💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › alexander-green-stirner-and-marx.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:05:02. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Stirner and Marx
Author: Alexander Green
Date: 2006
Language: en
Topics: egoism, Karl Marx, Max Stirner, Non Serviam
Source: Retrieved 06/15/2022 from https://web.archive.org/web/20080509100427/http://www.nonserviam.com/magazine/issues/23.html

Alexander Green

Stirner and Marx

Max Stirner: a historiographical sketch

The impact of Max Stirner’s The Ego and Its Own (1844)[1] on the modern

European thought has been strangely neglected. Few other figures in the

history of philosophy have been as systematically misread,

misunderstood, suppressed and pigeonholed as that of Max Stirner. He has

been labelled an anarchist, a nihilist, a crude “proto-Nietzsche” and

his influence constantly overlooked by both philosophical movements and

intellectual historians alike. Whilst there is no direct recipient of

Stirner’s version of egoism, it appears to exert a diffuse yet

substantial influence on modern philosophical thought. Identifying the

ultimate or unintended beneficiaries of Stirner’s ideas is challenging.

Recognition of his only major work emerged half a century after its

conception when The Egosurfaced in a range of intellectual projects,

recently including feminism and postmodernism. What is paradoxical about

Stirner’s impact is that his most critical influence – on the work of

Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, has been obscured from the field of

intellectual history. Stirner’s official role in the philosophically

fraught period which saw the birth of historical materialism (1844–5)

was relegated to more “deviant tributaries” of European philosophy.[2]

Despite its apparent distinctiveness, The Ego was very much a product of

the milieu of the eighteen forties and of the Left Hegelian movement in

particular. Ironically, it is in this context that some of the most

genuine praise for Stirner’s surprising contribution to Left Hegelianism

was voiced, despite the critique of the group’s theoretical leaders that

had prompted The Ego. “The Free Ones” (hereafter Die Freien) were a

group of radical Berlin publicists, poets and philosophers who gathered

daily in Hippel’s Weinstube; many of its members were imbued with

revolutionary fervour, others were simply inebriated.[3] The group’s

leaders were the Bauer brothers, Bruno and Edgar. Marx, Engels and the

poets Herwegh and Hoffmann von Fallersleben were occasional

visitors.Hence Bauer’s later characterisation of the group as Berlin’s

“beer literati”.[4] Ludwig Feuerbach, Moses Hess, Ludwig Bühl, Adolf

Rutenberg, Eduard Meyen, and Julius Faucher also frequented Hippel’s.

Arnold Ruge, the self-appointed godfather of these Hegelians, carried on

nightly debates which were often very bitter.[5] Engels gives a

description of Stirner at such a gathering in his comic poem “The

Triumph of Faith”:

[Fig. I: Pencil sketch by Engels, Stirner stands on the middle right,

leaning against the table. He is a lonely figure: highbrowed,

bespectacled and smoking a cigarette. For Engels illustrated letters

see: Zwischen 18 und 25 Jugend Briefe von Friedrich Engels.]

Die Freien were the last remnants of Bruno Bauer’s “Doktorklub” – the

same club had once counted Marx as a member. Stirner cannot have joined

before the end of 1841. At that time the young Marx was leaving for

Paris and, as a result, the two were never to meet. Stirner spent most

of 1843 completing The Ego; it was published in November of 1844. For

English readers, the English-Latin word ego comes constrained by nuances

of a possible Freudian or Protestant analysis. However a careful reading

suggests that “The Unique One & His Property” (or Own-ness) would better

elucidate Stirner’s intentions. “The Unique One” might be best

understood as the individual self, not in opposition to later concepts

of the Freudian id or libido or even the “spirit” or “soul”, but as a

certain kind of absolute. The Ego immediately established Stirner as one

of the most formidable opponents of the very people with whom he had

seemed to have so much in common. Communists, critical philosophers,

humanitarians and reformers of every degree were attacked in Stirner’s

philosophy, a philosophy that Engels labelled “Egoism”.[6]) Among the

Young Hegelians, Bauer, Ruge, Moses Hess and even the famous Feuerbach

joined forces in order to combat what they saw as the menacing nihilism

of Stirner’s egoism.

Bruno Bauer and Szeliga both wrote articles, Feuerbach also replied.

Hess wrote an essay whilst Marx and Engels wrote the best part of a

book.[7] All seemed happy to admit Stirner was an adversary of note.

Bauer wrote that Stirner was “the most capable and courageous of all

combatants” of his own theory of “pure criticism”,[8] whereas Feuerbach

described Stirner as “the most gifted and the freest writer it has been

given me to meet”.[9] Arnold Ruge even heralded Stirner as the

“theoretical liberator” of German philosophy; The Ego had represented a

triumph on behalf of the concrete living individual over abstract

generalities. Engels himself, in a letter to Marx, wrote that “among the

Freien it is plain that Stirner has the most talent, personality and

energy”.[10] S.E. Parker[11] notes that Engels’s initial sympathetic

response to Stirner was probably subject to a severe reprimand from

Marx. Engels’ views radically changed as we shall see, and deference is

made to Marx in dealing with the chimera of Stirner’s egoism.

Nevertheless, Stirner enjoyed fleeting and alarming fame, his “conscious

egoism” was parodied in a popular novel and he himself had even

appeared, thinly disguised, as a philosophical character in another

novel.[12]

However, the speculative excitement over The Ego was as frantic as it

was transient, and the political events of 1848 obliterated the traces

of those philosophical struggles which had preceded them. In that year,

along with the revolutionary hopes of German radicals, the Left Hegelian

movement “collapsed into itself, becoming insignificant in both

intellectual and political life”,[13] emasculated “in the face of an

adamant union between a defensive Church and a reactionary

Monarchy”.[14] The Ego had sounded the theoretical death knell for the

group and Left Hegelianism reached “a final and angry impasse”.[15]

Stirner had made a “clean sweep of everything, leaving only naked

self-assertion”; with The Ego he had taken the Hegelian system to its

dialectical limit “… and transformed it into its opposite”.[16]

[Fig. II: Max Stirner Pencil sketch, inscription reads “Max Stirner.

Drawn from memory by Frederick Engels, London, 1892” reproduced in MECW

5:267, (Moscow 1976).]

Johann Caspar Schmidt (1806–56), who wrote and was known as Max Stirner,

had been a close friend of Engels during the year he spent in Berlin.

Engels was evidently impressed by Stirner, who was his senior by a

number of years. He was able to render a pencil sketch of Stirner fifty

years later, and recalled that they were “great friends”

[Duzbrüder].[17] However, it was Engels who helped in obscuring evidence

of Stirner’s influence on his colleague and lifelong friend, Karl Marx.

After reading The Ego, Engels wrote to Marx explicitly stating his

opinion, one which would powerfully colour Stirner’s legacy: “We must

not simply cast it [The Ego] aside, but rather use it as the perfect

expression of the present-day folly, and, while inverting it, continue

to build on it.”[18] Marx responded by burying himself in The Ego, and

constructing his reply in The German Ideology.[19] For Marx and Engels,

coming to terms with The Ego was a deeply fundamental moment in the

development of Communist theory. Marx claimed that the aim of The German

Ideology was simply “to settle accounts with our erstwhile philosophical

conscience”.[20] First published in 1932, the bulk (three quarters) of

the work is a chapter entitled “Sankt Max”, Marx’s epic yet

uncomfortable diatribe on The Ego. The unpublished status of The German

Ideology did not allow for public discussion of Marx’s criticisms of

Stirner, in his own words it was “left to the gnawing criticism of

mice”.[21]

Stirner’s legacy suffered yet more interference from Engels’ essay

“Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy” (1886),

his account of the development of historical materialism. It attempted

to minimise the importance of The German Ideology, and therefore The Ego

in Marx’s formative philosophy. Engels claimed Darwin’s theory of

evolution had played a critical role in the route to dialectical

materialism, though Marx was always more of a Hegelian than Engels would

give him credit for. However, Engels at least recognised Feuerbach’s

influence whose concept of “species-being”/essence was easily transposed

onto Marx’s “social being”, conveniently replacing the old materialism

with a new “dialectical” form. There is no mention that Marx’s rejection

of Feuerbach’s humanism was only made possible by reading The Ego in

1844. Engels’ account mentions Stirner only in passing: “Stirner

remained an oddity, even after Bakunin blended him with Proudhon and

labelled the blend ‘anarchism’. Feuerbach alone was of significance as a

philosopher”.[22] Engels occluded Stirner’s self-evident “catalytic”[23]

contribution to the young Marx’s early philosophic formulations. By

labelling him the “prophet of contemporary anarchism”, Engels misaligned

Stirner with Proudhon and Bakunin, two thinkers he had openly condemned.

Marxists studying the theoretical development of the young Marx tend to

follow Engels and ignore the criticisms of Stirner featured in “Sankt

Max”. For the purposes of the “Marxist exegesis”, Marx’s most

characteristic aphorisms are to be found in the deceptively short yet

lucid chapter on Feuerbach, the most bona fide “Marxist” chapter of The

German Ideology. However, as we will learn, Marx’s criticisms of

Feuerbach were merely “perspectives” which “had been progressively

opened to Marx and Engels in the course of their study of Der Einzige

und sein Eigenthum”.[24]

At the close of the nineteenth century John Henry Mackay, a Scottish

poet turned Germanophile, rediscovered Stirner and initiated what has

since been called the “Stirner renaissance”.[25] Mackay happened to find

a brief citation regarding Stirner in Lange’s History of Materialism:

“The man who in German literature has preached Egoism most recklessly

and logically, Max Stirner, finds himself in distinct opposition to

Feuerbach”. After finding a copy of The Ego, Mackay immediately became a

disciple, and claimed the role of necromancer to the lifeless corpse of

Stirner’s thought. Stirner’s revival was also concurrent with the impact

of Friedrich Nietzsche’s work. As Karl Löwith points out “Stirner has

often been compared with Nietzsche, to the point of asserting that

Stirner was ‘intellectual arsenal’ from which Nietzsche derived his

weapons”.[26] Some went further in this comparison, Eduard von Hartmann

claimed “not only is this [The Ego] a brilliant work not inferior in

respect of style to Nietzsche’s work, but in respect of philosophical

value it surpasses the latter a thousand times”.[27] The spreading of

Nietzsche’s celebrity ignited a fresh and sympathetic interest in

Stirner’s ethic of self-will and indirectly helped to sustain

historians’ interest in The Ego into the twentieth-century.

Few historians have found consensus when discussing Stirner’s place in

the history of philosophy, not to suggest that they should. Scholars

remain divided in determining the place that The Ego might belong in

European thought, or even if it should belong at all. Mackay’s

resurrection of Stirner’s book caused a more extensive response; it

confirmed Stirner’s identification with his most commonly assigned

philosophical genre. For over a century The Ego has maintained a place

among the founders and luminaries of modern anarchism. Woodcock states

that “of all the libertarian classics [The Ego] remains the expression

of a point of view that belongs clearly to one end of the varied

spectrum of anarchist theory”.[28] The anarchic elements in Stirner’s

thought are even pronounced enough for Avron to declare Stirner

“anarchism’s most original and most consistent thinker”.[29] The

orthodox Marxist Hans G. Helms has argued that the influence of The Ego

has been as much political as philosophical. In his recent study, Die

Ideologie der anonymen Gesellschaft,[30] he argues that Stirner inspired

various German groups who were the immediate precursors of fascism.

Stirner has even been used by the New Right specifically to evoke the

darkness of the “interregnum” and emphasise the need for a total

cultural transformation.[31] In the 1963 Libertarian Book Club edition

of The Ego, James J. Martin wrote “it is at once a historical document,

a pamphlet of the intellectual disturbance of the mid-nineteenth

century, and a timeless classic”.

The publication history of The Ego also shows the strength of this

initial revival of Stirner. Forty-nine editions appeared between 1900

and 1929. However, after the 1930s, The Ego again slipped into relative

obscurity. Even amongst the thinkers who knew Stirner, opinion was

radically divided. There were a few during that period who had a better

insight into the meaning of Stirner’s thought. In 1939, Sidney Hook

indicated that the forgotten debate between Marx and Stirner involved

“the fundamental problems of any possible system of ethics or public

morality”,[32] and later in 1963 Isaiah Berlin noted that “the theory of

the alienation of the proletarians was enunciated by Max Stirner at

least one year before Marx.”[33] These voices were in the extreme

minority, yet significantly they identified the unresolved nature of the

Stirner-Marx relationship, and suggested that Stirner’s influence might

not be as negligible as was previously thought. These writers have paved

the way for a revaluation of Stirnerian thought.

In 1968 a new German edition of The Ego made its appearance. It had been

preceded, two years earlier, by a full study of Stirner’s thought and

influence, the first since Henri Avron’s in 1954, which had linked

Stirner with existentialism.[34] 1971 saw the publication of the first

extensive study of Stirner’s philosophy ever to appear in English: R. W.

K. Patterson’s The Nihilistic Egoist. Paterson’s study sought to be the

most comprehensively objective treatment of Stirner to date, yet Marx’s

accusations against Stirner are restated, minus the vitriol, and

Stirner’s vision is described as “frivolous”. The Nihilistic Egoist

remains a useful, if dated, springboard for a revisionist perspective

aiming to rediscover Stirner’s own intentionality.

In John Carroll’s Break-out from the Crystal Palace, The

Anarcho-Psychological Critique: Stirner, Nietzsche, Dostoyevsky (1974),

a sociological approach was applied to Stirner’s thought. Carroll

recognised the psychological dimension of anarchism beyond its more

familiar appearance as political ideology. Whilst identifying Stirner’s

radical individualist psychology, he sees Stirner much like Georges

Sorel in considering society as senile, in need of fresh, invigorating

passions; a view that appealed to the young Mussolini and to the French

fascist aesthete Robert Brasillach (see William Tucker’s The Fascist

Ego). Carroll ultimately presents Stirner as a difficult, inspiring, yet

flawed champion of rebellion and the unceasing quest for

self-understanding, self-realization, and new values.

William Brazill’s recent work, The Young Hegelians (1970) as well as

David McLellan’s The Young Hegelians and Karl Marx (1980) both direct

considerable attention to Stirner’s thought. In addition, John Edward

Toews has significantly revised Stirner’s place in the history of

philosophy in his recent study Hegelianism, The Path Toward Dialectical

Humanism, 1805–41 (1980), opening the way up for a more historically

sensitive, rather than philosophical/ideological interpretation of

Stirner’s contribution to the history of philosophy. Toews

contextualises Stirner’s position amongst the Left Hegelians, and

attacks those who see Stirner’s egoism as “purely subjective”.[35] He

identifies the core contradiction that Hegel’s radical heirs had to

wrangle with during the 1840s, that self-liberation and self-affirmation

required “revolutionary destruction” in order for their “concrete

historical actualisation”.[36] However, revolution necessitated

“commitment to suprapersonal values” and “a belief in an objective

meaning in history”.[37] Such values were a direct denial of the

“individual autonomy, self-expression and self-enjoyment” that

constituted Stirner’s aim of an inward rebellion which sought to end the

“historical pathology of self-alienation”.[38] Toews’ penetrating work

indicates that The Ego was deeply rooted in the struggles of Hegelian

thought during the 1840s and importantly Stirner is given an independent

and original role in disintegration of the Left Hegelian movement. As

Lawrence Stepelevich notes hopefully, we may be seeing the “beginning of

another cycle of interest in Stirner”.[39] The continued publication of

the journal Stirner-Studien since 1994 similarly reflects the renewed

academic interest in Stirner in his native Germany.[40]

The debate of 1845 still reverberates in late twentieth-century European

intellectual discourse. Indeed, there are many unusual and overlooked

parallels between Stirner’s critique of Enlightenment humanism,

universal rationality and essential identities, and similar critiques

developed by thinkers such as Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, Gilles

Deleuze and others. Such intellectual affinities have recently prompted

Saul Newman to attempt to reconcile classical anarchism with

poststructuralist thought (in order to define “postanarchism”) using

Stirner to “break out of the Enlightenment humanist paradigm of

essentialism … which continues to inform radical political theory”.[41]

Stirner’s ideas are also discernible in “primitivism” (John Zerzan),

“immediatism” (Hakim Bey) and “insurrectionary anarchism” (Alfredo

Bonnano).

This thesis aims to assess the difficult relationship between Marx and

Stirner and their respective ideas. It is timely to reconsider Stirner’s

place amongst the philosophic heavyweights of the nineteenth century,

after years where he has suffered under the suffocating modernity of

Marx and Nietzsche and been misconstrued by many as an intellectual

oddity. It is high time that the relevance of Stirner’s thought,

especially in relation to the development of Marx’s theories, was

restored to its correct place in history of philosophy. When we examine

Marx’s critique in The German Ideology, it will emerge that Stirner’s

legacy is more than that of an “anarcho-existentialist” whose egoism is

untenable. Both thinkers will be firmly set against the context of the

rise and fall of Left Hegelian humanism. Whilst by 1845 its key

luminaries accused each other of retreating to abstract and

undialectical positions of either metaphysical idealism or materialism,

all (including Marx and Stirner) had laid claim to dialectical

inheritance (Hegel). Therefore, it is instructive to see the thinkers on

a level playing field, Marx, Feuerbach, Bauer and Stirner all sharing

this “existential” ontology. We should similarly regard their opposing

solutions as embedded in their own context, remembering that the

“existential reductions” of 1844–5 were put forward as constructive

appropriations of the real content of Hegelian thought. Stirner was no

exception as his form of nihilism did not abandon the redemptive core of

the Hegelian project. Rather than a simple appendage of Marx’s early

formulations, The Ego must be given independent value and seen as

serious attempt to tackle the problems facing German philosophy in the

1840s. The main objective of this thesis will be to extricate Stirner

from Marx’s rambling, left-handed invective and reinstate him as a

thinker who deserves our attention and whose relevance and influence

have not been fully appreciated. We cannot simply overlook “Sankt Max”

as key evidence of Marx’s formative intellectual development. Marx

clearly exerted much cerebral effort to write a critique that ended up

being lengthier than The Ego itself. In short, the full effects of The

Egoupon the philosophy of the young Marx “have yet to be fully

assessed”.[42]

It is relatively easy to grasp the basic contemporary relevance,

significance and durability of The Ego in the history of philosophy. Yet

we still need to perceive more about Stirner’s complex, often

incongruous, relationship with Karl Marx – a figure who seems destined

to remain significant, despite the recent interest in Nietzschean

thought. What Derrida says of Marx is equally applicable to Stirner: “a

ghost never dies” nor can there be any “future” without “the memory and

inheritance … of at least one of his spirits”.[43]

Chapter I: Context and purpose in The Ego and Its Own .

[Figure III: Stirner’s birthplace, from John Henry Mackay’s book Max

Stirner: Sein Leben und Sein Werk.]

Born in 1806, Johann Caspar Schmidt was the son of Albert and Sophia

Schmidt who lived in a comfortable house overlooking the Marktplatz in

Bayreuth. The Schmidts were a lower-middle-class family of evangelical

Lutheran denomination. In 1826 Stirner matriculated in the Philosophy

Faculty of the University of Berlin and spent two years studying a range

of subjects including logic, Greek literature and geography. Whilst at

Berlin, unlike Marx, Strauss or Engels, Stirner attended Hegel’s

lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, the History of Philosophy, and

in the winter of 1827 his lectures on the Philosophy of the Subjective

Spirit. In 1832 Stirner returned to Berlin, where he would spend the

rest of his life. Continuing his philosophical studies, he attended a

two-semester course on Aristotle conducted by the Hegelian philosopher

Karl L. Michelet. Stirner’s formal acquaintance with Hegelian

philosophy, as well as Hegelian philosophers themselves, far surpassed

that obtained by other Left Hegelians. However, Stirner fell short of

academic success in his formal examinations in the upper forms of the

gymnasium and was awarded a conditional facultas docendi, never

realising his ambition to become a Gymnasiallehrer.

In 1839, Stirner obtained regular employment at a Berlin girls’ school.

He taught both history and literature with great success, and for next

five years enjoyed a relatively stable and ordered life, with a modest

income and ample freedom to pursue his philosophical reflections.

Ostensibly, this quiet middle-class school teacher hardly seems a likely

candidate to produce what has been called the “most revolutionary [book]

ever written”.[44] However, 1840’s Berlin was a melting pot of political

disaffection and intellectual unrest, whilst the revolution was not

being fought for in blood, the clubs and cafes of Berlin formed

political hubs in which groups of young radicals could meet and make

preparations. Stirner began attending meetings of Die Freien in 1841;

his formal education was undoubtedly supplemented by meetings with

Hegelians at various clubs and Weinstuben. During long boisterous

evenings at their favourite haunt (Hippel’s), Stirner would have had the

chance to review the metaphysical exuberance of Berlin’s disaffected and

rootless intelligentsia and literati. In the midst of such radical

clamour, Stirner met Bruno Bauer, the only member of Die Freien in the

Left Hegelian circle with whom he maintained a close relationship until

his death. It was through socialising with Die Freien that Stirner also

met his second wife (his first wife had died giving birth to a

still-born child), Marie Dahnhart. Marie was an uninhibited cigar

smoking, beer-drinking 25 year old who was about to enjoy an inheritance

of 30,000 thalers. In 1843, Stirner astutely married her.

The years between 1815 and 1848 have been seen as an “era of

polarisation”,[45] a conflict between modernity and tradition. However,

the post-1815 era of German restoration was not threatened by

philosophical trends; neither the moral creeds and entrenched dogmas of

rigid conservatives, nor the passionate individualism of the Romantics

sought to challenge the feudal complacency that still survived in some

German states. The loathed German Confederation soon showed its true

colours, with censorship and surveillance laws embodied in the Karslbad

Decrees of 1819 and the “Final Act” of 1820. Both ushered in an era of

oppression and illiberality for the German states, one that would be

strongly attacked by many contemporary thinkers.

During the 1830s the movement known as Junges Deutschland (Young

Germany), produced poets, thinkers and journalists, all of whom reacted

against the introspection and particularism of Romanticism. The Romantic

Movement was seen as apolitical lacking the activism that Germany’s

burgeoning intelligentsia required. Decades of compulsory school

attendance in German states had resulted in mass literacy and an excess

of educated males which the establishment could not subsume. Combined

with the advantage of the low cost printing press these factors caused a

rush into the so-called “free professions”.

The German states, specifically the Prussian government, had a basic

distrust of speculative thought. On occasion the state would sometimes

sponsor philosophical teachings that offered an intellectual foundation

for the authoritarian organisation of society.[46] Hegelianism was

adopted as the academic standard for appointments in 1820s and 30s. To

begin with, Hegelianism was regarded as “the staunchest ideological

bulwark of Prussian aristocracy”, yet by the 1840s devotion to Hegelian

thought had led to a period of readjustment, and the late 1830s and

early 1840s resembled more a post-mortem of Hegelianism in which

thinkers extended or recast Hegelian phenomenology.[47] One outcome of

this method of criticism was the radical Left Hegelianism of the early

1840s, which Stirner found himself heir to. The “Young Hegelians”

(hereafter referred to as “Left”) sought to decisively challenge both

Church and State, finding resonance with the “Young Germany” of the

1830s; no longer allies of the establishment, they were rejected as

intellectual outcasts. The official Hegelianism that was extolled in

lecture theatres in Stirner’s undergraduate days had become the

“philosophy of disaffection”.[48]

Stirner occupied a unique position among the Left Hegelians, sharing an

essentially similar methodology to his closest contemporaries. By using

classical Hegelian concepts and modes of argument, the Left Hegelians

quickly reached conclusions that in effect nullified the whole upshot of

Hegel’s original system. Hegel’s universal synthesis of Being had begun

to produce discordant results. By reviving the republican idealism of

the eighteenth century, Left Hegelians believed education and political

liberties would solve all social problems without changing the system of

property on which material production and economic exchanges were based.

Stirner’s early work reflected these broad aims.

The False Principle of Our Education is considered the “most valuable

and significant of Stirner’s shorter works”.[49] Stirner, for the first

time, can be seen in pursuit of the goal of individual self-awareness

and an insistence on the primacy of the individual personality. He

rejected both humanism and realism as authorities external to the

individual that limited his freedom. In formal education, Stirner saw

that “the world of antiquity through classics and the Bible rule over us

as a mistress”.[50] He went on to stress the importance of personality

and the “free-moving ego” in education, insisting bluntly that education

is the most important “social question” in the world. Stirner’s

surprisingly modern insistence on the primacy of education and knowledge

was tied to man’s self-discovery: through “Truth” man discovers himself

and experiences “the liberation from all that is alien, the uttermost

abstraction or release from all authority, the re-won naturalness”.[51]

However, the Left Hegelians sought in vain to “educate” their fellow

countrymen and the 1840s brought disenchantment and schism; political

rulers and academics strove uselessly to restore a cultural unity and a

national idealism to Germany.

The disintegration of the Left Hegelian movement was born out of the

inability to make its philosophy the focus of any political movement,

especially one involving the country’s social forces. Mass poverty,

economic dislocation and social unrest had been rife in Germany, from

the student protests of the 1830s to the “hungry 1840s”. In some areas

socialists and communists had taken advantage of this. Yet unlike Marx’s

experiences in Britain, industrialization had only made very modest

advances in German states by 1848. German society was overwhelmingly

rural even during the 1840s; 70% of the population still worked on the

land. Within a short space of time the Left Hegelians became static and

ineffective, wrecked by their own internal theoretical disputes and

confined to Berlin’s bourgeois, pre-industrial world.

Before its disintegration, the Left Hegelian movement underwent a series

of “transformations”. The “emanation of divergent positions”, is crucial

in regard to Stirner, who inherited and then reacted against the

semiotic system or “distinctive” language that Hegelian thinkers created

and altered.[52] The period between 1835 and 1843 can be seen as a

period in which thinkers attempted to translate the original

metaphysical Hegelian language of Absolute Spirit into the language of

Hegelian humanism. During this period the concept Absolute Spirit was

replaced by “the idea of humanity”, “human species-being” or “human

self-consciousness”.[53] This secularisation or humanisation of Hegelian

thought was the basis for the radical Left Hegelian movement. Strauss

began this trend with his Life of Jesus (1835) where he asserted that

religious representation was the objectification of human essence, thus

religious consciousness contributed to alienation and kept human beings

from their own essential nature. By the time Strauss had cemented his

new humanist outlook in 1840–41, Bruno Bauer had developed his own

variant of the transformative humanist interpretation of the Hegelian

language of Absolute Spirit. For Bauer, Strauss had not gone far enough;

the “idea of humanity” itself remained enigmatic unless it actualised

itself in human history through its internalisation in the “free

activity of human self-consciousness”.[54] In book and articles

published in 1840–42, Bauer denounced terms such as “God”, “Absolute

Spirit” and “world-spirit” as deceptions implying a supranatural

transcendent power realising itself in human self-consciousness. Bauer’s

critical theory of human self-consciousness therefore sought to liberate

“the I” which “lives, creates, works and is everything” and “is the only

power in the world and history, and history has no other meaning than

the becoming and development of self-consciousness”.[55]

A third version of the humanist translation of Hegelianism was

constructed by Ludwig Feuerbach around 1840. Hegel’s “Absolute Spirit”

was a transcendent mystification, a self-alienation of a human process

and limitation on human thought. InThe Essence of Christianity (1840–41)

Feuerbach claimed religious consciousness and language meant “a

projection of humanity’s essential nature as an emotional and sensuous

being, governed and made happy only by images”.[56] Whilst the rightful

content of Hegelian metaphysics was thus affirmed by Bauer as human

self-consciousness, for Feuerbach such essential human content was more

a sensuous and emotional “essence”. By 1841, these thinkers were

publicly attributed with developing a distinctive theoretical

perspective, and Bauer and Feuerbach accepted their roles as the

intellectual mentors of radical “Left” Hegelians.

Historical reality ultimately undermined Hegelian humanism when its

theoretical practice failed to gain wide appeal. Left Hegelianism was in

terminal decline when The Ego was published in 1844. Academic positions

were denied to the Left Hegelians in the city that they deemed

philosophically and politically the capital of Germany. The constant

pressure of governmental censorship and academic rejection meant that

even Arnold Ruge’s attempts to rally a political party around the banner

of Left Hegelianism soon failed. In 1843, the Deutsche Jahrbücher was

prohibited from publication, even in “liberal” Saxony. It was equally a

defeat by politics as it was by abstract thought itself. Soon most

members of the movement became disillusioned with the idea of a

political public as the agent of liberation. The declarations of

Feuerbach, Bauer, Hess and Ruge in 1841 had set the Left Hegelians

against all prevailing orthodoxy be it religious, philosophical,

economic or political; yet all had failed at insurrection of existing

institutions or a political association based its ideas.

Such failure was reflected in the thought produced during the period

1843–46, which saw the publication of The Ego. It was a divisive process

of mutual criticism, where Stirner and others criticised the

“theological” illusions of a movement caught in a language of essence.

Stirner inherited the problem that “reality” must be comprehended and

described as contingent, concrete, finite “existence” with reason and

meaning emerging from actions of individual beings. The “analytic of

existence” was self-consciously presented not merely as a translation,

but as a step beyond Hegelian thought in some respects, seeking to

transcend it.[57] The humanism that had for a short time enjoyed the

attention of the movement’s most able thinkers was scoffed at by

Stirner: “In our days, … they have not realised that man has killed God

in order to become – “sole God on high” … God has had to give place, not

to us, but to – humanity”.[58] Stirner specifically condemned Feuerbach

and Bauer for creating this new god, “Humanity” to replace the Christian

god. For Stirner this was simply a “change of masters”.[59]

Hegelian humanism encountered strong criticism from former disciples and

comrades, most significantly in the publication of Stirner’s The Ego and

Marx’s The German Ideology. Both thinkers proposed a more radical break

with past Left Hegelian positions, and the language that had justified

it. Despite accusations of nihilism, Stirner’s “heaven-storming”

dismissal of the objectivity, universality, value, truth and meaning

still presented a description of individual-centred existence, with the

ego as sovereign as a positive appropriation of the true content of his

cultural and philosophical inheritance. It is a mistake therefore to see

Stirner as an anomaly in the history of philosophy or even as

“discordant” in some way.[60] The Ego did not exist in an intellectual

vacuum, and the context of Left-Hegelianism reveals how Stirner’s

thought was a legitimate product of this movement’s wider discourse, a

serious attempt to understand the transition from religion to

philosophy. Stirner (as all Left Hegelians did) saw himself as

dialectically concluding and fulfilling the Hegelian project. Similarly

Marx saw that within Hegelian thought were the means, and even the

imperative, to go beyond Hegel. He understood exactly what Stirner was

attempting, “a step which leads beyond Hegelian idealism and negates

it”;[61] he also knew how potentially damaging this could be to the

direction of his own work.

Rather than view The Ego as some wild or “severely mutilated”[62]

transformation of Hegel’s characteristic concepts, its construction

should be seen as a result of that philosophical paradigm which all Left

Hegelians practiced and embraced: dialectical development. There is even

room to regard Stirner as a concordant Hegelian par excellence. His

intimacy with Hegel has been explored by Stepelevich, who argues that

Stirner reinterprets Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit with new and

improved vision.[63] For Hegel, the “Absolute” is “the power of the

negative”;, i.e. that which views and criticises every determinate

thought – the Subject. For Stirner, in his critique, this “power of the

negative” is the single consciousness – himself, or the ego. Karl Löwith

similarly detected a logical connection stating that The Ego “is in

reality an ultimate logical consequence of Hegel’s historical

system”.[64] Whilst these interpretations elevate Stirner from the often

eccentric billing he is given in intellectual history, describing

Stirner as the “Last of the Hegelians” implies that The Ego is the “end

of a historical series of ever more decadent inheritors of Hegel’s

doctrines”.[65] We should recognise that whilst he attacked Hegelianism,

Stirner’s thought was still a product of it, bound within its

parameters, be they linguistic or logical. Therefore the choice lies

between seeing a “terminal orantithetical” relationship, one which could

make Stirner, in a sense, “the perfected Hegelian”.[66]

Chapter II: The crisis of 1845: The Ego and the origins of historical

materialism.

The dissolution of Left Hegelianism coincided with the early thinking of

Marx who grew up among the ruins of their philosophy. Together with

Stirner, Marx accepted the philosophical categories and problems of

Hegelian thought. Placing Stirner among the many strands and mutations

of Hegelian thought highlights his intellectual proximity to the thought

of the young Marx. Whilst preparing to demolish German Idealism, Marx

entered the metaphysical fray at the same moment as Stirner, and

wrestled with the same ontological questions. The publication of The Ego

shook the pro-Feuerbachian position Marx found himself in 1844 and

perhaps more than any of his contemporaries, Marx was to experience the

depth and implications of Stirner’s criticism. Marx had originally

planned to write a review of The Ego; however he stalled whilst Bauer

and Feuerbach fielded their responses. Then, feeling clearly personally

provoked, Marx postponed previously commissioned works to pen “Sankt

Max”. After completing the work, Marx wavered and the criticism of

Stirner remained unprinted. Within this privately led dispute, The

German Ideology contained the seeds of a new philosophy, created to be

immune to a Stirnerian criticism: historical materialism. The birth of

this radical new theory was muted. These ideas were left in a drawer

along with “Sankt Max”, whilst Marx, wishing to escape the idealist

philosophy of the Left Hegelians, charged into political life, into

intellectual feuds with Proundhon and Bakunin.

Between 1844 and 1846 Marx and Engels were busy forging their new

revolutionary outlook. The German Ideology was composed in Brussels,

where Marx had moved in 1845 following his deportation from Paris by the

Guizot government who had been pressured by Prussia to expel the leading

collaborators of Vorwärts. During the last three months of 1845, Marx

and Engels wrote The German Ideology. In early 1846, both men visited

London in order to found a network of communist correspondence

committees to provide German, French and English socialists with access

to each other’s ideas and activities. The backdrop to Marx’s life was

one of financial struggle, censorship and political activity and exile.

However, the pair had integrated their theoretical and practical aims,

revolutionary communist teaching and rallying the progressive elements

of the proletariat and revolutionary intelligentsia.

In theoretical terms, this revolutionary outlook was partially created

through the intellectual struggle with what Marx saw as bourgeois and

petty bourgeois ideology of the Left Hegelians, of which Max Stirner was

seen as the perfect embodiment. The German Ideology directed criticism

against the many apparent failings of Left Hegelianism, many which echo

Stirner’s own critique of the movement. For Marx, however, the authority

of delusions or Stirner’s “spooks” over human minds was not a result of

mental distortion cured by working upon the consciousness, but rather

rooted in social conditions. For both Stirner and Marx, Left Hegelian

humanism was governed by false ideas where men are enslaved to the

creations of their minds. For Marx, the power of philosophy was to

expose and destroy these false ideas and revolutionise society. In the

Preface of The German Ideology Marx outlined his objections to the Left

Hegelians, and saw clearly his task in:

“uncloaking these sheep, who take themselves and are taken for wolves;

of showing that their bleating merely imitates in a philosophic form the

conceptions of the German middle class; that the boasting of these

philosophic commentators only mirrors the wretchedness of the real

conditions in Germany.”[67]

Throughout The German Ideology Marx clearly enjoys making fun of the

philosophical pretensions of the Left Hegelians, yet he also levels the

serious claim that the movement’s achievements only embodied a

corruption of Hegel, i.e. “the putrescence of the absolute spirit”.[68]

Why then compose such a lengthy rebuttal of German post-Hegelian

philosophy if all it amounted to was “shadows of reality”?[69] The

answer is simple: Stirner. Marxists tend to regard The German Ideology

as nothing more than a secondary attack against Left Hegelians, even an

enlarged version of The Holy Family. However, The Ego had unsettled

Marx; regardless of whether a public debate was to be had, he felt

inclined to convince himself at least that Stirner was wrong. Marx

realised that Stirner’s position was perfectly concordant with general

development of post-Hegelian dialectics in German philosophy and thus an

alternative to his profanization of the Hegel. In reading The Ego, Marx

came to reject Feuerbachian humanism, of which he had previously thought

highly, praising Feuerbach’s “brilliant arguments” in the Essence of

Christianity and defending his “real humanism” in The Holy Family. Now

revealed as a “pious atheist” by Stirner, Marx could not avoid

denunciating Feuerbach, but equally had to avoid an association with the

powerful Stirnerian position that had originally prompted the

rejection.[70] The German Ideology was less an attack, but more as an

angry defence against the theologically inspired and passivist humanism

of Feuerbach and the extreme voluntarism and subjectivist individualism

of Stirner.[71]

Marx’s familiarity with the aims of Left Hegelianism meant he agreed

that the more progressive an idea was, the more it desecrated the

quasi-religious status Hegel’s legacy. In The German Ideology Marx

attempted to be more radical than both Bauer and Feuerbach in profaning

the regions of Hegel’s thought which had been “transfigured”. However

whilst Marx believed that, like Stirner, he could fight against

illusions and opiates, against religion, political ideals and eventually

against Hegelian philosophy itself, he still retained the hidden

“eschatological attitude” and “implicit revolutionary drive” underlying

Hegelianism in mid-1840s.[72] Unlike Marx, Stirner didn’t retain Hegel’s

eschatology and regarded it as simply another “phantom” to be exorcised

from the mind, one perhaps essential if Hegelian thought was to be

overcome. Marx adhered to Hegel in so far as he chose not to abandon

some form of philosophical reconciliation, though not of the speculative

sort. For reconciliation to be attained in the materialtransformation of

the real world, Marx would have to elaborate and expound one of his most

controversial and debated theories: historical materialism.

Rather disingenuously the old Marx considered the birth of historical

materialism as simply theoretical analysis eschewing from purely

theoretical research.[73] Unfortunately there was no comprehensive or

detached study of “socioeconomic realities” that came to support Marx’s

theory in 1845; instead he was motivated by his desire to defend the

“passion and idealism” emanating from the dissolution of Hegel’s

philosophy against Stirner’s noxious philosophy of “total

disillusionment”.[74] Stirner, as a minority of commentators have

observed, played a decisive role in motivating Marx’s socialist thought

in this direction. The subjective origins of the “materialistic

conception of history” reflected Marx’s attempt to show that “the

putrescence of the absolute spirit” must not go as far as it does in The

Ego, yet it was perfectly acceptable to be a Hegelian of “revolutionary”

inspiration. It seems paradoxical to think that historical materialism,

Marx’s great epistemological “break”, could have emerged from the

context described above. Stirner’s impact has been displaced. Regardless

of the self-assured position Marx felt he had reached in The German

Ideology with regard to the specific criticisms of Left Hegelians, the

real gem of the work was clearly the materialist conception of history.

For Marx, it provided an ingenious escape route from the all-too

parochial problems of Left Hegelianism and German Idealist Philosophy,

whilst it also served as a methodological prerequisite for a new

political economy. In a letter to German publishers in Leske on August 1

1846, Marx pointed out that the publication of a polemical work against

the German philosophers was necessary in order to “prepare readers for

his point of view in this field of economic science”. The German

Ideology should therefore be seen chiefly as a polemical work; one that

Marx felt sure would lift him up and away from the ontological

squabbling of the Left Hegelians towards economics, historical analysis

and socialism.

For Marx, speculative philosophy had resulted in idealist self-deception

epitomised in the work of the Left Hegelians. Marx frequently attacked

the sterile and static nature of his milieu, stating “German critique

has, right up to its latest efforts, never left the realm of

philosophy”.[75] The movement’s ignorance of both of the need to specify

an agent for revolutionary change and of the nature of social and

historical explanation had meant their philosophy failed. Despite the

decline of Left Hegelian humanism, Marx’s complaint was essentially

methodological.[76] The Left Hegelians, like Descartes, thought that the

illusions of social life could be left behind if one takes the

standpoint of “self-consciousness”, “species” or the “ego”. For Marx,

this was a truly insulated standpoint. However, Stirner too had attacked

the Archimedean standpoint or standpoint “outside the world” in 1844:

“This foreign standpoint is the world of mind, of ideas, thoughts,

concepts, essences; it is heaven”.[77] In concordance with Marx, Stirner

attacked the Left Hegelians with similar gusto, identifying the same

weaknesses:

“Now nothing but mind rules in the world. An innumerable multitude of

concepts buzz about in people’s heads, and what are those doing who

endeavour to get further? They are negating these concepts to put new

ones in their place! … Thus the confusion of concepts moves

forward.”[78]

In recognising the force of Stirner’s criticism and the implications for

Left Hegelian modes of thought, Marx had to be just as “hard-line” on

idealism as Stirner had been. He had to adopt a position in which all

ideas were divested of their independence and autonomy. For a moment at

least, Marx was allied with Stirner’s heaven-storming nihilism, but only

in order to escape it:

“Morality, religion, metaphysics … have no history, no development; but

human beings, developing their material production and their material

intercourse, alter, along with this, their reality; also their thinking

and the products of their thinking.”[79]

Marx’s response, that the “material world” takes primacy over the ideal,

consciousness or thought itself, was not merely a major development in

terms of his thinking, but was the “thermo-nuclear” antidote to

Stirnerian egoism he desperately needed.[80]

Hegel had maintained that the ideal determined the material; Marx’s

supposed modernism was finding the Hegelian dialectic “standing on its

head” and turning it “right side up again”.[81] Quite what Marx means is

not readily apparent. He inverted the primacy of the ideal found in

German Idealist, Hegelian and post-Hegelian philosophy by replacing it

with an older form of materialism. The materialist conception of

consciousness can be summed up Marx’s famous axiom “Life is not

determined by consciousness, but consciousness by life” (1846). Marx’s

paradigmatic shift invoked eighteenth-century materialism, which took

matter as primary and regarded consciousness, thought and sensation as

secondary. The French materialists of the eighteenth century provided

Marx with the simple mechanical categories that constituted the terms in

which the origin and history of man were to be explained. The “newness”

of Marxian materialism, the idea of conceiving of matter dialectically,

highlights Marx’s innate debt to Hegelian thought. Yet historical

materialism was also a backwards step. Marx wanted to reassert the

fundamental principle of eighteenth-century historical naturalism; that

historical events have natural causes. Hegel had broken away from

naturalism but had not demanded an autonomous history, “Marx went back

on this demand and swept Hegel away; he subjected history to dominion by

natural science which Hegel had freed it from”.[82] Thus Marx took a

“retrograde step”, which was simultaneously also prelude to an advance

in terms of political economy.[83] Despite cryptic statements such as

“standing Hegel on his feet instead of his head”, Marx’s “conjuring

trick” essentially took over the idea, inherited from both Kant and

Hegel, in which history culminated in the complete unity of man, the

identification of existence with essence and the abolition of

contingency in human life. For Marx, humanity was not doomed to

contingency, as Stirner maintained.[84]

As his response to Stirner suggests, Marx’s theory had no real

scientific basis, and its genesis appears in a somewhat dubious light.

Whilst it allowed Marx to condemn the present world order in terms of

the immanent laws of history itself, as a solution it was both

“ingenious and disingenuous”.[85] Stirner’s nihilism meant Marx had to

defend the basic claim to seek meaning in an ideal, rather than giving

up the whole conception of a salvation of man. Marx was of course keen

to emphasise that he was not really pursuing an ideal at all; his

presuppositions were “not arbitrary ones, not dogmas, but real

presuppositions from which abstraction can only be made in the

imagination”.[86] Marx saw them as empirical facts. Stirner, on the

other hand claimed “I presuppose only myself – and since it is I who

presuppose myself, I have no presuppositions”.[87] Marx painstakingly

insists Stirner himself does have ideals and even his own morality. Yet,

the materialistic reduction of ideals to historical necessities very

closely resembles a Stirnerian abandoning of ideals; nihilism was

inherent in both positions. How can Marx’s thought retain its

revolutionary aspect if economic patterns and laws thoroughly determine

man’s historical existence? Yet far from relinquishing his revolutionary

ideals, Marx believed he had succeeded in preserving by integrating them

into real history. This was the core of both Marx’s defence against

Stirner and the essence of the materialistic conception of history: the

ideals pursued by the Left Hegelians were declared to be the “immanent

telos of history itself”.[88] The Left Hegelian revolutionary force

became an immanent law of objective history. In other words, Marx turned

an ought into an is.

It has not been properly acknowledged just how much The Ego is

responsible for pushing Marx into this epistemological corner. By

attempting to incorporate ideals into actual history, Marx went as far

as it is possible to rationalise the Left Hegelian revolutionary drive

without abandoning the “basic Left Hegelian insight”.[89] Marx had

reached an impossible dilemma, one which has haunted his more

intelligent disciples until today. As such, Marx could no longer

encourage action as he now predicted change; history did not depend upon

man’s conscious intentions; it depended on what humans do. This seems

incompatible with Marx’s dismissal of ideals and represents the basic

ambiguity of his thought, a blind spot which he left for Marxists to

excuse or explain. The contradictory nature of Marx’s position reflected

how “almost against his will” Marx was forced into dismissal by

Stirner.[90] On the one hand we have Marx the determinist, who will

later refer to laws and tendencies that work “with iron necessity

towards inevitable results”,[91] on the other we have Marx the

voluntarist, keen to incite the proletariat to rebellion. However, the

materialist conception of history was, in itself, a change of

consciousness, merely a new theory of reality and thus “recognition of

the existing order by means of another interpretation”.[92] The real

difference between Marx and the Left Hegelians was that instead of

pretending to save the world by changing their ideas, Marx arrived at an

idea that couldn’t be changed, a theory in which humanity saves itself,

regardless of philosophical speculations.

Historical materialism was the result of an attempt to preserve the Left

Hegelian humanist heritage in spite of Stirner’s challenge. Stirner’s

exposure of quasi-religious basis of Man undermined the idiom developed

by Marx in his pre-1845 writings. To escape the neo-Christian ethics of

humanism it was not enough to simply discard the legitimacy of the

humanist or socialist goal. In a totalitarian fashion, Marx divested all

ideas of any “autonomous” role whatsoever. Many commentators have argued

that the doctrine of historical materialism provided Marx with his most

powerful weapon against idealist philosophy. It did not – despite how

much Marx may have convinced himself – deal sufficiently with Stirnerian

thought. Like Marx, Stirner’s project was destructive. The Ego sought to

simply abolish philosophy in general by affirming that it was all

nonsense, summed in Stirner’s famous aphorisms “I have set my cause upon

nothing” and “Nothing is more to me than myself”.[93] Stirner’s

modernity resides in this progressive leap beyond Marx, beyond a

revolutionary mentality which required “moral postulates” or an ought.

For Stirner, uniqueness and creativity begin only when a person goes

beyond social identity and roles. He had shocked Marx into revising the

ethical and humanistic assumptions of a socialist agenda. At the same

time Stirner indirectly contributed to the creation and evolution of the

distinctive and classical “Marxist” doctrines.

In short, The Ego moved Marx from a passionately moral, even

sentimental, commitment to communism as a humanitarian creed, to a

sociological affirmation of communism as the historical outcome of

objective economic forces. During the mid-1840s Marx and Engels saw

themselves at a decisive stage in working out the philosophical

principles of scientific communism or “the scientific world outlook of

the revolutionary proletariat”.[94] Marx must have been painfully aware,

therefore, of the need to qualify his own action in theory. This crisis

for Marx reached its height in 1845, when The German Ideologyindicated

Marx’s final abandonment of the speculative abstractions of Feuerbach

and others; the very abstractions which had served as the metaphysical

foundations of his socialism. The unresolved nature of Marx’s

uncomfortable encounter with Stirner is also evident in the development

of the materialist conception of history. Historical materialism’s more

inconvenient implications and thus the spectre of The Ego haunted Marx;

burdening him with the “self-defeating task of reconciling a

“voluntarist movement” in an “economically determined historical

process”.[95]

By revealing “the hollowness of slogans which appealed to humanity,

country, or abstract freedom…” Stirner had “prepared the way for a

realistic analysis of the issues these phrases were used to

conceal”.[96] Despite Stirner’s nascent influence on the thought of the

young Marx, Marx came to dominate the historical era, his solution to

the crises of Hegelian ontology emerged as legitimate, whilst the

history and intentionality of Stirner’s thought were “excluded” in a

Foucauldian sense. However, as I have demonstrated by studying of the

genesis of historical materialism, the impact of The Ego on the

evolution of socialist thought was far from negligible.

Chapter III: Stirner contra Marx: morality, society and liberty.

In many respects, Stirner’s work stands as an anticipatory attack on

Marx’s thought. Modern critics of Marxism have frequently pointed out

inadequacies in the Marxist conception of history, especially concerning

what the theory had rendered obsolete in traditional philosophy. The Ego

essentially anticipated these inadequacies. 1845 is judged to be the

moment in Marx’s philosophical career where he “left behind” a

fundamental discourse on ethics; one that Hook argues “still occupies us

today”.[97] Marx’s new theory of historical materialism cut short a

discussion about any systems of ethics or public morality. Many have

recognised this negation in Marx’s work. For Marx, the crucial issue was

the validity of his theory of history; he felt notions of morality and

of religion had finally been eliminated from his work. However, the old

assumption that “scientific socialism” was a scientific system has

yielded to the notion that such a system of thought is in essence

moralistic or even religious; what Martin Buber calls a “socialist

secularisation of eschatology”.[98] If we accept this radical new

perspective, as many do, then Stirner’s stance in The Ego emerges as

more modern and radical than was previously considered. Stirner would no

doubt have agreed that the materialist conception of history was

eschatological; a religious mode of thought. Therefore, Stirner’s early,

if somewhat undeveloped attack on morality, often disguised as ideology,

assumes a vital position as the original critique of the young Marx.

In spite of the anti-moral nature of historical materialism and Marx’s

explicit repudiations of morality, his early thought was packed with

moral judgements, (e.g. condemnations, directions etc). Whether or not

we see Marx as moralist is beside the point. Marx did not practice moral

philosophy in the traditional sense of developing any form of system of

ethics, or enquiry. Whilst criticising The Ego, Marx was inspired to

claim:

“The communists … preach no morality, which Stirner does too much … on

the contrary, they know well that egoism as well as self-sacrifice is,

in certain circumstances, a necessary form of the self-assertion of

individuals.”[99]

The question of Marx’s status as a clandestine moralist who openly

opposed moral philosophy remains a key contradiction, especially in his

early thought. It represents a temporal rip in the fabric of Marxian

thought that still plagues its acolytes today. Its origins, found in

young Marx’s reading of The Ego, may further unsettle his adherents. If

Marx needed inspiration, or even encouragement to abandon his more

explicit moral leanings, then he needed to look no further than

Stirner’s polemic. Stirner had refuted Left Hegelian humanism,

especially targeting its innate moral content. He also attacked most

forms of moral convention, challenging the absolute basis of moral

edicts against polygamy, blasphemous desecration and even incest. Such

acts were still able to cause a “moral shudder”[100] in the common man,

an indication for Stirner that the actual emancipation of the ego, what

others might call spiritual emancipation, had yet to be realised.

For Stirner, self-possession was to be sought by the judicious

organisation of desire, rather than its arbitrary suppression. Taking

his cue from Charles Fourier, Stirner lauded animal appetites as more

healthy and poetic than a life of abstinence. Just as Feuerbachian

humanism was seen as the negation of traditional theology, Stirnerian

egoism was hailed the “negation of traditional ethics”.[101] Instead of

Man creating God in his own image, Stirner taught that the individual

ego had created Man in his own image. In The Essence of

Christianity(1841) Feuerbach believed he was being truly radical by

having dissolved the subject (God) into all of its predicates (Man);

Stirner had simply demonstrated how far such dialectical sabotage could

logically go, he chose to dissolve the predicate Society, into the

individual pronouns – I, me, myself. The individual ego was Stirner’s

“laughing heir” to the whole Hegelian project.[102] Stirnerian egoism

was not conceived of as a new form of morality, rather it was opposed to

morality. This is not to say egoism was inherently immoral; Stirner

rejected the idea of absolute opposition between moral categories,

“good” and “evil”, regarding them as “antediluvian”.[103]

Stirner’s claims of ethical antinomianism were deeply felt and taken

seriously by Marx. The Ego encouraged him to dispel any ethical ideas

from the new direction of his thought. Marx already regarded the

Hegelian accounts of political, judicial and moral conceptions as

critically wrong, but The Ego tipped the balance. If Marx’s moral or

metaphysical scepticism stems from Stirner, then the potency of his

criticism of the nihilism inherent in The Ego needs to be re-assessed.

Marx used Stirner’s desecration of morality to justify his own thought,

then proceeded to decry Stirnerian egoism as religious thought, as even

“preaching” a morality. Classifying all idealistic philosophies as

theodicies, a “surreptitious sort of clericalism”[104] that must be

repudiated, was a result of the dogmatic materialist positions that Marx

and Engels came to adopt. All idealists were by default religious

thinkers, yet the materialistic basis of their thought did little to

elucidate their position on moral teaching. The mystification

surrounding Marx’s conception of morality finds its basis in his

distortion of Stirner’s moral nihilism. Rather than offering an

alternative moral theory for communism Marx had disregarded all morality

in the pursuit of revolution and class struggle.

In truth, evacuating the moral content of his thought was something Marx

only aspired to. Ultimately, Stirner had pushed Marx to a philosophical

position where the moral content of his work now had to be implicit.

Sidney Hook states “Marx leaned so far backward that, soon after his

death, the myth became current that he had no place for any ethics in

his philosophy of social activity”.[105] Marx’s reaction was a tactical

manoeuvre, allowing him to preserve the silent moral content of his

work. Karl Popper saw Marx as a man for whom “principles of humanity and

decency … needed no discussion” they were “to be taken for

granted”.[106] However, if Marx decided to adopt a personal notion of

moral principles, why respond to Stirnerian egoism which was so

obviously an aberration? It is difficult to believe that Marx simply

avoided explicit moral theory because he disliked “preaching”, as Popper

assumes. Marx’s real antipathy for moral philosophy was rooted in his

actual thought. The very thought consolidated in The German Ideology as

a result of reading The Ego.

Regardless of the problems Marx left unresolved, the crisis of 1845 had

helped him finally realise the aim of his thought: to prove future world

revolution. However, yet again another Marxian impossibility emerged;

the problem of reconciling historical inevitability with an ethical

model. Historical inevitability could hardly function as an inherent

moral value for Marx.[107] The determinism of the materialist conception

of history had necessitated an angry confrontation with Stirner. It also

illuminated a displeasing characteristic of the young Marx, his

inability to recognize any opposition to his revolution. Further, it

showed that Marx underestimated the role of discontent in historical

events, which Stirner and Hegel did not; they had allowed contingency an

important role in the historical process. Crucially, unlike Marx,

Stirner argued that the historical process had to be the work of human

hands; history was never an abstraction that caused events. It was

concrete, specific and human in all its forms. He also recognised that

certain thinkers had hijacked history, and divested it of its autonomy:

“History seeks for man: but he is I, you, we. Sought as a mysterious

essence, as the divine, first as God, then as man (humanity, humaneness,

and mankind), he is found as the individual, the finite, the unique

one.”[108]

Stirner saw that all kinds of politics wanted to educate man, to bring

him to the realisation of his “essence”, to give man a “destiny” to make

something out of him – namely, a “true man”.[109] This itself was a

ruse, making thinkers fall for “the proper error of religion”.[110]

Whether one saw destiny as divine or human was of no concern. Stirner

found that both positions held that man should become this and that:

this postulate, this commandment, to be something.

Incongruously, in his reading of The Ego Marx felt he could finally

reject a system of morality and yet maintain moral positions. He was

extremely anxious about the fact that his description of socialism could

become tainted by abstract moral ideals, ideals which Stirner had shown

to be transcendent. However, it was Stirner who had equipped Marx with

the very tools to wage a methodological campaign against Feuerbach’s

quasi-religious conception of “Man”, enabling him to reject an “ethics

of love” or a “politics of socialism” through his analysis of the social

nature of man. Such a solution would have been implausible to Stirner.

To many, the religious essence of historical materialism was

“superficially obscured by Marx’s rejection of the traditional

religions”.[111] However, Stirner had already identified such religious

essence in Marx’s pre-1845 intellectual allies. His criticisms of

Feuerbach were equally applicable to the young Marx who had stated: “The

criticism of religion ends with the precept that the supreme being for

man is man”.[112] In the same way Stirner observed the religious essence

of Left Hegelian humanism and early socialism, Marx too stands accused,

his atheism was still a categorically religious proposition.[113] Thus,

Stirner’s original accusation of the “pious” atheism of the Left

Hegelians is particularly compelling when applied to the thought of

young Marx.[114]

It is probable that Stirner would have seen the young Marx as a kind of

post-theological moralist attempting to solve problem of original sin

and ethical commitment through the redemptive power of human “History”.

The picture that Marx paints of capitalists and the bourgeois as

manifestations of evil, and his dismissal of the individual’s

responsibility for their own misery would surely be seen as the

personification of “clericalism”. Stirnerian critique would no doubt

pronounce Marx a vulgar moralist, subordinating the individual to the

new God, “History”. Now that history itself was moralised, the profound

Hegelian awareness of history as amoral was lost.

Like morality, Stirner regarded society as an equally fictive notion,

and saw that moral obligation was presumably derived from the social

nature of man. Stirner observed that man’s social dimension was merely

an alternative type of religious and moral ideology. His hostility to

“sacred society” abounds in The Ego; it was the arena in which “the most

oppressive evils make themselves felt”,[115] its domination was more

brutal and insensitive than any previous despotism. Not only was

Stirner’s notion of state antithetical to Marxism, but by utterly

rejecting the constructions of idealist philosophers he could only

discover consciousness inside the mind; not in some trans-empirical ego

or the Marxian “social being”. For Stirner, emphasis upon the social

nature of the mind, the evaluation of all ideas in relation to the

social whole (or state), represented a menace to individual freedom and

to the autonomy of the individual. He considered social duties as purely

self-legislated. Our relationship to society was seen as one mediated by

the ego. Whilst society may pattern self-realisation and define the

egoist’s rebellion, its formative influence fades in favour of the

individual until “society” itself is entirely displaced. For Marx,

however, the “atomism” of civil society was offensive – and had to be

transcended: Stirner had failed to root his ideas in the social process,

hence the arbitrary nature of his ideology. However, Stirner implied

that certain ideas are not merely reflections of their social

environment and can remain outside the appraisal that they are socially

conditioned by. For Stirner these were the figurative orderings of

experiences, the result of the irreducible egocentric nature of the

individual; self-reflection mediated by personal drives and private

needs.

Marx’s communist vision would still require the individual to conform to

a pattern of behaviour, though not through traditional morals, but

through collective obligation. Stirner’s critique of Feuerbach and

Proudhon had already shown that socialist morality was full of

superstitions, just as much as the Apostles’ creed. Julius’ article in

the second volume of Wigands Vierteljahrschrift (1845) attacked the

essentially Feuerbachian character of Marx’s “practical humanism”, which

Julius considered “religious alienation” – clearly inspired by Stirner’s

perception of socialism.[116] Stirner’s criticisms anticipate much later

accusations, especially from contemporary existentialists, against

Marxism: “Society … is a new master, a new spook, a new “supreme being”

which takes us into its service and allegiance”.[117] If society held

the individual back from achieving autonomy then communism was its most

severe form of suppression. In criticising Weitling’s communism, Stirner

stated that the Communists sought the welfare of all, “true welfare”,

which would eventually degenerate into fixity.[118] Stirner regarded

communism as the “strictest” or most dogmatic paradigm based on the idea

of “Man”. It was a sovereign power exalting itself over men, becoming

their supreme essence, a new god. “Do we not with this come right to the

point where religion begins its dominion of violence?” Stirner

argued.[119] The philosophy of community was enshrined in the old

Feuerbachian problem: separation from human essence. Essence was set

above individuals as something to be striven for, and Stirner argued

that both “Communism, and, consciously egoism-reviling humanism, still

count on love”.[120] The socialist stipulation that individuals must

work to become truly human simply reproduced the religious division of

individuals into “an essential and unessential self”.[121] Here, Stirner

refers to an obscure article by a contemporary – the young Karl Marx.

The dualism that supported social liberalism in all of its various

guises could not be tolerated and was brashly dismissed by Stirner: “we

will hear nothing of this cutting in two”.[122]

Marx misread The Ego, regarding Stirner as an ideologue embroiled in the

malicious circle of critical diatribe which had crippled Left Hegelian

philosophy. Stirner, however, consciously refused to uphold egoism as a

set of ideas or principles.

“Owness includes in itself everything own, and brings to honour again

what Christian language dishonoured. But owness has not any alien

standard either, as it is not in any sense an idea like freedom,

morality, humanity and the like: it is only a description of the –

owner.”[123]

Stirner desired above all to break free of the conceptual quagmire of

the 1840s where to postulate revolution was the trend. Stirner’s

critique of morality and society had shook the young Marx, forcing him

to abandon notions of “species”, “man” and “estrangement” that had

previously been assigned crucial roles in his earlier thought, but

Stirner’s attack on the whole host ofisms went deeper still. If Marx’s

repudiation of The Ego necessitated expunging the questions of ethical

meaning from his thought, then the issues of individual fulfilment and

emancipation – the very nucleus of Stirner’s thought – would also have

to be negated.

Freedom for Stirner was always freedom from some thing or other. Human

freedom was better interpreted as “freedom to action”; Stirner logically

concluded “my freedom becomes complete only when my – might”.[124]

Neither is freedom something to be given, it must be taken and defended:

“If you took might, freedom would come of itself”.[125] Ideologues of

political liberty were more dangerous, in Stirner’s mind, than even

religious or philosophical thinkers. The idea of a society based upon a

single principle (e.g. Communism) was simply an obligation putting man

at the service of the state: “Liberty of the people is not

myliberty!”.[126] Stirner saw that modern socialism, especially the kind

espoused by Proudhon, interposed a new “principle” between the

individual and the property of all, the socialist notion of “social

justice”, a concept just as potentially oppressive as the religious

notion of “divine grace”. Both socialism and communism left the

individual’s mind unchanged; it was still “a mind of dependence”.[127]

Communism was a backward step, a “dependence on another … on the

generality or collectivity”, a “status, a condition hindering my free

movement, a sovereign power over me”.[128]

Marx’s new form of “social justice” was founded on the notion of labour,

compulsory work done in the service of society. For Stirner, the

division of labour, with all its subdivisions, was simply a conceptual

apparatus directed against the individual. This of course led to

alienated labour, which Marx too would later claim to resolve. Stirner

argued that for the individual to negotiate so many forms of alienation

in the world he simply had to “expropriate” his property, his creative

strength and activity, to enable him to rely peacefully on himself

again. Like Hegel, true concrete individuality (Einzelheit) was a return

from alienation. Stirner’s notion of the Einzige, the “Ego”, more

helpfully translated as “The Unique One” clarifies his whole project.

“The Unique One” is man in his irreducible uniqueness, thus egoism is

the final definition of the human “essence”, not the subject of an

ethical category, but an uncomplicated existential fact. If one could

perceive this, all conceivable forms of alienation, conscious or

unconscious, would be impossible. Eigentum (Own-ness or Property) did

not mean a seizure of some moral content, but a man’s identity with his

manifestations, above all, with his individual existence. The notion has

Hegelian heritage: In Philosophy of Right the immediate manifestation of

right (liberty) was the possession by man of his body and his bodily

functions (work). Stirner took his position from the minor degree of

liberty advocated by Hegel. But the idea of liberty, like so many

concepts for Stirner, had been set up as a new absolute, that man should

be free. Stirner declared such a concept was nothing more than “… a new

longing, a new torment, a new deviation, a new deity, a new contrition …

”.[129]

Stirner’s opposition to the dogmatic ideologues clearly engaged the

thought of the young Marx. However, their two antithetical worlds – the

concrete direct experience of The Ego and the world of universal labour

outlined in The German Ideology – would never be reconciled. Marx, as

ever the disciple rather than the usurper of Hegelian thought, had still

sought some kind of accord. In attempting reconciliation, Marx decided

to put forward the doctrine of individual consciousness mediated by

social consciousness. The real question was to what extent social ties

necessarily determined individual consciousness. Marx could not give a

definitive answer. Such ambiguity lends support for Stirner; for if

consciousness was completely determined by society then nothing was to

be done, and an upheaval in the minds of men was therefore not possible.

Stirner allowed individual consciousness to retain some autonomy,

epitomised in the individual ego.

Marx could not perceive of any form such “oppositionist

consciousness”[130] that characterised Stirner’s position and surely

must arise if credence is given to ideas that intend to transform

political reality. Both Stirner and Bauer held that recognition of

dissent or “oppositionist consciousness” was essential to their project:

the merciless use of the principles of criticism, the principle of the

dialectic that would destroy the empty forms founded on dualism.[131]

For Marx, criticism or thought alone was not enough. Thought was the

acknowledged servant of human needs, and desired that philosophy

(generalised thought) become an instrument in changing the world. There

was no “oppositionist consciousness”; only moments of opposition that

were inevitably transformed into successive phases of development in the

historical process. Marx’s notion of social consciousness allowed him to

transcend Stirner’s individualism and as well as the abstract morality

of French materialism, and modify their historical conceptions with the

notion of a dynamic, propelling movement in nature and human thinking –

the dialectic.

Stirner saw man as progressing through stages of conflict and

alienation. He understood as Hegel had, that freedom in contemporary

society was explainable in terms of an individual’s orientation to a set

of moral postulates and social practices. Whilst opposing Hegel, Stirner

ironically posed a truly Hegelian problem: Could the “negativity”

inherent in Hegel’s process of change, the dialectic, ever be halted for

any possible ideological reasons? Both Stirner and Marx laid claim to

the Hegelian dialectic, and both claimed they were demystifying its

nature. Yet Marx’s “fundamental difficulty vis-à-vis Stirner” was the

question of “how will man be once he is free of alienation?”.[132]

Stirner refused to observe that the ideological process required an

intermediate stage; a “total alienation” of consciousness. For Marx,

this stage was to be found in the proletarian classes and necessitated

revolution. Stirner’s reality was the world of his immediate experience;

he wanted power straight away, not after some remote and hypothetical

“proletarian revolution”.

Despite Marx’s own revolutionary tactics and tendencies of the future he

saw displayed in his own age, historical materialism meant he lacked a

doctrine for the immediate present – least of all for those whose

existence was resigned to the limits of the capitalism’s grasp and

economic process. On the other hand, for dissenting members of society

who had yet to become socialist and look forward to the dawn of a “new

order”, Stirnerian egoism provided an alternative protest: disobedience,

radical questioning, active resistance and bodily enjoyment. Most

importantly, it aimed at the deconstruction of linguistic “spooks”,

fixed ideas which ruled the real world. For Marx, Stirner’s radical

resistance did not engage the working class and was dismissed as a

“petty bourgeois essence”. It is ironic that Marx considered Stirner as

a quintessential wallflower of history, epitomising a shopkeeper’s

egoism. Stirner considered himself as going beyond dissent, conjuring a

picture of insurrection, rather than the polarised image of society that

engendered a new, Communistic change of masters: a new religion of

society. Stirner saw it as deceptive that the Enlightenment had simply

amounted to transferring the balance of religion to humanism in its

various bogus guises. Out of this last divisive stage of Hegelianism,

Stirner saw no reason for the dialectic to be subsumed in history.

Unlike Marx, he laid claim to its destructive force in the battle

against alienating concepts:

“… why should I only dissent (think otherwise) about a thing? Why not

push the thinking otherwise to its last extremity, that of no longer

having any regard at all for the thing, and therefore thinking its

nothingness, crushing it? Then the conception itself has en end, because

there is no longer anything to conceive of it.”[133]

Now it is possible to understand how Stirner would seen have the

“historical dialectic” as the “Will of God” reiterated in pseudo-secular

terms, and that Marx, in true theological fashion, attempted to mask the

causal efficacy given to ideological abstractions as “empirical” forces.

Stirner’s position was clearly nihilistic, but by attacking the very

idea of European Enlightenment in the nineteenth-century he had called

into question much more than its socialist doctrines, and insisted that

we lose all of our ideological props.

Conclusion: The divergent perspectives of “intimate” enemies: Marxian

history and Stirnerian egoism.

Marx’s critique of Stirner in The German Ideology was a means of

distinguishing himself from what was, in his eyes, the impotent Left

Hegelian movement. For Marx, alienation was no longer a spiritual

phenomenon, but the objective forms of man’s economic products, the

separation of man from his production. Nevertheless, Marx’s position can

be interpreted as a relapse into Left Hegelianism: He urged a change of

consciousness in order to observe the correctness of a new standpoint;

the communistBetrachtungsweise (mode of view). Instead of the standpoint

from which consciousness is taken as the living individual, Marx wanted

to highlight the rational superiority of his new position adopted in

1844 i.e. that consciousness was a “social product”. More generally,

Marx wanted to establish that labour was our fundamental human relation

to the world and must be regarded as the “celebrated unity of the human

being and nature”.[134] In line with his attempt to leave behind

“philosophy” as he saw it, Marx refused to treat this as a metaphysical

question to be answered by the creation of a metaphysical premise.

Stirner, as opposed to Marx and many others, saw no prescriptive or

essential elements in human nature. He had acquiesced “I am a man just

as the earth is a star”.[135] Neither would Stirner fall into the trap

of picturing a future for man, since it would entail constructing

another external ideal:

“People have always supposed that they must give me a destiny lying

outside myself, so that at last they demanded that I should lay claim to

the human because I am – man. This is the Christian magic circle.”[136]

Stirner’s greatest fear was the “transcendent alternatives” that those

philosophically closest to him were creating: the state, humanity,

politics and the newest “spook” offered by the socialists: society. Like

all Left Hegelians, Stirner knew that he was experiencing the initial

stages of the apocalypse that would replace the old Christian world with

philosophical humanism. This fear is reflected in the “dynamic titanism”

of his own ego which became its own sort of absolute.[137] Dispossessed

by academic and political circumstances of any real power in shaping

humanity and its institutions, the Left Hegelians, particularly Stirner,

had to satisfy themselves with the role of subjective critics.[138]

Social or political action, vindicated by the younger generation of

Hegelians (especially Marx and Engels), was held in contempt. Stirner’s

inherent social atomism was evidently incompatible with the idea Marx

shared with the Utopian French socialists: the desire for a truly

“human” society.

If we regard Hegel as the last of the contemplative philosophers who

possessed the “secret of contemplation”, post-Hegelian philosophy

becomes what one commentator has called a “lost paradise”.[139] Stirner

reverted to the acquiescent attitude of a self-effacing mortal who must

find his entire fulfilment in his own life. Marx, to counter what he

perceived as Stirner’s and Hegel’s quietism, developed a universal

theory of action where contemplation was replaced by intolerance of

those who seek out a better state of things. Marx’s answer was a form of

materialistic fatalism that operated through economic laws. Stirner had

forced not so much an Althusserian “epistemological break” in the young

Marx’s thought, but had required him to retreat from a normative

conception of human nature. Marx’s historical ontology meant either

equating good with what happens or denying that there is any good: The

outcome was either way a form of nihilism. Whilst apparently repudiating

Stirner’s nihilistic egoism, Marx incorporated this nihilism into his

theory of history. For if man creates himself in history, then there is

no human essence from which he can be alienated. Therefore Marx cannot

justifiably assert the pre-eminence of communist society. The

incoherence of Marx’s philosophical anthropology was as much a result of

his intense encounter with Stirner as well as with non-German

philosophical concepts that had entered his work. In the mid-eighteen

forties Marx and Engels absorbed French ideas into the Hegelian

metaphysic. The French experience as well as that of the wider

industrial world – such as the advanced industrialisation of Victorian

England – dictated that the social question of industrial change and

labour emerged as the most significant of their age.[140]

Occupying another world, isolated and thoroughly bourgeois, the “Berlin

Buddhists” remained indifferent to these apparently epochal changes.

Only in Germany, where intellectuals inhabited an eccentric world of

blithe fantasy, would Marx’s reading of the “social question” not be

explicable. For Marx, German theoretical engagement with political forms

had consequently assumed a more abstract form than prevalent

elsewhere.[141] Nonetheless this context affords Stirner the unique

position of a disenfranchised academic dissenter, a point of

disinterestedness between the proletariat and the bourgeoisie. Stirner

occupied a disoriented historical moment, one before the experience of

capitalism and industry had been filtered through the paradigmatic

Marxian idioms. Moreover, Stirner did attempt to tackle the social

phenomenon of “pauperism” (the progressive impoverishment of the lower

social strata) which has been identified as the “dominant” social issue

of “pre-March” period.[142] Unlike the social problems that Marx

identified, pauperism was not a direct result of capitalism or even of

rapid industrialization, but a problem of demographic growth and was a

singularly (ignoring Berlin) rural phenomenon. Pauperism differed much

from traditional poverty. It was collective and structural rather than

determined by individual contingencies. Stirner recognized this social

phenomenon and discussed it at length in The Ego.[143] He was not

failing to grasp the true “social question” as Marx makes out; instead

he was analyzing his own reality: the parochial, yet unique,

pre-Industrial phase of German history – what Eric Hobsbawn called “the

last, and perhaps worst, economic breakdown of the ancien régime”.[144]

Stirner, along with the other Left Hegelians, saw himself as exclusively

concerned with the historical transition from religion to philosophy,

the fall-out of Hegelian thought. Marx, on the other hand, had already

proposed to disentangle himself from what he called “philosophy” through

his theory of history. It is therefore little wonder that these two

thinkers clashed theoretically, and that the specific ontological

debates would be forgotten. In a crossed sentence from The German

Ideology Marx confessed “We know only a single science, the science of

history”.[145] Marx’s conception of history meant every profound

philosophical problem would resolve itself as an empirical fact, and

thus Marx felt free to abandon the metaphysical conception of essence

that had been central to his thought up to 1845. With the division of

labour, one’s orientation to the world was a less important concern. By

rejecting this significant component of his conception of human nature,

Marx struggled to avoid his philosophical obligations. The German

Ideology was an attempt to avoid having to defend one’s standpoint

philosophically, to escape the Hegelian prerequisite to occupy a

supposedly epistemologically privileged position.

For all the progression that Marxists like to attribute to it, The

German Ideologywas also a reductive exercise. Marx and Engels swept

aside certain issues (ethics, individuality, consciousness) which they

longer wanted on their “erstwhile philosophical conscience”. The Ego had

conditioned Marx’s ontological response to Left Hegelian humanism. As we

have already seen, The Ego was not only a catalyst in Marx’s adoption of

the philosophical method of historical materialism, but also stood as an

anticipatory critique of its emergent form. Stirner had forced Marx to

break with Left Hegelian modes of thought, fracturing the epistemology

and materialism Marx had developed in Theses on Feuerbach and the

Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844. In doing this, he forced

Marx to fundamentally reappraise his position on the role of human

nature in relation to his social criticism.

As a theoretical conclusion to the criticism of religion, the

“materialist conception of history” was an ambiguous explanation. Rather

than settlingMarx’s conscience, The German Ideology emphatically

displayed it as a badconscience. For many, Marx’s anger seems

disproportionate to the threat posed by Stirner, yet a closer analysis

has revealed just how much was at stake in their encounter. Marx chose

to make Stirner into a scapegoat, an opportune external object onto

which to project the unresolved inner conflict of his early thought. The

garrulous “Sankt Max” was the work of an intellect under threat. Derrida

recognised this:

“My feeling … is that Marx scares himself, he himself pursues

relentlessly someone who almost resembles him to the point that we could

mistake one for the other: a brother, a double, thus a diabolical image.

A kind of ghost of himself.”[146]

Parallels between the two thinkers are often neglected. However, as we

have seen, Marx and Stirner shared much in terms of philosophical

language and theoretical goals. Regardless of the claims about Marxian

humanism, Stirnerian egoism was just as much the “true” heir to German

Idealist Philosophy. Stirner had realised the fundamental nihilistic

element present in secularised Hegelianism and – through dialectics –

fearlessly drawn the consequence that “everything is permitted”.[147] Or

as Giles Deleuze more boldly claimed, “Stirner is the dialectician who

reveals nihilism as the truth of the dialectic”.[148] Stirnerian

nihilistic egoism, not Marxian humanism, certainly seems more consistent

with an overthrow of suprahistorical values. The sovereignty of the ego

and the exercise of self-assertion are the more spontaneous consequences

of the “death of God” and transcendent norms, as opposed to a philosophy

of community.

Marxists who see Marx and Engels’ socialism eschewing naturally from

Left Hegelian humanism remain blinded by the alternative, highly

inaccurate, account of their early thought which both men later

developed. The Ego remains a unique and powerful attack on Marxism as

well as all forms of socialism; Stirner highlighted the contradictions

and problems inherent any form of socialist or communist society. Yet

ironically for Max Stirner, the force of The Ego pushed Marx to embrace

the totalising perspective of an essential communism, nascent in The

German Ideology, rather than devalue the future of socialist thought

which it had, in part, helped create. With the advent of Marxism,

Stirner’s work was displaced in intellectual history. If Stirner is to

undergo rehabilitation as a thinker, it is important that this must not

revolve solely around Marx’s “leading role”, or in assigning debt to

Stirner where it is due. Future scholarship must attempt to escape his

status as the “too much intimate enemy” of Marx.[149]

In conclusion, Stirner’s answer to problems of the Hegelian dialectic

was to rewrite in existential terms as the historico-cultural narrative

of the self-actualisation of the spirit. His book described the

liberated, self-expressive, contingent, existing individual as the

“laughing heir”[150] of a dialectical development from immediacy through

self-division, to self-conscious freedom and transparency. In The Ego,

the Hegelian description of redemption found an existential form in

“living oneself out”.[151] Stirner set his existential perspectives

against the essentialism of Marx and others. Marx’s The German Ideology

was an attempt to wrench socialism from its utopian yearnings and

transform it philosophically into an empirical science. In doing so,

Marx escaped the Hegelian conception of “consciousness” by turning

consciousness into a by-product, socially determined. These two terminal

and antithetical standpoints occupied by Stirner and Marx in 1845 have

allowed fragments of the Hegelian project to continue to shape and frame

the Marxist/Existentialist debate of the last and present century.

Bibliography

Primary Sources

Engels, F., “Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German

Philosophy” in MarxEngels Collected Works, vol. 26. (London 1976).

Feuerbach, L., The Essence of Christianity trans. George Eliot (New

York, 1957).

Marx, K. & Engels F., The German Ideology in Marx Engels Collected

Works,vol. 5 (London 1976), 19–539.

Marx, K. & Engels F., Selected Writings, ed. D. McLellan (Oxford, 2000).

Marx, K. Capital (New York 1972–73), vol. I.

Stirner, M., The Ego and His Own trans. Steven T. Byington, ed. David

Leopold (Cambridge, 1995).

Stirner, M., The False Principle of our Education, or, Humanism and

Realism, ed. James J. Martin (Colorado Springs, Ralph Melees 1967).

Secondary Sources

Berlin, Isaiah, Karl Marx: His Life and Environment 4^(th) ed. (Oxford

2000)

Brazill, William J., The Young Hegelians (Yale 1970.).

Browning, G., Hegel & the History of Political Philosophy (Macmillan

1999).

Brudney, D., Marx’s Attempt to Leave Philosophy (Harvard 1998).

Buber, Paths in Utopia (London 1949).

Carroll, J., Break-out from the Crystal Palace: The

Anarcho-Psychological Critique; Stirner, Nietzsche, Dostoevsky (London

1974).

Churbanov, L., Preface to The German Ideology , Institute of

Marxism-Leninism, in Marx, K, “The German Ideology” in MarxEngels

Collected Worksvol 5.

Clark, C., “Germany 1815–1848: Restoration or pre-March?” in German

History since 1800 ed. Mary Fulbrook (Arnold 1997), 38–60.

Clark, John P., Max Stirner’s Egoism (London 1976.)

Collingwood, R. G., The Idea of History (Oxford 1956).

Deleuze, G., Nietzsche & Philosophy (Columbia 1985).

Dematteis, P. B., Individuality and the Social Organism: The Controversy

between Max Stirner and Karl Marx (New York 1976).

Derrida, J., Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of

Mourning, and the New International trans. Peggy Kamuf, (London 1994).

Dupré, L., The Philosophical Foundations of Marxism (New York 1966).

Fleischmann, E. “The role of the individual in pre-revolutionary

society: Stirner, Marx, and Hegel” in Hegel’s Political Philosophy,

Problems and Perspectives: A Collection of Essays edit. Z.A. Pelczynski

(Cambridge 1971).

Griffin, R. “Between metapolitics and apoliteia: the New Right’s

strategy for conserving the fascist vision in the “interregnum”,Modern

and Contemporary France, 8 : 2 (2000).

Grimes, C.E. & Simmons, E.P. “A Reassessment of Alienation in Karl

Marx’s in The Western Political Quarterly Vol. 23, No.2 (Jun 1970), pp.

266–275.

Helms, Die Ideologie der anonymen Gesellschaft (Cologne 1968).

Arvon, H., Aux sources de 1’existentialisme Max Stirner (Paris 1954).

Hook, S. “Philosophy of Dialectical Materialism”, pt. 1 Journal of

Philosophy, 25 :5,

(1March 1928) and pt 2. Journal of Philosophy, 25 : 6 (15 March 1928).

Hook, S. From Hegel to Marx: Studies in the Intellectual Development of

Karl Marx (Michigan 1962).

Huneker, J., Egoists: A Book of Supermen (New York 1909).

Kolakowski, L., Main Currents of Marxism vol. 1–3, (Oxford 1978).

Laska, Bernd A., “A Durable Dissident”, in Stirner-Studien No. 2

(Nuremberg 1996) trans. Shveta Thakrar (June 2001),

http://www.lsr-projekt.de/poly/eninnuce.html.

Leopold, D., “Introduction” in TheEgo and Its Own , (Cambridge 1995)

xi-xxxii.

Lobkowicz, N., “Karl Marx and Max Stirner” in Demythologising Marxism,

ed. Frederick J. Adelmann (The Hague 1969) 64–95.

Lobkowicz, N., Theory and Practice: History of a Concept from Aristotle

to Marx (Notre Dame 1967).

Lowith, K. From Hegel to Nietzsche: The Revolution in Ninteeth-Century

Thought, trans. David E. Green (NY, 1967). (Original German edition,

1941)

Mackay, J. H., Max Stirner. Sein Leben und sein Werk, 2^(nd) edition

(Berlin 1914).

Mackay, J. H., Max Stirner’s Kleinere Schriften (Berlin 1914).

Nielsen K. and Patten S. (eds) Marx and Morality (Ontario 1981).

McLellan, D., The Young Hegelians and Karl Marx, (Macmillan 1969).

Myers, D. B. “Marx and the Problem of Nihilism” in Philosophy and

Phenomenological Research, 37 : 2 (Dec 1976), 193–204.

Newman, S., From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-Authoritarianism and the

Dislocation of Power (Lexington 2001).

Parker, S.E, “Introduction” in The Ego and Its Own (London 1982).

Paterson, R. W. K. The Nihilistic Egoist Max Stirner (Hull 1971).

Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies vol. II (London 2002).

Stedman-Jones, G., “Introduction” in The Communist Manifesto (Penguin

Classics 2002).

Stepelevich, L. “Introduction” in The Young Hegelians: An Anthology edit

L. S. Stepelevich (Cambridge 1983).

Stepelevich, Lawrence S., “Hegel and Stirner: Thesis and Antithesis”,

Idealistic Studies, 6 : 3 (September 1976).

Stepelevich, Lawrence S., “Max Stirner and Ludwig Feuerbach”, Journal of

the History of Ideas (1978) 39 : 451–463.

Stepelevich, Lawrence S., “Max Stirner as Hegelian”, Journal of the

History of Ideas (1985) 46 : 597–614.

Stepelevich, Lawrence S., “The Revival of Max Stirner” Journal of the

History of Ideas 35 : 2 (April – June 1974), 323–328.

Stepelevich, Lawrence S., (ed.) The Young Hegelians: An Anthology

(Cambridge 1983).

Stern , R. Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit (Routledge 2002).

Thomas, P. “Karl Marx and Max Stirner” in Political Theory, 3 : 2 (May

1975), 159–179.

Toews, John Edward., Hegelianism: The Path Toward Dialectical Humanism,

1805–1841. (Cambridge 1985).

Toews, John Edward., “Transformations of Hegelianism, 1805–1846”, in The

Cambridge Companion to Hegel ed. Frederick C. Beiser (Cambridge 1993),

378–413.

Tucker, R., Philosophy and Myth in Karl Marx (Cambridge 1972).

[1] The Ego and Its Own (Leipzig, 1845). This work appeared in December

of 1844, and press copies were available even earlier, as Moses Hess had

read and forwarded his copy to Fredrich Engels no later than early

November of 1844. I will use David Leopold revised version of “The Ego

and His Own” (Cambridge 1995) based on Steven Byington’s original

translation. This edition will hereafter be referred to as The Ego.

[2] Patterson (1971): 102.

[3] Hence Bauer’s later characterisation of the group as Berlin’s “beer

literati”.

[4] Patterson (1971): 8.

[5] On Die Freien see: Patterson (1971) : 67–93; and Gustav Mayer, “Die

Anfange des politischen Radikalismus im vormarzlichen Preussen,” in

Zeitschrift für Politik. (1913) 6: 45–72.

[6] First usage: Engels to Marx, 19^(th) November 1844 in MECW, 38: 11.

[7] See Hess’ “The Recent Philosophers” in Stepelevich (1983).

[8] Cited by McLellan (1969): 130.

[9] McLellan (1969): 130.

[10] Engels to Marx, 19^(th) November 1844, MECW, 38: 13.

[11] Parker, S.E, “Introduction” The Ego and Its Own (1982).

[12] Patterson (1971) : 98.

[13] Stepelevich (1983): 14.

[14] Stepelevich (1983): 14.

[15] Stepelevich (1983): 14.

[16] Stepelevich (1983): 14.

[17] Cited by Stepelevich (1974) : 323.

[18] Engels to Marx, 19^(th) November 1844 in MECW, 38 : 11.

[19] The German Ideology in MECW (1976) 5 : 19–539.

[20] Marx Selected Writings ed. D. McLellan (2000) : 177.

[21] McLellan (2000) : 177.

[22] Engels, F. “Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German

Philosophy” in MECW, vol. 26.

[23] Patterson (1971) : 105.

[24] Avron (1954) : 149.

[25] Mackay (1898).

[26] Löwith (1967) : 187.

[27] Quoted in Basch, L’individualisme anarchiste: Max Stirner : ii-iii.

[28] Woodcock, Anarchism, ch. 4. cited by Patterson (1971) : 126–127.

[29] Avron (1954) cited by Patterson (1971) : 127.

[30] Helms (1968).

[31] Griffin, R. “Between metapolitics and apoliteia: the New Right’s

strategy for conserving the fascist vision in the “interregnum”, Modern

and Contemporary France 8 : 2 (2000).

[32] Hook (1962): 165.

[33] Berlin (2000) : 143.

[34] Avron (1954).

[35] Toews (1985) : 368.

[36] Toews (1985) : 369.

[37] Toews (1985) : 369.

[38] Toews (1985) : 369.

[39] Stepelevich (1974) : 325.

[40] Laska, Bernd A. LSR Publishing House, Nuremberg.

[41] Newman (2001) : 9.

[42] Stepelevich (1974) : 328.

[43] Derrida (1994 ) : 99.

[44] Huneker (1909) : 350.

[45] Clark (1997) : 38.

[46] Patterson (1971): 22.

[47] Patterson (1971): 33.

[48] Patterson (1971): 33.

[49] Mackay (1914) : 235.

[50] Stirner, The False Principle of Our Education Or Humanism And

Realismfirst published in the supplements to four numbers of the

Rheinische Zeitungbetween the 10^(th) and l9th of April, 1842 edited by

James J. Martin (Colorado Springs 1967).

[51] Stirner, The False Principle of Our Education from

http://www.nonserviam.com/egoistarchive/stirner/articles/false.html

[52] Toews (1993) : 378.

[53] Toews (1993) : 391.

[54] Toews (1993) : 393.

[55] Bauer, B. Die Posaune des jüngsten Gerichts über Hegel den

Atheisten und Antichristen: Ein Ultimatum (Leipzig, 1841) : 77, 70.

[56] Feuerbach, (1957) : 75.

[57] Toews (1993) : 400.

[58] Stirner (1995) : 140.

[59] Stirner (1995) : 204.

[60] Patterson (1971) : 20.

[61] Lobkowicz (1969) : 85.

[62] Patterson (1971) : 20.

[63] Stepelevich (1985) : 601.

[64] Löwith (1967) : 102.

[65] McLellan (1969) : 119 cited by Stepelevich (1985).

[66] Toews (1985) : 604.

[67] Marx (1976) : 23.

[68] Marx (1976) : 27.

[69] Marx (1976) : 24.

[70] Stirner (1995) : 166

[71] Lobkowicz (1967) : 394.

[72] Lobkowicz (1967) : 395.

[73] Marx, “A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy”, MECW,

8 : 362.

[74] Lobkowicz (1967) : 397.

[75] Marx (1976) : 28.

[76] Brudney (1998) : 272.

[77] Stirner (1995) : 64–5

[78] Stirner (1995) : 88

[79] Marx (1976) : 36–37.

[80] Stedman-Jones (2002) : 144.

[81] Marx (1972–73) 1 : 19, 20.

[82] Collingwood (1956) : 125.

[83] Collingwood (1956) : 125.

[84] Kolakowski (1978) 2 : 403.

[85] Stedman-Jones (2002): 145.

[86] Marx (1976): 31.

[87] Cf. Stirner’s anonymously published article, “Recensenten Stirners”

in Wigands Vierteljahrsschrift 3 (1845) 183. Cf. MECWvol 3. cf. 248.

[88] Lobkowicz (1978) : 412.

[89] Lobkowicz (1978) : 415.

[90] Lobkowicz (1967) : 413.

[91] Marx (1972–73) 2 : 863.

[92] Lobkowicz (1967) : 413.

[93] Stirner (1995) : 5, 7.

[94] Preface to The German Ideology, Lev Churbanov, Institute of

Marxism-Leninism in Marx, K, The German Ideology, MECW 5 : xiii.

[95] Stedman-Jones (2002) : 146.

[96] Hook (1962): ch.5, sec. II, I (a).

[97] Hook (1962) : 165.

[98] Buber (1949) : 10.

[99] Marx (1976) : 247.

[100] Stirner (1995) : 45.

[101] Hook (1962) : 171–172.

[102] Stirner (1995) : 286.

[103] Stirner (1995) : 317.

[104] Hook (1928) : 121.

[105] Hook (1962) : 51

[106] Popper (2002) : 187–8

[107] Tucker (1972) : 22.

[108] Stirner (1995) : 217.

[109] Stirner (1995) : 215.

[110] Stirner (1995) : 215.

[111] Tucker (1972) : 22.

[112] 1844, cited by Tucker (1972).

[113] Tucker (1972) : 22.

[114] However, Tucker like so many others, misses the importance of The

Ego. Stirner not only voiced essentially moderncriticisms of communist

ideology, but he did so long before Marx’s thought was formally

consolidated in The Communist Manifesto.

[115] Stirner (1995) : 106.

[116] Arnold Ruge’s thought was influenced in the same way, and

expressed his admiration in his work entitled Our Last Ten Years.

[117] Stirner (1995) : 131.

[118] Stirner (1995) : 271.

[119] Stirner (1995) : 273.

[120] Stirner (1995) : 274.

[121] Stirner (1995) : 34.

[122] Stirner (1995) : 32.

[123] Stirner (1995) : 154.

[124] Stirner (1995) : 151.

[125] Stirner (1995) : 151.

[126] Stirner (1995) : 190.

[127] Stirner (1995) : 228.

[128] Stirner (1995) : 228.

[129] Stirner (1995) : 216.

[130] Hook (1967 ): 176.

[131] Brazill (1970) : 177–225.

[132] Hook (1962): 227.

[133] Stirner (1995) : 299.

[134] Brudney (1998) : 287

[135] Brudney (1998) : 163.

[136] Brudney (1998) : 318.

[137] Brazill (1970) : 224.

[138] Brudney (1998) : 224.

[139] Stern (2002).

[140] Brazill (1970) : 271.

[141] Marx (1976) : 489, 493

[142] Clark (1997) : 53.

[143] Stirner (1995) : 224–227.

[144] Cited by Clark (1997) : 53.

[145] Marx (1976) : 28.

[146] Derrida (1994) : 139–140.

[147] Myers (1976) : 193.

[148] Deleuze (1985) : 161.

[149] Calasso, R. “Accompagnamento alla lettura di Stirner”, in Max

Stirner, L’Unico e la sua proprietà, Adelphi, (Milan 1999), 412.

[150] Stirner (1995) : 286.

[151] Stirner (1995) : 293, 294.