💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › stephen-pearl-andrews-the-labor-dollar.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:08:44. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Labor Dollar Author: Stephen Pearl Andrews Date: 1881 Language: en Topics: equitable commerce, labor theory of value, labor notes, money, mutual banking Source: Retrieved on 10th August 2021 from https://archive.org/details/2916966.0001.001.umich.edu/page/2/mode/2up. Notes: Published in the *Radical Review*
As the labor question is steadily and rapidly increasing in recognized
importance, every effort should be made to place its “social solutions”
upon a thoroughly scientific basis. One of these “solutions” relates
specially to the true and ultimate system of currency. I have just
received from some unknown friend, probably the author, a small pamphlet
entitled “The Labor Question: what it is, method of its solution, and
remedy for its evils,” by Charles Thomas Fowler. In it Mr. Fowler says,
with great terseness of expression and with truth, that “the birth of
the first bill of exchange was the death of the last specie dollar.”
Bills of exchange, bank checks, and negotiable paper of all sorts add
just so much to the body of the currency; and this issue is unlimited by
law, and unlimited in fact, except by the exigencies of trade.[1] They
are just as really currency as the specie dollar, the greenback, or the
bank bill. A field which has no fence upon one of its sides is not
fenced in, no matter how high and strong its fences may be on the other
sides. So, the volume of the currency is not, in any true sense, limited
by prohibitions of free banking, by a return to specie basis, or by any
other means, so long as negotiable paper can be freely issued by
individuals; and this free issue of negotiable paper is too useful, and
too well intrenched in necessity, ever hereafter to be interfered with.
Commerce can be hindered and trammeled to some extent—it may even, for a
time, be seriously disturbed—by statute arrangements claiming to
regulate the currency, whether by restrictive measures, or by flooding
the community with over-issues; but the volume of the currency can no
longer be adjusted by such means.
There is, it is true, a certain temporary advantage in the specie basis,
simply because it is traditionally believed in, and beliefs or ideas
enter into the question of the stability of values. This fact is felt by
the advocates of a specie basis. They, and others, would not have so
much of the sensation that “the bottom is all knocked out,” if we could
return to such a basis, and that confidence would go for something. On
the other hand, the sole alternative, so far as seen by the advocates of
specie basis, is a fluctuating and limitless issue from time to time of
government paper money, with no other regulation than that of an
ignorant and changeable public opinion, operated by interested political
and financial agitators and wireworkers. Such are the grounds of the
honest advocacy, so far as it is intelligent, of a return to a specie
basis.
On the other hand, the advocates of paper money and expansion have their
side of the truth. They see or feel the fallacy of the claim that specie
basis really means any thing but an illusion, knowing as they do that
gold and silver are real commodities rising and falling in value along
with all other commodities, and that they will in no event make the
whole volume of the currency, but will be only a fixed factor—in so far
as fixed—along with other changeable factors in the composition of its
total volume; a fence upon one side of a field which, on some other
side, is an open common. They also see or feel that the best currency
would be such as should have some kind of adjusted elasticity, or an
expansive and contractile quality, adapted to the fluctuating activities
of trade, of which currency is the instrument; and, in fine, that
government might, if it knew enough and were honest, subserve by its
conceded powers this demand for an adaptation between the needs of trade
and the appropriate supply of its instrument.
But, on the one hand, the supposed stability resulting from a specie
basis is a mere illusion, and one which is fast being found out and
exposed, while the remedy offered by the opponents of a specie basis is
not, in fact, the only alternative; and, on the other hand, no existing
government does know enough wisely to regulate the currency, and, as a
rule, existing governments are not honest.
The political issue about finance, now coming to the front in the United
States, and in a degree in other countries, is, therefore, on neither
side intelligent or wholly well-intentioned, while yet, on either side,
representing something of the truth. The discussion and agitation are,
nevertheless, to be hailed as among the most auspicious signs of the
times. They signify politics become educational—electioneering a
university training-school for the whole people. The community may have
to pay dearly for its instruction before it is through with this new war
of ideas ; but the right knowledge of the subject will be ultimately
evolved, and the war itself will be the opportunity of the true
teachers.
I have said that government paper is not the only alternative of a
specie basis. It is, however, the only one to which much attention has
been given; and the other—that to which I wish to call attention—will
need to be carefully elaborated and described from time to time to make
it clearly apprehended as, in fine, the science of the subject. I mean a
currency and a system of banking based directly on labor and, in a
sense, self-regulating; that is to say, regulated and administered by
individuals, or by the people themselves, without let or hindrance,
without interference or prescription from the government; although
beneficent adjustments may possibly take place between the action of the
government and this labor system of free banking.
The object of the present essay is not, however, chiefly to define or
describe either currency in its specific details, or labor banking as a
system. It is rather preliminary to those considerations, and will be
confined in a great measure to the simple ascertainment of THE UNIT OF
LABOR, which, when ascertained, may be taken as the dollar of the Labor
Bank.
Every system of thought, every science which is accurately constituted,
has what is technically called its unit, its starting-point, that from
which all its investigations take their departure, and to which they
recur as regulative of them all. Thus the unit of arithmetic is the
numerical unit, or the number one; the unit of geometry is the point, or
minim of length; the unit of weight is the pound; the unit of long
measure is the foot; the unit of mechanical force is the foot-pound; the
unit of mechanical power is the horse power; and the unit of resistance
to the transmission of electricity is the ohm. The following definitions
are furnished me by Prof. P. H. Van Der Weyde:—
A foot-pound, the unit of force or of work, is one pound weight lifted
one foot high against gravitation, the gravitation taken at the surface
of the ocean at forty-five degrees latitude. The latter two
considerations are, however, practically neglected. The element of time
in which the work is done is here left out of the account.
A horse power, the unit of power or of the amount of force exerted or
work done in a given time, is thirty-three thousand foot-pounds per
minute; that is to say, thirty-three thousand pounds lifted one foot
high per minute, or three hundred and thirty pounds lifted one hundred
feet high per minute, or five and one-half pounds one hundred feet high
per second, or fifty-five pounds ten feet high per second.
A man power is one-eighth horse power; so that a man may lift seven
pounds ten feet high per second, or four hundred and twenty pounds ten
feet per minute, or four thousand two hundred pounds one foot per
minute, or seventy pounds one foot per second.
The French unit of force is the kilogrammeter, one kilogram lifted one
meter high, or seven and two-tenths times our unit of force. A kilogram
equals two and two-tenths pounds; a meter equals nearly three and
one-third feet. A French horse power is seventy-five kilogrammeters per
second.
The ohm has been accepted by the British Association as the unit of
resistance in telegraph wires and other conductors of electricity; and
as the strength of the battery power must overcome such resistance, it
has at the same time become the measure of battery strength. The ohm is
the resistance which an electric current undergoes in passing through
one-tenth of a mile of No. 9 iron wire.
The French unit of electrical resistance is that of one meter of mercury
contained in a glass tube of one square millemeter section.
These definitions are introduced here for the purpose of showing the
pains-taking accuracy with which the student of mechanics determines his
units of measurement,—with which, in other words, he establishes
standards, or measures those things by which other things are to be
measured,—and to emphasize the statement that Radical Political Economy,
or, so to speak, this branch of Social Mechanics, will begin to be
rightly constituted as a science only when we shall have established,
with equal accuracy, the unit of labor. Unless the measure itself is
measured, there is no accuracy, no certainty, no scientific result.
By the science of Radical Political Economy I mean the science of the
laws of price-bearing wealth, as wealth should be produced and
distributed in order to secure the absolutely equitable exchange of
labor and commodities.
I say Radical Political Economy, because ordinary or current Political
Economy inquires, rather, into the laws of wealth as it is in fact
produced and distributed, with only such suggestions of improvement as
do not affect, radically, the present system. I say price-bearing
wealth, because there is much wealth which is, or should be, unpriced or
priceless; which does not, or ought not, therefore, to enter into
commerce at all, in the ordinary sense of commerce. The blessed air of
heaven, the affection we bear to lovers, children, and friends, have in
them a world of wealth to those who receive them; but they are, or
should be, a free gift, uncalculated and unmeasured by price, definite
estimate, or equivalent. Our affections are degraded when they are
reduced to the level of price-bearing commodities. It is only,
therefore, price-bearing commodities which are the subject-matter of
Radical Political Economy.
All price-bearing commodities—all, that is to say, which are rightfully
such, or which should be such—are the products of labor; and it is the
amount of labor concreted in the commodity which is the true measure of
its price,[2] This labor is sometimes called labor-cost, or the cost in
labor of producing the commodity; and it is then said that, from the
point of view of Radical Political Economy, COST IS THE LIMIT OF PRICE.
The principle is the same if the price is put directly upon the labor,
without awaiting its concretion in a commodity. Hence it follows that,
in order to obtain the true measure of cost, and so of price, and so a
true standard of exchange or trade, i. e., a true dollar as the unit of
trade,—all these being now identified with each other,—we must first
ascertain, or in some way determine upon, the unit of labor.
The first and simplest suggestion, in the inquiry after a unit of labor,
is the day's work. The hour's work is an important fraction of the day's
work, but it is not so naturally the unit as the day's work. The day's
work is, it will be found, virtually the labor dollar, and the hour's
work accords rather with the dime or bit. But a day's work is, as the
matter now stands, too indeterminate to serve as the scientific measure
of something else supposed to need measurement.
Work of any kind, in order to be accurately and completely defined, must
be determined in three aspects:—
First, as to the length of time;
Second, as to the degree of its intensity or severity;
Third, as to the degree of acquired skill, or ability previously
accumulated by other work preparatory to the work now in hand; and as to
certain other minor considerations.
The day's work, to be made standard, and to serve as the labor dollar,
or the instrument by which all other work may be measured or estimated,
must, therefore, be itself defined in all these three particulars.
First, as to the length of the standard day's work. We may take for this
purpose eight hours. It is not necessary to insist that this is
inherently the true limit of the working day, though much has been said,
and may be said, in favor of the division of the day of twenty-four
hours into three equal parts,—one for work, one for sleeping and eating,
and one for study and recreation. It suffices for our purpose to adopt
this period,—arbitrarily, if you will. Certainty is all that is
necessary. The “meter,” the scientific yard, serves sufficiently well to
measure cloth, whether it be precisely ascertained to be the
ten-millionth part (which it is intended to be) of the earth's diameter,
or not.
Next, in respect to the severity of the work; and I am here especially
indebted to Mr. Fowler for introducing the term intensity, Josiah
Warren, recognizing that the character of the work is an element of the
problem, used the phrase “the amount of repugnance overcome” to denote
the degree of hardship or burdensomeness of labor. The expression is
accurate, but, like his pounds of corn as a device for measuring labor,
it is cumbersome; and the idea is, for most purposes, better expressed
by the simple word intensity. There is another reason why the
introduction of this term, as a technicality for the purpose, is
important, and fairly entitles Mr. Fowler to claim to have enlarged and
improved the technical machinery, in this particular, of the science of
Radical Political Economy. I was never satisfied with the moderate
degree of success which Mr. Warren—or myself, in my effort to expound
Mr. Warren's ideas on this subject twenty-three years ago (see “Science
of Society”)—had achieved in attempting to make clear the nature of, and
mode of measuring, the elements of work other than the time occupied. I
struggled with the difficulty at the time, and have always felt that I
partially failed. It is Mr. Fowler's use of the term intensity in this
connection which has stimulated me to this renewal of the subject.
The special aptness of this term for this purpose, and the reason why I
deem it so important, will appear from the following considerations.
Continuity in time, mere forth-stretching in the given direction, is
called by the philosophers Protension (forth-stretching); a stretching
outward and around in all directions, as in space, is called Extension
(out- or from-stretching); and the energy of effort, by which things
are, as it were, drawn in upon and by the centering personality of the
actor, is called intensity (in-stretching). What we are dealing with is
a department of measure—the measure of labor, cost, and price; and the
metaphysicians have pointed out that these three modes are the only
three possible requisites of complete or exhaustive measurement; so that
we may, when we have thoroughly applied them, rest assured that, by such
recurrence to first principles, we have scientifically compassed the
subject. Hickok, for example, in his “Empirical Psychology,” expresses
this proposition in these terms: “No quantity can have measure in any
other directions than extension in space, duration in time (protension),
and intensity in degree; and when an act of attention has stretched over
the limits filled by the distinct quality in all these several
directions, it has determined it in all the forms which any quality can
possess, and made it to be known definitely in all its measures of
quantity.” The subject we are investigating is the quantity of labor;
and the question is: Of what does it consist in these three possible
modes of considering it?
In respect to time measure, the protensity of labor, we have said all
that is requisite at the moment. In respect to its intensity or severity
we have ascertained that this is also a proper element of the standard
day's work, and so of the measure of all work; and we must now inquire
by what standard it can itself be measured or estimated, and how,
practically, the standard can be applied. The subject is confessedly a
difficult one. All sorts of people put all sorts of different estimates
upon the relative intensity or severity of all sorts of different labor.
It may almost be said that no two agree upon any point touching the
subject. But fortunately science is now sufficiently advanced to teach
us how to overcome this difficulty. The statistical and other branches
of science have familiarized us with the method of general averages. It
is possible to tell with proximate accuracy how many persons will commit
suicide next year in London, Paris, or New York; and even how many will
choose the razor, how many the rope, how many the pistol, and how many
drowning, as the means of effecting death. It will be found possible, in
a similar way, when the world wishes to know, to ascertain how many
women think washing harder work than ironing, and how many think the
other way; and how many men would prefer to work out of doors, and how
many under shelter. All these statistics of the details of human labor,
and of the estimates which men and women make of the desirableness and
undesirableness of every given pursuit and condition, will in the future
become subjects of science, and then of practical every-day knowledge
and utility; and the labor dollar, then having come into use, will
furnish the unit of all such calculations. In that future when equity
shall give labor its own, the modes of rightly apportioning the burdens
of life will be studied with intensity, and there will be found nothing
insuperable in the nature of the problem. The first great step is to
convince the minds of men of the desirableness of such knowledge.
It should be borne in mind that, when exchanges of goods shall be made
in accordance with a known law of equity based exclusively upon
labor-cost, trade secrets, being no longer of any advantage, will be
abandoned, and all knowledge of all trades will be thrown open to all
people. There will then be greater facility among men for changing their
occupations, and for gratifying their tastes in their pursuits. This
change will also enable people to know far better than they now know
what labors they really like best, and are willing to do at the cheapest
rate. There will then grow up a legitimate labor-market, and all kinds
of labor and products will be tendered at the minimum price as measured
by the average estimate of the degree of severity of the labor involved
in them. In other words, every act of purchase and sale will then be the
result of the votes of two parties on the relative repugnance and
attractiveness of the two varieties of labor involved; and the whole
body of trade will be a continuous canvassing of all such questions. It
is so now in part, and except that ideas are confused on the subject;
that each party to every trade considers himself entitled to take
advantage of the other, which is an illegitimate element—as much so in
principle, as the sword or the slave whip thrown into the bargain; and
that no labor dollar, and therefore no instrument of adjusting
labor-cost, has hitherto existed.
Assuming, then, that by the prevalence of equity, or the true
interchange of equivalents in labor-cost, we had a full supply of
everybody's estimates of every kind of work in respect to its relative
repugnance or attractiveness,—its intensity, in fact, as hard or easy
work,—it would be easy to strike an average which should be very
exact—the true par of labor intensity; all above that average being work
of extra or plus intensity, or above par, and all below it being work of
minor intensity, or below par. We have not, it is true, as the case now
stands, the necessary data for establishing the exact par of labor
intensity; for the world has not hitherto thought it worth while to
study such facts. The best that can be done therefore, to begin with, is
to assume an average which will approach in some measure to accuracy,
and to go on constantly eliminating error and arriving at a higher
decree of precision.
Everybody has some idea of what constitutes an ordinary or average
degree of hard work. We may now, then, without attempting to fix the
idea any more definitely beforehand, further define the labor dollar as
a day's work of eight hours—of course whether male or female labor—of
the average degree of severity or intensity. I think the bare abstract
idea of an average, or par, is all that is needed, and that it is better
than Mr. Warren's corn measure. We all know sufficiently well what we
mean by “the usual degree of health," and do not have to add "as well as
Mr. A or Mr. B;” and, if we should undertake to settle the matter more
exactly in that way, we should most likely diverge at once into a
discussion over the question whether Mr. A's or Mr. B's health was of
the average degree; thus demonstrating that the bare idea of the average
is more definitely fixed in our minds than the particular state of the
health of any individual. This view does not, however, antagonize the
previous suggestion that the extended and systematic observation of
details will ultimately render the abstract idea still more definite.
If parties, in negotiating an exchange, regard their labor as of the
ordinary degree of intensity,—which would occur in the great majority of
cases, especially under the criticism of a worldful of appraisers,—that
determines the point without further parley. If, on the contrary, one or
both differ in their estimate from the average, that is matter of
negotiation. If one too much depreciates his labor, it will become, with
culture, under this system, matter of courtesy to insist on raising the
estimate. While, then, ordinarily a dollar note will be paid for the
day's work or its produce in a commodity, the price and payment may go
up to a dollar and a half, or down to the half dollar, or may deviate to
any other- degree, the dollar serving in every case as the unit of
comparison,—as, in a word, the standard of labor-cost, price, and
labor-value, which all come to be identical; value meaning in this case,
not utility, but the buying-capacity of the dollar.
To illustrate: suppose a community reduced by any cause to the primitive
condition of barter. Instead of the poor device of the
shinplaster,—referring for its measure of value to the silver or gold
dollar, which has taken its departure and is no standard,—let the labor
note be substituted. Miss Smith undertakes the teaching of the village
school. She will teach eight hours a day, and she estimates her labor as
neither above nor below the average degree of intensity as hard work.
This, then, being exactly the value of the labor dollar as above
defined, Miss Smith charges one dollar—a labor dollar—a day for her
work. She has an average of twenty pupils. For each pupil the parents
become, therefore, indebted to Miss Smith the twentieth part of a
dollar, or one half labor dime, or five labor cents, per day; and they
pay her in their own labor notes, or in the labor dollars, dimes, and
cents which have come into their hands from their trade with others. The
labor money bills only differ from every body's individual notes written
on common paper in the fact that the storekeeper or postmaster has got
up his own notes in better style, printed and perhaps vignetted, and
issues them in the place of the common written scraps of paper.' These
he keeps in his safe instead, as his specie basis, they being the
immediate representative of the labor of the village, so far as it is in
market. As fast as the work promised is done, or its equivalent given in
products, the notes are redeemed and cancelled, or re-issued, and the
transaction is ended.
In this manner Miss Smith gets her entire pay in good labor dollars.
These will command every body's work and buy every thing produced in the
village. Dealing with the outside world involves an extension of the
problem which will not be considered at this point. The school teacher
may, in turn, to the extent of her credit, and wishing to anticipate
returns, issue her labor notes, transmutable into labor dollars by the
village banker —the postmaster or store-keeper, as before stated. In
this manner she, and every one in the village, becomes a capitalist to
the extent to which their neighbors have confidence in their future
ability and intention to fulfil their promises; and so, able to create
loan's for themselves at any moment to this extent; checked in the first
instance by any lack of confidence on the part of the immediate
neighbors, and then on the part of the village banker, who must have
confidence also before he will receive the individual's labor note and
replace it by his own issue. Thus a healthy and continuous vigilance
will be exerted over this otherwise perfectly free creation of the labor
bullion of our new banking system. Risk and actual losses will, however,
occur ; but they will be reduced to a minimum by the natural working of
the system; and the village banker will become an insurance agent to
cover them, being allowed to increase the currency beyond the bullion in
deposit the slight percentage found practically necessary to that end.
Apart from this percentage to cover losses,—which will be kept at the
lowest, as it will be added under the immediate inspection of the whole
village, each individual being constantly taxed his proportion of every
loss,—the village banker is not to be allowed to issue a single labor
dollar for which he has not the same amount of labor bullion—the labor
notes of the people—in deposit; including, however, his own labor notes
covering his services, and issued on the same terms as those of any
other citizen. Every over-issue should be deemed a fraud, and prevented
or remedied by well-devised checks upon the conduct of the banker,—such
as numbers on the bills issued, reports and inspections of committees,
etc.,—until confidence is so established as to dispense with unnecessary
caution. The banking office will be open to competition in respect to
the best management, like any other business. If a dozen bankers spring
up in the village, no matter.
Another element remains to be added in the constitution of the labor
dollar,—one which has been alluded to above, and then purposely
postponed until now. This is what we will technically call the Extensity
of the day's work,—an element which extends beyond, or goes outside of,
the particular day upon which the work is to be done. This element is
the acquired skill of the laborer, secured by previous labor fitting him
to do the work; the wear and tear of instruments or tools of his own,
which he brings into the work; particular risks of any kind assumed by
the laborer, etc. This item is fixed also by averages and the mutual
estimates of the parties contracting.
Prior labor giving skill is to be estimated upon the same principle as
other labor; but, the cost being distributed by estimate to all who will
be ever likely to avail themselves of the skill, it becomes generally a
small item in the individual case: such as it is, however, to be settled
by the estimates of the worker and employer, or tacitly covered by the
general price demanded for the day's work. So with the other matters
included under this head. All legitimate risks are legitimately covered
by an augmentation of price.
It is a curious working of this equitable system of exchanges that,
while acquired skill involving prior labor is an element of the price of
labor, superior natural ability—“the gift of God”— is left wholly out of
the account, and does not in any manner augment the price. This is a
point which is more frequently than any other misunderstood, and which,
when understood, is most likely to meet with objection from new
investigators of equity. A little close attention to it, however, will
remove all difficulty. It is undoubtedly true that superior natural
ability does give a natural advantage, which the possessor may, if he
will, and which at present he does, avail himself of in disposing of his
labor. The question now is, however, whether he ought really to do so;
or, in other words, whether the gift of Nature to the individual is
something entirely for his selfish individual benefit, or something in
which his weaker competitor especially, and the public at large, should
participate.
It is certain that the principle of equity, as rightly defined,—the
exchange of equivalent burdens, or of equivalent amounts of repugnance
overcome,—gives nothing for that which costs nothing. The handsome woman
degrades herself if she makes a charge for exhibiting her beauty. It is
wealth to the world, as it is also to herself, but not price-bearing
wealth; not an object of ordinary commerce or trade. Ought it not to be
the same with superior natural talents and endowments of all kinds? On
the race-course and in the prize-ring, where the object is—as here, in
respect to equity—to neutralize all undue advantages, it is not merely
the swiftest horse or the strongest man, pure and simple, who takes the
prize. All advantages are first equalized by granting to the weaker
party compensating advantages. The “light weight,” when pitted against a
bigger man, has a due concession made to him on account of his obvious
inferiority.
Should not laborers, in seeking equity for themselves, be ready to abide
by the behests of equity throughout; when it works against, as well as
when it works for, them? Should not the world's workers come to be as
generous, as honorable, as just, at least, as racers and prize-fighters?
No pugilist would call it a fair fight when a big fellow knocked down a
little one merely because Nature gave him the superior ability; merely,
in other words, because he could do it. No gamester would refuse to give
odds to one less versed than himself in the game. Curiously enough,
these are almost the only people who have ever been dealing with the
question of what is fair play in any competitive engagement of man with
his fellow. Ordinary political economy never asks the question, but only
inquires to what extent, and by what means, the big fellows actually get
the advantage; what are the laws and operations, in other words, of the
natural tendency to advantage-getting.
In those departments of life where courtesy is established, there is no
doubt on this question. If a weak woman burdened with a child is allowed
to stand in a crowded place, and strong men sit at their ease, it is
justly regarded as an outrage upon decency; and yet the strong men would
only be availing themselves of their natural advantages.
In a word, on principle, the question is settled beyond all doubt that
equity, in establishing prices, grants nothing on the ground of natural
superiority,—therein concurring with the principles of fair dealing as
understood in games, and of courtesy as understood in society. But
still, with our present habits of thought, the verdict may seem a harsh
one; and many persons will perhaps be more readily convinced if made to
see that the principle will work well in practice, than by the mere
sternness of the logic. This well-working of the principle is also
readily shown. But first, let us conclude our definition of the labor
dollar as the measure of radical equity.
The labor dollar is then, in fine, a vignetted paper representative,—or
its equivalent,—signed and issued by a labor banker, of a day's work, of
man, woman, or child, of eight hours' duration, of average intensity and
average extensity.
The general aspect of the labor dollar may be similar to that of a
current dollar bill more or less elaborately devised. Paper will be the
ordinary material, although it would not cease to fulfil the conditions
if some other available substance—as parchment for instance—were used
instead. Its cost and the labor of signing, issuing, cancelling,
renewing, etc., belong to expenses, and can be repaid to the banker,
equitably estimated, along with all other labor.
A promise of labor to the same amount signed by an individual not a
banker, not vignetted, etc., would pass under the more general
designation of “a labor note.” Together, and with all accessory
commercial paper of the same order, they would constitute the labor
currency.
The labor notes of the people, in the safe or vaults of the banker,
securing him in making his promises to render so much labor, or its
equivalent in products, are what I have denominated labor bullion.
Trade or commerce conducted on this basis may be denominated labor
trade; and the transactions of this trade, with the ruling rates for
different kinds of labor, will come to be rightly known as the labor
market; and the labor rates of every species of men's and women's labor,
down to minutiae, will be regularly quoted.
The radical, indeed the revolutionary, difference between a currency
based on this simple device and any previously existing currency may
still escape the reader, unless he again reflects that the labor dollar
means something defined, and therefore definite, and that the current
dollar means something wholly undefined and indefinite. Consider the
difference in this respect between a common token, such as a theatre
ticket or a railroad ticket, and a paper, or even a silver, dollar. The
token obtained to-day will purchase a seat in the theatre or the car
to-day, tomorrow, or six months hence: that is to say, it represents a
definite something, or, in other words, a fixed and ascertained
purchasing-power. Not so with the dollar, whether paper or metallic. You
may know what you can buy with them to-day, but what they will procure
for you to-morrow, a week hence, or six months hence:,you cannot know,
as their value may have fluctuated within any limits; in other words,
they have no fixed or ascertained, or ascertainable, purchasing-power.
The labor dollar has, then, the character of the fixed token, as
contrasted with that of our present currency; or the character of a
measure which is itself measured, as contrasted with an elastic
yard-stick, or the hand or foot used as a pound weight.
In an article on finance by Mr. McCulloch, ex-Secretary of the Treasury,
he says:
“There being but one universally recognized measure of value, and that
being a value in itself, costing what it represents in the labor which
is required to obtain it, the nation that adopts, either from choice or
temporary necessity, an inferior standard violates the financial law of
the world, and inevitably suffers for its violation. An irredeemable,
and consequently depreciated, currency drives out of circulation the
currency superior to itself; and if made by law a legal tender, while
its real value is not thereby enhanced, it becomes a false and
demoralizing standard, under the influence of which prices advance in a
ratio disproportioned even to its actual depreciation. Very different
from this is that gradual, healthy, and general modification of prices
which is the effect of the increase of the precious metals."
What is here said of the relative fixedness of paper and metallic
currency, which would be in a degree true if the comparison were with a
currency to consist of the precious metals and nothing else—which is not
pretended,—applies as a condemnatory criticism upon all systems of
finance which exist or have existed; and the encomium can only be
conferred rightly on the labor currency, which has the characteristics
insisted on in a still higher degree than the metals alone would have
them.
In the above definition of the labor dollar the day's work of a child is
estimated at the same as that of a man or a woman. This will be apt to
strike the investigator at first as erroneous, but he has only to recur
to the principle to perceive that it is strictly accurate. The severity,
or repugnance overcome, in keeping a child eight hours intensely at
work, is almost sure to be as great as, and is most likely to be much
greater than, that of so employing the time of a grown person; and by
our principle, it is this severity endured which is to be compensated or
equalized by the price paid for the labor. Such is, in other words,
precisely all that price can rightfully mean.
What, in the next place, would be the working results of this principle
upon the labor of children? Just this: as children's labor would have to
be paid as much as, or more than, that of grown people,—except when
employed at those light and pleasing labors which for them would
resemble play,—no employer would engage children for hard and unsuitable
work, except in cases of urgency or peculiar necessity; and then he
would submit to compensate them appropriately, according to the
principle. Children would then be, as it were, driven out of the labor
market (except in the emergencies above referred to); which means,
however, nothing more than that employers would prefer, if practicable,
to secure the heavier and harder variety of labor when it was at the
same time lower priced than the other; and secondly, that children would
be thereby left free for acquiring education, and for play or
untrammeled exercise, which is precisely what should happen. In other
words, children and grown people would be relegated, respectively, by
the working of a simple principle, to their true places,—a drift which
would co-operate exactly with what is now the effort of wise and
benevolent parents and guardians.
The case of children conducts us back to the question, reserved above,
of the similar working of the principle in denying pay for superior
endowments, which, as a portion of natural wealth, are by the theory
non-price-bearing commodities. Here also it will be found that the
effect is quietly to force every body—not now children alone—into their
true places; being in fact, thereby, one of the greatest of social
solutions. Under the principle, the best endowed and most efficient
labor comes into competition with inferior labor in each special branch,
not, as now, at a higher price, nor even at the same price, but
absolutely at a lower price. Of course, then, it will force itself in,
and force the inferior labor out. Let this be well understood. He who
should have the greatest natural fitness for a particular kind of work,
having greater facility in it, will—with some exceptions only—have also
the greatest attraction or fondness for that kind of industry. His
estimate of its intensity will therefore be less than that of other men.
In other words, it will not be as hard work for him as for them, and,
therefore, under this new principle, his price will be less. Of course,
then, he will be preferred, and those for whom it is harder work or more
burdensome will be set aside. The very best workmen will first be taken
up by the employers; then the second best; then the third best; and,
finally, and under necessity only, the poorer qualities; which, however,
if called in, will be paid the higher prices, as in the case of the
children. There is, even as matters now stand, a natural preference, of
course, among employers for superior workmen; but this preference is
nearly neutralized, and sometimes inverted, by the fact that such labor
must have the largest prices; so that poor laborers are about as readily
retained, and sometimes more so, than the superior ones, whereby the
survival-of-the-fittest principle is defeated, and the general quality
of products depreciated.
This paying of the best workmen the lowest prices upsets, of course, all
existing notions. It is a difficult point both for unphilosophical and
for selfish minds. It is, nevertheless, not only abstractly right, but
replete with the best possible results. It is on the road to the
reduction of all price to zero, or to the time when all labor shall be
play, and shall be exchanged for love without price. But far short of
this, and immediately, these results follow: 1. All labor will be
performed—as a rule—by the best workmen and with the utmost efficiency,
and, consequently, all products will be carried up to the highest
excellence. 2. All prices will be brought down to the minimum, or to the
very cheapest at which the labor, or the product, can be afforded
—tending to place both necessaries and luxuries within the reach of all,
3. Every body will be gently and unconsciously forced into just those
pursuits for which they are best suited, and for which they have most
liking; in other words, Attractive Industry will be in a great measure
realized. What could be asked for better than all this?
Upon this third point a word should be added. The inferior workman,
forced out of an employment, may and often will prove to be the superior
workman in some other; so that to be driven out of the labor market only
means, in fact, being transferred to something better, until the whole
world shall be employed at just that which it likes best to do.
A fourth result, perhaps the most important of them all, will be to
substitute a PRINCIPLE for the settlement of prices instead of the
system of universal higgling and overreaching which now prevails; a
civilized and scientific, instead of a barbarous, method. If war may be
defined as an inflammatory social fever tending to the surface, trade
for profit, by bargaining, may be regarded as the low or typhoid form of
the same, a disguised and diffused fever, a state of modified war of all
against all. This greatest effect of equity would then be to substitute
interstitial peace for a universal state of interstitial warfare in
society, opening the way to all kinds of beneficent cooperation in the
place of an antagonistic individuality.
It must not, however, after all has been said, be concluded that the
mere operation of the principle, “labor-cost the limit of price,” will
fulfil all the conditions of social harmony, and supply of itself the
true social organization. It is simply a plank in the ship, or, if you
will, the keel; but it is not the whole structure. Nor will it prove,
taken alone, altogether satisfactory. A society constituted merely under
the operation of this principle would, indeed, secure a genial and
beneficent equity, but it would also lead to a certain dead-levelism of
conditions which would lack an element of picturesqueness and variety
which the human mind also craves.
Nobody could ever become very rich; but the level prairie, or the
fertile plains of Lombardy, would prove dull, if the whole world had
nothing else to exhibit. Security of condition and a sense of prevailing
justice in life, while they are a basis of happiness, are only a basis.
The human soul has legitimate aspirations for distinction, preeminence,
largeness of individual environment, and the means of great and
beneficent achievement, which may demand the possession of exceptional
wealth of the acquired and price-bearing variety, as well as mere
natural endowment. These aspirations the existing order of society does,
to a considerable extent, gratify; but it does so at the expense of a
general denial of equity, and of a consequent all-prevalent irritation,
ending in the insecurity of the very wealth so acquired. Equity is,
therefore, a question of method, of economy, and of security, as well as
a question of the just distribution of wealth. The demand for some
opportunity for larger acquisitions than are afforded by mere equity is,
nevertheless, a true voice of the soul, and the supposition that the
doctrine of equity completely forbids any such aspiration is one of the
greatest hindrances to its acceptance. There is a secret repugnance to
the doctrine left in the mind, despite the logical cogency which may
compel an intellectual assent. This comes, however, entirely of
misapprehension. It is not essential that a devotion to exact and
technical equity should predominate in all human transactions. What the
doctrine affirms is merely that, by bargain and traffic regulated by
equity, large fortunes could not be acquired, while every body under the
operation of that principle might become measurably rich. It stops at
this. It does not concern itself with any other class of transactions
among men, neither denying nor affirming the possibility of acquiring
exceptional wealth by other methods. This particular doctrine is merely
a branch of social science, and does no more than merely furnish the law
of a single variety of human transactions. We must then look to social
science at large for the answer to the question whether there are
methods of gratifying the desire to wield great accumulations of wealth,
other than trade on the price-bearing basis, and not antagonistic to
commercial equity. As a student and teacher of social science, I can
only, at this moment, aver that such methods exist within the scope of a
true social order, and such as tend to even larger accumulations in rare
instances, and to a more undisturbed possession, than the existing order
renders possible. That subject, however,—the possibility of exceptional
instances of great wealth, especially if administered for- beneficent
uses, in a community whose trade is regulated by equity,—is a distinct
one sufficiently extensive to require separate treatment, and must be,
for the present, disposed of by this mere mention.
Let it be observed that no consideration whatsoever is given in this
article to the practical question,—to the possibility, that is to say,
and to the methods, if possible, of introducing the labor currency; of
engrafting it, so to speak, upon our present complicated civilization,
and making it the actual substitute for all other systems of currency.
It is the theoretical question only which is here considered—the
question of what is intrinsically the right and true thing, irrespective
of its feasibility. The practical question must be considered also, if a
demand arises for it, in a separate paper.
[1] The terms currency and money are generally used as synonymous. It
may be well, however, to discriminate. Boucher insists that the term
money can only apply to that which rests on the public confidence at
large and is intended to continue in circulation, whereas checks,
drafts, etc., are intended to serve on special occasions for the
convenience of individuals. There is no objection to noting this
difference, but it is not vital. It is still true that all these other
forms of paper promises which enter into commerce, and effect exchanges,
and represent values, and which in the aggregate are far the greater
part of such representative, are a portion of the currency properly so
called. Money is a distinct part of the transportation of a country; but
common roads and carriages and every other means of conveyance, down to
the dog cart and the legs of the individual walker, are also a part of
it, and in the total aggregate must be taken into the account. So, in
respect to the currency, checks, drafts, etc., must be taken into the
account as well as actual money, when the question is of arbitrarily
limiting the total bulk of the machinery of commercial exchanges.
A friend, to whom the manuscript of this article was submitted for
examination, takes the following exception, in a letter to the author,
to the latter’s statement that the issue of currency is unlimited by
law. “The Massachusetts statute-book, as well as those of most of the
other States in the Union, contains laws prohibiting, under penalties of
fines, the issue as currency of notes, bills, checks, and orders, except
such as are especially authorized by the State, United States, or
British Provinces of North America. True, these laws are not enforced;
but this is because the speculating classes have no occasion to demand
their enforcement. They are very glad to avail themselves of checks,
etc., so long as they can do so under the old plan; but, should any one
attempt to issue such money as you propose at a rate of discount just
high enough to cover the expenses of issue, thus beating the bankers on
their own ground, the laws would be enforced at once. The bankers oppose
every effort to have them removed from the statute-book.”
[2] It is the striking peculiarity of Radical Political Economy that it
emphatically denies that value, in the sense of utility, or the degree
of the purchaser's need, can rightly, i. e., equitably, have any thing
whatever to do with settling the price; the price depending (equitably)
wholly and absolutely, and exclusively, on the amount of labor invested
in the product. I cannot stop here to expound this important doctrine,
which is nevertheless matter of demonstration when the subject is
analyzed to the bottom of it. I allude to it because, if the reader
suppose that this essay is dealing with price as compounded, in an
uncertain way, of labor-cost and utility, as in ordinary political
economy, he will entirely mistake. Under the methods of Radical
Political Economy, the urgency of the purchaser's need no more affects
the price he is to pay than it affects the length of the yard-stick by
which the goods are to be measured. The price is a fixed quantity and
remains the same whether the article ever finds a purchaser or not. If
it proves unsalable at its price, it is withdrawn from the market, and,
in whatever way it may be disposed of at any other than its fixed price,
the transaction is understood to be outside of equitable commerce.
Equitable commerce is, in this respect, merely like the one-price store.