💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › a-j-baker-sydney-libertarianism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:10:40. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Sydney Libertarianism
Author: A.J. Baker
Date: March 1960
Language: en
Topics: Australia, diversity, ideology
Source: http://www.takver.com/history/sydney/baker1.htm
Notes: (Based on a paper given to the London Anarchist Group in March 1960)

A.J. Baker

Sydney Libertarianism

I. SOCIAL THEORY.

In explaining their position Sydney libertarians often refer to their

interest in social theory. But this phrase, “social theory,” can

suggest, not only empirical study, but also the making of certain

criticisms; and at the same time, the question may be asked: How are

these connected with the attitudes and sympathies libertarians have,

with their support for particular social causes? Thus (1) we should

expect social theory to be concerned with developing true views about

the nature and interconnection of social phenomena, and the position of

libertarians does depend partly on what they take to be certain facts

about how society operates.

But (2) this almost always gets connected with criticism and argument,

for the social theorist is led to demolish certain fallacious arguments

he encounters. For example, libertarians take the important thing about

religion to be the actual, earthly role of religious institutions, but

they are also led to attack the theological and moral views of religious

people. Or, as a different example, libertarians regard some of Marx’s

work as an important contribution to the study of society, but in view

of misunderstandings about Marxism and the deification of Marx by some,

clarity also demands that the predominant anti-empirical, metaphysical

part of Marxism be revealed and criticised.

It is easy to see why (1) comes to be accompanied by (2). In any subject

matter there are forces obstructing knowledge (cf. Copernicus, Galileo,

Darwin), but the obstructions are all the more powerful in the social

field. There, recognition of how things are cuts too deep and injures

personal hopes and illusions as well as offending influential social

groups. As a result, examination of concepts and criticism of beliefs

are imperative; people have little chance of becoming aware of truths

about society unless at the same time they come to see through

prevailing false or absurd beliefs about human conduct and social

affairs.

(3) Social theorists have preferences or policies of their own. (Of

course, to be a social theorist is not necessarily to be partial or

one-sided in a crude sense — Lenin’s dictum “all theory is partisan,” in

the crude way he meant it, illogically denies any distinction between

truth and falsity. But the academic notion of complete detachment or

disinterestedness wrongly treats the social theorist as a mere external

spectator with no social existence and interests of his own.) In the

case of libertarians, their social theory is accompanied and stimulated

by the interest they have in struggling against authoritarian forces and

ideas. And, as a matter of fact, those people who combine (1) and (2)

above, i.e.. who are not mere uncritical collectors of “facts,” usually

do take an anti-authoritarian stand. There can be exceptions; an example

of particular interest to libertarians being Pareto, for he presented an

account of society much of which libertarians can accept and yet had

some authoritarian preferences. But this is rare. Nearly always what

passes for social theory amongst supporters of various kinds of

authoritarianism are ideology and false belief.

In other words, recognising how society goes on, criticising widespread

but mistaken beliefs, and having the interests they have or the

particular causes they support, together make up the libertarian

position. (As will emerge, it is the anti-authoritarian sympathies they

share with them which give libertarians their affinity with, but their

social theory which distinguishes them from, classical anarchists.)

What social beliefs do libertarians reject as uncritical? What account

do they give of society? An indication may be given if I say something

about two categories or concepts which appear indispensable to social

theory — those which can be labeled “pluralism” and “ideology.”

(‘a) Social pluralism is roughly the view that society is not a single

thing but a diversity of different and often competing activities and

interests. A popular way of bringing this out is by exposing appeals to

the“common good”, “the welfare of the people,” etc. These phrases

suggest unanimity and singleness of interest , but in fact receive

emphasis only when there is variety and conflict — i.e., they enable a

particular group to masquerade as representative of all, and so to

advance its own particular policies in a covert way. (Note that this is

true not only in the case of attempted justifications of censorship,

Crimes Acts, the illegalisation of abortion, and so on, it is also true

of such things as an interest in good health, fresh air, etc., which,

being favoured by most members of society, may appear to be more

plausible examples of the common interests of society. These rarely

become social or political issues; when they do, however, as with issues

about national health services, compulsory T.B. tests, the eradication

of smog, and so on, it is quite clear that to refer to them as “the

interests of all” is to conceal genuine conflicts of interest.) Contrary

to the unitary view of society — which would make past history and

present day-to-day politics inexplicable — there are in society many

different interests. some of which are simply irreconcilable and remain

in permanent conflict.

(b) Libertarians emphasise what is one of Marx’s most defensible

concepts, that of ideology. Of course, everyone uses the word “ideology”

today: Russian and American politicians and all the newspapers, and in

relation to Marx’s original meaning they all use it wrongly — i.e., they

use it to refer to any set of ideas which is taken to support a

political interest. Now there were ambiguities in what Marx himself

said, and Lenin and the other Russian Communists were mainly responsible

for the wrong use current to-day, but what I have in mind is Marx’s use

of the word “ideology” to describe theories or beliefs which are

unconscious expressions of something else or camouflage the promotion of

special interests. Compare Marx’s own best example: that in 1848 the

bourgeoisie spoke of Liberty, Fraternity, Equality, but what they really

meant were Infantry, Cavalry, Artillery. (Note the ironic truth which

results when we translate into Marx’s use references by Khrushchev to

“our Communist ideology” or by Eisenhower to “our Christian ideology”.)

It is convenient, though not essential, to bring out the nature of

ideologies by referring to Marx. Pareto, for instance, drew attention to

the same type of thing in a different, more ramified way by emphasising

the fact that throughout history there have been myths, superstitions,

religious views, moral theories, and so on, which taken at their face

value are empty of content and. indeed, meaningless, and yet have had

immense influence in history. For that matter, if we make even a cursory

study of moral justifications, it is easy to detect the presence of

ideological processes. Almost every group speaks in the name of the

good, right, justice, natural law, progress, happiness, and so on, but

it is usually transparent that these are unconscious covers for the

promotion of certain policies or interests at the expense of others.

(The reference to unconscious covers is to be stressed. Using ideology

is quite different from being a cynical or unscrupulous Machiavellian —

when people say they are furthering the good, etc., they usually

sincerely believe what they say.) It is as if individuals and groups

have a blockage, they cannot face up to the unpleasant fact that there

are conflicts and differences of interest in society. Hence arises the

tendency they have, to use ideology to disguise from themselves and

others what their policies really are.

To sum up: An ideology is a belief (or set of beliefs) which (I)

masquerades as a true belief and is taken by its believers simply to be

a true belief, (ii) in fact, taken literally, is neither true nor false,

but instead is absurd or meaningless, (iii) has the actual social role

of covertly assisting special interests. Such beliefs or theories,

libertarians point out, are not expendable extras which are occasionally

let loose on society; on the contrary, they are exceedingly prevalent

and influential: it is a rare social or political controversy which is

not marked by liberal use of ideological concepts and beliefs. From this

arises the importance libertarians attach to criticising ideologies and

bringing out their real social roles.

II. ANARCHISM WITHOUT ENDS.

Given this type of social theory, Sydney libertarians point out that

although they share the anti-authoritarian interests of classical

anarchists they cannot help but be critical of utopian anarchism — i.e.,

of the kind of anarchism which fixes its sights on the future and

contends that the main thing is to work for the achievement of the

future “free society.” Such a view is open to criticism (a) because it

involves a false social theory and (b) because its emphasis on the

future obscures what has always been the most important feature of

anarchist and libertarian activity, being anarchist or libertarian here

and now.

Thus the problem for the utopian anarchist is to explain how the passage

from an unfree to a free society is going to take place.But the solution

offered (e.g., by Kropotkin) greatly over-emphasises the part that can

be played by co-operation and rational persuasion. The ideas and

practices which prevail in existing society, it is claimed; are so

obviously vicious and illogical that they cannot persist. With the

spread of education and the growth of a saner attitude to political and

social questions we must expect the gradual triumph of the rational and

freedom-loving outlook.

The trouble with this belief is that it assumes education and persuasion

occur in a social vacuum, when in fact they occur under definite social

conditions, and we can by no means alter these conditions at will. It is

likewise assumed that the rational decisions of men have an immense

influence on the course of events, when the social facts go against this

assumption. Thus, take the operation of social institutions like the

State, Churches, the army, universities, and so on. These don’t arise

because (or just because) certain people get together and decide to

create them nor do they continue to exist because certain people have

decided to prolong their existence. Institutions are usually there,

going on in certain specifiable ways, irrespective of what rational

decisions individuals make or fail to make. Anarchists have always been

the first to point this out in regard to the State -e.g., that those

like the Bolsheviks, who think they capture or control the State are, in

fact, captured or controlled by the State; hence the continuity of the

State machine and its manner of working from Tsarist to Soviet times.

But the same is true of other institutions. Imagine a revolutionary

minded bank manager trying to reform the activities of a bank. It is

obvious that banking activities have ways of going on, which set severe

limits to what individuals can do -e.g., if the manager started giving

unlimited overdrafts the bank would collapse; and there is also a second

kind of limit: the training, outlook, etc., usually required for a man

to become a bank manager. So, the general conclusion we have to draw is

this: far from the ideas and decisions of men controlling social

activities and institutions, it is much more the other way round. Parts

of State apparatus such as the army and public service are not just

instruments of the politicians, let alone of “the people”; like

newspaper organisations, trade union secretariats, and so on, they have

a “life” of their own, and largely shape the outlook of the men who work

in them.

All this conflicts with the hopeful belief of the utopian anarchist that

by education and rational persuasion men can be led to decide on the

formation of a free society. (In this respect, Syndicalists and the

I.W.W. — “a new society within the shell of the old” — had a more

defensible, though still utopian, position.)

To take concrete case: consider the type of sexually free society

Wilhelm Reich advocated. In existing society we have what Reich called

the “authoritarian sexual morality,” i.e., the denial of adolescent

sexuality, emphasis on compulsive monogamy, and so on, which means that

the great mass of the people, even jealousy or other disturbances to

their sexualities. But, in contrast with this, when they are married,

are subject to guilt feelings, possessive, Reich argued, it is

biologically perfectly possible for people to have non-authoritarian,

orgiastically much more satisfactory, sexual relationships.Well, then,

suppose we want to bring about a society in which this kind of sexual

freedom prevails. It is highly utopian to think that people could be

rationally educated into this, even if many of them would gain from

doing so. For sexual freedom to occur on a large scale, two things would

have to be achieved: first, a negative requirement, the power of

religious and other moralistic forces in society would have to be

destroyed; and, secondly, on the positive side, new social conditions

would have to arise or be brought about in which it would be possible

for straightforward and non-guilt ridden sexual relationships to become

widespread. But a policy of rational argument and good wishes would not

achieve these results. Thus, to bring about the second, not only would

there need to be such obvious conditions as the availability of

contraception and abortion, there would also have to be the absence of

neurosis and guilt feelings in the people themselves. But these guilt

feelings -or, as Reich says, the incapacity of people for orgastic

satisfaction — are mainly derived from childhood training and from the

guilts and prohibitions instilled by the existing educational system.

But how do we, the would-be revolutionaries, change the existing

educational system? By educating the existing educators? But in that

case we should need to be already running the educational system! In

other words, it is one thing to know how the prevailing sexual ideology

affects the sexual life of most people and a quite different thing to

bring about a significant disappearance of that ideology.

For reasons of this kind, then, Sydney libertarians are wary of talking

about reforming society or about future freedom. Instead they use such

phrases as “anarchism without ends.” “pessimistic anarchism,” “permanent

protest”. “Anarchism without ends” indicates that there are

anarchist-like activities such as criticising the views of

authoritarians, resisting the pressure towards servility and conformity,

having unauthoritarian sexual relationships, which can be carried on for

their own sake, here and now, without any reference to supposed future

ends. Similarly, the label, “pessimistic anarchism.” indicates that you

can expect authoritarian forces in any society whatever, that freedom is

something you always have to struggle for, and is not something which

can be guaranteed in some future society. (“Pessimistic anarchism” also

hits off the fact that libertarians have many of the sympathies:and

interests of the classical anarchists, but have views about the nature

of society more akin to those of the “pessimistic sociologists,” Pareto,

Mosca and Michels.) Then there is the slogan, “permanent protest,” which

has been borrowed from Max Nomad, who also refers to “permanent

revolution” and “perpetual opposition.” (Compare, e.g., his books,

Rebels and Renegades and Apostles of Revolution.) The libertarian use of

the phrase, “permanent protest,” has some differences from Nomad’s use,

for he has more in mind mass revolutionary movements and argues that the

underdog is born to be betrayed by all of his would be emancipators, but

that the only thing for the underdog to do is to go on protesting.

(Compare Albert Camus in The Rebel: “The historic mission of the

proletariat is to be betrayed;” and his distinction between (constant)

rebellion which he supports and (final) revolution which he opposes

because it merely introduces a new form of tyranny.) But while Nomad

refers particularly to protest against the social structure as a whole

(the overall distribution of power and privilege), libertarians in

speaking of “permanent protest” wish rather to stress the carrying on of

particular libertarian activities within existing society (i.e., in a

country like Australia which has social conditions rather different from

those, e.g., in Bulgaria, Spain or Cuba).

What are examples of these activities? A very obvious one is the work of

criticism carried on by the Libertarian Society. There are various false

theories, metaphysical views, overt and concealed moral and political

assumptions that have wide influence in society; the role of the critic

is to expose these as illusions or ideologies, and this is a permanent

job which has to be carried on from generation to generation.

Politicians, priests and policemen don’t change just because their

justifications of themselves are shown to be illogical or absurd.

Similarly, other libertarian activities are carried on here and now and

not with an eye to some future state of affairs when they will cease to

exist. The utopian picture of a future free society would not even be

intelligible to us if we were not already acquainted with examples of

unauthoritarian activities in our present society. Contrary to the

utopian, the libertarian looks not to some future society in which

authoritarianism will have been got rid of and freedom supposedly

brought into existence for the first time. Instead, he takes it to be a

matter of keeping alive what already exists, of keeping up protest,

keeping on struggling to emancipate himself from myths and illusions,

and of keeping going his own positive activities. You don’t have to

reform or overthrow the State before you can carry on libertarian

activities. You don’t have to wait hopefully for the destruction of

religion; you can, here and now, with your children and your friends,

resist the pressure from Christian forces. You don’t have to try to make

the world safe for sexual freedom of the Reichian kind, but you can here

and now fight against guilts and ideology and, at least to some extent,

live a straightforward, uncompulsive sexual life. In other words, free

or unauthoritarian activities are not future rewards, but are activities

carried on by anarchist or libertarian- minded groups, here and now, in

spite of authoritarian forces.