đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş jacques-ranciere-ten-theses-on-politics.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:31:16. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Ten Theses on Politics* Author: Jacques Ranciere* Date: 2001* Language: en* Topics: dissensus, democracy, politics* Source: http://www.egs.edu/faculty/jacques-ranciere/articles/ten-thesis-on-politics/*
Politics ought to be defined on its own terms, as a mode of acting put
into practice by a specific kind of subject and deriving from a
particular form of reason. It is the political relationship that allows
one to think the possibility of a political subject(ivity) [le sujet
politique] not the other way around. ** To identify politics with the
exercise of, and struggle to possess, power is to do away with politics.
But we also reduce the scope of politics as a mode of thinking if we
conceive of it merely as a theory of power or as an investigation into
the grounds of its legitimacy. If there is something specific about
politics that makes it something other than a more capacious mode of
grouping or a form of power characterized by its mode of legitimation,
it is that it involves a distinctive kind of subject considered, and it
involves this subject in the form of a mode of relation that is its own.
This is what Aristotle means when, in Book I of the Politics, he
distinguishes between political rule (as the ruling of equals) from all
other kinds of rule; or when, in Book III, he defines the citizen as âhe
who partakes in the fact of ruling and the fact of being ruled.â
Everything about politics is contained in this specific relationship,
this âpart-takingâavoir-part],[3] which should be interrogated as to its
meaning and as to its conditions of possibility. ** An interrogation
into what is âproperâ to politics must be carefully distinguished from
current and widespread propositions regarding âthe return of the
political.â In the past several years, and in the context of a
state-consensus, we have seen the blossoming of affirmations proclaiming
the end of the illusion of the social and a return to a âpureâ form of
politics. Read through either an Arendtian or Straussian lens, these
affirmations focus on the same Aristotelian texts gestured to above.
These readings generally identify the âproperâ political order with that
of the eu zen (i.e., a conception of the good) as opposed to a zen
(conceived as an order of mere living). On this basis, the frontier
between the domestic and the political becomes the frontier between the
social and the political; and to the idea of a city-state defined by its
common good is opposed the sad reality of modern democracy as the rule
of the masses and of necessity. In practice, this celebration of pure
politics entrusts the virtue of the âpolitical goodâ to governmental
oligarchies enlightened by âexperts;â which is to say that the supposed
purification of the political, freed from domestic and social necessity,
comes down to nothing more (or less) than the reduction of the political
to the state [lâĂŠtatique]. ** Behind the current buffooneries of the
âreturnsâ of the political (that include âthe return of political
philosophyâ), it is important to recognize the vicious circle that
characterizes political philosophy; a vicious circle located in the link
between the political relationship and the political subject. This
vicious circle posits a way of life that is âproperâ to politics. The
political relationship is subsequently deduced from the properties of
this specific order of being and is explained in terms of the existence
of a character who possesses a good or a specific universality, as
opposed to the private or domestic world of needs or interests. In
short, politics is explained as the accomplishment of a way of life that
is proper to those who are destined for it. This partition â which is
actually the object of politics â is posited as its basis. ** What is
proper to politics is thus lost at the outset if politics is thought of
as a specific way of living. Politics cannot be defined on the basis of
any pre-existing subject. The political âdifferenceâ that makes it
possible to think its subject must be sought in the form of its
relation. If we return to the Aristotelian definition, there is a name
given to the subject (politès) that is defined by a part-taking
(metexis) in a form of action (archein â ruling) and in the undergoing
that corresponds to this doing (archesthai â being ruled). If there is
something âproperâ to politics, it consists entirely in this
relationship which is not a relationship between subjects, but one
between two contradictory terms through which a subject is defined.
Politics disappears the moment you undo this knot of a subject and a
relation. This is what happens in all fictions, be they speculative or
empiricist, that seek the origin of the political relationship in the
properties of its subjects and in the conditions of their coming
together. The traditional question âFor what reasons do human beings
gather into political communities?â is always already a response, and
one that causes the disappearance of the object it claims to explain or
to ground â i.e., the form of a political part-taking that then
disappears in the play of elements or atoms of sociability. ** Thesis 2:
its participation in contrarieties. Politics is a paradoxical form of
action. ** The formulations according to which politics is the ruling of
equals, and the citizen is the one who part-takes in ruling and being
ruled, articulate a paradox that must be thought through rigorously. It
is important to set aside banal representations of the doxa of
parliamentary systems that invoke the reciprocity of rights and duties
in order to understand what is extraordinary in the Aristotelian
articulation. This formulation speaks to us of a being who is at once
the agent of an action and the one upon whom the action is exercised.[4]
It contradicts the conventional âcause-and-effectâ model of action that
has it that an agent endowed with a specific capacity produces an effect
upon an object that is, in turn, characterized by its aptitude for
receiving that effect. ** This problem is in no way resolved by
reverting to the classic opposition between two modes of action:
poiesis, on the one hand, governed by the model of fabrication that
gives form to matter; and praxis, on the other, which excludes from this
relation the âinter-beingâ [lâinter-ĂŞtre][5] of people devoted to
politics. As we know, this opposition â replacing that of zen and eu zen
â sustains a conception of political purity. In Hannah Arendtâs work,
for instance, the order of praxis is that of equals with the power of
archein, conceived of as the power to begin anew: âTo act, in its most
general sense,â she explains in The Human Condition, âmeans to take an
initiative, to begin (as the Greek word archein, âto begin,â âto lead,â
and eventually âto ruleâ indicates);â she concludes this thought by
subsequently linking archein to âthe principle of freedom.â[6] Once
Arendt defines both a proper mode and sphere of action, a vertiginous
short-cut is formed that allows one to posit a series of equations
between âbeginning,â âruling,â âbeing free,â and living in a city-state
(âTo be free and to live in a polis is the same thingâ as the same text
puts it). ** This series of equations finds its equivalent in the
movement that engenders civic equality from the community of Homeric
heroes; equals, that is, in their participation in the power of arche.
The first witness against this Homeric idyllic, however, is Homer
himself. Against the garrulous Thersites â the man who is an able public
speaker despite the fact that he is not qualified to speak â Odysseus
recalls the fact that the Greek army has one and only one chief:
Agamemnon. He reminds us of what archein means: to walk at the head.
And, if there is one who walks at the head, the others must necessarily
walk behind. The line between the power of archein (i.e., the power to
rule), freedom, and the polis, is not straight but severed. In order to
convince oneself of this, it is enough to see the manner in which
Aristotle characterizes the three possible classes of rule within a
polis, each one possessing a particular title: âvirtueâ for the aristoi,
âwealthâ for the oligoi, and âfreedomâ for the demos. In this division,
âfreedomâ appears as the paradoxical part of the demos about whom the
Homeric hero tells us (in no uncertain terms) that it had only one thing
to do: to keep quiet and bow down. ** In short, the opposition between
praxis and poiesis in no way resolves the paradoxical definition of the
politès. As far as arche is concerned, as with everything else, the
conventional logic has it that there is a particular disposition to act
that is exercised upon a particular disposition to âbe acted upon.â Thus
the logic of arche presupposes a determinate superiority exercised upon
an equally determinate inferiority. In order for there to be a political
subject(ivity), and thus for there to be politics, there must be a
rupture in this logic. ** Thesis 3: ** Politics is a specific rupture in
the logic of arche. It does not simply presuppose the rupture of the
ânormalâ distribution of positions between the one who exercises power
and the one subject to it. It also requires a rupture in the idea that
there are dispositions âproperâ to such classifications. ** In Book III
of the Laws, Plato devotes himself to a systematic inventory of the
qualifications (axiomata) for ruling, along with certain correlative
qualifications for being ruled. Out of the seven he retains, four are
traditional qualifications of authority based on a natural difference;
that is, the difference in birth. Those qualified to rule are those
âborn beforeâ or âborn otherwise.â This grounds the power of parents
over children, old over young, masters over slaves, and nobles over
serfs. The fifth qualification is introduced as the principal principle
that summarizes all natural differences: It is the power of those with a
superior nature, of the stronger over the weak â a power that has the
unfortunate quality, discussed at length in the Gorgias, of being
indeterminate. The sixth qualification, then, gives the only difference
that counts for Plato; namely, the power of those who know [savoir] over
those who do not. There are thus four couplings of traditional
qualifications to be had, along with two theoretical couplings that
claim priority over them: namely, ânaturalâ superiority and the rule of
âscienceâ qua knowledge. ** The list ought to stop there. But there is a
seventh qualification: âthe choice of god,â otherwise referring to a
drawing of lots [le tirage au sort] that designates the one who
exercises arche. Plato does not expand upon this. But clearly, this kind
of âchoiceâ points ironically to the designation by god of a regime
previously referred to as one only god could save: namely, democracy.
What thus characterizes a democracy is pure chance or the complete
absence of qualifications for governing. Democracy is that state of
exception where no oppositions can function, where there is no
pre-determined principle of role allocation. âTo partake in ruling and
being ruledâ is quite a different matter from reciprocity. It is, in
short, an absence of reciprocity that constitutes the exceptional
essence of this relationship; and this absence of reciprocity rests on
the paradox of a qualification that is absence of qualification.
Democracy is the specific situation in which there is an absence of
qualifications that, in turn, becomes the qualification for the exercise
of a democratic arche. What is destroyed in this logic is the particular
quality of arche, its redoubling, which means that it always precedes
itself within a circle of its own disposition and its own exercise. But
this exceptional state is identical with the very condition for the
specificity of politics more generally. ** Thesis 4: ** Democracy is not
a political regime. Insofar as it is a rupture in the logic of arche â
that is, in the anticipation of rule in the disposition for it â
democracy is the regime of politics in the form of a relationship
defining a specific subject. ** What makes possible the metexis proper
to politics is the rupture of all those logics of allocation exercised
in the part-taking of arche. The âfreedomâ of a people that constitutes
the axiom of democracy has as its real content the rupture of the axioms
of domination: a rupture, that is, in the correlation between a capacity
for rule and a capacity for being ruled. The citizen who partakes âin
ruling and being ruledâ is only thinkable on the basis of the demos as a
figure that ruptures the correspondence between a series of correlated
capacities. Democracy is thus precisely not a political regime in the
sense of a particular constitution that determines different ways of
assembling people under a common authority. Democracy is the institution
of politics â the institution of both its subject and its mode of
relating. ** As we know, democracy is a term invented by its opponents,
by all those who were âqualifiedâ to govern because of seniority, birth,
wealth, virtue, and knowledge [savoir]. Using it as a term of derision,
they articulated an unprecedented reversal of the order of things: the
âpower of the demosâ means that those who rule are those who have no
specificity in common, apart from their having no qualification for
governing. Before being the name of a community, demos is the name of a
part of the community: namely, the poor. The âpoor,â however, does not
designate an economically disadvantaged part of the population; it
simply designates the category of peoples who do not count, those who
have no qualifications to part-take in arche, no qualification for being
taken into account. ** This is exactly what Homer describes in the
Thersites episode evoked above. Those who want to speak, though they
belong to the demos, though they belong to the undifferentiated
collection of the âunaccounted forâ [lâhors-compte] (anarithmoi), get
stabbed in the back by Odysseusâ scepter. This is not a deduction but a
definition: The one who is âunaccounted-for,â the one who has no speech
to be heard, is the one of the demos. A remarkable passage from Book XII
of the Odyssey illustrates this point: Polydamas complains because his
opinion has been disregarded by Hector. With you, he says, âone never
has the right to speak if one belongs to the demos.â Now Polydamas is
not a villain like Thersites; he is Hectorâs brother. Demos thus does
not designate a socially inferior category: The one who speaks when s/he
is not to speak, the one who part-takes in what s/he has no part in â
that person belongs to the demos. ** Thesis 5: ** The âpeopleâ that is
the subject of democracy â and thus the principal subject of politics â
is not the collection of members in a community, or the laboring classes
of the population. It is the supplementary part, in relation to any
counting of parts of the population that makes it possible to identify
âthe part of those who have no-partâ [le compte des incomptĂŠs][7] with
the whole of the community. ** The people (demos) exists only as a
rupture of the logic of arche, a rupture of the logic of
beginning/ruling [commencement/commandement]. It should not be
identified either with the race of those who recognize each other as
having the same origin, the same birth, or with a part of a population
or even the sum of its parts. âPeopleâ [peuple] refers to the supplement
that disconnects the population from itself, by suspending the various
logics of legitimate domination. This disjunction is illustrated
particularly well in the crucial reforms that give Athenian democracy
its proper status; namely, those reforms enacted by Cleisthenes when he
rearranged the distribution of the demes [8] over the territory of the
city. In constituting each tribe by the addition of three separate
boundaries â one from the city, one from the coast, and one from the
countryside â Cleisthenes broke with the ancient principle that kept the
tribes under the rule of local aristocratic chieftainships whose power,
legitimated through legendary birth, had as its real content the
economic power of the landowners. In short, the âpeopleâ is an artifice
set at an angle from the logic that gives the principle of wealth as
heir to the principle of birth. It is an abstract supplement in relation
to any actual (ac)count of the parts of the population, of their
qualifications for part-taking in the community, and of the common
shares due to them according to these qualifications. The âpeopleâ is
the supplement that inscribes âthe count of the unaccounted-forâ or âthe
part of those who have no part.â ** These expressions should not be
understood in their more populist sense but rather in a structural
sense. It is not the laboring and suffering populace that comes to
occupy the terrain of political action and to identify its name with
that of the community. What is identified by democracy with the role of
the community is an empty, supplementary, part that separates the
community from the sum of the parts of the social body. This separation,
in turn, grounds politics in the action of supplementary subjects that
are a surplus in relation to any (ac)count of the parts of society. The
whole question of politics thus lies in the interpretation of this void.
The criticisms that sought to discredit democracy brought the ânothingâ
which constitutes the political people back to the overflow of the
ignorant masses and the greedy populace. The interpretation of democracy
posed by Claude Lefort gave the democratic void its structural
meaning.[9] But the theory of the structural void can be interpreted in
two distinct ways: First, the structural void refers to an-archy, to the
absence of an entitlement to rule that constitutes the very nature of
the political space; Secondly, the void is caused by the
âdis-incorporationâ of the kingâs two bodies â the human and divine
body.[10] Democracy, according to this latter view, begins with the
murder of the king; in other words, with a collapse of the symbolic
thereby producing a dis-incorporated social presence. And this originary
link is posed as the equivalent of an original temptation to
imaginatively reconstruct the âglorious body of the peopleâ that is heir
to the immortal body of the king and the basis of every totalitarianism.
the people is not a modern consequence of the sacrifice of the sovereign
body but rather a given constitutive of politics. It is initially the
people, and not the king, that has a double body and this duality is
nothing other than the supplement through which politics exists: a
supplement to all social (ac)counts and an exception to all logics of
domination. ** The seventh qualification, Plato says, is âgodâs part.â
We will maintain that this part belonging to god â this qualification of
those who have no qualification â contains within it all that is
theological in politics. The contemporary emphasis on the theme of the
âtheologico-politicalâ dissolves the question of politics into that of
power and of the grounding event that is its fundament. It re-doubles
the liberal fiction of the contract with the representation of an
original sacrifice. But the division of arche that conjoins politics and
democracy is not a founding sacrifice: It is, rather, a neutralization
of any founding sacrifice. This neutralization could find its exact
fable at the end of Oedipus at Colonus: it is at the price of the
disappearance of the sacrificial body, at the price of not seeking
Oedipusâ body, that Athenian democracy receives the benefit of its
burial. To want to disinter the body is not only to associate the
democratic form with a scenario of sin or of original malediction. More
radically, it is to return the logic of politics to the question of an
originary scene of power; in other words, to return politics to the
state. By interpreting the empty part in terms of psychosis, the
dramaturgy of original symbolic catastrophe transforms the political
exception into a sacrificial symptom of democracy: It subsumes the
litigiousness proper to politics under any of the innumerable versions
of an originary âcrimeâ or âmurder.â ** Thesis 6: ** If politics is the
outline of a vanishing difference, with the distribution of social parts
and shares, then it follows that its existence is in no way necessary,
but that it occurs as a provisional accident in the history of the forms
of domination. It also follows from this that political litigiousness
has as its essential object the very existence of politics. ** Politics
cannot be deduced from the necessity of gathering people into
communities. It is an exception to the principles according to which
this gathering operates. The ânormalâ order of things is that human
communities gather together under the rule of those qualified to rule â
whose qualifications are legitimated by the very fact that they are
ruling. These governmental qualifications may be summed up according to
two central principles: The first refers society to the order of
filiation, both human and divine. This is the power of birth. The second
refers society to the vital principle of its activities. This is the
power of wealth. Thus, the ânormalâ evolution of society comes to us in
the progression from a government of birth to a government of wealth.
Politics exists as a deviation from this normal order of things. It is
this anomaly that is expressed in the nature of political subjects who
are not social groups but rather forms of inscription of âthe (ac)count
of the unaccounted-for.â ** There is politics as long as âthe peopleâ is
not identified with the race or a population, inasmuch as the poor are
not equated with a particular disadvantaged sector, and as long as the
proletariat is not a group of industrial workers, etc⌠Rather, there is
politics inasmuch as âthe peopleâ refers to subjects inscribed as a
supplement to the count of the parts of society, a specific figure of
âthe part of those who have no-part.â Whether this part exists is the
political issue and it is the object of political litigation. Political
struggle is not a conflict between well defined interest groups; it is
an opposition of logics that count the parties and parts of the
community in different ways. The clash between the ârichâ and the
âpoor,â for instance, is the struggle over the very possibility of these
words being coupled, of their being able to institute categories for
another (ac)counting of the community. There are two ways of counting
the parts of the community: The first only counts empirical parts â
actual groups defined by differences in birth, by different functions,
locations, and interests that constitute the social body. The second
counts âin additionâ a part of the no-part. We will call the first
police and the second politics. ** Thesis 7: ** Politics is specifically
opposed to the police. The police is a âpartition of the sensibleâ [le
partage du sensible] whose principle is the absence of a void and of a
supplement. ** The police is not a social function but a symbolic
constitution of the social. The essence of the police is neither
repression nor even control over the living. Its essence is a certain
manner of partitioning the sensible. We will call âpartition of the
sensibleâ a general law that defines the forms of part-taking by first
defining the modes of perception in which they are inscribed. The
partition of the sensible is the cutting-up of the world and of âworld;â
it is the nemeĂŻn upon which the nomoi of the community are founded. This
partition should be understood in the double sense of the word: on the
one hand, that which separates and excludes; on the other, that which
allows participation (see Editorâs note 2). A partition of the sensible
refers to the manner in which a relation between a shared âcommonâ [un
commun partagĂŠ] and the distribution of exclusive parts is determined
through the sensible. This latter form of distribution, in turn, itself
presupposes a partition between what is visible and what is not, of what
can be heard from the inaudible. ** The essence of the police is to be a
partition of the sensible characterized by the absence of a void or a
supplement: society consists of groups dedicated to specific modes of
action, in places where these occupations are exercised, in modes of
being corresponding to these occupations and these places. In this
fittingness of functions, places, and ways of being, there is no place
for a void. It is this exclusion of what âthere is notâ that is the
police-principle at the heart of statist practices. The essence of
politics, then, is to disturb this arrangement by supplementing it with
a part of the no-part identified with the community as a whole.
Political litigiousness/struggle is that which brings politics into
being by separating it from the police that is, in turn, always
attempting its disappearance either by crudely denying it, or by
subsuming that logic to its own. Politics is first and foremost an
intervention upon the visible and the sayable. ** Thesis 8: ** The
principal function of politics is the configuration of its proper space.
It is to disclose the world of its subjects and its operations. The
essence of politics is the manifestation of dissensus, as the presence
of two worlds in one.[11] ** Let us begin from an empirical given:
police intervention in public spaces does not consist primarily in the
interpellation of demonstrators, but in the breaking up of
demonstrations. The police is not that law interpellating individuals
(as in Althusserâs âHey, you there!â) unless one confuses it with
religious subjectification.[12] It is, first of all, a reminder of the
obviousness of what there is, or rather, of what there isnât: âMove
along! There is nothing to see here!â The police says that there is
nothing to see on a road, that there is nothing to do but move along. It
asserts that the space of circulating is nothing other than the space of
circulation. Politics, in contrast, consists in transforming this space
of âmoving-alongâ into a space for the appearance of a subject: i.e.,
the people, the workers, the citizens: It consists in refiguring the
space, of what there is to do there, what is to be seen or named
therein. It is the established litigation of the perceptible, on the
nemeĂŻn that founds any communal nomos. ** This partition constituting
politics is never given in the form of a lot, of a kind of property that
obliges or compels politics. These properties are litigious as much in
their understanding as in their extension. Exemplary in this regard are
those properties that, for Aristotle, define a political ability or are
intended for âthe good life.â Apparently nothing could be clearer than
the distinction made by Aristotle in Book I of the Politics: the sign of
the political nature of humans is constituted by their possession of the
logos, the articulate language appropriate for manifesting a community
in the aisthesis of the just and the unjust, as opposed to the animal
phone, appropriate only for expressing the feelings of pleasure and
displeasure. If you are in the presence of an animal possessing the
ability of the articulate language and its power of manifestation, you
know you are dealing with a human and therefore with a political animal.
The only practical difficulty is in knowing which sign is required to
recognize the sign; that is, how one can be sure that the human animal
mouthing a noise in front of you is actually voicing an utterance rather
than merely expressing a state of being? If there is someone you do not
wish to recognize as a political being, you begin by not seeing them as
the bearers of politicalness, by not understanding what they say, by not
hearing that it is an utterance coming out of their mouths. And the same
goes for the opposition so readily invoked between the obscurity of
domestic and private life, and the radiant luminosity of the public life
of equals. In order to refuse the title of political subjects to a
category â workers, women, etc⌠â it has traditionally been sufficient
to assert that they belong to a âdomesticâ space, to a space separated
from public life; one from which only groans or cries expressing
suffering, hunger, or anger could emerge, but not actual speeches
demonstrating a shared aisthesis. And the politics of these categories
has always consisted in re-qualifying these places, in getting them to
be seen as the spaces of a community, of getting themselves to be seen
or heard as speaking subjects (if only in the form of litigation); in
short, participants in a common aisthesis. It has consisted in making
what was unseen visible; in getting what was only audible as noise to be
heard as speech; in demonstrating to be a feeling of shared âgoodâ or
âevilâ what had appeared merely as an expression of pleasure or pain. **
The essence of politics is dissensus. Dissensus is not the confrontation
between interests or opinions. It is the manifestation of a distance of
the sensible from itself. Politics makes visible that which had no
reason to be seen, it lodges one world into another (for instance, the
world where the factory is a public space within the one where it is
considered a private one, the world where workers speak out vis-Ă -vis
the one where their voices are merely cries expressing pain). This is
precisely why politics cannot be identified with the model of
communicative action since this model presupposes the partners in
communicative exchange to be pre-constituted, and that the discursive
forms of exchange imply a speech community whose constraint is always
explicable. In contrast, the particular feature of political dissensus
is that the partners are no more constituted than is the object or the
very scene of discussion. The ones making visible the fact that they
belong to a shared world the other does not see â cannot take advantage
of â the logic implicit to a pragmatics of communication. The worker who
argues for the public nature of a âdomesticâ matter (such as a salary
dispute) must indicate the world in which his argument counts as an
argument and must demonstrate it as such for those who do not possess a
frame of reference to conceive of it as argument. Political argument is
at one and the same time the demonstration of a possible world where the
argument could count as argument, addressed by a subject qualified to
argue, upon an identified object, to an addressee who is required to see
the object and to hear the argument that he or she ânormallyâ has no
reason to either see or hear. It is the construction of a paradoxical
world that relates two separate worlds. ** Politics thus has no âproperâ
place nor does it possess any ânaturalâ subjects. A demonstration is
political not because it takes place in a specific locale and bears upon
a particular object but rather because its form is that of a clash
between two partitions of the sensible. A political subject is not a
group of interests or ideas: It is the operator of a particular mode of
subjectification and litigation through which politics has its
existence. Political demonstrations are thus always of the moment and
their subjects are always provisional. Political difference is always on
the shore of its own disappearance: the people are close to sinking into
the sea of the population or of race, the proletariat borders on being
confused with workers defending their interests, the space of a peopleâs
public demonstration is always at risk of being confused with the
merchantâs agora, etc. ** The deduction of politics from a specific
world of equals or free people, as opposed to another world lived out of
necessity, takes as its ground precisely the object of its litigation.
It thus renders compulsory a blindness to those who âdo not seeâ and
have no place from which to be seen. Exemplary, in this regard, is a
passage from Arendtâs On Revolution discussing the manner in which John
Adams identifies the unhappiness of the poor with the fact of ânot being
seen.â[13] Such an identification, she comments, could itself only
emanate from a man belonging to a privileged community of equals. And,
by the same token, it could âhardly be understoodâ by the people
comprising the relevant categories. We could express amazement at the
extraordinary deafness of this affirmation in the face of the
multiplicity of discourses and demonstrations of the âpoorâ concerning
precisely their mode of visibility. But this deafness has nothing
accidental about it. It forms a circle with the acceptance of an
original partition, a founding politics, with what was in fact the
permanent object of litigation constituting politics. It forms a circle
with the definition of homo laborans as a partition of the âways of
life.â This circle is not that of any particular theoretician; it is the
circle of âpolitical philosophy.â ** Thesis 9: ** Inasmuch as what is
proper to âpolitical philosophyâ is to ground political action in a
specific mode of being, so is it the case that âpolitical philosophyâ
effaces the litigiousness constitutive of politics. It is in its very
description of the world of politics that philosophy effects this
effacement. Moreover, its effectiveness is perpetuated through to the
non-philosophical or anti-philosophical description of the world. **
That the distinguishing feature of politics is the existence of a
subject who ârulesâ by the very fact of having no qualifications to
rule; that the principle of beginnings/ruling is irremediably divided as
a result of this, and that the political community is specifically a
litigious community â this is the âpolitical secretâ that philosophy
first encounters. If we can speak of the privileged stature of the
âAncientsâ over the âModerns,â it is a consequence of their having first
perceived this âsecretâ and not of having been the first to oppose the
community of the âgoodâ to that of the âuseful.â At the head of the
anodyne expression âpolitical philosophyâ one finds the violent
encounter between philosophy and the exception to the law of arche
proper to politics, along with philosophyâs effort to resituate politics
under the auspices of this law. The Gorgias, the Republic, the Politics,
the Laws, all these texts reveal the same effort to efface the paradox
or scandal of a âseventh qualificationâ â to make of democracy a simple
case of the indeterminable principle of âthe government of the
strongest,â against which one can only oppose a government of those who
know [les savants]. These texts all reveal a similar strategy of placing
the community under a unique law of partition and expelling the empty
part of the demos from the communal body. ** But this expulsion does not
simply take place in the form of the opposition between the âgoodâ
regime of the community that is both one and hierarchised according to
its principle of unity, and the âbadâ regimes of division and disorder.
It takes place within the very presupposition that identifies a
political form with a way of life; and this presupposition is already
operating in the procedures for describing âbadâ regimes, and democracy
in particular. All of politics, as we have said, is played out in the
interpretation of democratic âanarchy.â In identifying it with the
dispersal of the desires of democratic man, Plato transforms the form of
politics into a mode of existence and, further, transforms the void into
an overflow. Before being the theorist of the âidealâ or âenclosedâ
city-state, Plato is the founder of the anthropological conception of
the political, the conception that identifies politics with the
deployment of the properties of a type of man or a mode of life. This
kind of âman,â this âway of being,â this form of the city-state: it is
there, before any discourse on the laws or the educational methods of
the ideal state, before even the partition of the classes of the
community, the partition of the perceptible that cancels out political
singularity. ** The initial gesture of political philosophy thus has a
two-fold consequence: On the one hand, Plato founds a community that is
the effectuation of a principle of unity, of an undivided principle â a
community strictly defined as a common body with its places and
functions and with its forms of interiorisation of the common. He founds
an archi-politics[14] based on a law of unity between the âoccupationsâ
of the city-state and its âethos,â (in other words its way of inhabiting
an abode), as law but also as the specific âtoneâ according to which
this ethos reveals itself. This etho-logy of the community once again
makes politics and police indistinguishable. And political philosophy,
inasmuch as it wants to give to the community a single foundation, is
condemned to have to re-identify politics and police, to cancel out
politics through the gesture that founds it. ** But Plato also invents a
âconcreteâ mode for describing the production of political forms. In a
word, he invents the very forms of the refusal of the âideal state,â the
settled forms of opposition between philosophical âa-prior-ismâ and
concrete sociological or political-scientific analyses of the forms of
politics as expressions of ways of life. This second legacy is more
profound and more long-lasting than the first. The sociology of the
political is the second resource â the deuteron plous â of political
philosophy that accomplishes (sometimes against itself) its fundamental
project: to found the community on the basis of a univocal partition of
the sensible. In particular, de Tocquevilleâs analysis of democracy,
whose innumerable variants and ersatz versions feed the discourses on
modern democracy, the age of the masses, the mass individual, etc., fits
into the continuity of the theoretical gesture that cancels out the
structural singularity of âthe qualification without qualificationsâ and
the âpart of the no-part,â by re-describing democracy as a social
phenomenon, of the collective effectuation of the properties of a type
of man. ** Inversely, the claims for the purity of the bios politikos
(of the republican constitution and of the community versus the
individual or democratic mass, and the opposition between the political
and the social) share in the effectiveness of the same knot between the
a-prior-ism of the ârepublicanâ re-founding, and the sociological
description of democracy. No matter which side one rests on, the
opposition between the âpoliticalâ and the âsocialâ is a matter defined
entirely within the frame of âpolitical philosophy;â in other words, it
is a matter that lies at the heart of the philosophical repression of
politics. The current proclamations of a âreturn to politicsâ and
âpolitical philosophyâ are an imitation of the originary gesture of
âpolitical philosophy,â without actually grasping the principles or
issues involved in it. In this sense, it is the radical forgetting of
politics and of the tense relationship between politics and philosophy.
The sociological theme of the âend of politicsâ in post-modern society
and the âpoliticoâ theme of the âreturn of politicsâ both derive from
the initial double gesture of âpolitical philosophyâ and both move
towards the same forgetting of politics. ** Thesis 10: ** The âend of
politicsâ and the âreturn of politicsâ are two complementary ways of
canceling out politics in the simple relationship between a state of the
social and a state of statist apparatuses. âConsensusâ is the vulgar
name given to this cancellation. ** The essence of politics resides in
the modes of dissensual subjectification that reveal the difference of a
society to itself. The essence of consensus is not peaceful discussion
and reasonable agreement as opposed to conflict or violence. Its essence
is the annulment of dissensus as the separation of the sensible from
itself, the annulment of surplus subjects, the reduction of the people
to the sum of the parts of the social body, and of the political
community to the relationship of interests and aspirations of these
different parts. Consensus is the reduction of politics to the police.
In other words, it is the âend of politicsâ and not the accomplishment
of its ends but, simply, the return of the ânormalâ state of things
which is that of politicsâ non-existence. The âend of politicsâ is the
ever-present shore of politics [le bord de la politique] that, in turn,
is an activity of the moment and always provisional. âReturn of
politicsâ and âend of politicsâ are two symmetrical interpretations
producing the same effect: to efface the very concept of politics, and
the precariousness that is one of its essential elements. In proclaiming
the end of usurpations of the social and the return to âpureâ politics,
the âreturn of politicsâ thesis simply occludes the fact that the
âsocialâ is in no way a particular sphere of existence but, rather, a
disputed object of politics. Therefore, the subsequently proclaimed end
of the social is, simply put, the end of political litigation regarding
the partition of worlds. The âreturn of politicsâ is thus the
affirmation that there is a specific place for politics. Isolated in
this manner, this specific space can be nothing other than the place of
the state and, in fact, the theorists of the âreturn of politicsâ
ultimately affirm that politics is out-dated. They identify it with the
practices of state control which have, as their principal principle, the
suppression of politics. ** The sociological thesis of the âend of
politicsâ symmetrically posits the existence of a state of the social
such that politics no longer has a necessary raison-dâĂŞtre; whether or
not it has accomplished its ends by bringing into being precisely this
state (i.e., the exoteric American Hegelian-Fukayama-ist version) or
whether its forms are no longer adapted to the fluidity and
artificiality of present-day economic and social relations (i.e., the
esoteric European Heideggerian-Situationist version). The thesis thus
amounts to asserting that the logical telos of capitalism makes it so
that politics becomes, once again, out dated. And then it concludes with
either the mourning of politics before the triumph of an immaterial
Leviathan, or its transformation into forms that are broken up,
segmented, cybernetic, ludic, etc⌠â adapted to those forms of the
social that correspond to the highest stage of capitalism. It thus fails
to recognize that in actual fact, politics has no reason for being in
any state of the social and that the contradiction of the two logics is
an unchanging given that defines the contingency and precariousness
proper to politics. Via a Marxist detour, the âend of politicsâ thesis â
along with the consensualist thesis â grounds politics in a particular
mode of life that identifies the political community with the social
body, subsequently identifying political practice with state practice.
The debate between the philosophers of the âreturn of politicsâ and the
sociologists of the âend of politicsâ is thus a straightforward debate
regarding the order in which it is appropriate to take the
presuppositions of âpolitical philosophyâ so as to interpret the
consensualist practice of annihilating politics. ** ** Notes* ** [1] The
original translation of the âTen Thesesâ was done by Rachel Bowlby.
However, some phrases were modified by Davide Panagia in consultation
with Jacques Rancière. Terms in square brackets are Rancièreâs original
French expressions.* ** * [2] Our English âpolitical subject(ivity)â
does not give an adequate sense of Rancièreâs âle sujet politique,â a
term that refers both to the idea of a political subjectivity and to the
âproperâ subject of politics. [3] Rancière plays on the double meaning
of the avoir-part as both a âpartakingâ and a âpartition.â* ** * [4] The
reference is to Arendtâs claim that âthe human capacity for freedom,
which, by producing the web of human relationships, seems to entangle
its producer to such an extent that he appears much more the victim and
the sufferer than the author and the doer of what he has doneâ (The
Human Condition, p. 233â234; Chicago: The University of Chicago Press,
1989).* ** * [5] The word-play, here, is on the idea of an âinter-estâ
referring both to a principle of inter-relating and to the idea of
societal âinterest.â Rancière is invoking an Arendtian distinction found
in her The Human Condition (see pages 50â58).* ** * [6] Hannah Arendt,
The Human Condition, p. 177.* ** * [7] Though the literal translation of
the French is âthe count of the unaccounted-forâ the formulation found
in the English translation of Dis-agreement: Politics and Philosophy,
(Julie Rose trans., Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999) is
retained for the sake of consistency.* ** * [8] Demes were townships or
divisions of ancient Attica. In modern Greece the term refers to
communes.* ** * [9] See Democracy and Political Theory (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1988) especially Part IV: âOn the
Irreducible Element.â* ** * [10] Rancière is invoking Ernst
Kantorowiczâs work on medieval political theology, also present in
Lefortâs study.* ** * [11] Rancièreâs conception of dissensus counts as
an instance of the paradox of the âone and the manyâ characteristic of
democratic politics.* ** * [12] Rancière here refers to Althusserâs
âIdeology and Ideological State Apparatusesâ (see Lenin and Philosophy,
New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971).* ** * [13] See Arendtâs chapter
entitled âThe Social Questionâ from On Revolution; especially pages
68â71 (New York: Penguin Books, 1990).* ** * [14] See Rancièreâs
Dis-agreement (Chapter 4) for an extended discussion of this concept. **