đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș stirner-the-wise-guy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:11:05. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Stirner, the Wise Guy Author: Wolfi Landstreicher Date: 2017 Language: en Topics: Max Stirner, egoism, Hegel, egoist, Wolfi Landstreicher, taoism, Source: https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/max-stirner-the-unique-and-its-property
Almost every scholar of Stirner, whether self-taught or
university-trained, insists on referring to the author of The Unique...
as a philosopher. I canât recall Stirner ever referring to himself as
such, and certainly, by the time he wrote his book, he had concluded
that philosophy was a joke that its purveyors took far too seriously,
buffoonery deserving only laughter. And to call the mocker of philosophy
a philosopher is as absurd as calling the impious atheist[1] a
theologian.
Philosophers pursue answers in the ultimate senseâuniversal answers. And
so they are, indeed, lovers of wisdom. They conceive of wisdom as
something objective, as something that exists in itself, beyond any
individual, and so as something they have to pursue, rather than as
their own property, their attribute, to use as they see fit. They are
still attached to the idea of a âwisdomâ that is greater than them, you
or me. Stirner called them âpious atheists,â a particularly biting barb
in a country where the most extreme Christians were known as âpietists.â
So long as a person continues to pursue this external, supposedly
universal wisdom, he may well be a wise man (whatever that means), but
he will never be a wise guy. Stirner was a wise guy, because he
recognized that there is no ultimate, universal wisdom to find; the
philosopherâs goal is a pipe dream worthy only of mockery and laughter.
And Stirner mocked and laughed often in the most delightfully crude ways
in his writings. Unfortunately, both his critics and his disciples have
largely missed the joke.[2] And explaining a joke is never as much fun
as playing the joke. Hence, Stirnerâs increasing exasperation (still
humorously and even savagely expressed) in Stirnerâs Critics and âThe
Philosophical Reactionaries.â
Despite the tedium of explaining a joke, I will make the effort to do so
to some extent, largely because some who have taken Stirner too
literally and seriously have drawn the most ridiculous conclusions about
him and those rebels who have found his writings useful in developing
their own rebellious thought.
To begin with, Stirner is mocking philosophy itself. This is evident in
his comments on Socrates in The Unique and Its Property, as well as in
âThe Philosophical Reactionaries.â Though he certainly aimed his
laughter most fiercely at the philosophy and the philosophers of Germany
in his timeâHegel, his precursors, his disciples and his âleft
Hegelianâ[3] criticsâStirnerâs mocking, playful logic undermines the
whole of the philosophical project, leaving no place for metaphysics,
ontology, ethics, etc., beyond an individualâs own personal preferences
in behavior.
The main focus of his mockery is the Hegelian method, as this had become
the dominant philosophical method in Germany at the time Stirner lived.
And his joke is woven throughout this book. First of all, he carefully
constructed the outline of The Unique to parallel that of Hegelâs The
Phenomenology of the Spirit and Feuerbachâs The Essence of Christianity,
while undermining the foundations of both works. Some scholars have
called him the ultimate Hegelian, because he makes use of Hegelâs
dialectical method[4] in his book. However, in âThe Philosophical
Reactionaries,â Stirner explains that this too was part of the joke: âDo
you philosophers actually have an inkling that you have been beaten with
your own weapons? Nothing but an inkling. What retort can you hearty
fellows make against it, when I again dialectically demolish what you
have just dialectically put up? You have shown me with what âeloquenceâ
one can make all into nothing and nothing into all, black into white and
white into black. What do you have against it, when I turn your neat
trick back on you? But with the dialectical trick of a philosophy of
nature, neither you nor I will cancel the great facts of modern natural
research, no more than Schelling and Hegel did.â[5] Stirner chose to use
the methods of those he was mocking to undermine what they claimed those
methods showed, not because he believed in those methods, but because he
wanted to show that, at best, they were mere intellectual tools, ones
that could be turned to damn near any use in the realm of ideas.
In fact, what Stirner has to say leaves no room for any sort of
universal or historical progress, dialectical or otherwise. It is no
accident that Stirner begins and ends his book with the same words,
taken from Goetheâs poem âVanitas! Vanitatum Vanitas!â I have translated
these words (fairly literally) as: âI have based my affair on nothing.â
Goetheâs poem has the feel of a drinking song, something friends might
sing laughingly together at a bar. Stirnerâs use of it at the beginning
and the end of the book was a way of saying, âIâm having fun, and thatâs
all that matters, so donât take any of this too seriously.â And what he
proposesâfully aware self-enjoyment and self-creation for your own
enjoymentâare as thoroughly ahistorical and anti-progressive (in any
universal or historical sense) as moralists and ideologues of the left
and right may claim. But this is what makes his proposal genuinely
rebellious and genuinely anti-authoritarian. Because history and
progress have always been the history and the progress of ruling powers
who want everyone to live for them and the ideals and values they
impose.
In light of Stirnerâs anti-historical, anti-progressive, thoroughly
in-the-moment, self-centered perspective, readers need to realize that
any talk of historical processes and any apparently progressive
descriptions in Stirnerâs book are part of the joke, part of his mockery
of the positions he is tearing apart. I recently read a pamphlet[6] in
which one of the writers assumes that the section in The Unique entitled
âA Human Lifeâ expresses Stirnerâs view of how individuals develop. But
in the very title of this section, Stirner gave us a heavy-handed hint
that this is not his viewpoint, that it is part of the joke. Though
Stirnerâs mockery is an attack on all fixed ideas, on all ideals placed
above each unique being and his self-enjoyment, its central attack is on
the humanism that Feuerbach, Bruno and Edgar Bauer (and the other
âcritical criticsâ), and the various liberals and radicals of the time,
put forward as the replacement for christianity and theism. When Stirner
speaks of a âhuman life,â he is not talking about his life, your life,
my life, or the life of âhumanityâ in general[7] (since for Stirner,
âhumanityâ itself is a mere phantasmâas he explicitly says more than
once). He is telling the reader who gets the joke that he is presenting
a caricatured, mocking perspective of how his opponents view human
development, with the intent of twisting it against them.
In the same way, the picture Stirner presented of a supposed historical
progress in âPart I: Humanityâ (and particularly in âThe Hierarchy) was
not his own perspective on history. Stirner was quite intentionally
ahistorical. Instead he was making a mockery of Hegelâs dialectically
progressive view of history in order to twist it back on those who used
this Hegelian view to support their perspectives. The apparent racial
hierarchy found in the perspective Stirner was mocking comes straight
out of Hegel[8] (though Hegel, like most of the progressive thinkers of
the time, did not understand race biologically and assumed all humanity
could eventually achieve the progressive transformation in which he
believed), and Stirnerâs mockery is a delightfully politically incorrect
joke on the cultural hierarchy Hegel assumed. Stirnerâs playful argument
is that, even if you assume that there is a history that progresses, by
Hegelâs own logic, you have to end up back at egoism. All that progress
wonât bring us anywhere else... And his attribution of âMongolismâ to
his German contemporaries shows that even one of his tactics for
avoiding the censors (using âChinaâ or âJapanâ instead of âGermanyâ
whenever he was making a critical reference to the German authorities of
his time) was part of the joke.
In fact, Stirner may well have been making a deeper joke here. I
realized on my first reading of Byingtonâs translation of Stirner that
there were many parallels between Stirnerâs ideas and aspects of taoism
and buddhism. Already, in 1906, Alexandra David-Neel[9] compared
Stirnerâs ideas to those of the taoist Yang-Chou. Stirner emphasized the
transience of each individual and rejected any crystallized, permanent
âIâ as much as any other permanent idea, seeing it as yet another
phantasm. He saw getting beyond the limits of thought as a necessary
part of living fully as oneâs transient self here and now. He saw
self-enjoyment as most fully achieved in self-forgetfulness. And in
Stirnerâs Critics, he spoke of the unique (der Einzige) in ways quite
similar to those used to speak of the tao in the Tao Te Ching: âStirner
names the unique and says at the same time ânames donât name it.â He
utters a name when he names the unique, and adds that the unique is only
a name. ... What Stirner says is a word, a thought, a concept; what he
means is neither a word, nor a thought, nor a concept. What he says is
not the meaning, and what he means cannot be said.â[10] Was Stirner
aware of these similarities? I donât know which of Hegelâs lectures
Stirner attended while he was at the university in Berlin, but I have
confirmed that Hegel gave lectures on Eastern philosophy. This indicates
that buddhist, taoist, and other Eastern writings were available in
Germany at the time. And I would like to think that Stirner read some of
these and, as is appropriate for an egoistic self-creator, took what he
found appealing and useful from these writings to enhance his own way of
living and viewing the world. If so, this adds a certain ironic depth to
his play on German âmongolism.â
I could go on trying to explain more of Stirnerâs jokes, more of his
humor, his sarcasm, his mockery, but as I said above, explaining jokes
is never as much fun as making them. For Stirner, there was no ultimate
aim of history, no inherent progress, and so for him the dialectic could
never be anything more than a tool. The use he found for this tool was
precisely that of using the dialectic to undermine the dialectic. And
this worked best through mockery and sarcasm. Stirner was a thoroughly
impious atheist, what I like to call a barefisted atheist. He had no
need or desire for a god in his life, not even some ultimate
crystallized âIâ to be achieved, and he was willingâand in fact took
pleasure inâaccepting the full implications of his godlessness. Without
a god there is no basis for morality; without a god there is no basis
for the sacred; without a god there is no universal meaning, no
universal aim, no universal purpose; in fact, no universal universe. The
universe is an absurdity. The only meanings, aims, purposes, and
universes are the very ephemeral, transient ones that individuals create
for themselves. In the face of this overall absurdity, you could choose
to ignore it and assume the universality of your own meanings, thus
becoming what Stirner called a âduped egoistâ; this is the path typical
of the religious (including ideologues like Marx and his followers,
Hitler and his, or Mises[11] and his). You could let it overwhelm you
and fall into a new religion of cosmic pessimism, where the absurdity is
a horrifying god (whether you call it by that name or not), and so again
become a âduped egoist.â Or you could do what Stirner did and see the
humor in the ultimate absurdity, recognizing that this lack of universal
meaning and purpose is what gives you and I the capacity to willfully
create our lives for ourselves. Stirner willfully grasped his own
self-creative power and took aim at all that was considered sacred with
the intention of demolishing it. He knew the best weapon for demolishing
the sacred is mocking laughter. Instead of being a wise man, Stirner
chose to be a wise guy, and if you donât get the joke, the jokes on
you...
[1] As opposed to both the theist and the pious âatheistsâ who replace
god with another deity.
[2] No one who got the joke could ever be a disciple of Stirner, since
he provided no answers, nothing whatsoever to believe in, nothing more
than some tools for undermining all belief, all fixed thought.
[3] This term was not one used by any of those given the label, but one
imposed later by historians of philosophy to make it easier to
distinguish these mid-nineteenth-century critics of Hegel from the more
orthodox followers of Hegel. A number of them were friends or at least
associates in groups like die Freien (the Free Ones), who met in
Hippelâs wine bar. Stirner took part in this group.
[4] I specifically say âHegelâs dialectical method,â because his
dialectic was a very specific, progressive formulation which was
supposed to achieve an ultimate synthesis at the end of history, unlike
the ancient Greek dialectic which simply referred to ongoing discussion
of ideas with no final culmination.
[5] Stirner, Max, âThe Philosophical Reactionaries,â in Stirnerâs
Critics (translated by Wolfi Landstreicher), pp. 106â107, LBC Books and
CAL Press, 2012.
[6] Max Stirnerâs Political Spectrography (Spectral Emissions, Seattle,
2015), by Fabian Ludueña, introduction by Alejandro de Acosta.
[7] To use the phrase of Alejandro de Acosta, âa more or less
intentional gesture towards a prehistoric anthropogenic momentâ (ibid.,
p. vii).
[8] See particularly Hegelâs Encyclopaedia and History of Philosophy.
[9] Best known for her adventures wandering in Tibet and her writings on
Tibetan buddhism that sprang from these adventures, Alexandra David-Neel
was a young friend of Elisée Reclus and sometimes wrote for anarchist
publications. In âThe Theory of the Individual in Chinese Philosophy:
Yang-Chou,â she compared the ideas of an early (and somewhat
controversial) taoist, Yang-Chou, to those of Stirner. This essay can be
found in Neither Lord nor Subject: Anarchism and Eastern Thought, Enemy
Combatant Publications, 2016.
[10] Stirner, Max, op. cit., p. 54, p. 55.
[11] Ludwig von Mises was one of the major theorists of the Austrian
school of economics, an extreme laissez-faire school of economic theory.
The proponents of this school of economic thought remain thoroughly
mired in Aristotelian thinking and so assume that Reason (in an
absolute, unitary sense) provides the best understanding of economic
forces at play. For this reason, they remain as religious in their
thinking as marxists. A number of Libertarians, anarcho-capitalists, and
other free-market anarchists adhere to the doctrines of the Austrian
school.