💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › stephen-pearl-andrews-the-labor-dollar.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:08:44. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Labor Dollar
Author: Stephen Pearl Andrews
Date: 1881
Language: en
Topics: equitable commerce, labor theory of value, labor notes, money, mutual banking
Source: Retrieved on 10th August 2021 from https://archive.org/details/2916966.0001.001.umich.edu/page/2/mode/2up.
Notes: Published in the *Radical Review*

Stephen Pearl Andrews

The Labor Dollar

As the labor question is steadily and rapidly increasing in recognized

importance, every effort should be made to place its “social solutions”

upon a thoroughly scientific basis. One of these “solutions” relates

specially to the true and ultimate system of currency. I have just

received from some unknown friend, probably the author, a small pamphlet

entitled “The Labor Question: what it is, method of its solution, and

remedy for its evils,” by Charles Thomas Fowler. In it Mr. Fowler says,

with great terseness of expression and with truth, that “the birth of

the first bill of exchange was the death of the last specie dollar.”

Bills of exchange, bank checks, and negotiable paper of all sorts add

just so much to the body of the currency; and this issue is unlimited by

law, and unlimited in fact, except by the exigencies of trade.[1] They

are just as really currency as the specie dollar, the greenback, or the

bank bill. A field which has no fence upon one of its sides is not

fenced in, no matter how high and strong its fences may be on the other

sides. So, the volume of the currency is not, in any true sense, limited

by prohibitions of free banking, by a return to specie basis, or by any

other means, so long as negotiable paper can be freely issued by

individuals; and this free issue of negotiable paper is too useful, and

too well intrenched in necessity, ever hereafter to be interfered with.

Commerce can be hindered and trammeled to some extent—it may even, for a

time, be seriously disturbed—by statute arrangements claiming to

regulate the currency, whether by restrictive measures, or by flooding

the community with over-issues; but the volume of the currency can no

longer be adjusted by such means.

There is, it is true, a certain temporary advantage in the specie basis,

simply because it is traditionally believed in, and beliefs or ideas

enter into the question of the stability of values. This fact is felt by

the advocates of a specie basis. They, and others, would not have so

much of the sensation that “the bottom is all knocked out,” if we could

return to such a basis, and that confidence would go for something. On

the other hand, the sole alternative, so far as seen by the advocates of

specie basis, is a fluctuating and limitless issue from time to time of

government paper money, with no other regulation than that of an

ignorant and changeable public opinion, operated by interested political

and financial agitators and wireworkers. Such are the grounds of the

honest advocacy, so far as it is intelligent, of a return to a specie

basis.

On the other hand, the advocates of paper money and expansion have their

side of the truth. They see or feel the fallacy of the claim that specie

basis really means any thing but an illusion, knowing as they do that

gold and silver are real commodities rising and falling in value along

with all other commodities, and that they will in no event make the

whole volume of the currency, but will be only a fixed factor—in so far

as fixed—along with other changeable factors in the composition of its

total volume; a fence upon one side of a field which, on some other

side, is an open common. They also see or feel that the best currency

would be such as should have some kind of adjusted elasticity, or an

expansive and contractile quality, adapted to the fluctuating activities

of trade, of which currency is the instrument; and, in fine, that

government might, if it knew enough and were honest, subserve by its

conceded powers this demand for an adaptation between the needs of trade

and the appropriate supply of its instrument.

But, on the one hand, the supposed stability resulting from a specie

basis is a mere illusion, and one which is fast being found out and

exposed, while the remedy offered by the opponents of a specie basis is

not, in fact, the only alternative; and, on the other hand, no existing

government does know enough wisely to regulate the currency, and, as a

rule, existing governments are not honest.

The political issue about finance, now coming to the front in the United

States, and in a degree in other countries, is, therefore, on neither

side intelligent or wholly well-intentioned, while yet, on either side,

representing something of the truth. The discussion and agitation are,

nevertheless, to be hailed as among the most auspicious signs of the

times. They signify politics become educational—electioneering a

university training-school for the whole people. The community may have

to pay dearly for its instruction before it is through with this new war

of ideas ; but the right knowledge of the subject will be ultimately

evolved, and the war itself will be the opportunity of the true

teachers.

I have said that government paper is not the only alternative of a

specie basis. It is, however, the only one to which much attention has

been given; and the other—that to which I wish to call attention—will

need to be carefully elaborated and described from time to time to make

it clearly apprehended as, in fine, the science of the subject. I mean a

currency and a system of banking based directly on labor and, in a

sense, self-regulating; that is to say, regulated and administered by

individuals, or by the people themselves, without let or hindrance,

without interference or prescription from the government; although

beneficent adjustments may possibly take place between the action of the

government and this labor system of free banking.

The object of the present essay is not, however, chiefly to define or

describe either currency in its specific details, or labor banking as a

system. It is rather preliminary to those considerations, and will be

confined in a great measure to the simple ascertainment of THE UNIT OF

LABOR, which, when ascertained, may be taken as the dollar of the Labor

Bank.

Every system of thought, every science which is accurately constituted,

has what is technically called its unit, its starting-point, that from

which all its investigations take their departure, and to which they

recur as regulative of them all. Thus the unit of arithmetic is the

numerical unit, or the number one; the unit of geometry is the point, or

minim of length; the unit of weight is the pound; the unit of long

measure is the foot; the unit of mechanical force is the foot-pound; the

unit of mechanical power is the horse power; and the unit of resistance

to the transmission of electricity is the ohm. The following definitions

are furnished me by Prof. P. H. Van Der Weyde:—

A foot-pound, the unit of force or of work, is one pound weight lifted

one foot high against gravitation, the gravitation taken at the surface

of the ocean at forty-five degrees latitude. The latter two

considerations are, however, practically neglected. The element of time

in which the work is done is here left out of the account.

A horse power, the unit of power or of the amount of force exerted or

work done in a given time, is thirty-three thousand foot-pounds per

minute; that is to say, thirty-three thousand pounds lifted one foot

high per minute, or three hundred and thirty pounds lifted one hundred

feet high per minute, or five and one-half pounds one hundred feet high

per second, or fifty-five pounds ten feet high per second.

A man power is one-eighth horse power; so that a man may lift seven

pounds ten feet high per second, or four hundred and twenty pounds ten

feet per minute, or four thousand two hundred pounds one foot per

minute, or seventy pounds one foot per second.

The French unit of force is the kilogrammeter, one kilogram lifted one

meter high, or seven and two-tenths times our unit of force. A kilogram

equals two and two-tenths pounds; a meter equals nearly three and

one-third feet. A French horse power is seventy-five kilogrammeters per

second.

The ohm has been accepted by the British Association as the unit of

resistance in telegraph wires and other conductors of electricity; and

as the strength of the battery power must overcome such resistance, it

has at the same time become the measure of battery strength. The ohm is

the resistance which an electric current undergoes in passing through

one-tenth of a mile of No. 9 iron wire.

The French unit of electrical resistance is that of one meter of mercury

contained in a glass tube of one square millemeter section.

These definitions are introduced here for the purpose of showing the

pains-taking accuracy with which the student of mechanics determines his

units of measurement,—with which, in other words, he establishes

standards, or measures those things by which other things are to be

measured,—and to emphasize the statement that Radical Political Economy,

or, so to speak, this branch of Social Mechanics, will begin to be

rightly constituted as a science only when we shall have established,

with equal accuracy, the unit of labor. Unless the measure itself is

measured, there is no accuracy, no certainty, no scientific result.

By the science of Radical Political Economy I mean the science of the

laws of price-bearing wealth, as wealth should be produced and

distributed in order to secure the absolutely equitable exchange of

labor and commodities.

I say Radical Political Economy, because ordinary or current Political

Economy inquires, rather, into the laws of wealth as it is in fact

produced and distributed, with only such suggestions of improvement as

do not affect, radically, the present system. I say price-bearing

wealth, because there is much wealth which is, or should be, unpriced or

priceless; which does not, or ought not, therefore, to enter into

commerce at all, in the ordinary sense of commerce. The blessed air of

heaven, the affection we bear to lovers, children, and friends, have in

them a world of wealth to those who receive them; but they are, or

should be, a free gift, uncalculated and unmeasured by price, definite

estimate, or equivalent. Our affections are degraded when they are

reduced to the level of price-bearing commodities. It is only,

therefore, price-bearing commodities which are the subject-matter of

Radical Political Economy.

All price-bearing commodities—all, that is to say, which are rightfully

such, or which should be such—are the products of labor; and it is the

amount of labor concreted in the commodity which is the true measure of

its price,[2] This labor is sometimes called labor-cost, or the cost in

labor of producing the commodity; and it is then said that, from the

point of view of Radical Political Economy, COST IS THE LIMIT OF PRICE.

The principle is the same if the price is put directly upon the labor,

without awaiting its concretion in a commodity. Hence it follows that,

in order to obtain the true measure of cost, and so of price, and so a

true standard of exchange or trade, i. e., a true dollar as the unit of

trade,—all these being now identified with each other,—we must first

ascertain, or in some way determine upon, the unit of labor.

The first and simplest suggestion, in the inquiry after a unit of labor,

is the day's work. The hour's work is an important fraction of the day's

work, but it is not so naturally the unit as the day's work. The day's

work is, it will be found, virtually the labor dollar, and the hour's

work accords rather with the dime or bit. But a day's work is, as the

matter now stands, too indeterminate to serve as the scientific measure

of something else supposed to need measurement.

Work of any kind, in order to be accurately and completely defined, must

be determined in three aspects:—

First, as to the length of time;

Second, as to the degree of its intensity or severity;

Third, as to the degree of acquired skill, or ability previously

accumulated by other work preparatory to the work now in hand; and as to

certain other minor considerations.

The day's work, to be made standard, and to serve as the labor dollar,

or the instrument by which all other work may be measured or estimated,

must, therefore, be itself defined in all these three particulars.

First, as to the length of the standard day's work. We may take for this

purpose eight hours. It is not necessary to insist that this is

inherently the true limit of the working day, though much has been said,

and may be said, in favor of the division of the day of twenty-four

hours into three equal parts,—one for work, one for sleeping and eating,

and one for study and recreation. It suffices for our purpose to adopt

this period,—arbitrarily, if you will. Certainty is all that is

necessary. The “meter,” the scientific yard, serves sufficiently well to

measure cloth, whether it be precisely ascertained to be the

ten-millionth part (which it is intended to be) of the earth's diameter,

or not.

Next, in respect to the severity of the work; and I am here especially

indebted to Mr. Fowler for introducing the term intensity, Josiah

Warren, recognizing that the character of the work is an element of the

problem, used the phrase “the amount of repugnance overcome” to denote

the degree of hardship or burdensomeness of labor. The expression is

accurate, but, like his pounds of corn as a device for measuring labor,

it is cumbersome; and the idea is, for most purposes, better expressed

by the simple word intensity. There is another reason why the

introduction of this term, as a technicality for the purpose, is

important, and fairly entitles Mr. Fowler to claim to have enlarged and

improved the technical machinery, in this particular, of the science of

Radical Political Economy. I was never satisfied with the moderate

degree of success which Mr. Warren—or myself, in my effort to expound

Mr. Warren's ideas on this subject twenty-three years ago (see “Science

of Society”)—had achieved in attempting to make clear the nature of, and

mode of measuring, the elements of work other than the time occupied. I

struggled with the difficulty at the time, and have always felt that I

partially failed. It is Mr. Fowler's use of the term intensity in this

connection which has stimulated me to this renewal of the subject.

The special aptness of this term for this purpose, and the reason why I

deem it so important, will appear from the following considerations.

Continuity in time, mere forth-stretching in the given direction, is

called by the philosophers Protension (forth-stretching); a stretching

outward and around in all directions, as in space, is called Extension

(out- or from-stretching); and the energy of effort, by which things

are, as it were, drawn in upon and by the centering personality of the

actor, is called intensity (in-stretching). What we are dealing with is

a department of measure—the measure of labor, cost, and price; and the

metaphysicians have pointed out that these three modes are the only

three possible requisites of complete or exhaustive measurement; so that

we may, when we have thoroughly applied them, rest assured that, by such

recurrence to first principles, we have scientifically compassed the

subject. Hickok, for example, in his “Empirical Psychology,” expresses

this proposition in these terms: “No quantity can have measure in any

other directions than extension in space, duration in time (protension),

and intensity in degree; and when an act of attention has stretched over

the limits filled by the distinct quality in all these several

directions, it has determined it in all the forms which any quality can

possess, and made it to be known definitely in all its measures of

quantity.” The subject we are investigating is the quantity of labor;

and the question is: Of what does it consist in these three possible

modes of considering it?

In respect to time measure, the protensity of labor, we have said all

that is requisite at the moment. In respect to its intensity or severity

we have ascertained that this is also a proper element of the standard

day's work, and so of the measure of all work; and we must now inquire

by what standard it can itself be measured or estimated, and how,

practically, the standard can be applied. The subject is confessedly a

difficult one. All sorts of people put all sorts of different estimates

upon the relative intensity or severity of all sorts of different labor.

It may almost be said that no two agree upon any point touching the

subject. But fortunately science is now sufficiently advanced to teach

us how to overcome this difficulty. The statistical and other branches

of science have familiarized us with the method of general averages. It

is possible to tell with proximate accuracy how many persons will commit

suicide next year in London, Paris, or New York; and even how many will

choose the razor, how many the rope, how many the pistol, and how many

drowning, as the means of effecting death. It will be found possible, in

a similar way, when the world wishes to know, to ascertain how many

women think washing harder work than ironing, and how many think the

other way; and how many men would prefer to work out of doors, and how

many under shelter. All these statistics of the details of human labor,

and of the estimates which men and women make of the desirableness and

undesirableness of every given pursuit and condition, will in the future

become subjects of science, and then of practical every-day knowledge

and utility; and the labor dollar, then having come into use, will

furnish the unit of all such calculations. In that future when equity

shall give labor its own, the modes of rightly apportioning the burdens

of life will be studied with intensity, and there will be found nothing

insuperable in the nature of the problem. The first great step is to

convince the minds of men of the desirableness of such knowledge.

It should be borne in mind that, when exchanges of goods shall be made

in accordance with a known law of equity based exclusively upon

labor-cost, trade secrets, being no longer of any advantage, will be

abandoned, and all knowledge of all trades will be thrown open to all

people. There will then be greater facility among men for changing their

occupations, and for gratifying their tastes in their pursuits. This

change will also enable people to know far better than they now know

what labors they really like best, and are willing to do at the cheapest

rate. There will then grow up a legitimate labor-market, and all kinds

of labor and products will be tendered at the minimum price as measured

by the average estimate of the degree of severity of the labor involved

in them. In other words, every act of purchase and sale will then be the

result of the votes of two parties on the relative repugnance and

attractiveness of the two varieties of labor involved; and the whole

body of trade will be a continuous canvassing of all such questions. It

is so now in part, and except that ideas are confused on the subject;

that each party to every trade considers himself entitled to take

advantage of the other, which is an illegitimate element—as much so in

principle, as the sword or the slave whip thrown into the bargain; and

that no labor dollar, and therefore no instrument of adjusting

labor-cost, has hitherto existed.

Assuming, then, that by the prevalence of equity, or the true

interchange of equivalents in labor-cost, we had a full supply of

everybody's estimates of every kind of work in respect to its relative

repugnance or attractiveness,—its intensity, in fact, as hard or easy

work,—it would be easy to strike an average which should be very

exact—the true par of labor intensity; all above that average being work

of extra or plus intensity, or above par, and all below it being work of

minor intensity, or below par. We have not, it is true, as the case now

stands, the necessary data for establishing the exact par of labor

intensity; for the world has not hitherto thought it worth while to

study such facts. The best that can be done therefore, to begin with, is

to assume an average which will approach in some measure to accuracy,

and to go on constantly eliminating error and arriving at a higher

decree of precision.

Everybody has some idea of what constitutes an ordinary or average

degree of hard work. We may now, then, without attempting to fix the

idea any more definitely beforehand, further define the labor dollar as

a day's work of eight hours—of course whether male or female labor—of

the average degree of severity or intensity. I think the bare abstract

idea of an average, or par, is all that is needed, and that it is better

than Mr. Warren's corn measure. We all know sufficiently well what we

mean by “the usual degree of health," and do not have to add "as well as

Mr. A or Mr. B;” and, if we should undertake to settle the matter more

exactly in that way, we should most likely diverge at once into a

discussion over the question whether Mr. A's or Mr. B's health was of

the average degree; thus demonstrating that the bare idea of the average

is more definitely fixed in our minds than the particular state of the

health of any individual. This view does not, however, antagonize the

previous suggestion that the extended and systematic observation of

details will ultimately render the abstract idea still more definite.

If parties, in negotiating an exchange, regard their labor as of the

ordinary degree of intensity,—which would occur in the great majority of

cases, especially under the criticism of a worldful of appraisers,—that

determines the point without further parley. If, on the contrary, one or

both differ in their estimate from the average, that is matter of

negotiation. If one too much depreciates his labor, it will become, with

culture, under this system, matter of courtesy to insist on raising the

estimate. While, then, ordinarily a dollar note will be paid for the

day's work or its produce in a commodity, the price and payment may go

up to a dollar and a half, or down to the half dollar, or may deviate to

any other- degree, the dollar serving in every case as the unit of

comparison,—as, in a word, the standard of labor-cost, price, and

labor-value, which all come to be identical; value meaning in this case,

not utility, but the buying-capacity of the dollar.

To illustrate: suppose a community reduced by any cause to the primitive

condition of barter. Instead of the poor device of the

shinplaster,—referring for its measure of value to the silver or gold

dollar, which has taken its departure and is no standard,—let the labor

note be substituted. Miss Smith undertakes the teaching of the village

school. She will teach eight hours a day, and she estimates her labor as

neither above nor below the average degree of intensity as hard work.

This, then, being exactly the value of the labor dollar as above

defined, Miss Smith charges one dollar—a labor dollar—a day for her

work. She has an average of twenty pupils. For each pupil the parents

become, therefore, indebted to Miss Smith the twentieth part of a

dollar, or one half labor dime, or five labor cents, per day; and they

pay her in their own labor notes, or in the labor dollars, dimes, and

cents which have come into their hands from their trade with others. The

labor money bills only differ from every body's individual notes written

on common paper in the fact that the storekeeper or postmaster has got

up his own notes in better style, printed and perhaps vignetted, and

issues them in the place of the common written scraps of paper.' These

he keeps in his safe instead, as his specie basis, they being the

immediate representative of the labor of the village, so far as it is in

market. As fast as the work promised is done, or its equivalent given in

products, the notes are redeemed and cancelled, or re-issued, and the

transaction is ended.

In this manner Miss Smith gets her entire pay in good labor dollars.

These will command every body's work and buy every thing produced in the

village. Dealing with the outside world involves an extension of the

problem which will not be considered at this point. The school teacher

may, in turn, to the extent of her credit, and wishing to anticipate

returns, issue her labor notes, transmutable into labor dollars by the

village banker —the postmaster or store-keeper, as before stated. In

this manner she, and every one in the village, becomes a capitalist to

the extent to which their neighbors have confidence in their future

ability and intention to fulfil their promises; and so, able to create

loan's for themselves at any moment to this extent; checked in the first

instance by any lack of confidence on the part of the immediate

neighbors, and then on the part of the village banker, who must have

confidence also before he will receive the individual's labor note and

replace it by his own issue. Thus a healthy and continuous vigilance

will be exerted over this otherwise perfectly free creation of the labor

bullion of our new banking system. Risk and actual losses will, however,

occur ; but they will be reduced to a minimum by the natural working of

the system; and the village banker will become an insurance agent to

cover them, being allowed to increase the currency beyond the bullion in

deposit the slight percentage found practically necessary to that end.

Apart from this percentage to cover losses,—which will be kept at the

lowest, as it will be added under the immediate inspection of the whole

village, each individual being constantly taxed his proportion of every

loss,—the village banker is not to be allowed to issue a single labor

dollar for which he has not the same amount of labor bullion—the labor

notes of the people—in deposit; including, however, his own labor notes

covering his services, and issued on the same terms as those of any

other citizen. Every over-issue should be deemed a fraud, and prevented

or remedied by well-devised checks upon the conduct of the banker,—such

as numbers on the bills issued, reports and inspections of committees,

etc.,—until confidence is so established as to dispense with unnecessary

caution. The banking office will be open to competition in respect to

the best management, like any other business. If a dozen bankers spring

up in the village, no matter.

Another element remains to be added in the constitution of the labor

dollar,—one which has been alluded to above, and then purposely

postponed until now. This is what we will technically call the Extensity

of the day's work,—an element which extends beyond, or goes outside of,

the particular day upon which the work is to be done. This element is

the acquired skill of the laborer, secured by previous labor fitting him

to do the work; the wear and tear of instruments or tools of his own,

which he brings into the work; particular risks of any kind assumed by

the laborer, etc. This item is fixed also by averages and the mutual

estimates of the parties contracting.

Prior labor giving skill is to be estimated upon the same principle as

other labor; but, the cost being distributed by estimate to all who will

be ever likely to avail themselves of the skill, it becomes generally a

small item in the individual case: such as it is, however, to be settled

by the estimates of the worker and employer, or tacitly covered by the

general price demanded for the day's work. So with the other matters

included under this head. All legitimate risks are legitimately covered

by an augmentation of price.

It is a curious working of this equitable system of exchanges that,

while acquired skill involving prior labor is an element of the price of

labor, superior natural ability—“the gift of God”— is left wholly out of

the account, and does not in any manner augment the price. This is a

point which is more frequently than any other misunderstood, and which,

when understood, is most likely to meet with objection from new

investigators of equity. A little close attention to it, however, will

remove all difficulty. It is undoubtedly true that superior natural

ability does give a natural advantage, which the possessor may, if he

will, and which at present he does, avail himself of in disposing of his

labor. The question now is, however, whether he ought really to do so;

or, in other words, whether the gift of Nature to the individual is

something entirely for his selfish individual benefit, or something in

which his weaker competitor especially, and the public at large, should

participate.

It is certain that the principle of equity, as rightly defined,—the

exchange of equivalent burdens, or of equivalent amounts of repugnance

overcome,—gives nothing for that which costs nothing. The handsome woman

degrades herself if she makes a charge for exhibiting her beauty. It is

wealth to the world, as it is also to herself, but not price-bearing

wealth; not an object of ordinary commerce or trade. Ought it not to be

the same with superior natural talents and endowments of all kinds? On

the race-course and in the prize-ring, where the object is—as here, in

respect to equity—to neutralize all undue advantages, it is not merely

the swiftest horse or the strongest man, pure and simple, who takes the

prize. All advantages are first equalized by granting to the weaker

party compensating advantages. The “light weight,” when pitted against a

bigger man, has a due concession made to him on account of his obvious

inferiority.

Should not laborers, in seeking equity for themselves, be ready to abide

by the behests of equity throughout; when it works against, as well as

when it works for, them? Should not the world's workers come to be as

generous, as honorable, as just, at least, as racers and prize-fighters?

No pugilist would call it a fair fight when a big fellow knocked down a

little one merely because Nature gave him the superior ability; merely,

in other words, because he could do it. No gamester would refuse to give

odds to one less versed than himself in the game. Curiously enough,

these are almost the only people who have ever been dealing with the

question of what is fair play in any competitive engagement of man with

his fellow. Ordinary political economy never asks the question, but only

inquires to what extent, and by what means, the big fellows actually get

the advantage; what are the laws and operations, in other words, of the

natural tendency to advantage-getting.

In those departments of life where courtesy is established, there is no

doubt on this question. If a weak woman burdened with a child is allowed

to stand in a crowded place, and strong men sit at their ease, it is

justly regarded as an outrage upon decency; and yet the strong men would

only be availing themselves of their natural advantages.

In a word, on principle, the question is settled beyond all doubt that

equity, in establishing prices, grants nothing on the ground of natural

superiority,—therein concurring with the principles of fair dealing as

understood in games, and of courtesy as understood in society. But

still, with our present habits of thought, the verdict may seem a harsh

one; and many persons will perhaps be more readily convinced if made to

see that the principle will work well in practice, than by the mere

sternness of the logic. This well-working of the principle is also

readily shown. But first, let us conclude our definition of the labor

dollar as the measure of radical equity.

The labor dollar is then, in fine, a vignetted paper representative,—or

its equivalent,—signed and issued by a labor banker, of a day's work, of

man, woman, or child, of eight hours' duration, of average intensity and

average extensity.

The general aspect of the labor dollar may be similar to that of a

current dollar bill more or less elaborately devised. Paper will be the

ordinary material, although it would not cease to fulfil the conditions

if some other available substance—as parchment for instance—were used

instead. Its cost and the labor of signing, issuing, cancelling,

renewing, etc., belong to expenses, and can be repaid to the banker,

equitably estimated, along with all other labor.

A promise of labor to the same amount signed by an individual not a

banker, not vignetted, etc., would pass under the more general

designation of “a labor note.” Together, and with all accessory

commercial paper of the same order, they would constitute the labor

currency.

The labor notes of the people, in the safe or vaults of the banker,

securing him in making his promises to render so much labor, or its

equivalent in products, are what I have denominated labor bullion.

Trade or commerce conducted on this basis may be denominated labor

trade; and the transactions of this trade, with the ruling rates for

different kinds of labor, will come to be rightly known as the labor

market; and the labor rates of every species of men's and women's labor,

down to minutiae, will be regularly quoted.

The radical, indeed the revolutionary, difference between a currency

based on this simple device and any previously existing currency may

still escape the reader, unless he again reflects that the labor dollar

means something defined, and therefore definite, and that the current

dollar means something wholly undefined and indefinite. Consider the

difference in this respect between a common token, such as a theatre

ticket or a railroad ticket, and a paper, or even a silver, dollar. The

token obtained to-day will purchase a seat in the theatre or the car

to-day, tomorrow, or six months hence: that is to say, it represents a

definite something, or, in other words, a fixed and ascertained

purchasing-power. Not so with the dollar, whether paper or metallic. You

may know what you can buy with them to-day, but what they will procure

for you to-morrow, a week hence, or six months hence:,you cannot know,

as their value may have fluctuated within any limits; in other words,

they have no fixed or ascertained, or ascertainable, purchasing-power.

The labor dollar has, then, the character of the fixed token, as

contrasted with that of our present currency; or the character of a

measure which is itself measured, as contrasted with an elastic

yard-stick, or the hand or foot used as a pound weight.

In an article on finance by Mr. McCulloch, ex-Secretary of the Treasury,

he says:

“There being but one universally recognized measure of value, and that

being a value in itself, costing what it represents in the labor which

is required to obtain it, the nation that adopts, either from choice or

temporary necessity, an inferior standard violates the financial law of

the world, and inevitably suffers for its violation. An irredeemable,

and consequently depreciated, currency drives out of circulation the

currency superior to itself; and if made by law a legal tender, while

its real value is not thereby enhanced, it becomes a false and

demoralizing standard, under the influence of which prices advance in a

ratio disproportioned even to its actual depreciation. Very different

from this is that gradual, healthy, and general modification of prices

which is the effect of the increase of the precious metals."

What is here said of the relative fixedness of paper and metallic

currency, which would be in a degree true if the comparison were with a

currency to consist of the precious metals and nothing else—which is not

pretended,—applies as a condemnatory criticism upon all systems of

finance which exist or have existed; and the encomium can only be

conferred rightly on the labor currency, which has the characteristics

insisted on in a still higher degree than the metals alone would have

them.

In the above definition of the labor dollar the day's work of a child is

estimated at the same as that of a man or a woman. This will be apt to

strike the investigator at first as erroneous, but he has only to recur

to the principle to perceive that it is strictly accurate. The severity,

or repugnance overcome, in keeping a child eight hours intensely at

work, is almost sure to be as great as, and is most likely to be much

greater than, that of so employing the time of a grown person; and by

our principle, it is this severity endured which is to be compensated or

equalized by the price paid for the labor. Such is, in other words,

precisely all that price can rightfully mean.

What, in the next place, would be the working results of this principle

upon the labor of children? Just this: as children's labor would have to

be paid as much as, or more than, that of grown people,—except when

employed at those light and pleasing labors which for them would

resemble play,—no employer would engage children for hard and unsuitable

work, except in cases of urgency or peculiar necessity; and then he

would submit to compensate them appropriately, according to the

principle. Children would then be, as it were, driven out of the labor

market (except in the emergencies above referred to); which means,

however, nothing more than that employers would prefer, if practicable,

to secure the heavier and harder variety of labor when it was at the

same time lower priced than the other; and secondly, that children would

be thereby left free for acquiring education, and for play or

untrammeled exercise, which is precisely what should happen. In other

words, children and grown people would be relegated, respectively, by

the working of a simple principle, to their true places,—a drift which

would co-operate exactly with what is now the effort of wise and

benevolent parents and guardians.

The case of children conducts us back to the question, reserved above,

of the similar working of the principle in denying pay for superior

endowments, which, as a portion of natural wealth, are by the theory

non-price-bearing commodities. Here also it will be found that the

effect is quietly to force every body—not now children alone—into their

true places; being in fact, thereby, one of the greatest of social

solutions. Under the principle, the best endowed and most efficient

labor comes into competition with inferior labor in each special branch,

not, as now, at a higher price, nor even at the same price, but

absolutely at a lower price. Of course, then, it will force itself in,

and force the inferior labor out. Let this be well understood. He who

should have the greatest natural fitness for a particular kind of work,

having greater facility in it, will—with some exceptions only—have also

the greatest attraction or fondness for that kind of industry. His

estimate of its intensity will therefore be less than that of other men.

In other words, it will not be as hard work for him as for them, and,

therefore, under this new principle, his price will be less. Of course,

then, he will be preferred, and those for whom it is harder work or more

burdensome will be set aside. The very best workmen will first be taken

up by the employers; then the second best; then the third best; and,

finally, and under necessity only, the poorer qualities; which, however,

if called in, will be paid the higher prices, as in the case of the

children. There is, even as matters now stand, a natural preference, of

course, among employers for superior workmen; but this preference is

nearly neutralized, and sometimes inverted, by the fact that such labor

must have the largest prices; so that poor laborers are about as readily

retained, and sometimes more so, than the superior ones, whereby the

survival-of-the-fittest principle is defeated, and the general quality

of products depreciated.

This paying of the best workmen the lowest prices upsets, of course, all

existing notions. It is a difficult point both for unphilosophical and

for selfish minds. It is, nevertheless, not only abstractly right, but

replete with the best possible results. It is on the road to the

reduction of all price to zero, or to the time when all labor shall be

play, and shall be exchanged for love without price. But far short of

this, and immediately, these results follow: 1. All labor will be

performed—as a rule—by the best workmen and with the utmost efficiency,

and, consequently, all products will be carried up to the highest

excellence. 2. All prices will be brought down to the minimum, or to the

very cheapest at which the labor, or the product, can be afforded

—tending to place both necessaries and luxuries within the reach of all,

3. Every body will be gently and unconsciously forced into just those

pursuits for which they are best suited, and for which they have most

liking; in other words, Attractive Industry will be in a great measure

realized. What could be asked for better than all this?

Upon this third point a word should be added. The inferior workman,

forced out of an employment, may and often will prove to be the superior

workman in some other; so that to be driven out of the labor market only

means, in fact, being transferred to something better, until the whole

world shall be employed at just that which it likes best to do.

A fourth result, perhaps the most important of them all, will be to

substitute a PRINCIPLE for the settlement of prices instead of the

system of universal higgling and overreaching which now prevails; a

civilized and scientific, instead of a barbarous, method. If war may be

defined as an inflammatory social fever tending to the surface, trade

for profit, by bargaining, may be regarded as the low or typhoid form of

the same, a disguised and diffused fever, a state of modified war of all

against all. This greatest effect of equity would then be to substitute

interstitial peace for a universal state of interstitial warfare in

society, opening the way to all kinds of beneficent cooperation in the

place of an antagonistic individuality.

It must not, however, after all has been said, be concluded that the

mere operation of the principle, “labor-cost the limit of price,” will

fulfil all the conditions of social harmony, and supply of itself the

true social organization. It is simply a plank in the ship, or, if you

will, the keel; but it is not the whole structure. Nor will it prove,

taken alone, altogether satisfactory. A society constituted merely under

the operation of this principle would, indeed, secure a genial and

beneficent equity, but it would also lead to a certain dead-levelism of

conditions which would lack an element of picturesqueness and variety

which the human mind also craves.

Nobody could ever become very rich; but the level prairie, or the

fertile plains of Lombardy, would prove dull, if the whole world had

nothing else to exhibit. Security of condition and a sense of prevailing

justice in life, while they are a basis of happiness, are only a basis.

The human soul has legitimate aspirations for distinction, preeminence,

largeness of individual environment, and the means of great and

beneficent achievement, which may demand the possession of exceptional

wealth of the acquired and price-bearing variety, as well as mere

natural endowment. These aspirations the existing order of society does,

to a considerable extent, gratify; but it does so at the expense of a

general denial of equity, and of a consequent all-prevalent irritation,

ending in the insecurity of the very wealth so acquired. Equity is,

therefore, a question of method, of economy, and of security, as well as

a question of the just distribution of wealth. The demand for some

opportunity for larger acquisitions than are afforded by mere equity is,

nevertheless, a true voice of the soul, and the supposition that the

doctrine of equity completely forbids any such aspiration is one of the

greatest hindrances to its acceptance. There is a secret repugnance to

the doctrine left in the mind, despite the logical cogency which may

compel an intellectual assent. This comes, however, entirely of

misapprehension. It is not essential that a devotion to exact and

technical equity should predominate in all human transactions. What the

doctrine affirms is merely that, by bargain and traffic regulated by

equity, large fortunes could not be acquired, while every body under the

operation of that principle might become measurably rich. It stops at

this. It does not concern itself with any other class of transactions

among men, neither denying nor affirming the possibility of acquiring

exceptional wealth by other methods. This particular doctrine is merely

a branch of social science, and does no more than merely furnish the law

of a single variety of human transactions. We must then look to social

science at large for the answer to the question whether there are

methods of gratifying the desire to wield great accumulations of wealth,

other than trade on the price-bearing basis, and not antagonistic to

commercial equity. As a student and teacher of social science, I can

only, at this moment, aver that such methods exist within the scope of a

true social order, and such as tend to even larger accumulations in rare

instances, and to a more undisturbed possession, than the existing order

renders possible. That subject, however,—the possibility of exceptional

instances of great wealth, especially if administered for- beneficent

uses, in a community whose trade is regulated by equity,—is a distinct

one sufficiently extensive to require separate treatment, and must be,

for the present, disposed of by this mere mention.

Let it be observed that no consideration whatsoever is given in this

article to the practical question,—to the possibility, that is to say,

and to the methods, if possible, of introducing the labor currency; of

engrafting it, so to speak, upon our present complicated civilization,

and making it the actual substitute for all other systems of currency.

It is the theoretical question only which is here considered—the

question of what is intrinsically the right and true thing, irrespective

of its feasibility. The practical question must be considered also, if a

demand arises for it, in a separate paper.

[1] The terms currency and money are generally used as synonymous. It

may be well, however, to discriminate. Boucher insists that the term

money can only apply to that which rests on the public confidence at

large and is intended to continue in circulation, whereas checks,

drafts, etc., are intended to serve on special occasions for the

convenience of individuals. There is no objection to noting this

difference, but it is not vital. It is still true that all these other

forms of paper promises which enter into commerce, and effect exchanges,

and represent values, and which in the aggregate are far the greater

part of such representative, are a portion of the currency properly so

called. Money is a distinct part of the transportation of a country; but

common roads and carriages and every other means of conveyance, down to

the dog cart and the legs of the individual walker, are also a part of

it, and in the total aggregate must be taken into the account. So, in

respect to the currency, checks, drafts, etc., must be taken into the

account as well as actual money, when the question is of arbitrarily

limiting the total bulk of the machinery of commercial exchanges.

A friend, to whom the manuscript of this article was submitted for

examination, takes the following exception, in a letter to the author,

to the latter’s statement that the issue of currency is unlimited by

law. “The Massachusetts statute-book, as well as those of most of the

other States in the Union, contains laws prohibiting, under penalties of

fines, the issue as currency of notes, bills, checks, and orders, except

such as are especially authorized by the State, United States, or

British Provinces of North America. True, these laws are not enforced;

but this is because the speculating classes have no occasion to demand

their enforcement. They are very glad to avail themselves of checks,

etc., so long as they can do so under the old plan; but, should any one

attempt to issue such money as you propose at a rate of discount just

high enough to cover the expenses of issue, thus beating the bankers on

their own ground, the laws would be enforced at once. The bankers oppose

every effort to have them removed from the statute-book.”

[2] It is the striking peculiarity of Radical Political Economy that it

emphatically denies that value, in the sense of utility, or the degree

of the purchaser's need, can rightly, i. e., equitably, have any thing

whatever to do with settling the price; the price depending (equitably)

wholly and absolutely, and exclusively, on the amount of labor invested

in the product. I cannot stop here to expound this important doctrine,

which is nevertheless matter of demonstration when the subject is

analyzed to the bottom of it. I allude to it because, if the reader

suppose that this essay is dealing with price as compounded, in an

uncertain way, of labor-cost and utility, as in ordinary political

economy, he will entirely mistake. Under the methods of Radical

Political Economy, the urgency of the purchaser's need no more affects

the price he is to pay than it affects the length of the yard-stick by

which the goods are to be measured. The price is a fixed quantity and

remains the same whether the article ever finds a purchaser or not. If

it proves unsalable at its price, it is withdrawn from the market, and,

in whatever way it may be disposed of at any other than its fixed price,

the transaction is understood to be outside of equitable commerce.

Equitable commerce is, in this respect, merely like the one-price store.