đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș hilton-bertalan-when-theories-meet.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:45:18. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: When Theories Meet Author: Hilton Bertalan Date: 2011 Language: en Topics: Post-Anarchism: A Reader, Emma Goldman, post-structuralist, post-anarchism, Friedrich Nietzsche, essentialism, gender, love, reform, prefigurative politics Source: Retrieved on 2 September from http://um-ok.co.nf/post.pdf Notes: from Post-Anarchism: A Reader, Pluto Press 2011
Naturally, life presents itself in different forms to different ages.
Between the age of eight and twelve I dreamed of becoming a Judith. I
longed to avenge the sufferings of my people, the Jews, to cut off the
head of their Holofernos. When I was fourteen I wanted to study
medicine, so as to be able to help my fellow-beings. When I was fifteen
I suffered from unrequited love, and I wanted to commit suicide in a
romantic way by drinking a lot of vinegar. I thought that would make me
look ethereal and interesting, very pale and poetic when in my grave,
but at sixteen I decided on a more exalted death. I wanted to dance
myself to death. (Goldman, 1933: 1)
The spaces in which subjectivities and perspectives are affirmed as
non-hegemonic, mobile, and constantly drifting are often associated with
post-structuralist thought. Yet this language resonates elsewhere. In
fact, it can be located in radical voices and texts often considered out
of reach to the theoretical abstractions of post-structuralist thought.
Perhaps most surprising is that it can be found in the
anarchistâfeminist Emma Goldman. Known best for her assiduous political
activity, unkillable energy, repeated arrests, remonstrative oratory
skills, sardonic wit, and status as the âmost dangerous woman in the
worldâ, another reading of Goldmanâs work reveals a dimension that is
often overlooked; that is, one that is connectable to the theoretical
and political efforts of several contemporary theorists. To be sure,
this initial and modest knotting of voices is only a beginning, an
interceding requisition for future analysis, or, put simply, a
punctuating of moments in Goldmanâs work worthy of closer examination.
Such work, I would argue, is necessary to avoiding a disavowal of
anarchist histories, and to understanding how the traces of certain
textual and political histories resonate with, and can work to inform,
contemporary conditions. If, in our contemporary condition, we are left
without a state of things to be reached or attained â if we have buried
pedantic, concretizing thoughts of revolution and subjectivity, and
instead found some measure of comfort in contingent, prefigurative,
productively failing and always labouring presuppositions â it is
important that in asking what it means to articulate futures and measure
efficacy under such conditions, we first glean the past for figures who
confronted similar dilemmas. I would argue that Goldman is such a
figure. In doing so I am suggesting that the manner in which many
contemporary activists and social movements conceptualize resistance and
organization is not entirely new. I am not attempting to graft the past
onto contemporary theoretical and political conditions, nor suggesting a
genealogical line between the two, but rather, locating resonances
between fields so as to support still relevant ethico-political
projects. What is most important about this task is a regenerative
reading of Goldman that draws out her commitment to ceaseless
epistemological and political change. This affinity echoes not only with
contemporary activists and social movements, but also, in particular for
my purposes here, the thought of Friedrich Nietzsche, Gloria AnzaldĂșa,
Judith Butler and Gilles Deleuze. Using these thinkers to facilitate a
remembrance of Goldman makes it possible to connect her work with that
of post-structuralist anarchism (and post-structuralist thought more
generally).
At the outset I should mention feeling some displeasure toward the
brevity with which Iâm forced speak of those who have written about
Goldman. Despite my sense of affinity for this diminutive group, I feel
it necessary to offer an accounting, albeit brief, of the ways Goldman
has been discussed. Considering the attention Goldman received during
and after her life, her emblematic mugshot, and her iconic status within
activist culture and anarchist historiography and scholarship, it may
appear puzzling to suggest that her work has not been read in the way I
am arguing it could. What is of interest to me here is how Goldman has
been read, and therefore, how it has come to be that certain elements of
her work have been given little consideration â how particular
dimensions have been overlooked or addressed with only passing, tepid
reference.
Collections, historiography and contemporary anarchist theory tend to
credit Goldman with introducing feminism to anarchism, and for her
tireless and diverse activism, yet fail to take her seriously as a
political thinker with an original voice. Anarchist anthologies (Graham,
2005), anarchist historiographies (Avrich, 1994), anarcha-feminist
collections (Dark Star Collective, 2002), and anarchist reference
websites (anarchyarchives.org) have all dedicated a great deal of
attention to Goldman. Despite this, however, they do not discuss
theoretical dimensions of her work, but rather, give a broad account of
her personal and political life. More recent theoretical discussions of
anarchist thought make no mention of Goldman (Day, 2005; Sheehan, 2003),
while George Woodcockâs important text, Anarchism: A History of
Libertarian Ideas and Movements (2004), and more contemporary texts from
Todd May (1994), Lewis Call (2002), Saul Newman (2001) and Murray
Bookchin (1995) make only passing remarks. Although usually credited
with providing a âfeminist dimensionâ (Marshall, 1993: 396) that
âcompletely changedâ (Woodcock, 2004: 399) anarchist thought, subsequent
suggestions that she was âmore of an activist than a thinkerâ (Marshall,
1993: 396) overlook the extent to which she contributed to anarchist
theory. Murray Bookchin (1995) similarly praised Goldman yet took her
work even less seriously. Bookchinâs suggestion that he âcan only
applaud Emma Goldmanâs demand that she does not want a revolution unless
she can dance to itâ (1995: 2) is followed by a complaint about
âNietzscheans like Emma Goldmanâ (8). Bookchinâs text Social Anarchism
or Lifestyle Anarchism: An Unbridgeable Chasm (1995) is dedicated to
describing a perceived divide between the âpostmodernist [...] flight
from all form of social activismâ typified by Michel Foucault and
Friedrich Nietzsche (âlifestyle anarchismâ), and a commitment to
âserious organizations, a radical politics, a committed social movement,
theoretical coherence, and programmatic relevanceâ (19) typified by
âclassical anarchistsâ such as Michael Bakunin and Peter Kropotkin
(âsocial anarchismâ). While it is easy to recognize Bookchinâs
preference, what is most interesting is that Goldman is the only figure
he places on both sides of the chasm. Although he associates Goldman
with the postmodernists who, he suggests, âdenigrate responsible social
commitmentâ (10), he commends her dedication to social change. Bookchin
never responds to this disjunctive tension or the implications it has
for his prescribed schism. Instead, he mentions Goldman only once more,
suggesting that she âwas by no means the ablest thinker in the
libertarian pantheonâ (13). Not only does this provide another example
of refusing to take Goldman seriously as a thinker, it also demonstrates
how she provided a committed political articulation alongside an
affinity for the ceaseless transgressions that Bookchin finds to be such
a troubling and apolitical dimension of postmodernist thought.
In his canonical The Political Philosophy of Poststructuralist Anarchism
(1994), Todd May also makes a quick, albeit important reference to
Goldman. In a seminal text dedicated to the intersections of anarchist
and post-structuralist thought, Goldman is mentioned only once. By using
the work of Bakunin, Kropotkin, and Pierre-Joseph Proudhon to discuss
anarchism, May is able to show the similarities between anarchism and
post-structuralism yet also sketch a demarcation between the
âessentialismâ of the former and âanti-essentialismâ (13) of the latter.
A third of the way through, however, May claims that Goldman is one
exception to the essentialism of anarchism. âWhile anarchists like Emma
Goldman resisted the naturalist path (in an echo of Nietzsche, who was
founding for poststructuralist thought)â, argues May, âthe fundamental
drift of anarchism has been toward the assumption of a human essenceâ
(64). Although I am not disputing the decision to focus on the
âfundamental driftâ of anarchism, I am suggesting that Mayâs valuable,
albeit brief, reading of Goldman inaugurated a new way of reading her
work. In his book Postmodern Anarchism (2002), Lewis Call also makes a
single positive reference to Goldman. According to Call, Goldman
âanticipatedâ the postmodern âtheory of simulation [and] denial of the
realâ (93). Similarly here, it is interesting that the anarchist who
âanticipatedâ a type of thought that Call connects to Nietzsche,
Deleuze, Foucault and Butler does not stimulate more interest or
enquiry. Further distinguishing between classical anarchism and
postmodern anarchism â for the purpose of demonstrating the radical
nature of Nietzscheâs theoretical project â Call argues that âprevious
concepts of subjectivity (and thus previous political theories) focused
on beingâ (50). Call then suggests that Nietzsche has âshifted our
attention to becomingâ and further demonstrated that âour subjectivity
is in a constant state of fluxâ (50). Coincidentally, âconstant state of
fluxâ is the precise wording Goldman used to describe herself. And so
while their dealings with Goldman are curiously concise, I am indebted
to May and Call for their intimation, and for retrieving Goldman
(however measured their glances might be) by recognizing her connection
to contemporary thought.
director of the Emma Goldman Papers Project) uses the term âGoldmaniacsâ
to describe those with a passionate interest in Goldman (xviii). The
term âGoldmanologistsâ was used to describe those who may object to the
historically inaccurate Broadway musical portrayal of Goldmanâs
involvement in the assassination of McKinley (June Abernathy âOn
Directing Assassinsâ, <www.sondheim.com/shows/essay/
assassin-direct.html>).
In a documentary produced for PBS, Emma Goldman: An Exceedingly
Dangerous Woman, Alice Wexler (2003), one of the most prominent Goldman
biographers, suggests that Goldman couldnât bring herself to criticize
Leon Czolgosz for his assassination of American President William
McKinley because she âidentified him with Berkmanâ (Goldmanâs long-time
partner). Wexlerâs view toward sublimation represents the tendency to
psychoanalyse Goldmanâs life while ignoring certain elements of her
work. Wexler ignores not only the fact that Berkman himself condemned
Czolgosz, but most importantly, Goldmanâs equable, thoughtful arguments
for why she, nearly alone amongst her contemporaries, refused to
criticize Czolgosz (despite the fact that he credited her as his
inspiration). One way to imagine this more clearly is to think of
Deleuzeâs (2004) discussion of the judgeâs response in the trial of
American activist Angela Davis. Deleuze writes:
Itâs like the repressive work by the judge in the Angela Davis case, who
assured us: âHer behavior is explicable only by the fact that she was in
loveâ. But what if, on the contrary, Angela Davisâs libido was a
revolutionary, social libido? What if she was in love because she was a
revolutionary? (273).
The point Deleuze is making is that we should rethink the assumption
about the motivating factors in lives of revolutionaries â that they are
radical because they are in love. Instead, we can view Davis, and for
our purposes here, Goldman, as driven by a broader ethic of love that
makes each more radical, open and vulnerable. She is in love, and able
to defend Czolgosz, because she is radical, not because of some sense of
substitutability. Therefore, it is because of a radical pre-existing
imaginary and a co-constitutive commitment that certain kinds of
relations are imaginable, that love can be articulated in the ways set
out by Goldman (ways that I will explicate below). For Goldman, only
when it is always already there can it be unconditionally expressed,
rather than something that can be picked up and discarded, manipulated
and strategically deployed, or rooted, as in the case of Wexler, in the
confused projections of the heart.
In the first biography of Goldman, Richard Drinnon (1961) initiated the
aforementioned trend by suggesting Goldman âwas by no means a seminal
social or political thinkerâ (314). In the first biography to focus on
Goldmanâs feminism, Alix Kates Shulman (1971) similarly argued that
Goldman was âmore of an activist than a thinkerâ (37). One year later,
Shulman (1972) again emphasized that Goldman âwas more of an activist
than a theoreticianâ, stating further that âher major contribution to
anarchist theory was to insist on gender as a primary category of
oppressionâ (36). Goldman is often commended as an indefatigable and
inspiring political force, yet one whose only theoretical contribution
is the grafting of gender upon a pre-existing anarchist framework.
Martha Solomon (1987) continued the theme by suggesting that Goldman was
ânot, however, an original theoristâ, but rather, a âpropagandist of
anarchismâ (38). According to Solomon (1988), even those who came to see
Goldman speak âcame to see her as an eccentric entertainer rather than a
serious thinkerâ (191). Nearly ten years later, Oz Frankel (1996)
locates Goldmanâs âmain strengthâ not in her theoretical insights, but
rather, âher wizardry on the stumpâ, âtheatrical presentationâ, and her
âfull control of voice modulationâ (907). The more recent suggestion
that âGoldman was a person of action, not primarily a thinker and a
writerâ (Moritz and Moritz, 2001: 6), perfectly demonstrates that more
than 40 years of biographies have declined to classify Goldmanâs life
and work as especially relevant to political thought or, for that
matter, as particularly radical, but rather, as the interesting work of
a vigorous and spirited agitator.
There are, on the other hand, a number of writers who have mined
Goldmanâs work for its theoretical and political merit. Bonni Haaland
(1993), Lori Jo Marso (2003), Terence Kissack (2008) and Jody Bart
(1995) have each examined Goldmanâs feminism through a close reading of
her views on gender, sexuality, reproduction and the womenâs suffrage
movement. Most important to contemporary Goldman scholarship is the work
of Kathy Ferguson (2004), who has examined the connections between
Goldman and Foucaultâs later work on the care of the self. Jim Jose
(2005) has also presented a criticism of the limited roles in which
Goldman has been cast and how the exclusive focus on her as an
interesting diarist and activist has served to overlook her
contributions to political thought. Leigh Starcross (2004) offers the
lone but important examination of Goldmanâs connection to Nietzsche. In
her short but vital article, Starcross initiates a discussion that takes
seriously the âfundamentality of Nietzsche for Goldmanâ (29) by pointing
out the number of times she lectured on Nietzsche and several of their
shared targets (state, religion, morality).
Throughout the rest of this piece, I shall periodically reference Lewis
Callâs (2002) distinction between postmodern and classical anarchism to
explicate Goldmanâs bridging of the two. According to Call, postmodern
anarchism maintains classical anarchismâs objection to the state,
capitalism and centralized authority, but adds further dimensions by
analysing power outside the government and the workplace, and by
rejecting humanistic and naturalistic notions of subjectivity. More
specifically, Call claims that classical anarchism suffered from three
theoretical tendencies that distinguish it from postmodern anarchism,
thus âseriously limiting its radical potentialâ (22). The three
characteristics that Call argues create this incommensurability are:
classical anarchismâs tendency to carry âout its revolution under the
banner of a problematically universal human subjectâ; an âalmost
exclusive focus on the undeniably repressive power structures
characteristic of capitalist economies [thus] overlooking the equally
disturbing power relations which are to be found outside the factory and
the government ministry: in gender relations, in race relationsâ; and
anarchismâs ârationalist semioticsâ and its subsequent application of
âthe method of natural sciencesâ (15â16). Yet much of Goldmanâs
understanding of social change was not prescriptive, nor did it argue
for the final liberation of a universal self. [1] Her view of power as
present in fields of sexuality, gender, culture, everyday life and
internal struggle illustrates that her analysis was not exclusively
focused on class or economic systems. And as May (1994) points out, she
âresisted the naturalist pathâ (64) followed by many of her
contemporaries. These distinctions allow us to begin reading Goldman as
an important thinker in the trajectory of post-anarchist thought and as
a bridge between it and classical anarchism.
I had to do my reading at the expense of much-needed sleep, but what was
physical strain in view of my raptures over Nietzsche? (Goldman, 1970a:
172)
I have been told it is impossible to put a book of mine down â I even
disturb the nightâs rest. (Nietzsche, 1992: 43)
Goldman was mostly alone when letting in encounters with particular
philosophers, none more so than with her political and textual love of
Nietzsche. Most radicals of her era dismissed Nietzsche as a disquieting
and depoliticizing aristocrat whose work undermined the unquestionable
and fixed liberatory and procedural equation of anarchism. Against this
habit, Goldman searched Nietzscheâs work for its impulse toward revolt,
poring through his texts looking for the undetected spirit of radical
incitation. Described by Call (2002) as âstrand oneâ of the âpostmodern
matrixâ (2) and by May (1994) as âfounding for poststructuralist
thoughtâ (64), Nietzsche helps locate moments in Goldmanâs work that
resonate with certain contemporary fields of theory. Goldman spoke more
highly and with greater intensity about Nietzsche than any other thinker
(anarchist or otherwise). âThe fire of his soul, the rhythm of his
songâ, said Goldman (1970a), âmade life richer, fuller, and more
wonderful for me.â âThe magic of his language, the beauty of his
visionâ, she continued, âcarried me to undreamed-of heightsâ (172).
Nietzscheâs influence on Goldman distanced her from most contemporaries,
many of whom viewed him with derision, as a âfoolâ with a âdiseased
mindâ (Goldman, 1970a: 193). Reflecting upon a heated exchange with Ed
Brady (her partner at the time) about the relevance of Nietzscheâs work,
Goldman described their relationship as âa month of joy and abandon
[that] suffered a painful awakening [...] caused by Nietzscheâ (1970a:
193). On a similar occasion, a friend, bewildered by her commitment,
assumed Goldman would be apathetic to Nietzsche due to the lack of a
palpably political tone in his work. Goldman, enriched by, and defensive
of, his work, argued that such a conclusion stemmed from an intransigent
refusal to understand that anarchism, like the work of Nietzsche,
âembraces every phase of life and effort and undermines the old,
outlived valuesâ (1970a: 194). [2] For Goldman, anarchism constantly
challenged existing values, and should therefore have found its greatest
inspiration in the theorist whose work was, according to Deleuze (1983),
prefaced upon the belief that âthe destruction of known values makes
possible a creation of new valuesâ (193). For Nietzsche (1969), thinking
should âfirst be a destroyer and break valuesâ (139). Elsewhere,
Nietzsche (1989) clarified the affirming character of this destruction
as âsaying Yes to and having confidence in all that has hitherto been
forbidden, despised, and damnedâ (291). At times, Goldmanâs conception
of anarchism directly draws from this aspect of Nietzscheâs work.
Anarchism âis the destroyer of dominant valuesâ, Goldman (1998) argued,
and the âherald of NEW VALUESâ (147). In the same essay Goldman used
Nietzschean-inspired language by calling anarchism the âTRANSVALUATORâ,
what she termed âthe transvaluation of accepted valuesâ (169). [3]
Elsewhere, Goldman (1969) explicitly acknowledged that she borrowed this
concept from Nietzscheâs work: âI believe, with Nietzsche, that the time
has come for a transvaluation of thingsâ (241). Following Nietzsche,
Goldman viewed the transformation of values as a constant process â one
that created new values while undermining the basis and legitimacy of
existing ones. In claiming that âNietzsche was an anarchist [...] a
poet, a rebel and innovatorâ (1970a: 194), Goldman saw a political
relevance in his work at a time when many radicals perceived Nietzsche
as apolitical and irrelevant. At the height of political censorship in
the United States (1913â1917) â when Goldman was frequently arrested,
refused access to many halls and theatres, and her lectures closely
monitored or cancelled by local authorities â she spoke on Nietzsche
more than at any other time.[4] From this I conclude two things: one,
that Goldman responded to consistent persecution by lecturing on
Nietzsche at a time when his work was not considered threatening or
radical; and two, that Goldman perceived undetected anarchistic
sensibilities in his work and used this to intimate the radicality of
her speeches. What local authorities failed to realize was that much of
Goldmanâs anarchism was rooted in Nietzsche, in whose work she saw the
greatest potential for radical social and individual transformation.
It is not surprising then that the phrase for which Goldman has come to
be known (âIf I canât dance I donât want to be part of your revolutionâ)
resonates with an analogy that was very important for Nietzsche.
Throughout his work, Nietzsche makes use of dance to explain perpetual
and creative epistemological shifts. As Deleuze (1983) suggests, for
Nietzsche, âdance affirms becoming and the being of becomingâ (194).
Nietzscheâs (1995) most fervent admiration is reserved for âbooks that
teach how to dance [and] present the impossible as possibleâ (139), as
well as those that allow its reader âto be able to dance with oneâs
feet, with concepts, with wordsâ (Nietzsche, 1982: 512). Works of this
motif would, according to Nietzsche (1969), ideally âgive birth to a
dancing starâ (46). This is precisely the effect Nietzsche had on
Goldman. Although the famously attributed phrase was never actually
spoken by Goldman, the story from which it is taken conveys Goldmanâs
embodiment of Nietzscheâs âdanceâ.[5] Upon dancing with what was
described as âreckless abandonâ, Goldman was taken aside and told that
âit did not behoove an agitator to danceâ, especially someone âwho was
on the way to become a force in the anarchist movementâ (Goldman, 1970a:
56). Considering her passionate commitment to his work, Goldmanâs style
of dance itself might have been stirred by her attachment to Nietzsche:
âbetter to dance clumsily than to walk lamelyâ, Nietzsche said (1969:
305).[6] Subjected to governessy reproof and told âher frivolity would
only hurt the Causeâ, Goldman (1970a) became furious with the austere
suggestion that âa beautiful idealâ such as anarchism âshould demand the
denial of life and joyâ (56). Not only does this story provide an
example of Goldman envisioning social change as taking place in everyday
spaces and expressions â challenging Callâs reading of âclassicalâ
anarchists as exclusively concerned with politics and the economy â it
also suggests that her conception of joy, play, dance and free
expression (notions that more generally contributed to her view of
social change) were inspired by Nietzsche. More than simply the physical
embodiment of creative expression, or the counterpoint to the perceived
and sought-after gravitas of classical anarchism, dance describes
Goldmanâs approach to an anarchist life. Goldmanâs desire to dance
herself to death (present in the epigraph of this piece) â that is, to
remain in a permanent state of conceptual and political motion â was
directly influenced by Nietzscheâs work.
Goldmanâs (1998) view of the state was another aspect of her thought
inspired by Nietzsche. Echoing one of Nietzscheâs most oft-cited
metaphors, she wrote, âI still hold that the State is a cold monster,
and that it devours everyone within its reachâ (426).[7] According to
Goldman, the state âalways and everywhere has and must stand for
supremacyâ (1998: 103). Similarly, Nietzsche called for âas little state
as possibleâ (1982: 82), pointing toward his ideal location outside of
its purview: âthere, where the state ceases â look there, my brothersâ
(Nietzsche, 1969: 78). According to Call (2002), however, Nietzscheâs
criticism of the state did not result in a rationalist counter-system as
it did for many classical anarchists. âA Nietzscheanâ, according to
Call,
could argue that the anarchists ended up promoting a political theory
which would replace the nations of Germany and France with a ânationâ of
Bakuninites. The dominant figure in Nietzscheâs utopian political
imaginary is much more profoundly nonsectarian. She is indeed nomadic in
character. (41)
Precisely, she is Goldman. Here Call is referring to tendencies amongst
classical anarchists to prescriptively construct hegemonically utopian,
and often pastoral, imaginings. Goldman, however, problematized this
tendency. Goldman did not envision a nation of Goldmanites, nor did she
imagine the final eradication of domination brought forth by a new
system based on rationalist principles of human nature. Goldman
recognized that any conception, however rational it may have seemed, was
the product of particular conditions, and that those conditions were
always subject to change. As Nietzsche (1968) put it, âthe character of
the world in a state of becoming is incapable of formulationâ (280).
Following Nietzsche, Goldman (1998) argued that the state (and for that
matter, any social or economic system) âis nothing but a name. It is an
abstraction. Like other similar conceptions â nation, race, humanity â
it has no organic realityâ (113).[8] Goldmanâs willingness to divorce
herself from ideas premised upon a move toward rational and natural
conditions or social systems does, in fact, separate her work from many
classical anarchists. Goldman (1998) suggested that âthe true, real, and
just State is like the true, real, just God, who has never yet been
discoveredâ (102). Here again Goldman questioned the desire to formulate
a final and ideal social world based on rationalist assumptions.
Nietzsche (1968) similarly attacked socialism âbecause it dreams quite
naively of âthe goodâ, true, and beautifulâ (398).[9] From Nietzsche,
Goldman borrowed a sense of constant change that necessarily undermined
notions of a universal and final solution to domination and oppression.
Although at times Goldman remains wedded to the dream of many socialists
and anarchists, her reading of Nietzsche couples her fantast moments
with a commitment to forms of chance and transformation. In fact,
despite Nietzscheâs lack of interest in politics and his vocal disdain
for nineteenth-century socialism and anarchism, Goldman was, in many
ways, the type of thinker he foresaw â the proverbial fish he hoped to
catch:
Included here is the slow search for those related to me, for such as
out of strength would offer me their hand for the work of destruction. â
From now on all my writings are fish-hooks: perhaps I understand fishing
as well as anyone? [...] If nothing got caught I am not to blame. There
were no fish. (Nietzsche, 1979: 82)[10]
Two themes inform the rest of this piece: the concept of transformation
as it relates specifically to social change and political theory, and
transformation more generally focused on the self. For Goldman,
transformation of the social (organization, resistance, theorizing
social change) is equal to transformation of the self (responsibility,
care, ethics of relationality, issues of control and domination, notions
of subjectivity). I will here continue to make use of Callâs distinction
between classical and postmodern anarchism to show how the
transformative elements in Goldmanâs work can be viewed as both
theoretically anticipatory and as a bridge between two seemingly
disparate modes of thought.
According to Call (2002), by ârefusing to claim for itself the mantle of
absolute truthâ, postmodern anarchism âinsists upon its right to remain
perpetually fluid, malleable, and provisionalâ (71). Yet Goldman too
voiced this refusal, and similarly viewed anarchism in this light.
âAnarchismâ, Goldman (1969) argued, âcannot consistently impose an
iron-clad program or method on the futureâ (43). It âhas no set rulesâ,
she proposed, âand its methods vary according to the age, the
temperament, and the surroundings of its followersâ (2005a: 276).
Nietzsche also refused to offer a blueprint for future (or even present)
readers to follow. âRevolution [...] can be a source of energyâ,
Nietzsche (1995) wrote, âbut never an organizer, architect, artist,
perfecter of human natureâ (249). Nietzscheâs (1982) further claim to
âmistrust all systematizersâ (470) not only describes the approach of
Callâs postmodern anarchism, but is also similar to Goldmanâs conception
of anarchism. As her statement above suggests, Goldmanâs anarchism was
non-prescriptive and contingent. That is, she viewed it not as a closed
mapping that sketched forms of resistance or social organization, but
rather, as a flexible and open political philosophy in a state of
perpetual transformation. Mayâs description of a contemporary politics
informed by Deleuze reiterates Goldmanâs view: âOur task in politics is
not to follow the program. It is not to draft the revolution or to
proclaim that it has already happened. It is neither to appease the
individual nor to create the classless society [...] Our task is to ask
and answer afresh, always once more because it is never concludedâ (May,
2005: 153). Deleuze (1983) himself states likewise that âthe question of
the revolutionâs future is a bad one, because, as long as it is posed,
there are going to be those who will not become revolutionariesâ (114).
Call (2002) too argues for âa state of permanent and total revolution, a
revolution against beingâ (51). What this demonstrates is that Goldmanâs
work resonates with the shared affinity of Deleuze, Call, and May for a
political philosophy that âleaves posterity free to develop its own
particular systemsâ (Goldman, 1969: 43). Her work shares with them a
desire for struggle, victories, political dissensus and processes, and
social change, without an accompanying interest in becoming a totalizing
discourse, movement, or political philosophy. As Deleuze is arguing
above, the foreclosure of the unknown not only prevents people from
becoming revolutionaries, it also serves to stop revolutionaries from
becoming. Or, as Goldman (2005a) made clear, âthere is no cut-and-dried
political cureâ (402).
Goldmanâs (1998) refusal to âclaim that the triumph of any idea would
eliminate all possible problems from the life of man for all timeâ (440)
was met with discontentment. ââWhy do you not say how things will be
operated under Anarchism?ââ, Goldman (1969) lamented, âis a question I
have had to meet a thousand timesâ (43). Deleuze and Guattari (1983)
would have supported her reluctance: âWhere are you going? Where are you
coming from? What are you driving at? All useless questions [...] all
imply a false conception of voyage and movementâ (58). Goldman believed
that a political philosophy could be radical and emancipatory without
tethering itself to anodyne universals or essentialist notions. For
Goldman, anarchism was not encoded with a linear progression â it did
not have an identifiable beginning, ending or goal. Instead, it was
closer to Deleuze and Guattariâs (1983) claim that âthere is no general
recipeâ (108) than the attempts by many of Goldmanâs contemporaries to
locate the most egalitarian and natural forms of social organization. As
one of the most tireless and prolific radicals of the twentieth century,
Goldman was uniquely clear that her efforts were not focused upon a
single, attainable goal. Rather, her anarchism could best be described
as based on what Deleuze (2004) called âceaseless oppositionâ (259) â an
approach that remains âopen, connectable in all its dimensions [...]
capable of being dismantled [...] reversible, and susceptible to
constant modificationâ (Deleuze and Guattari, 1983: 26). What was for
Goldman (1969) a political philosophy that had âvitality enough to leave
behind the stagnant waters of the old, and build, as well as sustain,
new lifeâ (49) is, for Deleuze and Guattari (1983), âthe furniture we
never stop moving aroundâ (47). âHow, then, can anyone assume to map out
a line of conduct for those to come?â, Goldman wondered (1969: 43). The
approach one could instead take, according to Deleuze (2004), is by ânot
predicting, but being attentive to the unknown knocking at the doorâ
(346). Goldman would have agreed. âI hold, with Nietzscheâ, she argued,
âthat we are staggering along with the corpses of dead ages on our
backs. Theories do not create life. Life must make its own theoriesâ
(2005a: 402). Goldmanâs anarchism did not predict or initiate a single
and dramatic political shift, but rather, was constantly renewed by the
context and conditions of resistance and the collectives and individuals
taking part in struggles.
Goldmanâs political activity demonstrates just how radical the concept
of constant transformation is. It is not an apathetic, detached,
apolitical theoretical exercise lacking a consideration for
consequences. Positions are taken, identities are asserted, injustices
are addressed, and conceptual and logistical spaces are occupied.
However, as the above section has shown, contingency and the
accompanying refusal to prescribe or locate a static utopian social or
personal state are affirming and highly political positions that serve
to open up and cultivate possibilities for social change. As Call (2002)
states of Nietzscheâs âutopianâ thought, âit develops a devastating
critique of the world as it is, and dreams of a better future. But the
construction of that future is for those who followâ (55). Deleuze and
Guattari (1987) also warned that
smooth spaces are not in themselves liberatory. But the struggle is
changed or displaced in them, and life reconstitutes its stakes,
confronts new obstacles, invents new paces, switches adversaries. Never
believe that a smooth space will suffice to save us. (500)
Likewise, Goldman can be seen to have searched for smooth spaces while
recognizing that this search was constant and contextual. Even the
similar phrasing of Nietzsche, Deleuze, AnzaldĂșa and Goldman is, at
times, particularly striking: âcontinual transitionâ (Nietzsche, 1968:
281); âstate of permanent creationâ (Deleuze, 2004: 136); âstate of
perpetual transitionâ (AnzaldĂșa, 1987: 100); âstate of eternal changeâ
(Goldman, 1970b: 524). This similarity stands in contrast to Callâs
(2002) argument that the âongoing, open-ended, fluid anarchist
discourseâ of postmodern anarchism is categorically distinct from the
âmodern anarchist traditionâ (65) in which Goldman is most often
situated (by Call and others). For example, Goldman did not envision a
core human nature that could be set free from political and economic
constraints. âHuman natureâ, Goldman (1998) argued, âis by no means a
fixed quantity. Rather, it is fluid and responsive to new conditionsâ
(438). Engaged in what Butler (1993) would come to term âresistance to
fixing the subjectâ (ix), Goldman perceived identity as always shifting.
In Goldmanâs (2003) work there is a move away from a fixed being;
instead she refers to âlittle plastic beingsâ (270).
Goldmanâs (1970b) talk of âlife always in fluxâ and ânew currents
flowing from the dried-up spring of the oldâ (524) introduced a notion
of anarchism as âconstantly creating new conditionsâ (Goldman, 1969:
63). The fact that these statements span 40 years of Goldmanâs life also
demonstrates that this current is present throughout most of her work.
These elements of Goldmanâs work extended beyond her thoughts on
political and state apparatuses, also informing her views of gender and
sexuality. In fact, her rejection of the argument that gender is
biologically determined anticipated the anti-essentialism of many fields
of contemporary feminist thought. Goldmanâs (1998) understanding of
identity as always âin a state of fluxâ (443) marks a shift in anarchist
notions of gender (and identity more generally). Most of Goldmanâs
contemporaries maintained a gendered binary that perceived women as
having biological predispositions that distinguished them from men. If
women were considered as deserving of political and economic equality
they were, at best, viewed simply as different biological characters,
and at worst, undeveloped thinkers. The latter was put forth by
Kropotkin (one of the pillars of classical anarchism) during a
discussion with Goldman:
âThe paper is doing splendid work,â he warmly agreed, âbut it would do
more if it would not waste so much space discussing sex.â I disagreed,
and we became involved in a heated argument about the place of the sex
question in anarchist propaganda. Peterâs view was that womanâs equality
with man had nothing to do with sex; it was a matter of brains. âWhen
she is his equal intellectually and shares in his social ideals,â he
said, âshe will be as free as himâ. (Goldman, 1970a: 253)
For many of Goldmanâs contemporaries, âsexâ was either an issue of
little or no importance or justified as a category of exclusion. For
others, the inequality and oppression that stemmed from dichotomous
distinctions based on âsexâ was itself the issue to be opposed, rather
than the categories themselves, as well as their accompanying naturalist
assumptions. Goldman on the other hand, was not simply engaged in a
public discussion of gendered oppression and exclusion â for though she
was outspoken on this topic, she was not alone (a big fish in a small
bowl perhaps). Rather, what resonates with contemporary discourses is
the way Goldman conceptualized âsexâ. Goldmanâs (1969) demand that we
âdo away with the absurd notion of the dualism of the sexes, or that man
and woman represent two antagonistic worldsâ (225) is a good example of
this. Not only is this a unique rejection of the (still standing)
biological distinction between men and women, it also pre-dates Simone
de Beauvoirâs (1989) famous assertion that âone is not born, but becomes
a woman. No biological, psychological, or economic fate determines the
figure the human female presents in society: it is civilization as a
whole that produces this creatureâ (267). Gender, like morality and the
belief in the necessity of the state, is, for de Beauvoir and others, an
inscribed referent. âThis conceptual realizationâ, Monique Wittig (1992)
wrote, âdestroys the idea that women are a ânatural groupââ (9). âThe
concept of difference between the sexesâ, she continued, âontologically
constitutes women into different/othersâ (29). For Goldman and those who
followed, this divisive binary both failed to understand the historical
and cultural specificity of gender and served to limit the diverse ways
it could be conceptualized and expressed. What Goldman (1933) called
âthe various gradations and variations of genderâ (2) abandoned the
delimiting belief in a biological predisposition, thus anticipating
contemporary articulations of gender and identity as âshifting and
multipleâ (AnzaldĂșa, 1987: 18). Adopting this perspective is, as
AnzaldĂșa suggests, âlike trying to swim in a new element, an âalienâ
elementâ (ibid). Like the kind of fish Nietzsche hoped to catch,
however, Goldman swam against the conventional current of her day,
adopting a unique view of gender that resonates with a contemporary form
of thought whose âenergy comes from continual creative motion that keeps
breaking down the unitary aspect of each new paradigmâ (ibid.: 2).
This nuanced mode of thought came through most in Goldmanâs criticism of
the womenâs suffrage movement. âWoman will purify politics, we are
assuredâ Goldman (1969: 198) said with some irony. The essentialist
footing of the suffrage movement not only failed to ask who was
economically and politically excluded from the category of âwomanâ, it
also assumed that the simple presence of women (privileged white women)
would deracinate the workings of chauvinisms, inequities and injustices
and initiate democratic, sensitive, convivial and inclusive practices.
âI do not believe that woman will make politics worseâ, Goldman (1998)
argued, ânor can I believe that she could make it betterâ (209).
Elsewhere, Goldman (1970c) stated, âI am not opposed to woman suffrage
on the conventional ground that she is not equal to it, but that cannot
possibly blind me to the absurd notion that woman will accomplish that
wherein man has failedâ (53). Instead, âwomanâ must, according to
Goldman (1969), begin âemancipating herself from emancipationâ (215).
That is, women, in fact everyone, should cast off the conceptual and
personal devotion to a static and universal self that can be liberated
through even the most minor participation (voting) in a liberal
democracy. As Butler (1993) puts it, the category of gender âbecomes one
whose uses are no longer reified as âreferentsâ, and which stand a
chance of being opened up, indeed, of coming to signify in ways that
none of us can predict in advanceâ (29). Interestingly, Goldmanâs
(2005b) criticism of the suffrage movement and her refusal to adopt its
naturalist category of âwomanâ was perceived as anti-feminist and
injurious to a crucial and unquestionable political cause (two
criticisms that Butler has confronted).
Another important dimension of Goldmanâs work is her prefigurative
conception of social change. In rejecting the idea of a natural,
universal, permanently liberated self, and by divorcing herself from the
dominant yearning for the singular revolutionary event, Goldman
envisioned social change as a continuous process that mirrored the
sought-after social world. For Goldman (1998), âthe means used to
prepare the future become its cornerstoneâ (403). In this context,
democratic forms of interacting and organizing are not deferred, but
rather, borne out immediately. âNo revolution can ever succeed as a
factor of liberationâ, Goldman argued, âunless the MEANS used to further
it be identical in spirit and tendency with the PURPOSES to be achievedâ
(1998: 402). Not only does this indicate a rupture from Marxist and
utopian socialist pictorials of a better world to be constructed at a
later date, it also differs from several anarchist contemporaries who
imagined a revolutionary moment springing from an inborn, natural human
condition. Anarchism, according to Goldman (1970b), âis not a mere
theory for a distant futureâ, but rather, âa living influenceâ (556).
Goldman took this further by also focusing on personal transformation.
Rather than paying exclusive attention to the alteration or eradication
of external economic and political conditions, Goldman (1998) demanded a
struggle against what she called the âinternal tyrantsâ (221) that, as
she further suggests, âcount for almost nothing with our Marxist and do
not affect his conception of human historyâ (122). Goldmanâs thoughts on
tendencies toward the domination of the self and others resonate with
thinkers often cast as voices of post-structuralist thought. Foucault
(1983), for example, similarly advocated for âthe tracking down of all
varieties of fascism, from the enormous ones that surround and crush us
to the petty ones that constitute the tyrannical bitterness of our
everyday livesâ (xiv). For both Goldman and Foucault, there is no pure
individual to be left alone or cultivated in the ideal environment.
Desire, justice, democracy and revolutionary social change do not appear
simply by adjusting external fields or institutions. Rather, they appear
when radical visions of social change are immediate aspects of our
interactions, language and forms of organization, and when we work to
make better versions of ourselves as we do better versions of our social
world.[11] Concerned with living their political philosophy, and
unwilling to accept the argument that âbetterâ selves are simply and
retrievably stalled or contained by manipulative sources of power,
Goldman and Foucault each questioned how a strong allegiance to
authority (our desire to dominate and to be dominated) maintained such a
strong psychic footing. Foucaultâs (1983) curiosity toward âthe fascism
that causes us to love power, to desire the very thing that dominates
and exploits usâ (xiii) is similar to Goldmanâs (1969) position that the
individual âclings to its masters, loves the whip, and is the first to
cry Crucify! the moment a protesting voice is raised against the
sacredness of capitalistic authority or any other decayed institutionâ
(77).
With yet another allusion to Nietzsche, Goldman (1998) explicates a self
animated by perpetual transformation:
I do not mean the clumsy attempt of democracy to regulate the
complexities of human character by means of external equality. The
vision of âbeyond good and evilâ points to the right to oneself, to
oneâs personality. Such possibilities do not exclude pain over the chaos
of life, but they do exclude the puritanic righteousness that sits in
judgment on all others except oneself. (215)
In contemporary terms, Goldmanâs recognition of the political
implications of self-reflection can be read as âstaying at the edge of
what we knowâ (Butler, 2004: 228) about both our social world and
ourselves â what Butler also calls the âradical pointâ (ibid.) or
AnzaldĂșa (1987) termed the âCoatlicue stateâ (63â73).[12] The Coatlicue
state, according to AnzaldĂșa, âcan be a way station or it can be a way
of lifeâ (68). This way of thinking can stand for immobile darkness and
inactivity or it can offer constant introspection that opens new
possibilities and refuses a certain amount of ethico-theoretical
comfort. For Goldman, self-reflection is a constant process. Thus, she
can be connected to AnzaldĂșa as well as Butler (2004), who argued that
the unitary subject
is the one who knows already what is, who enters the conversation the
same way as it exits, who fails to put its own epistemological
certainties at risk in the encounter with the other, and so stays in
place, guards its place, and becomes an emblem for property and
territory. (228)
Or, as Goldman (2005a) put it (with the unfortunate pronoun of course),
âI hold when it is said of a man that he has arrived, it means that he
is finishedâ (153). Goldman was not interested in subjects who sought
arrival at a final cognitiveâtheoretical resting point. Goldmanâs
anarchism was a political philosophy with currents that rejected the
desire for foundations, naturalist bases, fixed subjects and
prescriptions, instead, in a decidedly Nietzschean move, favouring the
unknown. Deleuze and Guattari (1983) express this notion of
transformation perfectly:
Form rhizomes and not roots, never plant! Donât sow, forage! Be neither
a One nor a Many, but multiplicities! Form a line, never a point! Speed
transforms the point into a line. Be fast, even while standing still!
Line of chance, line of hips, line of flight. Donât arouse the General
in yourself! Not an exact idea, but just an idea (Godard). Have
short-term ideas. Make maps not photographs or drawings. Be the Pink
Panther, and let your loves be like the wasp and the orchid, the cat and
the baboon. (57)
The works of AnzaldĂșa, Butler and Deleuze are clearly marked with an
affinity for multiplicity and interconnectivity â what I would refer to
as an ethic of love. Though known primarily for her discussion of love
with regard to her personal relationships and struggle for open sexual
expression, Goldman used the term to describe more broadly a spirit or
ethic that desired meaningful personal and organizational connections on
multiple levels. Love, according to Goldman (1970c), was a âforceâ,
providing âgolden raysâ and the âonly condition of a beautiful lifeâ
(46). Always more at home in promissory love letters than prescriptive
texts or travelling along programmatic routes, Goldman understood love
as the most important element of life. It was, I would argue, a constant
drift through her work that constituted an element of thought and
interaction that most assured radical social and personal change. Love
as a whirling of possibility, a potentially binding political landscape,
as an affinity for the unknown, for futurity, for constant
responsibility, open and vulnerable connection, the multiple â this is
the guiding spirit of Goldman and the thinkers I have so far discussed.
For Goldman, without an ethic of love, social change is meaningless:
âhigh on a throne, with all the splendor and pomp his gold can command,
man is yet poor and desolate, if love passes him byâ (Goldman, 1970c:
44). âLoveâ, continued Goldman, âis the strongest and deepest element in
all life, the harbinger of hope, of joy, of ecstasy; love, the defier of
all laws, of all conventions; love, the freest, the most powerful
moulder of human destinyâ (44). Once again we see the presence of
Nietzsche in Goldmanâs interest in the intractable, what Chela Sandoval
(2000), through her concept of âhermeneutics of loveâ, refers to as âa
state of being not subject to control or governanceâ (142). Or, as
Nietzsche (1989) wrote, âthat which is done out of love always takes
place beyond good and evilâ (103). In this, a Goldman sense of love, we
do not love under certain conditions, or because we understand one
another, or because we share a particular vision, or even because we
recognize each other as something relatable, translatable or familiar to
something in our psychic, preferential, emotional or political
sensibilities. It is not because we will be loved or find a desire
satisfied, a lack filled, or be offered something absent. Instead, for
Goldman, love takes place prefiguratively, before the encounter, before
the advance or event that usually marks its beginning or containment in
reachable social and political visions. This ethic of love also
articulates the desire for a multiplicity of political positions and
activities. As Foucault wrote:
We all melt together. But if we choose to struggle against power, then
all those who suffer the abuses of power, all those who recognize power
as intolerable, can engage in the struggle wherever they happen to be
and according to their own activity or passivity ... provided they are
radical, without compromise or reformism, provided they do not attempt
to readjust the same power through, at most, a change of leadership.
(Foucault and Deleuze, 2004: 213)
What is important for Foucault (and for other thinkers mentioned) is the
radical element â the element that does not re-inscribe, reform, or take
over existing systems of power. Love does not want power, nor does it
want what already exists. Multiplicity and interconnectivity, as
important aspects of love, cannot be found in hegemonic spaces of social
organization and resistance. Love does not seek to reform, but rather,
to transform, over and over, amidst a cluster of identities and tactics.
Goldman recognized the radical potential of this multiplicity:
âPettiness separates; breadth unites. Let us be broad and big. Let us
not overlook vital things because of the bulk of trifles confronting usâ
(Goldman, 1998: 167). Goldman not only saw danger in confrontations that
foreclosed multiplicity, she also celebrated multiple tactical and
political positions. The solidarity Goldman envisioned was not
contingent on a universal notion of social change or identity. Instead,
Goldman argued for solidarity for its own sake. As AnzaldĂșa (1990a) put
it, âunity is another Anglo invention like their one sole god and the
myth of the monopoleâ (146). Goldmanâs affinity for constant
transformation refused a fixed and stable unity while, paradoxically,
her ethic of love demanded interconnectivity and community. What this
interconnectivity is based on, however, remains shifting and under
review. As AnzaldĂșa (1987) suggested:
It is where the possibility of uniting all that is separate occurs. This
assembly is not one where severed or separated pieces merely come
together. Nor is it a balancing of opposing powers. In attempting to
work out a synthesis, the self has added a third element which is
greater than the sum of its severed parts. That third element is a new
consciousness â a mestiza consciousness â and though it is a source of
intense pain, its energy comes from continual creative motion that keeps
breaking down the unitary aspect of each new paradigm. (101â2)
Goldmanâs anarchism cultivated multiplicity rather than attempting to
universalize disparate positions under a single theoretical rubric.
Goldman (2005a) called for âdiversity [and] variety with the spirit of
solidarity in anarchism and non-authoritarian organizationâ (348). What
this meant for Goldman anticipates Foucaultâs indictment of the idea of
reform â an idea that, as Deleuze most clearly suggests (Foucault and
Deleuze, 2004), is âso stupid and hypocriticalâ (208). Goldman supported
those individuals and organizations that neither sought to reinforce
existing structures of power, nor refused connection with those whose
tactics, organization and political philosophy did not mirror their own.
Like Deleuze, Goldman (1970a) saw it as âridiculous to expect any
redress from the Stateâ (122), following Nietzsche (1995), who argued
that the state âtries to make every human being unfree by always keeping
the smallest number of possibilities in front of themâ (157). In this
regard, appealing to the state for change does not open it up to
multiplicity. At best, the state can be asked to include additional
elements, as long as those elements do not make certain demands (radical
change, uncertainty, revaluation of the legitimacy of the state). In a
politics of reform, the state form must remain dominant. However,
multiplicity not only demands diversity, but also refuses the domination
and centralization of a single form of organization, resistance,
interaction or identification. The starting point of such an ethic
âincludes instead of excludesâ (AnzaldĂșa, 1990b: 379). The question then
becomes, how can things be opened up, expanded, and interrogated, rather
than asking how others can be incorporated into an existing paradigm.
Goldmanâs (1998) praise of life as representing âbeauty in a thousand
variationsâ (150) also appears to be drawn from her reading of
Nietzsche. She states, âI venture to suggest that his master idea had
nothing to do with the vulgarity of station, caste, or wealth. Rather
did it mean the masterful in human possibilities [to] become the creator
of new and beautiful thingsâ (ibid.: 232â3). âNietzscheâs practical
teachingâ, Deleuze (1983) wrote, âis that difference is happy; that
multiplicity, becoming and chance are adequate objects of joy by
themselves and that only joy returnsâ (190). Deleuze (2004) argued that
Nietzsche should be understood as an âaffirmation of the multipleâ which
lies in âthe practical joy of the diverseâ (84). Goldman too understood
Nietzsche in this way, and consequently used his work to construct her
notion of anarchism as embracing the multiple and the relational.
Drawing from Nietzscheâs affinity for multiplicity, Goldmanâs work, like
AnzaldĂșaâs (1987) new mestiza, âoperates in a pluralistic modeâ (101).
âShe [the new mestiza] has discovered that she canât hold concepts or
ideas in rigid boundariesâ, AnzaldĂșa argued, âshe learns to juggle
cultures, she has a plural personalityâ (1987: 101). Put simply, Goldman
imagined the greatest potential for radical social change in the
cultivation and interconnection of multiple conceptual and political
forms.
And so it was that Goldman was content to occupy an itinerant
intellectual and political world without answers â happy to imagine a
thousand tactical, personal and political interconnecting variations.
Butler (2004) too expresses an affinity for âan affirmation of life that
takes place through the play of multiplicityâ (193). This demonstrates
that by relying upon Nietzsche and theoretical affinities that would
come to be associated with post-structuralist thought (indictment of
rationalist and naturalist assumptions, refusal to accept binaries,
rejection of fixed notions of revolution, social change and state forms,
and an affinity for multiplicity and perpetual transformation), Goldman
theorized resistance in a way that was distinct from many of her
predecessors and contemporaries. As Call (2002) points out, âtoday it
may not be enough to speak out only against the armies and the police,
as earlier anarchists didâ (11). Yet Goldman would have agreed with his
suggestion that an anarchist analysis must look further than the usual
targets. âAny solutionâ, Goldman (1969) argued, âcan be brought about
only through the consideration of every phase of lifeâ (50). Similarly,
Foucault (1980) contended that âwe canât defeat the system through
isolated actions; we must engage it on all frontsâ (230). AnzaldĂșa
(2002) too demanded that we âmake changes on multiple fronts:
inner/spiritual/personal, social/collective/materialâ (561). Goldman did
not concern herself with only the most traditional and recognizable
sites of power. Power, for Goldman, existed in all institutions and
relationships, and therefore the struggle against domination needed to
take place constantly and in every aspect of life. As Goldman (1998)
suggested with regard to âsexâ and power, âa true conception of the
relation of the sexes will not admit of conqueror and conqueredâ (167).
That is, power is not a force wielded by some and denied others, but
rather, is present in all relationships and institutions.
One of the ways Goldmanâs multiplicity manifested itself was through the
practice of solidarity. Goldmanâs solidarity with anti-colonial
struggles in Africa and the Philippines and the participants of the
Mexican and Spanish revolutions (as well as countless other groups and
struggles) was an important element of her work:
It requires something more than personal experience to gain a philosophy
or point of view from any specific event. It is the quality of our
response to the event and our capacity to enter into the lives of others
that help us to make their lives and experiences our own. (Goldman,
1998: 434)
For Goldman, ethico-political encounters must remain open and
democratic. For example, despite being credited as âthe most dangerous
woman in the worldâ for over two decades, Goldman rejected the call from
several contemporaries to counsel those fighting in the Spanish
revolution. âWe must give our Spanish comrades a chance to find their
own bearings through their own experienceâ, Goldman (1998: 424) argued.
Her constant displeasure with American workers and their failure to
align themselves with struggles taking place elsewhere in the world
(1969: 142) anticipated the popularized slogan âteamsters and turtlesâ,
used by many within contemporary anti-globalization struggles to explain
a ânewâ form of solidarity. However, the example that stands out most
among her contemporaries, and the one with which I will conclude, having
come full circle, was her defence of Czolgosz. Though she herself
disagreed with the tactic, Goldman (1998) made an important distinction
in her criticism: âI do not believe that these acts can, or even have
been intended to, bring about the social reconstructionâ (60). For
Goldman, each act of resistance did not have to be a sanctioned tactic
that acted as a component of a fixed trajectory toward the revolution.
Dissensus could and should be present (and coupled with democratic forms
of decision making) and tactics should be reconsidered, but not at the
expense of empathy, connection and a consideration of contexts. We
should not âarriveâ, as Goldman stated earlier, nor desire that everyone
else challenging power reside in the same politico-theoretical space.
Goldmanâs (1970a) insistence that âbehind every political deed of that
nature was an impressionable, highly sensitive personality and a gentle
spiritâ (190) signified a unique and nearly solitary understanding of
the event. Goldman not only rejected the prevailing wisdom of distancing
oneself from certain people or groups with the hope of avoiding the
indictment of power or public opinion, she also refused the dichotomous
view of acceptable or unacceptable tactics. Moreover, she located the
affirmative element within Czolgoszâs action. As Deleuze (1983)
suggested, âdestruction becomes active to the extent that the negative
is transmuted and converted into affirmative powerâ (174). By suggesting
that Czolgoszâs âact is noble, but it is mistakenâ (Goldman, 2003: 427),
Goldman was attempting to open an inter-tactical dialogue â one that
neither condemns nor endorses, but recognizes the limitations of any one
tactic. Goldmanâs suggestion that political acts need not be stepping
stones toward a universal and agreed-upon goal is similar to Michael
Hardt and Antonio Negriâs reading of Frantz Fanon and Malcolm X in
Empire (2000). Hardt and Negri defend what might be framed as an
unpopular tactic by arguing that the ânegative momentâ articulated and
supported by Fanon and Malcolm X âdoes not lead to any dialectical
synthesisâ nor act as âthe upbeat that will be resolved in a future
harmonyâ (132). As such, the dialectic is no longer a necessary
political framework through which activists make tactical decisions. In
Czolgoszâs case, Goldman understood that his act was not the dialectical
âupbeat that will be resolved in a future harmonyâ.
Under the wrinkling labour of contemporary political and theoretical
debates several questions have been asked. Among them: How is it
possible to maintain attachments to others, to subjectivities, to
futurity and imaginings, and to forms of organizing that remain
contingent? What does it mean to occupy the shaky scaffolding of
unstable and contradictory identities? What can be made of a theoretical
turn that involves the loosening of a commitment to a final
revolutionary moment? Prior still is the question about the consequence
of this shift and the coming to terms with certain losses? If radical
social change is perceived and articulated as an unrealizable fiction
that maintains a utopian imaginary without being wedded to its actual
realization, what becomes of political futures? Finally, are the
political protests, forums and ethico-political practices that have
captured the imagination of a wide range of theorists and been cast as
constitutive of a palpably euphoric and near utopian shift in social and
political possibility, and further, described as perpetually changing
and unique aggregates of previously conflicting groups and ideologies
now communicating and working across geographical and political lines,
entirely new? My argument here is simply that each of these questions
requires a dimension of remembrance, one that draws from the impetuses,
imaginings, political practices and failures of the past. To this end,
Emma Goldman offers one important and inheritable moment to which we can
look back as we move forward.
AnzaldĂșa, Gloria (2002). âNow Let Us Shift ... the Path of Conocimiento
... Inner Work, Public Actsâ. In This Bridge We Call Home: Radical
Visions for Transformation (G. AnzaldĂșa and A. Keating, eds). New York:
Routledge.
ââ (1990a). âEn rapport, in Opposition: Cobrando cuentas a las
nuesratsâ. In Making Face, Making Soul/Haciendo caras: Creative and
Critical Perspectives by Feminists of Color (G. AnzaldĂșa, ed.). San
Francisco: Aunt Lute Books.
ââ (1990b). âLa conciencia de la mestiza: Towards a New Consciousnessâ.
In Making Face, Making Soul/Haciendo caras: Creative and Critical
Perspectives by Feminists of Color (G. AnzaldĂșa, ed.). San Francisco:
Aunt Lute Books.
ââ (1987). Borderlands/La frontera: The New Mestiza (2nd edn). San
Francisco: Aunt Lute Books.
Avrich, Paul (1994) [1988]. Anarchist Portraits. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Bart, Jody (1995). ââIf I Canât Danceâ: The Political Philosophy of Emma
Goldmanâ. DAI 55(9) (March).
Beauvoir, Simone de (1989) [1949]. The Second Sex (H.M. Parshley, ed.
and trans.). New York: Vintage Books.
Bookchin, Murray (1995). Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An
Unbridgeable Chasm. San Francisco: AK Press.
Butler, Judith (2004). Undoing Gender. New York: Routledge.
ââ (1993). Bodies that Matter: On the Discursive Limits of âSexâ. New
York: Routledge.
Call, Lewis (2002). Postmodern Anarchism. New York: Lexington Books.
Dark Star Collective (2002). âForewordâ. In Quiet Rumours: An
Anarcha-Feminist Reader (Dark Star Collective, eds). San Francisco, CA:
AK Press.
Day, Richard (2005). Gramsci Is Dead: Anarchist Currents in the Newest
Social Movements. Toronto: Between the Lines.
Deleuze, Gilles (2004). Desert Islands and Other Texts, 1953â1974 (D.
Lapoujade, ed.; M. Taormina, trans.). Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).
ââ (1983). Nietzsche and Philosophy (H. Tomlinson, trans.). New York:
Columbia University Press.
ââ and FĂ©lix Guattari (1987). A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia (B. Massumi, trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
ââ ââ (1983). On the Line (J. Johnston, trans.). New York: Semiotext(e).
Drinnon, Richard (1961). Rebel in Paradise: A Biography of Emma Goldman.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Falk, Candace (1984). Love, Anarchy and Emma Goldman. London: Rutgers
University Press.
Ferguson, Kathy E. (2004). âE.G.: Emma Goldmanâ. In Feminism and the
Final Foucault (D. Taylor and K. Vintges, eds). Chicago: University of
Illinois Press.
Foucault, Michel (1983). âPrefaceâ. In Gilles Deleuze and FĂ©lix Guattari
(1983). Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia (R. Hurley, H.R. Lane
and M. Seem, trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
ââ (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings,
1972â1977 (Colin Gordon, ed.). New York: Pantheon Books.
ââ and Deleuze, Gilles (2004) [1972]. âIntellectuals and Powerâ. In
Deleuze (2004).
Frankel, Oz (1996). âWhatever Happened to âRed Emmaâ?: Emma Goldman,
from Alien Rebel to American Iconâ. Journal of American History 83(3):
903â42.
Goldman, Emma (2005a). Emma Goldman: A Documentary History of the
American Years, vol.2. Making Speech Free, 1902â1909 (C. Falk, B.
Pateman and J. Moran, eds). Berkeley: University of California Press.
ââ (2005b). The Social Significance of Modern Drama. New York: Cosimo
Classics.
ââ (2003). Emma Goldman: A Documentary History of the American Years,
vol.1. Made for America. (C. Falk and B. Pateman, eds). Berkeley:
University of California Press.
ââ (1998). Red Emma Speaks: An Emma Goldman Reader (3rd edn; A.K.
Shulman, ed.). New York: Humanity Books.
ââ (1970a). Living My Life, vol.1. New York: Dover Publications.
ââ (1970b). Living My Life, vol.2. New York: Dover Publications.
ââ (1970c). The Traffic in Women and other Essays on Feminism. Ojai, CA:
Times Change Press.
ââ (1969). Anarchism and Other Essays. New York: Dover Publications.
ââ (1933). âAn Anarchist Looks at Lifeâ. Retrieved in March 2004 from
http://sunsite3.berkely.edu/Goldman/Writingsw/Speeches/foyles.html
.
Graham, Robert (ed.) (2005). Anarchism: A Documentary History of
Libertarian Ideas. Montreal: Black Rose Books.
Haaland, Bonnie (1993). Emma Goldman: Sexuality and the Impurity of the
State. Montreal: Black Rose Books.
Hardt, Michael, and Negri, Antonio (2000). Empire. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press. Jose, Jim (2005). ââNowhere at Homeâ: Not Even
in Theoryâ. Anarchist Studies 13(1): 10â20.
Kissack, Terence (2008). Free Comrades: Anarchism and Homosexuality in
the United States, 1895â1917. Oakland, CA: AK Press.
Marshall, Peter (1993). Demanding the Impossible: A History of
Anarchism. London: Fontana Press.
Marso, L.J. (2003). âA Feminist Search for Love: Emma Goldman on the
Politics of Marriage, Love, Sexuality and the Feminineâ. Feminist Theory
4(3) (December): 305â20.
May, Todd (2005). Gilles Deleuze: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
ââ (1994). The Political Philosophy of Anarchism. Pennsylvania:
Pennsylvania State University Press.
Moritz, Theresa, and Moritz, Albert (2001). The Worldâs Most Dangerous
Woman: A New Biography of Emma Goldman. Vancouver: Subway Books.
Newman, Saul (2001). From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-Authoritarianism and
the Dislocation of Power. London: Lexington Books.
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1995). Human, All Too Human (G. Handwerk, trans.).
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
ââ (1989). Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future.
New York: Vintage Books
ââ (1982). The Portable Nietzsche (W. Kaufmann, trans.). London: Penguin
Books.
ââ (1979). Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What One Is (R.J. Hollingdale,
trans.). London: Penguin Books.
ââ (1969). Thus Spoke Zarathustra: A Book for Everyone and No One (R.J.
Hollingdale, trans.). London: Penguin Books.
ââ (1968). The Will to Power (W. Kaufmann, trans.). New York: Vintage
Books.
Sandoval, Chela (2000). Methodology of the Oppressed. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Sheehan, Sean M. (2003). Anarchism. London: Reaktion Books.
Shulman, Alix Kates (1991). âDances with Feministsâ. Womenâs Review of
Books 9(3): 1â3.
ââ (1972). âDancing in the Revolution: Emma Goldmanâs Feminismâ.
Socialist Review 61(12): 31â44.
ââ (1971). To the Barricades: The Anarchist Life of Emma Goldman. New
York: Crowell Press.
Solomon, Martha (1988). âIdeology as Rhetorical Constraint: The
Anarchist Agitation of âRed Emmaâ Goldmanâ. Quarterly Journal of Speech
74: 184â200.
ââ (1987). Emma Goldman. Boston: Twayne Publishers.
Starcross, Leigh (2004). ââNietzsche was an anarchistâ: Reconstructing
Emma Goldmanâs Nietzsche Lecturesâ. In I Am Not a Man, I Am Dynamite:
Friedrich Nietzsche and the Anarchist Tradition (J. Moore and S.
Sunshine, eds). Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia.
Wexler, Alice (2003). American Experience: Emma Goldman (PBS
transcript). Retrieved from
http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/amex/goldman/filmmore/pt.html
.
Wittig, Monique (1992). The Straight Mind and Other Essays (M. Wildeman,
trans.). Boston: Beacon Press.
Woodcock, George (2004) [1962]. Anarchism: A History of Libertarian
Ideas and Movements. Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press.
[1] Although Goldman, like many others (including Nietzsche) sometimes
spoke in terms of an imagined utopian space, this does not undermine the
argument I am making, for three reasons: One, my intention is to make
suggestions for further readings by locating certain elements of
Goldmanâs work. Two, I would argue that although Goldman did sometimes
speak in this way, she maintained the demand that utopian visions remain
open to constant modification and criticism. Three, I would further
argue that Goldmanâs vision of a democratic, creative and open world is
the expected result of political activity. That is, this vision does not
undermine oneâs ability to embrace uncertainty and multiplicity. Rather,
being inflexibly wedded to a very particular vision is what results in
the exclusion and lack of open-mindedness that Goldman problematized in
her work.
[2] The resistance Goldman experienced with respect to her attachment to
Nietzsche shows that what would otherwise be insignificant anecdotes
from her autobiography in fact represent important sources for
understanding her notion of anarchism.
[3] This clearly draws from Nietzscheâs notion of a ârevaluation of all
valuesâ (Nietzsche, 1979: 96; 1982: 579). The different terms
ârevaluationâ and âtransvaluationâ hold the same meaning for Goldman and
Nietzsche. In fact, Goldmanâs use of the term âtransvaluationâ seems to
be drawn directly from her German reading of Nietzsche, rather than a
new term inspired by him.
[4] Unfortunately, federal authorities confiscated the notes from
Goldmanâs lectures (including those on Nietzsche) during a raid at the
New York office of her anarchist journal, Mother Earth. They have since
been destroyed or have not been released.
[5] Considered an authority on Goldman, Shulman (1991) was asked to
provide a friend with a photo of Goldman and an accompanying phrase to
be embossed on T-shirts and sold at an anti-Vietnam protest in the early
1970s. Shulman provided a number of passages from which quotes could be
drawn, with particular emphasis on one from Goldmanâs autobiography. In
this passage, Goldman describes a party at which another anarchist
confronted her about her style of dance. What resulted was a
paraphrasing of this confrontation: âIf I canât dance I donât want to be
part of your revolutionâ.
[6] It is worth noting that this arguably ableist, albeit analogous,
comment not only predates disability studies, but is also connected to
Nietzscheâs general contempt for physical âsicknessâ/âimperfectionâ â
something he himself was for most of his life.
[7] In an earlier essay, Goldman credited Nietzsche with first calling
the state a âcold monsterâ (1998: 117).
[8] This comment also demonstrates Goldmanâs prescience and anticipation
of the contemporary (and arguably postmodernist) denial of organic
reality (the socially constructed ânatureâ) of categories such as race.
[9] Nietzsche viewed socialism and anarchism as an arrogant and
prescriptive âwill to negate lifeâ (1968: 77), desirous of homogeneity.
[10] Despite Nietzscheâs suspicion of activists, he did periodically
expose a certain appreciation: â[T]here is nothing contemptible in a
revolt as such [...] there are even cases in which one might have to
honor a rebel, because he finds something in our society against which
war ought to be waged â he awakens us from our slumberâ (Nietzsche,
1968: 391).
[11] I am indebted to Mark Lance for this phrasing.
[12] AnzaldĂșa describes the Coatlicue state as âa rupture in our
everyday world. As the Earth, she opens and swallows us, plunging us
into the underworld where the soul resides, allowing us to dwell in
darknessâ (1987: 68).