fact should be seared into the

consciousness of every American. A person who is not obsessed with this

realization is living in a world of fantasy. But we have not, as a

nation, learned to face this central fact of contemporary history. The

systematic destruction of a virtually defenseless Japan was carried out

with a sense of moral rectitude that was then, and remains today,

unchallenged-or nearly so. In fact, Secretary of War Henry Stimson said

at the time that there was something wrong with a nation that could

listen with such equanimity to the reports of the terror bombing of

Japanese cities. There were few voices to echo his doubts-which were

expressed before the two atom bombs, before the grand finale requested

by General Arnold and approved in Washington, a one thousand plane raid

on central Japan launched after the surrender had been announced but

before it had been officially received, a raid in which, according to

the report of victims, the bombs were interspersed with leaflets

announcing that Japan had surrendered. In Korea, the process was

repeated, with only a few qualms. It is the amazing resistance of the

Vietnamese that has forced us to ask: What have we done? There is little

doubt that, were this resistance to collapse, the domestic furor over

the war would disappear along with it.

Such facts as these-and endless details can all too easily be

suppliedraise the question whether what is needed in the United States

today is dissent or denazification. The question is a debatable one.

Reasonable men may differ. The fact that the question is even debatable

is a tragedy. I believe myself that what is needed is a kind of

denazification. There is, of course, no more powerful force that can

call us to account. The change will have to come from within. The fate

of millions of poor and oppressed people throughout the world will be

determined by our ability to carry out a profound “cultural revolution”

in the United States.

It might be argued that it is naive to discuss political and moral

consciousness as if they were other than a surface manifestation of

social institutions and the power structure and that, no matter what

individual Americans may think and feel and believe, the American system

will continue to try to dominate the earth by force. The inductive

argument for the latter thesis is substantial. The Vietnam war is hardly

without precedent in our history. It is, for example, distressingly like

our colonial venture in the Philippines seventy years ago. What is more,

it is remarkably similar to other episodes in the history of

colonialism, for example, the Japanese attempt to defend the

independence of Manchukuo from the “Communist threat” posed by Russia

and the “Chinese bandits.” Nevertheless, it is difficult to believe that

American society will collapse from its own “internal contradictions” if

it does not proceed to dominate the world. The belief that “the American

system could survive in America only if it became a world system”-to

quote President Truman in 1947-has, indeed, guided our international

policy for many years, as has the belief, enunciated by liberal and

conservative alike, that access to ever expanding markets and

opportunities for investment is necessary for the survival of the

American Way of Life. There is, no doubt, a large component of myth in

this ideology. In any event, the question is somewhat academic. Whether

we aim for reform or revolution, the early steps must be the same: an

attempt to modify political and moral consciousness and to construct

alternative institutional forms that reflect and support this

development. Personally, I believe that our present crisis is in some

measure, moral and intellectual rather than institutional and that

reason and resistance can go a certain way, perhaps a long way, toward

ameliorating it.

have not tried to justify but only to formulate-seem to me to provide

the framework within which an American should ask himself what is his

responsibility as a citizen. About this question there is a great deal

to be said, and still more to be done. It is not, however, the question

to which this session is addressed, and this is the central fact that

causes my difficulty, noted at the outset, in trying to discuss the

narrower topic of philosophers and public policy. At a time when we are

waging a war of indescribable savagery against Vietnam-in the interests

of the Vietnamese, of course, as the Japanese were merely trying to

create an earthly paradise in Manchukuo-at a time when we are preparing

for and in part already conducting other “limited wars” at home and

abroad, at a time when thousands of young men, many of them our

students, are facing jail or political exile because of their

conscientious refusal to be agents of criminal violence, at a time when

we are once again edging the world toward nuclear war, at such a time it

is difficult to restrict oneself to the narrower question: What is one’s

responsibility as a philosopher? Nevertheless, I will try to do so.

I think it is possible to construct a reasonable argument to the effect

that one has no particular responsibility, as a philosopher, to take a

stand on questions of public policy, whatever one’s duties may be as a

citizen. The argument might proceed as follows. To hold that

philosophers have some special responsibility in this regard suggests

either that they have some unique competence to deal with the problems

we face or that others-say biologists or mathematicians-are somehow more

free to put these problems aside. But neither conclusion is correct.

There is no specific competence that one attains through his

professional training as a philosopher to deal with the problems of

international or domestic repression, or, in general, with critique and

implementation of public policy. Similarly, it’ is absurd to claim that

biologists or mathematicians may freely dismiss these problems on the

grounds that others have the technical expertise and moral

responsibility to confront them. As a professional, one has only the

duty of doing his work with integrity. Integrity, both personal and

scholarly, demands that we face the questions that arise internally in

some particular domain of study, that are on the border of research, and

that promise to move the search for truth and understanding forward. It

would be a sacrifice of such integrity to allow external factors to

determine the course of research. This would represent a kind of

“subversion of scholarship.” The most meaningful contribution that an

individual can make toward a more decent society is to base his life’s

work on an authentic commitment to important values, such as those that

underlie serious scholarly or scientific work, in any field. But this

demands that, as a professional, he stick to his last.

I think this argument has a good deal of force. I do not doubt that

those who pursued their work at the Goethe Institute, in the shadow of

Dachau, justified themselves by such considerations as these. Two or

three years ago, I would have accepted this line of argument as correct,

and it still seems to be persuasive.

There is, of course, an apparent counterargument: namely, that in a time

of crisis one should abandon, or at least restrict, professional

concerns and activities that do not adapt themselves in a natural way

toward the resolution of this crisis. This argument is actually

consistent with the first; and it can, I think, be maintained that this

is all there is to the matter.

I think that for many professionals this may well be all that there is

to the matter. I do not, for example, see any way to make my work as a

linguist relevant, in any serious sense, to the problems of domestic or

international society. The only relevance is remote and indirect,

through the insight that such work might provide into the nature of

human intelligence. But to accept that connection as “relevance” would

be hypocrisy. The only solution I can see, in this case, is a

schizophrenic existence, which seems to me morally obligatory and not at

all impossible, in practice.

Philosophers, however, may be in a somewhat more fortunate position.

There is no profession that can claim with greater authenticity that its

concern is the intellectual culture of the society or that it possesses

the tools for the analysis of ideology and the critique of social

knowledge and its use. If it is correct to regard the American and world

crisis as in part a cultural one, then philosophical analysis may have a

definite contribution to make. Let me consider a few cases in point.

Our society stands in awe of “technical expertise” and gives great

prestige and considerable latitude of action to the person who lays

claim to it. In fact, it is widely maintained that we are becoming the

first “post-industrial society,” a society in which the dominant figure

will be not the entrepreneur but the technical expert or even the

scientist, those who create and apply the knowledge that is, for the

first time in history, the major motive force for social progress.

According to this view, the university and the research institution will

be the “creative eye,” the central institutions of this new society, and

the academic specialist will be the “new man” whose values will become

dominant and who will himself be at or near the center of power.

There are many who look forward to this prospect with great hope. I am

not one of them. It seems to me a prospect that is not appealing and

that has many dangers. For one thing, the assumption that the state can

be the source of effective social action is highly dubious. Furthermore,

what reason is there to believe that those whose claim to power is based

on knowledge and techniqueor at least the claim to knowledge and

technique-will be more humane and just in the exercise of power than

those whose claim is based on wealth or aristocratic privilege? On the

contrary, one might expect such a person to be arrogant, inflexible,

incapable of admitting or adjusting to failure, since failure undermines

his claim to power. To take just the most obvious instance, consider the

Vietnam war, which was in large measure designed by the new breed of

“action intellectuals” and which manifests all of these characteristics.

What is more, it is natural to expect that any group with access to

power will construct an ideology that justifies its dominance on grounds

of the general welfare. When it is the intelligentsia who aspire to

power, the danger is even greater than before, since they can capitalize

on the prestige of science and technology while, at the same time, now

drawn into the mechanism of control, they lose their role as social

critics. Perhaps the most important role of the intellectual since the

enlightenment has been that of unmasking ideology, exposing the

injustice and repression that exists in every society that we know, and

seeking the way to a new and higher form of social life that will extend

the possibilities for a free and creative life. We can confidently

expect this role to be abandoned as the intellectual becomes the

administrator of a new society.

These observations are hardly novel. I am simply paraphrasing a

classical anarchist critique, of which typical expressions are the

following:

Commenting on Marxian doctrine, Bakunin had this to say:

According to the theory of Mr. Marx, the people not only must not

destroy [the state] but must strengthen it and place it at the complete

disposal of their benefactors, guardians, and teachers-the leaders of

the Communist party, namely Mr. Marx and his friends, who will proceed

to liberate [mankind] in their own way. They will concentrate the reins

of government in a strong hand, because the ignorant people require an

exceedingly firm guardianship; they will establish a single state bank,

concentrating in its hands all commercial, industrial, agricultural and

even scientific production, and then divide the masses into two

armies-industrial and agricultural-under the direct command of the state

engineers, who will constitute a new privileged scientific-political

estate.[3]

Or compare the more general remarks by the anarchist historian Rudolf

Rocker:

Political rights do not originate in parliaments; they are rather forced

upon them from without. And even their enactment into law has for a long

time been no guarantee of their security. They do not exist because they

have been legally set down on a piece of paper, but only when they have

become the ingrown habit of a people, and when any attempt to impair

them will meet with the violent resistance of the populace. Where this

is not the case, there is no help in any parliamentary opposition or any

Platonic appeals to the constitution. One compels respect from others

when one knows how to defend one’s dignity as a human being. This is not

only true in private life; it has always been the same in political life

as well.[4]

History has shown the accuracy of this analysis, both with respect to

the role of an intellectual elite and with respect to the nature of

political rights, whoever may rule. I see little reason to expect the

future to show otherwise.

If it is true that the new, “post-industrial” society will be marked by

the access to power of an intellectual elite, basing its claim to power

on a presumably “value free” technology of social management, then the

importance of the social critic becomes more crucial than ever before.

This critic must be capable of analyzing the content of the claimed

“expertise,” its empirical justification, and its social use. These are

typical questions of philosophy. The same analytical approach that seeks

to explore the nature of scientific theories in general or the structure

of some particular domain of knowledge or to investigate the concept of

a human action can be turned to the study of the technology of control

and manipulation that goes under the name of “behavioral science” and

that serves as the basis for the ideology of the “new mandarins.”

Furthermore, this task will be of greater human significance, for the

foreseeable future, than the investigation of the foundations of physics

or the possibility of reducing mental states to brain states-questions

that I do not, incidentally, mean to disparage -I hope that is clear.

I think it would be important for the university to provide the

framework for critical work of this sort. The matter goes well beyond

politics in a narrow sense. There are inherent dangers in

professionalization that are not sufficiently recognized in university

structure. There is a tendency, as a field becomes truly

professionalized, for its problems to be determined less by

considerations of intrinsic interest and more by the availability of

certain tools that have been developed as the subject matures.

Philosophy is not free from this tendency, of course. In part, this is

of course not only unavoidable but even essential for scientific

progress. But it is important to find a way, in teaching even more than

in research, to place the work that is feasible and productive at a

certain moment against the background of the general concerns that make

some questions, but not others, worth pursuing. It is easy to give

examples to show how certain fields have been seriously distorted by a

failure to maintain this perspective. For example, I think it is

possible to show that certain simple and very useful experimental ideas

in the psychology of learning have for many psychologists taken on the

status of conditions that define the subject matter of learning theory,

much to the detriment of the field, in the long run. I think that in

most academic fields a graduate student would benefit greatly from the

experience, rarely offered in any academic program, of defending the

significance of the field of work in which he is engaged and facing the

challenge of a point of view and a critique that does not automatically

accept the premises and limitations of scope that are to be found in any

discipline. I am putting this too abstractly, but I think the point is

clear, and I think that it indicates a defect of much of university

education.

In the specific case of social and behavioral science in a

“post-industrial society” with the university as a central institution

of innovation and authority, the defect may become a disaster. To put it

succinctly, the university requires a conscience, free from the controls

that are implicit in any association with the organs of power, from any

role in the formation and implementation of public policy. I think that

any serious university should be thinking about how it might institute a

program of radical social inquiry that would examine the premises of

public policy and attempt a critical analysis of the prevailing

ideology. Ideally, such a program should, perhaps, not even have

separate faculty associated with it but should, rather, seek to involve

as wide a segment of the university community as possible in

far-reaching social criticism. A program of this sort would be a natural

and valuable outgrowth of the philosopher’s concern for conceptual

analysis.

Again, I would like to stress that the issue is not one of politics in a

narrow sense. I think that the applications of behavioral science in

education or therapy, to mention just two examples, are as much in need

of critical analysis as the applications to counterinsurgency. And the

assumptions and values that lie behind the poverty program or urban

renewal deserve the same serious analysis as those that lie behind the

manipulative diplomacy of the postwar era. A dozen other examples could

easily be cited. In the kind of liberal technocracy that we are likely

to evolve, repression may be somewhat more masked and the technique of

control, more “sophisticated.” A new coercive ideology, professing both

humane values and “the scientific ethic,” might easily become the

intellectual property of the technical intelligentsia, which is based in

the university but moves fairly freely to government and foundations.

The fragmentation and professionalization that accompanies the decline

of the “free-floating intellectual” who, we are told, is a relic from an

earlier stage of society, can itself contribute to new forms of social

control and intellectual impoverishment. This is not a necessary

development, but it is also not an unlikely one. And it is one that we

must find a way to resist, as much as we must find ways to resist other

less subtle forms of barbarism. It would be entirely within the

tradition of philosophy if it were to regard this task as its own.

More specific problems might be mentioned. Let me bring up just one. We

all know that thousands of young men may be found guilty of “civil

disobedience” for following the dictates of their conscience in the next

few months and may suffer severe penalties for their willingness to live

by the values that many of us profess. It would be a serious error to

regard this as merely a matter of enforcement of law. The substantive

content of the law is determined, to a significant extent, by the level

of intellectual culture and moral perception of the society is general.

If philosophers feel that these matters are part of their concern, then

they must contribute to shaping the principles and understanding that

determine what the interpretation of the law will be in concrete

instances. To mention simply the most obvious question: Why is it not

“civil disobedience” for the President to violate domestic and

international law by the use of force in Vietnam, while it is civil

disobedience for young men to refuse to serve as agents of criminal

acts? The answer to this question has little to do with the law, and

much to do with the distribution of force in our society. The courts are

not capable of deciding that it is illegal to send an American

expeditionary force to crush a rebellion in some foreign land, because

of the social consequences that would ensue from that decision. When a

powerful executive carries out criminal acts with impunity, the concept

“government of laws” erodes beyond recognition; and the entire framework

of law disintegrates. Those who would like to believe that their

commitment is to truth, not power, cannot remain silent in the face of

this travesty. It is too late to create a climate of opinion that will

enable the judiciary to function, thus saving men from imprisonment for

conscientious resistance to a demand that they be war criminals. It is

not too late to work for a reconstruction of values and for the creation

of a more healthy intellectual community to which these men can return

as welcome and honored members. Surely the university faces no more

urgent task, in the coming years, than to regenerate itself as a

community worthy of men who make this sacrifice out of a commitment to

the moral and intellectual values that the university pretends to honor.

And I think it requires no elaborate argument to show that -the faculty

of philosophy might well be at the forefront of this effort.

The temptation is overwhelming, in a discussion of this issue, to quote

Marx’s famous marginal comment on Feuerbach, that “the philosophers have

only interpreted the world differently; the point, however, is to change

it.” I will not try to resist the temptation; the task that faces the

responsible citizen is to work to change the world. But we should not

overlook the fact that the interpretation and analysis provided by the

philosopher, by the intellectual more generally, are essential

ingredients in any serious attempt to change the world. If student

radicalism often turns to an anti-intellectual direction, the fault in

part lies in the deficiencies of scholarship, of our intellectual

culture, of the disciplines-such as philosophy-and the institutions-such

as the university-that exist only to interpret and advance and defend

this culture. Senator Fulbright, in a recent and extremely important

speech on the Senate floor, stated that the universities have betrayed a

public trust by associating themselves with the government and the

corporate system in a military-industrial-academic complex. They have,

as he rightly said, largely abandoned the function that they should

serve in a free society and have forfeited their right to public

support, to a substantial degree, by this retreat-one might say, by this

treachery. Only a hypocrite can preach the virtues of non-violence to

the Vietnamese or to the black community in the United States, while

continuing to tolerate the incomparably greater violence to which they

are subjected by the society to which he belongs. Similarly, only a

hypocrite can condemn the antiintellectualism of student activists,

while tolerating the subversion of scholarship, the impoverishment of

intellect, let us be honest-the downright immorality of the academic

professions as they support American violence and repression by

contributing to weaponry and counterinsurgency, by permitting the social

sciences to develop as a technology of control and manipulation, or,

more subtly, by helping to create and uphold the system of values that

permits us to applaud the pragmatic and responsible attitude shown by

those who now oppose the war in Vietnam on grounds of tactics and cost

effectiveness. To restore the integrity of intellectual life and

cultural values is the most urgent, most crucial task that faces the

universities and the professions. Philosophers might take the lead in

this effort. If they do not, then they too will have betrayed a

responsibility that should be theirs.

[1] Vietnam: The Logic of Withdrawal (Boston: Beacon Press, 1967), p.

50.

[2] Arthur M. Schlesinger, Jr., The Bitter Heritage (Boston: Houghton

Mifflin, 1967), pp. 34, 47.

[3] “Statehood and Anarchy,” 1873; cited in P. Avrich, The Russian

Anarchists (Princeton, N.J., 1967), pp. 93–94.

[4] “Anarchism and Anarchosyndicalism,” in European Ideologies (New

York: Philosophical Library); reprinted in P. Eltzbacher (ed.),

Anarchism (London: Freedom Press, 1960), p. 257.