đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș ron-tabor-the-dialectics-of-ambiguity.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:47:20. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Dialectics of Ambiguity Author: Ron Tabor Date: 2004 Language: en Topics: dialectics, marxism, history, critique, historical materialism Source: Retrieved on 2005-05-11 Notes: Published in The Utopian, Volume 4.
This article is the latest in a series of essays devoted to a critique
of Marxism from the left. I began the articles in the early 1990swhen I
was affiliated with Love and Rage, a group that described itself as a
revolutionary anarchist federation. Prior to that time, I had been a
Marxist for many years and a member of two organizations that (in their
distinct ways) opposed the then-extant Communist societies as
representing the perversion of Marxism (and Leninism) and attempted to
uphold what they considered the true interpretation of that
worldview.During that time, I believed that Marxism and Leninism
embodied an outlook that stood for the liberation of the working class
and all other oppressed people, and the establishment of a truly
liberatedâdemocratic, cooperative and egalitarianâsociety, one that is
directly governed in all aspects by its members. More specifically, I
thought that the Bolshevik-led revolution in Russia in October 1917
represented a true proletarian revolution, one which was, moreover,
supported by the peasantry, the vast majority of people in the Russian
Empire.However, the circumstances in which it had taken
placeâparticularly the nature of Russian society, the material
destruction caused by World War I and the years of revolution and civil
war that followed, the failure of other socialist revolutions in
Germany, Hungary and elsewhere, and the viciousness of the attempted
counterrevolutionary struggleâresulted at first in the bureaucratization
of the revolutionary regime and ultimately in its total overthrow at the
hands of a bureaucratic elite organized and led by Joseph Stalin.
After some years of study and consideration, I eventually concluded that
this position was untenable. Rather than seeing the establishment of
totalitarian, state capitalist (Communist) systems as the negation of
Marxism, I came to believe that these societies in fact represented its
fulfillment, although this had not been explicitly perceived, let alone
advocated, by Marxist ideologists. As a result of reaching this
conclusion, while still maintaining my opposition to capitalism and
advocating the establishment of a liberated society, I became attracted
to anarchism. I was particularly drawn to its hostility to the state and
its opposition (in contrast to Marxism) to utilizing a state apparatus
to achieve its goal. I was also intrigued by its under-standing of
hierarchy, which subsumes questions of class,national, racial and sexual
oppression under a broader category without insisting on the
primacy/determining nature of anyone of them. Lastly, I was impressed by
what I believe to be implied by anarchism (if not always consistently
adhered to by anarchists themselves): a philosophical skepticism that
repudiates the belief in the Truth of any one political/philosophical
orthodoxy, in other words, its commitment to a form of ideological
pluralism. For this and other reasons, I participated in and joined what
eventually became Love and Rage.
Once in this organization, however, I began to discern that some of its
members, and one leader in particular, seemed to be attracted to certain
authoritarian aspects of Marxism.Having been involved in Students for a
Democratic Society in the 1960s, and having watched the evolution of its
politics from a kind of libertarian social democracy in its early years
to a form of militant Stalinism at the time of its split in1969, I was
concerned that Love and Rage not undergo a comparable life history. It
was with this in mind that I began a series of articles that I called an
anarchist critique of Marxism. Aside from offering the benefits of my
own experience (such as they might be) to those younger activists in
Love and Rage and elsewhere on the left who might be open to them, I
also wanted to clarify my own thinking, in a kind of settling of
accounts with past beliefs. I particularly wished to explain why the
practical results of Marxismâthe actual outcome of Marxist-led
revolutionsâhad been hideous totalitarian regimes rather than the
liberated, democratic and egalitarian societies that Marxists
proclaimed, and still proclaim, to be their goal. In the same vein, I
wished to explore why so many Marxists (the vast majority, it seems
tome) have been so bent on supporting, defending and justifying such
regimes, as well as others that were not the result of Marxist-led
revolutions, despite their obviously undemocratic and brutal character.
Finally, I wanted to understand why so many people involved in radical
politics, including anarchists themselves, have been drawn to this type
of authoritarian thinking;why, for example, some young anarchists today
view Che Guevara and the Weathermen, arch-Stalinists and elitists if
there ever were any, as heroes.
I now believe that Marxism must be held responsible for the
establishment of totalitarian state capitalist Communist regimes and
that this,not its claim to stand for the creation of liberated
societies, is its real meaning. In other words, Marxism leads to
totalitarianism. Of course, the question of historical responsibility is
a complicated one. State capitalism in Russia and elsewhere was
established under specific historical circumstances, not all of which
can be blamed on Marxism. But Marxism, which prides itself on being the
true understanding of history, its dynamics, direction and outcome, can
be held responsible for what Marxists did under these circumstances,and
why so many Marxists supported and support, and even seek to replicate,
the dictatorial regimes that Marxists established in the name of
freedom. As I see it, Marxism was a necessary, if not sufficient, cause
of such societies. If Marxism had never existed, Russia, the countries
of Eastern Europe, China,etc., might well have experienced centralized,
industrializing,so-called modernizing, governments intent on enabling
these countries to resist colonialist domination and imperialist
penetration and to compete on the capitalist world market. But the
specific nature of the regimes that were established in these
lands,including the official state ideologies, mandated atheism,
one-party rule, ideological campaigns, leadership cults, purges and
gulags,and particularly the extreme nature of the violence they
practiced, must, I think, be held to Marxismâs account.
In light of this, a critique of Marxism seems to me to be a preliminary
step in the process of developing an outlook that consistently promotes
the establishment of a free society. If we are to build a mass radical
movement that really stands for what it claims to, we need to figure out
what went wrong before.
When I initiated the series, there was some concern that I was wasting
my time (and that Love and Rage was wasting space in its newspaper).
Many people presumed that Marxism was dead, as it appeared to be in the
aftermath of the demise of the Soviet Union and the other state
capitalist regimes in Eastern Europe, and in the light of Chinaâs
evolution toward a more traditional form of capitalist economy. But
since I had lived through the 1950s and early 1960s, when Marxism (at
least in the United States) was also declared to be deceased only to
revive with great vigor in the late 1960s, I believed that my efforts
were not totally in vain. It was with this in mind that I was somewhat
reassured (if thatâs the right word), to learn that one of the large and
apparently influential anti-war coalitions to emerge in the buildup to
the war in Iraqâ the International Answer coalitionâwas dominated by the
Workers World Party, the embodiment of a particularly virulent form of
Stalinist Marxism. That this characterization of the group is apt was
revealed in the fact that one of the key points of unity of this
coalition was/is that no criticism of Saddam Hussein and his regime be
allowed. Although the anti-war protests have subsided and the
International Answer coalition has since kept a low profile, I believe
it will be only a matter of time before some sort of oppositionist
movement revives (which I am for), and the Workers World Party again
raises its head (which I am against). So much for Marxism being dead. Of
course, there are other organizations that defend more democratic
interpretations of Marxism, but I consider that efforts to contest the
Marxist terrain with hard-line Stalinists are futile. This is because,
as Iâve tried to show in these articles,I believe Marxism itself, in its
fundamental philosophical assumptions and in other aspects of its
outlook and program, is totalitarian.
Previous essays in this series have discussed Marxâs theory of the
state, his conception of the dictatorship of the proletariat and his
analysis of capitalism. In this article, I wish to take up his theory of
history, what Marxists refer to as âhistorical materialism.â Since the
theory, in its claim to explain the totality of human history,
encompasses a vast territory, I cannot even pretend to analyze it in its
entirety. I do wish to discuss some of its key tenets and
characteristics.
Significantly, nowhere in the huge corpus of Marx and Engelsâ writings
is there a fully elaborated presentation and explanation of the Marxian
theory of history as a whole. Instead, what we have are, on the one
hand, a few frustratingly brief summaries of the theory, and on the
other, detailed examples or, in more pretentious language,
exemplifications, of their historical conception, that is, relatively
worked-out studies of particular historical events that purport to be
applications of historical materialism. I include in this latter
category Marxâs monumental analysis of one socio-economic formation in
particular, Das Kapital / Capital. While some commentators, both within
and outside the left, have discerned a contradiction between the theory
of historical materialism and Marxâs analysis of capitalism, it seems
clear to me that Marx meant his theory of capital to be consistent with
his broader analysis of history. If there are contradictions between the
two, these are contradictions within the theory of historical
materialism itself.
It might appear to be convenient that there exists only a handful of
synopses of the Marxian theory of history from its originators. This
way, various analysts who might disagree on other issues relating to
Marxism might at least agree on what Marx and Engelâs conception
explicitly states. But, as we shall see, this is not the case.
In order to see why this is so, it is worth reproducing here two of
those statements of the overall theory. I begin with what is generally
considered, by both those who deem themselves to be Marxists and those
who donât, to be the bestâsuccinct but inclusiveâpresentation of the
theory. I am referring to the passages in Marxâs preface to one of his
preliminary studies of capitalism, A Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy.
Marx writes as follows (please forgive the length of the quotation):
The general conclusion at which I arrived and which,once reached,
continued to serve as the leading thread in my studies,may be briefly
summed up as follows: In the social production which men carry on they
enter into definite relations that are indispensable and independent of
their will; these relations of production correspond to a definite stage
of development of their material powers of production. The sum total of
these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of
societyâthe real foundation, on which rise legal and political
superstructures and to which correspond definite forms of social
consciousness. The mode of production in material life determines the
general character of the social, political and spiritual processes of
life. It is not the consciousness of men that determines their
existence,but, on the contrary, their social existence determines their
consciousness. At a certain stage of their development, the material
forces of production come in conflict with the existing relations of
production, orâwhat is but a legal expression for the same thingâwith
the property relations within which they had been at work before.From
forms of development of the forces of production these relations turn
into their fetters. Then comes the period of social revolution. With the
change of the economic foundation the entire immense superstructure is
more or less rapidly transformed. In considering such transformations
the distinction should always be made between the material
transformation of the economic conditions of production which can be
determined with the precision of natural science, and the legal,
political,religious,aesthetic or philosophicâin short ideological forms
in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out. Just as
our opinion of an individual is not based on what he thinks of himself,
so can we not judge of such a period of transformation by its own
consciousness; on the contrary, this consciousness must rather be
explained from the contradictions of material life, from the existing
conflict between the social forces of production and the relations of
production. No social order ever disappears before all the productive
forces, for which there is room in it, have been developed; and new
higher relations of production never appear before the material
conditions of their existence have matured in the womb of the old
society. Therefore, mankind always takes up only such problems as it can
solve; since, looking at the matter more closely, we will always find
that the problem itself arises only when the material conditions
necessary for its solution already exist or are at least in the process
of formation. In broad outlines we can designate the Asiatic, the
ancient, the feudal, and the modern bourgeois methods of production as
so many epochs in the progress of the economic formation of society. The
bourgeois relations of production are the last antagonistic form of the
social process of productionâantagonistic not in the sense of individual
antagonism, but of one arising from conditions surrounding the life of
individuals in society; at the same time the productive forces
developing in the womb of bourgeois society create the material
conditions for the solution of that antagonism. This social formation
constitutes, therefore, the closing chapter of the prehistoric stage of
human society. (A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy,
Karl Marx, Charles H. Kerr & Company, Chicago, 1904, pp.11â13.)
I will also reproduce here another, briefer explication of the Marxian
theory. This is from Friedrich Engelsâ 1888 preface to the Communist
Manifesto:
The Manifesto being our joint production, I consider myself bound to
state that the fundamental proposition which forms its nucleus, belongs
to Marx. That proposition is: That in every historical epoch, the
prevailing mode of economic production and exchange,and the social
organization necessarily following from it,form the basis upon which is
built up and from which alone can be explained, the political and
intellectual history of that epoch; that consequently the whole history
of mankind (since the dissolution of primitive tribal society, holding
land in common ownership) has been a history of class struggles,
contests between exploiting and exploited, ruling and oppressed classes;
that the history of these class struggles form [sic] a series of
evolutions in which, nowadays, a stage has been reached where the
exploited and oppressed classâthe proletariatâcannot attain its
emancipation from the sway of the exploiting and ruling classâthe
bourgeoisieâwithout at the same time, and once and for all, emancipating
society at large from all exploitation, oppression, class distinctions,
and class struggles.
This proposition...is destined to do for history what Darwinâs theory
has done for biology.... (Manifesto of the Communist Party, Karl Marx
and Frederick Engels,International Publishers, New York, 1948, p. 6.)
Although these two passages are generally considered to be
consistent,there is, in fact, a significant difference between the two
presentations of the theory. This is that while Engels emphasizes what
is often considered the most important proposition of Marxismâthat the
history of humanity (since the dissolution of primitive communism) has
been a history of class struggle (this contention is also very
prominently articulated at the beginning of section I of the Manifesto
itself)âMarx doesnât explicitly mention the class struggle at all.This
reveals what I consider to be a major characteristic of the Marxian
theory of history and Marxism as a whole. This is its lack of precision
and its resultant ambiguity: almost every category and concept is vague.
Historical materialism in fact consists of a large number of broad
generalizations that may appear to be valid at first glance, but which
break down when subjected to serious scrutiny. In other words, despite
its claim to be scientific (Engels, as we saw, compared it to Darwinâs
theory of evolution), the Marxist theory of history is ambiguous, even
rubbery, and can be subject to a variety of interpretations, both of its
overall meaning and of its specific tenets.
For a conception that insists on its scientific character, this is a
serious weakness. After all, one of the crucial characteristics of a
truly scientific theory is its precision. This enables it to beheld to
account, that is, proved or disproved, or, if one prefers, verified or
falsified. (I donât wish to get into a discussion here of precisely how
scientific theories are validated, to what extent they can be said to be
proved or disproved.Suffice it say, that most people, particularly
scientists and philosophers and historians of science, believe that
theories that purport to be scientific can be held to some criteria of
verifiability, and that this distinguishes scientific theories from
those that are not.) Most theories in physics, such as Newtonâs laws of
motion or Einsteinâs theory of relativity, are actually a series of
mathematical equations. They also make very precise predictions, which
can be verified or not to determine their validity. (This is true even
of probabilistic theories such as quantum mechanics.) While the
neo-Darwinian theory of evolution cannot be summarized mathematically,
it can be expressed in precise terms, at least precise enough so that
the theory can be tested: it too makes predictions (such as the
appearance of intermediate life-forms in the fossil record), that can be
confirmed or not. Even hypotheses in the social sciences that aspire to
the level of scientific theories (however few and limited in scope they
maybe),must be stated in terms sufficiently precise to be subject to
verification. Although historical materialism appears to make
predictions, it is not, and cannot be, expressed precisely enough to be
held accountable. From the point of view of Marxism,this
(unacknowledged) ambiguity is useful, even necessary. On a whole range
of questionsâare historical events uniquely determined or not, is
consciousness directly determined by socio-economic structures or just
conditioned by them, is socialism inevitable or merely necessary in
amoral senseâMarxism tries to have it both ways, to walk on both sides
of the street, as it were, and Marxists continually shift from one
interpretation of the theory to another in both their use of it and
their efforts to justify it. As a result, Marxism only appears valid if
it is given the benefit of the doubt. In other words, in order to
believe that Marxism is true, one has to want it to be true, and to look
for things that appear to confirm it, while denying or explaining away
things that donât. If subjected to a truly skeptical and critical
critique, Marxism does not hold up.
Before we proceed to a more detailed analysis of historical materialism,
it might be worth summarizing its basic propositions in more systematic
form for those who may find the passages from Marx and Engels cited
above somewhat confusing. Here is my attempt.
development of human productive technology,the tools and other equipment
that, along with human labor,enable human beings to transform the
products of nature and nature itself to fulfill our economic needs. The
materialâmeans of productionâ are produced by labor and can be seen as
material embodiments or âcongelationsâ of it. Labor, for Marxists, is
the unique and defining characteristic of the human species. As human
beings transform their natural and social environments through their
work, they transform themselves. A key aspect of this evolution is the
development of the instruments of laborâtools, machines, etc.,
technology in generalâthat multiply its power. Over time, these means of
production tend to become more productive. Taken together,this
technology and human labor constitute the âforces of production.â
requires a unique set of production relations, a specific arrangement of
human beings (such as the ownership of property), through which this
technology is controlled and utilized. These are called the ârelations
of production.â
a âmode of production.â The mode of production constitutes what Marxists
call the âmaterial baseâ of society.
non-exploitative. Under exploitative modes of production,the level of
technology is sufficient to make possible the production of a limited
social surplus. This is the basis for the condition of ârelative
scarcity,â which enables some, but not all, members of society, to live
without having to work. This,in turn,enables tiny, non-laboring classes,
to rule over and exploit laboring classes, appropriating the social
surplus both to maintain their dominant position and for their own
personal consumption. The division of society into exploitative and
exploited, ruling and ruled, classes gives rise to a conflict between
them, the âclass struggle.â For this reason, exploitative modes of
production are said to be âantagonistic.â Under non-exploitative modes
of production, society is not divided into ruling and ruled classes.
There is no class struggle, and economic production and all aspects of
social life are carried out in a cooperative manner. Such modes of
production are ânon-antagonistic.â
internal dynamicsâits âlaws of motionâ and âcontradictionsââwhich need
to be investigated and analyzed in their own right, while still
embodying the general tendencies or âlawsâof human society and history
as whole. Such laws of motion/contradictions determine the nature and
history of the societies based on the specific modes of production, so
that in general it can be said that under exploitative modes of
production the products of human beings, and particularly the means of
production and the laws governing their growth and development, dominate
human beings and determine their lives. Under exploitative modes of
production, humanity is thus dominated by its products.
that history in its broad outlines can be seen as a series of ever more
productive modes of production. This succession is impelled by the
tendency of technology and human labor (the forces of production) to
become ever more productive as history progresses.
social structuresâstates/forms of governmentâas well as distinct
patterns of culture and modes of thought, such as art,religion and
philosophy. Taken together, these are referred to by Marxists as the
political and ideological âsuperstructureâ of society. As a result, any
given mode of production creates and includes a unique superstructure
that corresponds and is appropriate to it.
superstructure, the superstructure is not a purely passive entity. It
has its own relatively autonomous internal dynamics and,in its turn,
reacts upon the material base, helping to shape its development. The
base and superstructure are said to relate to and determine each other
in a âdialecticalâ manner.
the more general fact that, for Marxists, human thought and
consciousness in generalâideas, religious and philosophical conceptions,
ideologyâgrow out of and reflect material conditions. As Marx puts it:
âsocial existence deter-mines...consciousness.â Yet here, too, thought
or consciousness is not a mere reflection, a mirror or echo, of material
conditions. Through its impact on human activity, the class struggle in
particular, it has an effect on and helps determine the nature and
development of those conditions. Thus, the relation between social
existence and social consciousness, like that between base and
superstructure, is âdialectical.â
an entirely cooperative one. In the early period of the development of a
given mode of production, the relations of production tend to encourage
the development of the forces of production. However, at a certain stage
in the history of that mode of production, the relations of production
start to impede the development of the productive forces, turning into
what Marx calls their âfetters.â This leads to an intensifying
contradiction between the forces and relations of production. This
contradiction is reflected in an increase in the class struggle between
the exploited and exploiting, dominated and dominating, classes.
break apart the old relations of production and, via a relatively rapid
economic transformation, a new mode of production is established. This
transformation is reflected in the political and ideological sphere,
that is, in the realm of the superstructure, as a period of violent
class struggle, or social revolution.
are capable of overcoming relative scarcity altogether. This is the
stage brought about by capitalism. Under this type of society, the
dynamic under which the laws of motion of the mode of production
dominate the lives and thoughts of those who live under it reaches its
apogee. Here the market has become freed of extra-economic constraints
and the means of production develop at a rapid rate. Because of this,
the lives of human beings are governed by the laws of motion of the
production and exchange of commodities, what Marx calls the âfetishism
of commodities.â Living labor is dominated by dead labor. This situation
leads not only to an increase in the oppression and exploitation of the
laborers; it also leads to a colossal increase both in the power of the
means of production and in the size and social weight of the laboring
class. Taken together, these developments make possible the elimination
of exploitation and the division of society into social classes and the
creation of a fully cooperative,that is, communist, society.
proletariat, the working class created by capitalism and brought to its
trueâproletarian, socialistâconsciousness by the struggles it has waged
against the capitalist class. The necessary outcome of the class
struggle is the establishment,in the course of the revolution, of the
âdictatorship of the proletariat,â the âproletariat organized as the
ruling class,â that nationalizes the means of production in its own
hands,suppresses the capitalist class and its hangers-on and proceeds to
establish a planned and truly cooperative society.
direct producers as they do under exploitative modes of production, are
subordinated to and controlled by them. This will lead to an even
greater growth of the forces of production, making possible the
shortening of the working day. This will enable all members of society
to participate in all aspects of the administration of society. The
increase in the forces of production will gradually result in the
elimination of relative scarcity and the social antagonisms that it
engenders,and the establishment of truly equal and cooperative relations
among all people. As this process proceeds, the state, the relic of
previous class-divided societies, âwithers away.â
In the above summary, I have tried to represent the Marxian theory of
historical materialism in the fullest, most logically consistent way I
have been able to, given the limitations of space. Since I have had to
interpret their theory and to interpolate ideas found elsewhere in Marx
and Engelsâ writings, rather than in just the passages quoted above,
some people may take issue with my rendition. Despite this, I believe I
have done justice to the Marxist conception and have avoided setting up
a straw man that will be easy for me to shoot down later. Letâs now
proceed to a more detailed evaluation of their theory.
I noted above that one of the chief characteristics of historical
materialism (and Marxism as a whole), is its ambiguity. This pertains
even in its title, specifically, its use of the word âmaterialism.â
Although the term appears to be precise, it is in fact used in two
distinct senses within Marxian theory. To Marxists, the two meanings are
understood to be compatibleâindeed, necessarily linked. But this is not
the case. The first, and more basic, use of the term is its
philosophical one; it pertains to that part of Marxist theory that has
come to be known asâdialectical materialism.â This is the philosophical
description of what Marxists believe to be their scientific outlook,
both its specific propositions and its methods. In philosophical
language, âdialectical materialismâ is both an ontology,that is,a theory
of being, a theory of the true nature and structure of reality, and an
epistemology, a theory of knowledge. Non-Marxist philosophers would call
thisâmetaphysical materialism,â a term Marxists usually object to since
they deny that their world view is metaphysical at all;to them,Marxism
is scientific, whereas bourgeois philosophy (that is, all other
philosophical outlooks), is âmetaphysics.â
In simple terms, this philosophical materialism asserts: (1) that the
fundamental element of the universe is matterâmolecules, atoms and their
component partsârather than spirit, ideas, or some other ideational
substance; (2) that ideas are an outgrowth of matter, specifically, the
motion and structure of material entitiesâthe firing of neurons, the
movement of atomic particles (molecules, ions, protons, neutrons and
electrons)âin the human body, particularly the brain.For materialists,
it is the impact of matter on and within the body, both over time and at
any given time, that gives rise to ideas. Marx and Engels considered
their outlook to be the extension and result of a long line of
philosophical thought, beginning with the pre-Socratics (Greek
philosophers prior to Socrates), particularly Democritus, who believed
the world was made up of atoms. It also included the later Greek
philosopher, Epicurus, and his Roman follower, Lucretius, the British
empiricists,Francis Bacon and John Locke, the political philosopher,
Thomas Hobbes, the radical French materialists of the Enlightenment,
such as Diderot, dâHolbach, and dâAlembert, and Marx and Engelsâ
immediate philosophical predecessor, Ludwig Feuerbach. For Marx and
Engels, their own outlook is saved from what they considered to be the
one-sided, mechanical flaws of these earlier philosophies by the
contributions of the German Idealists, Fichte, Schelling, and
particularly Hegel.
Although Marx and Engels used the same label (materialism)to describe
their theory of history, the sense of the word as used in this realm is
somewhat different. Here it refers to the production and distribution of
what are commonly called âmaterial goods,â that is, economic products.
But this label, as applied narrowly and more broadly to the theory of
historical materialism as a whole, is a bit of a misnomer since these
entities are not the only elements or factors involved in historical
development that can be considered to be material. What about factors of
geography or climate? These are certainly material elements, but they
are not, narrowly speaking, economic.One could,it seems to me, come up
with a theory of history that bases itself on these phenomena, and one
could legitimately, I think, call such a theory a form of
materialism,say âclimatologicalâ or âgeographicalâ materialism. Nor does
this exhaust the possibilities of materialist theories of history.
To Marxists, the state and state structures are also material entities.
Lenin, in his famous pamphlet, The State and Revolution, describes the
state as consisting of âspecial bodies of armed men having prisons,
etc., at their command.â (Collected Works, Volume 25, Progress
Publishers, Moscow, 1964, p. 389.) These are clearly material entities,
and by extension, one could develop a theory of history based on the
changing nature of the states that have characterized different
societies. Insofar as the state can be described, as Lenin did, in
material terms, this theory of history might also be called a form of
materialism. Such theories do exist. They are the ones that, for
example, see human history as the story of the evolution of bourgeois,
pluralist democracy. However, since the creators of such theories are
not Marxistsâindeed, they are usually opponents of Marxismâthey do not
describe their theories in materialist terms, but in idealist ones, such
as The Discovery of Freedom (an actual book by Rose Wilder Lane, Laissez
Faire Books, 1984). Yet one could legitimately recast these theories in
materialist language. They would then be materialist theories of
history, but they would not be what Marxists call âhistorical
materialism.â
Conversely, a theory of history based on the progressive evolution of
socio-economic formations (as Marxâs is), need not be materialist. As I
discussed in my articles on Marxâs theory of capital, although
technology exists in material formsâas factories, machines, tools,
etc.âthese entities do not fully describe what technology is. As the
information and bio-technology revolutions have brought out more clearly
than before,technology has an ideal component; it includes the
scientific theories, designs, mathematical expressions, including
computer programs, etc.âin short, the ideasâthat such machinery and
equipment are based on and express or represent. Indeed, one could
argue, the ideal expressions are more fundamental than the material
entities, and consequently, a theory of history based on the development
of technology (which is really what Marx and Engelsâ theory is), could
be more accurately cast in idealist terms, that is, as a form of
intellectual evolution. We would then have an economic (or
technological) theory of history that is not materialist.
What I am trying to get at here is that Marx and Engels use the term
âmaterialismâ in two distinct sensesâone philosophical,as a label for
their ontology and epistemology, and the other more prosaic, meaning
economicâand that the two are not necessarily connected nor implied by
each other. There is no reason why metaphysical/ philosophical
materialists must necessarily subscribe to what Marxists call the
materialist conception of history, nor why those who defend a
materialist conception of history must logically be required to be
philosophical materialists. As we know, there have been materialist
philosophers who were not Marxists and who defended other theories of
history. Likewise, there have been Marxists, even within the organized
Marxist left, who have held to Marx and Engelsâ theory of history, but
have not defended âdialectical materialism.â (Karl Liebknecht, Rosa
Luxemburgâs comrade in the left wing of German Social Democracy and in
the Spartacus League, was one such figure.) Indeed, among Marxists,
there has been a relatively long-standing trend of thinkers, such as the
Polish philosopher, Leszek Kolakowski,who draw a distinction between the
thought of Engels, supposedly the âscientisticâ inventor of
(deterministic) dialectical materialism,and that of Marx, who developed
the (non-deterministic) theory of historical materialism but supposedly
gave little thought to metaphysical questions, or at least did not agree
with his longtime friend and collaborator. (See Kolakowski, Main
Currents of Marxism, Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York,
1978.)
One result of this confusion of terms has been to allow the aura and
prestige of philosophical materialism to accrue to historical
materialism. In other words, since many people(including scientists,
science writers and philosophers), consider science to be materialistic,
calling the Marxist theory of history a form of materialism has helped
Marxists maintain that their theory is scientific, and hence to give it
an authoritative character that it has not earned on its own
account.Since the Marxist theory is a form of materialism, so the
argument goes, and since science is materialist, ergo historical
materialism must be scientific.
This is not the only large-scale ambiguity that characterizes the
Marxist theory of history. Another resides in the question of the
purpose of the theory itself: is historical materialism simply a method
of investigation and a corresponding mode of explanation/interpretation
of historical and social events or does it have predictive value?
In Marxist theory, this question should not even arise. Since Marxism
is, in its own view, scientific (and therefore correct),and since,
according to Marxism, the development of human society follows certain
objective laws that determine its history, Marxism offers both the
correct explanation/interpretation of past events as well as accurate
predictions about the future course of social development. Indeed, it
specifically predicts that capitalism will be superseded by socialism,
that this will occur through a proletarian revolution and, getting even
more precise, that this will necessarily happen through the
establishment of the dictatorship of the proletariat. (See Marxâs letter
to Joseph Weydemeyer, March 5, 1852, Letters to Americans, International
Publishers, New York, 1953. ) This idea is central to Marxism, and
specifically to its claim to be the âunity of theory and practice.â It
is key to its insistence that its variety of socialism is scientific
rather than âutopian.âWhereas the socialist thinkers on whom Marx and
Engels pinned that label developed their conceptions of cooperative
society as moral ideals, conceived of and to be implemented outside of
the historic process (through the actions of humanistic individuals,
such as Robert Owen, who established and managed model communities, or
by convincing people with power to put them into effect), Marx and
Engels insisted that their idea of socialism was grounded in history and
the very structure of human society. It reflected the underlying dynamic
of history and grew out of the historic process itself, rather than
having to be inserted into it, as it were, from without. They therefore
sought to base their notion of socialism, along with their strategy and
tactics, on an understanding of history as whole, and more precisely, on
an analysis of the dynamics of and the economic and social trends
discernible within capitalist society (e.g., the concentration and
centralization of capital, the growth of the proletariat, the expansion
of state intervention in the economy,etc.). In their own eyes, Marx and
Engels did not advocate socialism as a moral goal. They insisted that it
would necessarily (that is, inevitably) develop out of capitalism
itself. In short,in contrast to the utopians, who advocated socialism as
a âgood thing,â Marx and Engels predicted socialism.
But,in fact,Marxism can be understood and embraced in two ways. The
first is as it was explicitly propounded, complete with predictions,
specific theses and strategic/programmatic goals. The second is simply
as a framework for investigating,explaining and interpreting history and
the nature and dynamics of human society more generally, without any
claim to have predictive value, to advocate socialism or to be a guide
to practical activity to attain such an end. While this ambiguity has
existed within Marxism since its inception, it has become much more
apparent as capitalism has developed. Asa result, today Marxism can be
viewed as consisting of two fairly distinct variants. The first is its
traditionalâideological and programmaticâform, that is, as the
world-view of avowedly Marxist organizations and individuals, those who
advocate and carry out political activity to achieve socialism.The
second is a largely analytical variety, which uses Marxist theory, its
conceptions and terminology as tools for investigating and interpreting
social life.
The existence of this second variant, or mode, is in part the result of
the fact that Marxism offers a fruitful framework for analyzing human
society. This is particularly so when some of the extreme contentions of
the theory are modified into more considered statements. Who denies that
economic and social life conditions (rather than uniquely determines),
human consciousness? Who denies that the economic and structure of any
given society greatly influences the nature of its political system and
the culture it manifests? Who denies that societies can be analyzed in
terms of the social classes that constitute them, that there have been
and are struggles between such classes and that these struggles
significantly affect the evolution of those societies? Moreover, while
emphasizing the preponderant role of economic and social factors,
Marxism also attempts to integrate into its framework other phenomena,
such as political structures, ideologies, religions, art and philosophy,
and even the personalities of historically prominent individuals. As a
result of these and other features,Marxism has had a major impact on the
development of the social sciences as a whole, both through its own
contributions and by provoking reactions to itself. Specifically, given
its insistence on socio-economic processes and structures as the root
causes of historical events, Marxism has played a significant role in
opening up, or at least significantly expanding,certain fields of
investigation, such as economic and social history generally and, more
specifically, the study of the lives,conditions and struggles of members
of the lower classes,subjects that were largely ignored before Marx and
Engels began their work.And because of its effort to integrate
political, ideological and cultural phenomena into its analyses, Marxism
has also stimulated other areas, (e.g.,the history of art and science,
literary criticism), by supplying an alternative standpoint from which
to analyze the issues involved.
This analytical mode of Marxism actually emerged within the Marxist
movement itself. Explicitly Marxism-inspired research was carried out by
individualsâpolitical figures, theoreticians and academic
researchersâwho were avowed Marxists and were members of or loyal to
Marxist organizations, such as the Socialist or Communist Parties.Much
of it was also, at least in theory, pursued with the purpose of guiding
the political struggles of individual Marxists and Marxist
organizations.However, beginning in the 1930s, with the theoretical work
of those who would eventually constitute the Frankfurt Institute for
Social Research, (Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Walter Benjamin,
Herbert Marcuse and others), and at an accelerated rate in the late
1960s and theâ70s, Marxism, no longer explicitly attached to Marxist
organizations and consequently less dogmatic, diffused into the academic
community at large. This development has given rise to what may be
called âacademic Marxism.â Not surprisingly, this variety of Marxism
focuses on Marxist theory as a method of investigation and a mode of
explanation/interpretation of history and other economic, social and
cultural phenomena, and ignores or downplays claims that such theory has
predictive value.
While this academic Marxism has grown and prospered, the more
traditional version has continued to be the official ideology of avowed
Marxist organizations, inspiring and, at least in principle, guiding
their activities designed to promote social change and eventually to
bring about socialist revolutions. Integral to this variant, as we have
seen, is the insistence that Marxist theory has predictive value, that
it can make accurate predictions about the future development of human
society.
The emergence of academic Marxism and the de facto split between it and
the traditional forms of Marxist âpraxisâ have brought the distinction
between the two ways of interpreting Marxist theory into greater relief.
Yet, this division or ambiguity was present within Marxism from fairly
early on in its history and remains a notable characteristic of
traditional Marxism to this day.Among the manifestations of the
analytical mode of Marxism were various works of Marx and Engels and
later theoreticians that presented Marxist analyses of specific
historical events without attempting to use these explicitly to prove
the programmatic claims of Marxism.These efforts, such as Engelsâ The
Peasant War in Germany, Marxâs The Class Struggles in France 1848â1850
and The 18^(th) Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, and Karl Kautskyâs The
Foundations of Christianity, were meant in part, if not primarily,to
explicate the Marxist theory of history and to demonstrate its cogency.
The idea, apparently, was that by revealing historical materialismâs
ability to provide compelling explanations of historical events, one
thereby proved its overall validity, its truth value. Other examples of
this analytical mode within what I have called traditional Marxism were
attempts,embodied in letters, articles and books, on the part of Marx
and Engels and their followers to explain why history was not unfolding
in the way they had originally predicted: why, for example, the
socialist revolution hadnât occurred, why the working class was not (at
least not at that moment) revolutionary, why capitalism seemed more
resilient than Marxâs theory suggested, why it seemed (at least to some)
to be over-coming its internal contradictions, etc. Although these
analyses purported to orient Marxist practice in the present, there was
very little strategic or programmatic about them. They had more the
character of urging Marxists to hold on, for the time when the
proletariat would, once again, be revolutionary and Marxâs predictions
be borne out. Still another example of such interpretive Marxism arose
among Marxists active in or concerned about countries not deemed ripe
for socialist revolution (such as pre-revolutionary Russia). Here
researchers utilized Marxist theory simply to analyze their societies,
and if the results were put to political uses at all, they were often
intended to advocate policies that favored one or another type of
capitalist development. Many of the contemporary Marxist theories of
monopoly capitalism, imperialism, and related phenomena, such as
âunderdevelopment,â also have this primarily explanatory or interpretive
character.
Despite this, for Marx and Engels and virtually all Marxists in the
heyday of the Marxist movement (Kautsky, Luxemburg, Plekhanov, Martov,
Lenin, Bukharin, Trotsky, Stalin, Mao, Ho Chi Minh, Che Guevara, et.
al.), Marxism was, by definition,the âunity of theory and practiceâ and,
hence, predictive; to them,a purely analytical, theoretical or academic
Marxism was a contradiction in terms. Marx himself was explicit about
this. As early as 1844, he wrote in his Theses on Feuerbach: âHitherto
philosophers have only interpreted the world. The point, however, is to
change it.â
Today, this position cannot be so easily maintained. Part of the reason
for this is that Marxism has spread beyond the explicitly Marxist
organizations and milieu, into academia and beyond; Marxism now speaks
with many more voices than it once did. But equally important is the
fact that so many of the predictions of traditional Marxism have not
been borne out: capitalism has not evolved as Marx thought it would, the
international proletariat has not become revolutionary, the global
socialist transformation has not occurred,what many thought to be
socialist regimes in Russia and Eastern Europe have collapsed, China is
no longer the bulwark of militant Marxian socialism, as Maoists once
believed,etc. If anything, the working class has become less
revolutionary, the industrial proletariat, on which Marx pinned his
hopes,has shrunk relative to the size of the working population as a
whole, the global Marxist movement has dwindled,and Marxism today has
very few supporters even among its supposedly natural constituents, the
workers. Yet, these developments are explicable in terms of Marxist
theory itself. In other words, Marxist theoreticians have been able to
come up with reasonably convincing analyses that explain why the world
has not developed as Marx and Engels believed it would.Ironically, then,
analytical Marxism has enabled Marxism to survive, even to prosper,
despite the collapse of its specific predictions and the severe decline
in its traditional political and organizational manifestations.
The ambiguity of Marxist theory has thus turned out to be a source of
strength. For if Marxism is merely a mode of explanation and
interpretation, it is not refutable. As long as the crucial facts are
successfully integrated into its analyses,and as long as these analyses
seem plausible and logically consistent, Marxist interpretations of
history, or of anything else for that matter, become almost a question
of tasteâdoes one find them compelling or not?âand Marxism can-not be
held to account. In any case, it is certainly a lot easier to come up
with after-the-fact explanations than to be able to predict future
social developments. Here, too, Marxismâs ambiguities redound to its
advantage: where any given historical or social event appears to violate
specific Marxist tenets or predictions, Marxism can be given credit for
its empiricist integrity, that is, its commitment to the facts and its
willingness to recognizing the richness, the concreteness and the
âdialectical natureâ of history. As a mode of analysis,then, Marxism can
be quite fecund. But the fact that Marxist explanations may âmake senseâ
is not proof that Marxism as a whole is correct, that its theory of
history is true,or that its claims be scientific are valid. Despite
this,this is usually how Marxists argue. Indeed, as I have mentioned,
Marxists have utilized Marxist theory to explain why other aspects of
Marxism have not been borne out. This proves, so Marxists claim, that
despite the failure of many of its prognostications, Marxism is still
right.
This ambiguity works to Marxismâs advantage in yet other ways. Even when
Marxists defend the propositions of traditional Marxism, they constantly
shift from âtighterâ interpretations to âlooserâ ones and back again.
Sometimes socialism is inevitable; at other times, it is merely highly
likely or even just possible. Sometimes social existence determines
consciousness; at other times,it just shapes and conditions it.Sometimes
the material base of society determines the super-structure; sometimes
it merely engenders its overall nature. The superstructure is both
determined by the base and âdialecticallyâ determines it. The structure
and dynamics of capitalism explain both why the proletariat is
revolutionary and why it is not. Etc., etc. Given such flexibility,
Marxism can be made to provide equally valid Marxist explanations for
entirely contradictory phenomena. As a result, it cannot really be
proved or disproved, and it is not, therefore, scientific.
Letâs look at some of the specific aspects of historical materialism in
light of this.
In section I of the Communist Manifesto, Marx and Engels write:
âThe history of all hitherto existing society is the history of class
struggles.â (Communist Manifesto, p. 9) (Engels in his preface corrects
this with the caveat âsince the dissolution of primitive tribal
society....â)
This seems to be clear and definite enough, but we have already seen how
Marx, in his summary of historical material-ism in the Preface to the
Critique of Political Economy, fails even to mention the class struggle,
let alone to stress it. This suggests that the notion of the class
struggle, however important it may be to be to Marxists, may not be well
integrated with the other aspects of Marxist theory. In any case, a look
at the conception of class struggle will reveal that the idea is not as
precise as it may seem at first glance.
The problem starts with the very definition of class. Given the
centrality in Marxist theory of the question of economic production, for
Marxists, social classesâprobably the most important social category in
Marxist theoryâare defined by their respective positions in the
productive process, specifically, by their relation to the means of
production. Ruling/exploiting classes are those social groups that own
the means of production. Ruled/exploited classes are those groups that
do not own the means of production, but instead are under the domination
of and are exploited by those that do. This seems simple enough, but it
does not hold up consistently across the various types of society that
Marxists have considered.
For example, under feudal society, the ruling class, the feudal
nobility, did not actually own the land. Instead, the members of the
nobility held tracts of land as fiefdoms, that is, in a kind of
trustâuse in exchange for (military) serviceâfrom those above them in
the feudal hierarchy. Insofar as the land could be said to be owned at
all (and even this is questionable), it was owned by the individual at
the apex of the feudal aristocracy, the monarch, who in turn held the
land in trust from God. It was only as feudalism declined, and
capitalist commercial relations developed, that the land came to be
considered the private property of those who had held it historically.At
the other end of the social scale, the serfs are generally considered by
Marxists to be tied to the means of production,bound to the land and to
the lords immediately above them,and owing a variety of labor and other
services (taxes and dues) to them. Yet, the serfs were in fact highly
differentiated as to the degree of their enserfment and by the extent
and nature of the services they were required to supply. In fact,some
peasants were not serfs at all, some serfs were relatively well-to-do,
while some feudal estates were worked by slaves.As a result, to make the
Marxist definition of class âfitâ the case of feudalism, we have to
broaden the definition of ruling class to those who own or control the
means of production,while we have to narrow the empirical range of the
historical phenomena of serfdom toward an âideal type,â a supposedly
typical serf, and exclude or downplay those who donât quite fit the
category.
It is also worth noting here that the use of the term âfeudal-ismâor the
âfeudal mode of productionâ itself is a misnomer.Feudalism, properly
speaking, refers to the internal structure of the nobility and the
stateâthe hierarchical relations of lords and lieges,the holding of land
in trust from social superiors in exchange for serviceârather than to
the economic nature of the society. Feudalism, in this strict sense,
only exist-ed in parts of Western EuropeâFrance, England and parts of
Germanyâand in Japan, a rather small section of the world.A better term
would be âmanorial economy.â (See Europe Emerges, by Robert L. Reynolds,
The University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, 1961.) In an attempt to deal
with this difficulty (as well as others), some Marxists, such as Samir
Amin,have proposed to introduce a broader category, a âtributaryâmode of
production, into Marxist theory. This mode includes all societies
between primitive communism and capitalism.(See Samir Amin, Class and
Nation, Historically and in the Current Crisis, Monthly Review Press,
New York and London, 1980.)
There is a similar problem with the Marxist definition of class when we
look at what Marxists call the âAsiaticâ mode of production, or
âOriental Despotismâ (a category Marx described and attempted to analyze
but which he was not able to effectively integrate into his overall
theory). In these societies, the dominant classes did not directly own
the land, nor were the peasants serfs. The land was owned and farmed by
peasant families, who (along with artisans and merchants) were exploited
by the ruling elitesâprimarily state bureaucraciesâby means of taxation.
Even under capitalism, the Marxist definition of class is problematic.
In an early stage of the industrial revolution, the definition seemed to
fit the factsâcapitalists owned factories,while workers were alienated
from the means of production,that is, owned no land or tools, and were
forced to sell their labor-power to the capitalists in exchange for
wages. Yet, with the development of the modern corporation and the
diversification of stock ownership among broader sectors of the
population, the definition of capitalist becomes blurred. Many
individuals in the middle class (and sections of the working class, even
if only indirectly through their pension plans), own stocks; most
corporate executives are salaried personnel (in addition to being owners
of stock in their own and other companies), and the traditional
capitalist entrepreneur who directly managed his own firm, has declined
in social significance. Moreover, while small businesspersons do own the
means of production, they are not part of the ruling class. And of
course,there are significant sectors of the ruling class who are not
capitalists at all; professional politicians, top military officers,
government bureaucrats, corporate lawyers and other consultants, as well
as wealthy artists, actors, film directors, and figures in the sports
world, whose precise social position is harder to define. By the same
token, the social differentiation of the working class, the
proliferation of the service sectors of the economy and the expansion of
the professional middle classes have made the definition of proletarian
more difficult to pin down. In all these cases, we can maintain what we
might call the spirit of the Marxist definition of social class only by
broadening it and making it more flexible, in other words, by giving it
the benefit of the doubt.
The conception of the class struggle is also not as cut and dried as it
may initially seem. Engels defines class struggles as âcontests between
exploiting and exploited, ruling and oppressed classes.â This, too,
seems clear enough, but letâs ask some questions. We can all agree, I
suspect, that when the majority of workers in a given country carry out
a revolution or a general strike, this can properly be called the âclass
struggle.â This seems to be, as Engelsâ definition implies, a contest
between one class and another, meaning a struggle between each class as
a whole. But how about when the workers in a particular industry,
corporation or just one factory go out on strike? This is certainly not
a contest between the capitalist class, as a class, and the working
class, as a class. And what about when a worker calls in sick on a day
he or she is not really ill, just to take a day off? Is this the class
struggle? Or when a worker sabotages the assembly line or simply vents
hostility at a supervisor? And what are we to consider a struggle in
which white workers strike to prevent the hiring of Black or other
minority workers, or men strike to prevent the hiring of women, or
native-born workers strike to prevent the hiring of immigrants? Is this
the class struggle? Marxists would most likely contend that all these
actions are forms of class struggle, although âpartialâ or âdistorted.â
But more critical observers might disagree. And similar arguments can be
made about all the other modes of production. How many peasants need
riot before it is the class struggle? How many slaves need to break
tools or run away for these actions to be the class struggle? Or are
these actions the class struggle by definition? Here we can glimpse the
tautological character of much of Marxist theory. Since, according to
Marx and Engels,the history of humanity (excluding primitive communism),
is a history of class struggles, everything that happens in society is
either the class struggle, a manifestation of the class struggle, or an
effect or reflection of the class struggle. As we saw in the case of the
question of class, the Marxist conception of the class struggle can be
sustained only if it is helped along.
This might be considered to be knocking down a straw man,but even bigger
problems arise when we analyze Engelsâ claim that, apart from the era of
primitive communism, âthe whole history of mankind has been a history of
class struggles.â This is a bold statement.And, it seems to me, it can
only be seriously maintained if one broadens the definition of class
struggle to such an extent that it becomes virtually meaningless, or if
one looks at history entirely a priori through the lenses of Marxist
theory, or both. Because if one looks at history empirically and if the
idea of class struggle is taken literally and seriously, Engelsâ claim
is absurd. It makes some sense if it is taken to mean simply that class
struggles (and here I mean abroad definition of class struggle) have
occurred throughout history and have played an important role in
influencing its direction and outcome. But Engels says much more than
this.
Normally, when one uses the term class struggle in the Marxist sense,
one means struggles between the chief classesâthe ruling class and the
exploited classâthat constitute any given mode of production. Under
supposedly slave modes of production, say, slavery during the Roman
Republic and the Empire, this would mean struggles between slaves and
slave owners. Thus, Engelsâ statement would imply that the history of
Rome was, or was dominated or determined by, the struggles between these
two classes. But, unless one means by the âclass struggleâ things like
working slowly, breaking tools or running away (or the mere fear of a
slave revolt), there really wasnât that much of a class struggle between
slaves and slave owners during this period. Most significantly, there
were (unfortunately) very few substantial slave uprisings. I know of
only three: two in Sicily, ca. 135 and 100 BC, and the revolt led by
Spartacus in 73â71 BC. Itâs possible there were more but that I, in my
ignorance, donât know about them, or that the Romans, for a variety of
reasons, didnât write about them.But surely if the history of Rome can
seriously be said to be âa history of class struggles,â there ought to
be more than this. This relative lack of significant slave revolts is
perfectly understandable given the nature of slavery (the fact that
slaves were from many areas and spoke different languages, that they had
little opportunity to communicate with one another beyond relatively
small groups, let alone to organize themselves, that the owners held out
the possibility of manumission to obedient slaves,that slaves were
subject to cruel punishments, including torture,maiming and execution,
for even slight infractions, etc., etc.), and the military skill of the
Romans. But the fact remains, there wasnât that much of an ongoing class
struggle between slaves and slave-owners in Rome.(See Keith R. Bradley,
Slavery and Rebellion in the Roman World 140 B.C.-70 B.C., University of
Indiana Press,Bloomington and Indianapolis, 1989.)
Perhaps if we include the conflicts between the Roman patricians and the
Roman peasantry and other lower classes, what Marx and Engels in the
Communist Manifesto refer to as theâplebeians,â Engelsâ contention might
seem to be a more accurate description of Roman history. This may have
been true at various times under the Republic, but by the end of that
period, this was no longer the case. This was largely because by then
the Roman/Italian peasantry had been destroyed, not by a struggle
between it and the patricians, but largely as a result of the wars by
means of which Rome expanded (both the depredations of the conflicts and
the long-term service of the peasants in the army, which prevent-ed them
from working their farms). By then, the Roman army had become one of
professionals who owed their loyalty to their immediate commanders, and
the social conflicts of Rome had morphed into conflicts among these
generals and the various cliques among the ruling class that supported
them. Unless this entire process is seen as somehow representing the
class struggle, Engelsâ claim, in relation to this period too, seems
forced indeed.
As for the other major component of the lower classes, theâproletariat,â
it was hardly a class in the Marxist sense of the term,and the
proletarians were not a chief element in the mode of production. They
were a mass of mostly unemployed people who survived on periodic public
distributions of food. They certainly played a role in the internal
struggles of Rome,but mostly as pawns of various factions and groupings
within the elite classes.That there were struggles among various social
groupings in Rome is true. That these struggles constituted âthe class
struggleâ in the Marxist sense of the term, or that they defined the
history of Rome are highly dubious propositions. In this light, Marx and
Engelsâ discussion of the class struggle in the Communist Manifesto has
more of the character of a rhetorical device than a scientific
analysis.Unless one means by the class struggle every struggle waged
within and between the various social groupings in the ancient world,
including struggles among elites, city-states and ethnic groups (e.g.,
Greeks versus Persians, Athenians versus Spartans, Romans versus
Carthaginians, Greeks, and Jews,Jews versus Egyptians and Philistines),
the Marxist dictum that human history is the history of class struggle
is, when applied to that period, either a gross exaggeration or
down-right false.
Much the same can be said about the class struggle under feudalism.
There certainly were peasant uprisings, but there werenot that many, and
it is stretching things to say that the history of feudalism is simply
the history of the struggles betweenâlord and serf â or, in the same
vein, between âguild master and journeyman,â as the Communist Manifesto
puts it. There were also periodic struggles between towns persons and
the feudal nobility, but I doubt the history of feudalism as a whole can
legitimately be described as the history of this conflict. Certainly, at
the end of the feudal period the struggle between the emerging
bourgeoisie (primarily merchants) and the feudal nobility becomes
increasingly important (although,insofar as the monarch tended to ally
him/herself with the bourgeoisie against the rest of the nobility, this
has as much the character of an intra-elite conflict as the class
struggle),and might plausibly be characterized as dominating the history
of feudalism (if society can truly be said to be feudal) during this
period. But taking feudalism as a whole, it is simply not true that the
history of feudalism is the history of class struggles.
Nor can the history of capitalism simply be described as the history of
class struggle. What is true is that in the early period of capitalism
and throughout much of its history, the class nature of society became
much more obvious, class lines more definite, and the struggle between
the classes more openâless ensnared, as it were, in the various
non-economic trappings of previous societiesâand in general more
powerful and socially salient. In short, with the advent of
capitalism,the class struggle did become an increasingly important
factor on social life. It is this, I think, that had such a profound
effect on Marx and Engels. In particular, they were most likely
influenced by the fact that the French Revolution (and the succeeding
Napoleonic period), which had turned French society upside-down and had
dominated the political and social life of Europe for over 15 years, had
occurred relatively recently;that there had been a revolution in France
in 1830 and a substantial uprising of agrarian workers in England in the
same period; that they had lived through, indeed, had participated in,
the revolutions of 1848; that they had witnessed the Chartist agitation
in England, etc. Given the size, social impact and relative frequency of
these events, it was natural to generalize to the history of capitalism
as a whole and, more daringly, to the entire history of humanity
(excluding primitive communism). In other words, Marx and Engels, it
seems to me, looked at the most recent history of European
society,during which social classes and the class struggle between them
did play a paramount role, and generalized from there.Their
generalizations were of two kinds. First, from the idea that the class
struggle was a crucial factor in the history of early modern Europe,
they assumed that it was determinant.Second, they decided that what was
true of this period was true of all past history (except the era of
primitive communism), and would be true of the future. But these
generalizations do not necessarily follow. Thus, while it may be true
that in much of the history of capitalism the class struggle, in the
narrow sense of the term, has played a crucial role, it is not true that
the history of capitalism is the history of the class struggle, or that
it has been determined by the class struggle, let alone that all history
is or has been determined by the class struggle.
In fact, in the period after 1848, the outbursts of militant and
revolutionary class struggle that had occurred so regularly in the
previous 60 years gave way to a long period of relative inter-class
quiescence. There were wars between states (the Austro-Prussian and
Franco-Prussian Wars), as well as struggles to unify nation states
(Germany and Italy), but rather few mass outbreaks of the class struggle
(lower classes against upper classes) within states. The Paris Commune,
which occurred in the aftermath of the Franco-Prussian War and which has
assumed considerable importance in Marxist theory because of Marxâs (not
quite accurate) account of it as rep-resenting the dictatorship of the
proletariat, was much more the exception than the rule. This long-term
lull in the class struggle was the cause of considerable chagrin on the
part of Marx and Engels, which is reflected in their correspondence. The
period did see the rise of mass working class organizationsâtrade unions
and political partiesâand the growth in the influence of Marxism and
socialist ideology in general,but these organizations showed far more
tendencies toward accommodation with the capitalist state than
revolutionary opposition to it. And by the end of the 19^(th) century,
reformist trends in socialism (including within formally Marxist
organizations), were far more powerful than the revolutionary ones. Nor
was any significant sector of the working class consciously and
consistently revolutionary. As a result, a major concern of Marxist
theorists at this time (and in fact the entire period up to the outbreak
of World War I), was to explain why there wasnât more class struggle and
to assess the meaning of this for Marxist praxis. This was the origin of
the openly revisionist, reformist point of view, put forward by Eduard
Bernstein among others, in the Second (or Socialist)International in the
late 1890s. It was also, in part, the purpose of the various theories of
state capitalism and imperial-ism,aside, of course, from the need to
explain the post-1885scramble on the part of the major European powers
to carve up Africa. Leninâs theory of imperialism (much of it derived
from the English theorist, J. A. Hobson), is, to a considerable extent,
intended as an account of how imperialism serves to displace the class
struggle from within modern capitalist societies and to transform it
into a conflict among national states,that is, among the imperialist
powers, and one between those states and the colonized peoples.
This concern of Marxist theorists continued throughout the20th century.
Despite periods of radical class struggle, including the Russian
Revolution of 1917, the wave of abortive revolutions that followed it,
and the Spanish Revolution (1936â39),these revolts appeared to be
overwhelmed by conflicts between different nations and would-be nations:
the Balkan Wars, World Wars I and II, the Korean and Vietnam Wars,and
struggles for national liberation generally. Certainly since the
1950s,theories of imperialism (âmonopoly capitalism,ââlate-capitalism,â
the âpermanent arms economy,â etc.), most of them indebted to Lenin,
have been invoked to explain the relative absence of the class struggle,
as traditionally defined,within the imperialist/capitalist countries and
the corresponding quiescence and political conservatism of the working
class. All these theories represent variants of the notion that the
class struggle was âdisplacedâ from the imperialist âcenterâto the
âperipheryâ and transformed into national liberation/anti-imperialist
struggles. It is to Marxistsâ credit that they championed and often led
these struggles. But this has also served to hide the theoretical
maneuvers that this has entailed. These inter-imperialist and
imperialists-vs.-colonized conflicts certainly included class struggles.
Some may even be accurately described as representing the class struggle
in national forms, but to say that all these struggles simply were the
class struggle, or that the history of this period was determined by the
class struggle, is a gross simplification.
In light of this, we can discern two closely related ways of defending
the Marxist insistence that all of human history (since primitive
communism) has been the history of class struggle (beyond the tendency
to exaggerate the importance of the class struggle at any point in
time). One is to claim that all of the events that have occurred in
history, including the struggles between sections of the elite, wars
between national groupings and states, etc., even if they are not,
narrowly speaking, class struggles, really are the class struggle,
although in distorted in form. The other is simply to contend that all
these events somehow reflect the class struggle, that is,that underneath
everything, the class struggle makes everything else happen,even if it
is not actually discernible. Both of these have the advantage of greater
flexibility than the bald insistence that history simply is the history
of class struggles. But they are, in fact, fudges. They both broaden the
definition of âclass struggleâ to such an extent as to render it
meaningless, while at the same time defining history tautologically in
Marxist terms: in other words,since, according to Marxism, the history
of humanity is the history of class struggles, everything that happens
either is, or reflects, or is caused by the class struggle, even if this
is not apparent.
This reveals a kind of mystical tendency that underlies Marxism. History
is impelled by a hidden forceâhere, the class struggleâthat is not
always obvious,but always makes itself felt. It works in a mysterious,
underground way, and only those with special knowledgeâthose initiated
into the intricacies of Marxist theoryâcan comprehend it. In a previous
article, I described this notion at work in Marxâs theory of capital, in
which the logical development of value/laborâits dialectical
evolutionâdefines and governs the development and internal workings of
capitalism. In either form, this idea reveals the truly idealist nature
of Marxist theory underneath the materialist trappings.
Aside from imprecision and resultant flexibility, the ambiguities of the
Marxist notions of class and class struggle suggest another, and much
profounder, ambiguity that resides both within the theory of historical
materialism and within Marxism as a whole. This is the question of
whether history is a deterministic process or merely a contingent one.
Is history determined and therefore predictable, or is it âopenâ and
hence unpredictable; are various outcomes possible? This question is at
least implied by the difference between the two presentations of
historical materialism cited above,specifically, the fact that Engelsâ
presentation stresses the class struggle, while Marxâs doesnât even
mention it. This is because the notion of struggle, and therefore the
class struggle, implies contingency; the outcome of any given struggle
is not determined;either party can win or lose. Thus, a historical
conception that stresses the class struggle is a contingent or âopenâ
one, while one that stresses the inexorable development of the forces of
production and omits or downplays the question of class struggle is
deterministic and âclosed.â Some commentators have seen this ambiguity
as a contradiction between Marxâs theory of capital and the theory of
historical materialism. Others have viewed it as a conflict between
Marxâs and Engelsâ worldviews: in their interpretation, Marx,the real
Marxist, defends a contingent theory of history while Engels, a mere
âpositivist,â puts forward a deterministic one.
To me, the answer is obvious. The contradiction underlies Marxist theory
as a whole. It is another example, perhaps the most fundamental one, of
the fact that Marxism, in regard to all the crucial questions it
addresses and claims to answer,wants to have it both ways: history is
both contingent and determined; consciousness is determined by material
conditions, but not entirely; the base and superstructure interact
dialectically, but the base âultimatelyâ determines the super-structure;
socialism is inevitable, but not exactly.
We shall see similar ambiguities in Marxâs theory of the mode of
production, to which we now turn.
According to Marxism, the various forms of human society that have
existed throughout history have been based on a series of modes of
production that determine the nature, the internal dynamics and the
resultant history of those societies.To paraphrase Marx, each mode of
production consists in part of the relations of productionââdefinite
relationsâ that are âindispensable and independent of their [menâs]
willââthat they âenter intoâ when they engage in âsocial production.â
These relations âcorrespond to a definite stage of development of their
material powers of production,â or what Marxists call the âforces of
production,â and their âsum total constitutes the economic structure of
society.â This structure,made up of the forces and relations of
production, is the âreal foundation, on which rise legal and political
superstructures and to which correspond definite forms of social
conscious.ââThe mode of production in material life determines the
general character of the social, political and spiritual processes of
life.âA bit later on in this passage, Marx lists these modes of
production:
In broad outline, we can designate the Asiatic, the ancient, the feudal
and the modern bourgeois methods of production as so many epochs in the
progress of the economic formation of society.
Here, once again, instead of the precision required of truly scientific
theories, we get vagueness and ambiguity.
To begin with, there is the matter of definitions. What exactly does
Marx mean when he refers to these different âmethods of productionâ that
represent or correspond to differentâepochs in the progress of the
economic formation of societyâ? Although these âepochsâ are generally
taken by Marxists to represent distinct modes of production (which, with
their corresponding âsuperstructures,â represent distinct forms of
society), the nature and defining characteristics of each of these
epochs/methods/modes are not specified. Marx seems to assume that his
readers will understand what he means by them. Thus, when Marx refers to
the âancientâ methods of production, Marxists have generally assumed
that he was talking about an economy based upon slavery as it existed
among the Greeks and the Romans, what they call a slave mode of
production. But the âancientâ world consisted of far more than just
Greece and Rome: Egypt, the societies of the Tigris-Euphrates Valley,
Persia, leaving aside more distant areas, such as the civilizations in
the Indus Valley and in China (let alone the âuncivilizedâ parts of the
world). In addition, slavery was never the predominant form of labor in
the ancient world asa whole. It always existed side by side with other
forms,including free labor, so that the majority of the direct
produc-ers were not slaves. Indeed, even at the height of the Roman
Empire, when slavery and the slave trade were in full flower,and in the
political and economic center of that imperium, that is, Italy and
Sicily, where slavery was strongest and where,conceivably, it might be
said that an actual slave mode of production existed, slaves constituted
no more than one-third of the population. (See Michael Grant, The World
of Rome, The New American Library, New York and Toronto, 1960.)
Moreover, slavery was primarily a juridical category that obscured a
wide variety of types of work and workers. Aside from those slaves who
worked large agrarian estates, some slaves were granted the right to own
property, tools,machines, etc., and worked independently. Many of these
were highly skilled, such as architects, artists, and scholars.They kept
at least part of the profits of their work/enterprises,which they could
use to purchase their freedom. (See M. I. Finley, The Ancient Economy,
University of California Press,Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1973.) Thus,
even slave-based economies did not simply conform to what is commonly
understood as a slave mode of production. Given all this,what exactly
does Marx mean when he refers to the âancient methods of productionâ?
Questions also surround Marxâs reference to the feudal methods/mode of
production. We have already seen that the term feudalism refers
primarily to the social/political structure of the nobilityâits manner
of holding land in return for servicesârather than to a specific form of
economic production.Moreover, within feudalism in this more precise
sense there also existed other forms of labor besides that of serfs,
e.g.,that of the artisans organized in guilds in the towns and cities,
and that of slaves. And what about other agricultural societies, such as
Tsarist Russia, which were similar but not identical to feudal
societies, properly speaking? Here, too,Marx never specifies.
Beyond problems of definitions, there are other issues. For example, has
all of humanity passed through, or is all of humanity destined to pass
through, each of these âepochs?â This question was to become a major
point of contention within the Marxist movement itself, specifically,
within the Second and Third Internationals, when it came to discussing
the nature of Marxistsâ strategies in those countries which were not
deemed to be fully capitalist. For example, was the revolution in Russia
(and, later, China) to be a bourgeois revolution leading to the
establishment of a democratic republic and a fully capitalist economy,
or could the revolution pass through the âbourgeois democraticâ stage
rather quickly (or skip it altogether), and become a socialist
revolution? Or, in another Marxist mode of expression, is the feudal
mode of production inevitably succeeded by the capitalist mode of
production or can it be transformed, under appropriate circumstances,
into the socialist mode of production? Marx himself never really
answered this question, and Marxist theory on this point, as on many
others, is subject to a variety of interpretations.
Also, have these methods/modes of production existed in pure form or
have they always been intermixed, as it were,with each other? If we take
the world as a whole, it is obvious that, with the exception of
capitalism (and this only relatively recently), each of the
methods/modes of production listed by Marx existed in the context of, or
surrounded by, other methods/modes. In fact, for much of human history,
as Marx well knew, these other modes (hunting/gathering, nomadic
herding, free peasant agriculture), taken together, predominated.Even if
we take each of the modes that Marx mentions as self-contained wholes,
they rarely existed in pure forms. As we saw, although slave production
may have dominated in parts of the ancient (so-called âcivilizedâ)
world, it was not the pre-dominant form throughout. Likewise, under
feudalism, not all of the productive laborers were serfsâwe have already
mentioned slaves, while Marx himself referred to the masters,journeymen
and craftsmen in the guilds, leaving aside the relations found in the
incipient commercial and merchant capitalist sectors that existed
alongside, or, better put, in the interstices, of feudal society,
narrowly conceived.
There are still more questions. For example, do each of these epochs
succeed each other in time? Marxâs use of the termâprogressâ and his
discussion of the forces and relations of production imply that these
methods/modes/epochs occur in order of ascending productivity,
reflecting the growth of humanityâs âmaterial powers of production,â and
this is consistent with the rest of his theory. Unless this were so, why
would the âmaterial forces of production in society come into conflict
with the existing relations of production,â converting the latter âfrom
forms of development of the forces of productionâ into âfettersâ? This
only makes sense if the forces of production have a general tendency to
increase, in other words, if technology tends to develop and to increase
labor productivity throughout history. And, if the forces of production
do tend to grow, the various methods/modes/epochs of production that
Marx names ought to represent distinct stages based on ever more
powerful technology, and they should therefore succeed one another in
order of increasing technological development. But he never actually
says this.
Further, are the transitions from one mode of production to another
necessarily accompanied by âsocial revolutionsâ? As elsewhere, Marxâs
discussion of this point is ambiguous. He never fully and precisely
describes what he means by âsocial revolutions.â Nor does he explicitly
state that the transition from each of these methods/modes of production
to another entails such a revolution, although his discussion implies
that it does. Thus, after mentioning that the relations of production
eventually turn from being forms of development of the forces of
production into their fetters, he writes, âThen comes the period of
social revolution. With the change of the economic foundation, the
entire immense superstructure is more or less rapidly transformed.â From
their other writings, we do know that Marx and Engels believed that this
pattern was an accurate description of the transition from feudalism to
capitalism and, by extension, the transition from capitalism to
socialism, but they never elaborated this conception in relation to the
other modes of production. Indeed, from Marxâs limited discussions of
the ancient world, one can infer that in his view feudalism resulted
from the fact that the class struggle in Rome resulted in the âcommon
ruin of the contending classes,â the fact that the class struggle in
Rome was, in effect, unconsummated. Was this asocial revolution?
Integrally related to the concept of the mode of production in Marxist
theory is the question of the âstages of history.âDespite the lack of
clarity in Marxâs presentation and the myriad questions it raises, Marx
and Engelsâ writings have generally been understood, certainly within
the Marxist movement,to mean that they believed that human society has
developed,in whole or in part, through distinct stages, namely,
primitive communism, slavery, feudalism, capitalism and, ultimately,
socialism, in that order, with the Asiatic mode of production
constituting a kind of evolutionary dead-end or detour (waiting on the
sidelines until capitalism or socialism liberates it from its torpor).
This interpretation is certainly consistent with other tenets of Marxian
theory, particularly the claim that the forces of production tend to
grow over time, as well as the corresponding contention that labor
evolves through increasingly productive forms: slave-labor, serf-labor
and the(formally) free labor of capitalist society. In other words, the
idea held by many Marxists that human society has evolved through such
precise stages, based on increasing labor productivity and distinct
forms of the exploitation of labor,seems to be implied by and is
consistent with Marxâs discussion, but Marx himself never explicitly
said this. Despite this ambiguity over the Marxian provenance of the
theory of the stages of history, letâs look at it to see whether it can
withstand scrutiny.
First, the schema implies that primitive communism was generally
succeeded by slave-based societies; in other words, that when
class-divided, state-based societies were first established,these
societies rested on slave modes of production. Was this the case? I
donât think so. Many early state-dominated societies, such as those
established in the Tigris-Euphrates Valley, in Egypt and in the Indus
Valley were not primarily based on slavery and the laboring populations
did not consist entirely or even mostly of slaves. Moreover, as we saw,
even in Greek and Roman societies, which Marxists generally describe as
being based on slave modes of production, slavery was not the only, or
even the dominant, type of labor.
Second,the Marxist conception implies that slave-based modes of
production were replaced by feudalism. Weâve already seen that
feudalism, properly speaking, only existed in parts of Western Europe
and Japan. If so, what about the people who did not experience feudal
society? They appear to be left out of the schema altogether. Even if we
just focus on the relation between the Roman Empire in the western
Mediterranean and northwestern Europe (the lands of feudalism
proper),the theory has problems and can only be made to fit into the
Marxian schema with a great deal of fudging. Thus, in the later periods
of the western half of the Roman Empire, in various regions and for a
variety of reasons (particularly the decline of trade in general, and
there-fore of slaves), slave labor was replaced by the labor of coloni,
essentially tenant farmers bound in a variety of ways to the land.
Although Marxists may see these laborers as forerunners of feudal serfs,
they werenât serfs; nor was society in this part of the world feudal.
Feudalism is generally thought to have been established much later,
beginning in the 9^(th) and 10^(th) centuries, at the time of the Viking
invasions, and in a far different location, namely northwestern Europe
and England (and under different circumstances,Japan). This is an
awfully long and geographically attenuated transition, and can only be
made to correspond to the Marxian view by omitting entire regions and
historical periods from consideration.
Third, even assuming that Marx and Engelsâ description of the ancient
world and feudalism is correct, (that is, that the Roman Empire can be
described as a slave-based society and that it was replaced by
feudalism), it is not true that the change from a slave mode of
production to a feudal mode of production represented the replacement of
a less economically developed society by a more economically advanced
one. While in theory the labor of serfs might be assumed to be more
productive than that of slaves (insofar as serfs, in contrast to slaves,
have some positive incentive to workâa portion of the crop they
cultivated belonged to themselves), it is not true that feudal
agriculture was generally more productive than the large, slave-worked
estates during the Roman Empire. And, taken as a whole, feudalism was by
no means a more advanced form of society, even in the Marxist sense of
the term,than what it had replaced. There was considerably less trade,
the social division of labor was less developed and the standard of
living, certainly for the upper and middle classes,was not as high. In
what sense,then, can feudalism be described as more advanced or as being
based on more developed forces of production? At the very least, the
question is debatable. And if this is so, the succession of slavery by
feudal-ism cannot simply be described as occurring because the forces of
production grew to such an extent that they could not be contained by
the relations of production (slavery) so that the latter became their
fetters. Nor can the transition between the slave and feudal modes of
production be accurately described as occurring through a social
revolution,except in the most general sense of that term, that is, that
social conditions changed significantly.
Fourth, and what about the rest of the worldâs peoples/societies whose
histories in general cannot be characterized by the Marxian schema? None
of the methods/modes of production listed by Marx, with the exception of
the âmodern bourgeoisâ (and that only relatively recently) ever existed
on a truly international scale. They were all relatively localized, and
many, if not most,of the worldâs peopleâs lived outside them. What
happens to their history, or donât they have any, or doesnât it matter?
Specifically, what about those peoples and parts of the world that
experienced the various forms of the Asiatic mode of production
(sometimes called âOriental Despotismâ),whose internal dynamic,
moreover, cannot be described in Marxist terms? In Marxâs view, the
Asiatic mode of production was economicallyâbut not
politicallyâstagnant: the forces of production did not tend to develop
within these societies. And what do we make of the people who lived
instate-dominated societies in the Americas, or those who lived in
hunter-gatherer, herding, and other types of communities. Where do these
people fit in Marxâs schema? And what does this imply about the Marxist
theory of history? As this suggests, Marxâs historical schema is
militantly Eurocentric in character. The history of the world is seen
entirely from a Western European point of view. The history that
matters, the history that, for Marx and Engels, has real meaning, is the
history of âWestern Civilization,â as that civilization (the capitalist
societies of Western Europe, Great Britain and North America) sees
itself. The history of those parts of the world lying outside the
mainstream of history, as defined by Marx,doesnât matter. This is a
question we will return to later.
Fifth, do the forces of production that are to characterize the later
and more productive societies necessarily develop within the societies
that precede them? For example, did the forces of production
characteristic of the state-dominated, class-divided societies that
succeeded primitive communism necessarily develop within primitive
communism itself? It may have been true that such primitive societies
were economically advanced enough to produce a relative surplus. But
what if the capacity to produce that surplus was the direct result of
the establishment of a state? Specifically, what if the existence of the
state itself was the source of the ability to produce the surplus
through its power to mobilize the large masses of labor need-ed to build
the structuresâdams, dikes and aqueductsârequired to irrigate fields and
make agriculture more productive? In this case, new forces of production
need not have existed beforehand within the previous society.
Moreover, even where this contention of Marxâs seems to holdup, as in
the development of capitalist methods and relations of production within
feudalism, the truth is not so simple. In some sense, the expansion of
trade and the growth of the mercantile class that carried it out (the
forerunner of the modern capitalist class), occurred outside the bounds
of feudal society, properly speaking, rather than within it. This was
particularly true of the âputting outâ system that is generally
considered, and described by Marx, to be the origin of the so-called
free labor contract and the specifically capitalist method of
production. This took place, and necessarily so, outside the
restrictions of the system of guilds, that is, in some sense out-side
the feudal system, rather than within it. Indeed, the very growth of
towns and cities, particularly after the so-called âcommunal
revolution,â through which the towns won their independence from the
feudal lords, had this characteristic.
What this discussion reveals is that the schema we have been considering
is just that, a schema. Empirically, it doesnât fit the facts. As we
have seen, the epochs/methods/modes of production that Marx lists did
not in fact succeed each other in ascending order of
economic/technological progress. The transitions between each of these
societies were not always motivated by the growth of the forces of
production and their eventual conflict with the relations of production,
nor did they necessarily entail social revolutions, except in the most
general sense of the term. Not to mention the fact that the
characterization of some of the modes of production donât accurately
reflect the nature of the societies they are meant to denote: the
ancient world(even the so-called civilized part of it) was not based on
a slave mode of production, the term feudal (or feudalism)doesnât denote
a distinct mode of production at all, while it isnât at all clear that
all or even most societies in Asian are accurately described by what
Marx refers to as the âAsiaticâmethods of production. The entire
conception is obviously a very abstract and arbitrary construct into
which a great many historic developments are uncomfortably crammed,while
a large number of others are ignored altogether. It may seem plausible
at first glance, especially if one doesnât know too much about history,
but it falls apart upon further scrutiny. For more sophisticated
Marxists, it can only be made to work by being manipulatedâstretched,
tightened, pushed, prodded, redefined, etc.,âas needed. Like much else
in Marxist theory, the schema only makes sense if one wants to believe
it, gives it the benefit of the doubt and tries to fit historical
developments into the prescribed pat-tern. It is a daring generalization
that provides much mate-rial for thought and a framework for historical
investigation and interpretation. But it cannot sustain the claim to be
scientific, let alone to be able to base predictions of future social
development on it.
Of course,it can be argued that it is I who have set up this schema and
so made it easy to criticize. Marx, as we saw,merely âdesignatedâ in
âbroad outlineâ the âAsiatic, the ancient, the feudal and the bourgeois
methods of production as so many epochs in the economic formation of
society,â and he never assembled them in precisely the form that Iâve
presented and criticized. Yet, the schema is consistent with, and a
reasonable interpretation of, Marxâs overall theory. It is also how most
Marxists have understood it. And if it is not what Marx and Engels
intended, just what did Marx have in mind when he wrote the passage?
Some commentators have seen it as a kind of program for research, a
starting point for further investigation. But if it is merely this, then
it can only have a highly tentative character until it is verified by
that investigation. And, in fact, most research since Marxâs day
refutes, rather than confirms it,which is why some Marxists, such as
Samir Amin, have sought to modify it. As such, it cannot be used to
prove any-thing.It doesnât demonstrate the validity of historical
materialism and it certainly doesnât demonstrate that socialism is
inevitable. In fact, this passage (Marxâs schema, list or what-ever it
is), has the same ambiguous characteristic and plays the same rubbery
role that all his major concepts do.Sometimes it is presented as an
accurate description of the main contours of human history; at other
times it is simply part of Marxâs method, a program for research or
something else equally as vague. It is whatever any particular Marxist
wants it to be, as long as it serves to justify Marxist theory. (I know,
itâs dialectical.)
But letâs leave this question and turn to another central issue in the
theory of historical materialism. This is the relation-ship between the
base and the superstructure, along with the closely related question of
the relation between social existence and consciousness.
According to Marx and Engels, all societies can be under-stood as being
divided into two parts: (1) an economic, or material, base, consisting
of the forces and relations of production, which is the foundation of
any given society; (2) apolitical and ideological superstructure, made
up of the state, religion, art, philosophy and cultural in general,
which is built upon the economic base and is determined by it. At first
glance, this seems clear enough, yet here, too, as in the rest of the
Marxian theory, it doesnât withstand close analysis.
For one thing,the state does not fit clearly and comfortably into either
of the two categories. Generally speaking,Marxists have considered the
state to be part of the super-structure. This implies that it is a
secondary phenomenon,something that is based on something else that is
more fundamental. Yet, even according to Marxist theory, the state is in
many ways primary; it is a prerequisite of and necessary for the
establishment of the mode of production on which it is supposedly based.
For Marxists, the state is first and foremost an instrument of
oppression, a tool by which a ruling and economically exploiting class
maintains its domination over the subordinate class or classes. Without
the state, the ruling class would have no means to maintain those
classes in subjugation. If there were no state, there would be no
exploitative modes of production, no class-divided societies and no
ruling classes. It would seem, then, that rather than being part of the
superstructure, and hence secondary, the state is even more fundamental,
more basic, than the economic base.
It is also not as easy to draw a clear line between economic and
political structures as the base/superstructure dichotomy suggests. In
many, if not most, societies, the state plays a direct economic role,
beyond its general function of maintaining the subordination and
exploitation of the lower classes. For example, in the societies in the
ancient Middle East (the Tigris-Euphrates Valley) and Egypt and
elsewhere, the state was directly responsible for the irrigation of
farmlandâmaintaining the dams and waterways, calculating the seasons,
predicting the onset of seasonal rains and the flooding of the river
basinsâand mobilizing labor to carry out these tasks (as well as to
build monuments to the rulers/gods). If this isnât an economic function,
what is? It was the basis for the agriculture of these societies, on
which these civilizations as a whole were erected. Were these states
just part of the super-structure, or were they part of the base or part
of both? In Rome,the state was responsible for the recruitment,
organization and maintenance of the Roman army, as well as for the
construction of the roads, bridges, aqueducts, etc., all of which were
necessary not only for the Roman conquests, but also for the famous Pax
Romana(Roman Peace), that was the basis for the expansion and
maintenance of trade (including the slave trade), throughout the
Mediterranean region during this period. In some sense, then, the entire
economy of the civilized world under the Roman Empire rested on this
foundation. These functions were economic ones. Was the Roman state not,
therefore, part of the economic base?
The question of the state under feudalism presents similar problems. In
feudal societies, political authority was so fragmented that it is not
clear whether there truly was a state at all, while the feudal hierarchy
was so integral to the structure of society as a whole that it is
difficult to distinguish between it and the rest of society. As a
result, it is hard to draw a distinction between economic and political
(and religious/ideological) realms,and hence, between base and
superstructure, at all (leaving aside the question of the Catholic
Church, which directly held up to one-third of the land).
It is only under capitalism, and laissez-faire capitalism in particular,
that the base/superstructure, economic/political distinction can readily
be drawn. And it is no accident that it is as only capitalism emerges as
a distinct form of economy that the field of economics, initially called
âpolitical economy,â itself develops; and no accident, either, that many
of the representatives of the new field were advocates of laissez-faire
policies. Indeed, in their theorizing about the capitalist economy and
economics in general, they virtually exclude, as an a priori assumption,
the state from their purview. In other words, the early theoreticians of
the economics of capitalism (and this includes Marx), conceive of the
capitalist economy as an isolated phenomenon, that is, as distinct from
the state.
Yet, this act of abstraction, while perhaps necessary for the
development of the field and the continued elaboration of its
theoretical models, is in fact an arbitrary one that distorts the
reality it is intended to elucidate. Because even under capitalism, and
particularly as capitalism has evolved, the state has not been
independent of the economy, but has been and is heavily involved in its
management and direction.Even in the United States, where state
intervention has lagged relative to, say, European countries, the state
is integrally involved in the entire economy: the national banking
system capped by the Federal Reserve system, the regulation of the stock
market and much other economic activity, federal subsidies of
agricultural and other industries, the inter-meshing of government and
industry in arms production,the development and maintenance of the
infrastructure,public education, social security and other âwelfare
stateâprograms, etc., etc. In other words, even under capitalism,the
distinction between base and superstructure, particularly when it comes
to the role of the state, is not nearly as clear-cut as the Marxian
dichotomy suggests.
But perhaps even more problematic than this is the entire question, in
Marxist theory, of the precise relationship between base and
superstructure and the closely related question of social existence and
consciousness. Here, we will see,once again, the ambiguous nature of so
much of Marxian theory. In fact, Marxism makes two competing claims
about this relationship. On the one hand, we are told that the base
deter-mines the superstructure, both its nature and its evolution.On the
other hand, we are told that the superstructure has its own internal
autonomy and helps determine (âreacts uponâ) the development of the
base. This issue has given rise to a great deal of confusion in the
Marxist movement, and it is not easy to tease apart the issue. Not the
least reason for this that Marx and Engelsâ formulations of the question
are hedged at every turn.
For example, in the passage from the Preface to A Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy, Marx insists: âIt is not the
consciousness of men that determines their existence, but,on the
contrary, their social existence determines their consciousness.â This,
particularly the word âdetermines,â is a very definite (and very bold)
statement. But right before this sentence, Marx writes: âThe mode of
production in material life determines the general [my emphasisâRT]
character of the social, political and spiritual processes of life.â
Here the wordâgeneralâ undercuts the apparent precision (and the
audacity)of the overall contention. Does the mode of production
deter-mine the social, political and spiritual processes of life or
merely condition/influence them? Does it determine all of them or only
some of them, all of them to some degree, some of them entirely, but the
others not at all? And just what exactly is the âgeneral characterâ of
the social, political and spiritual processes of life?
That this is not just my personal reaction is revealed in the fact that
Marx and Engels were never quite able to clarify what they meant, even
to their own followers. Indeed, as their correspondence shows, they were
frequently frustrated by how often they were âmisinterpreted.â It got so
bad that in reference to those whom Engels calls the âFrench âMarxistsâ
of the late seventiesâ (who apparently produced what Marx and Engels
considered to be simplistic Marxist analyses), Marx used to comment:
âAll I know is that I am not a Marxist.â (Engels, Letter to C.Schmidt in
Stuttgart, August 5, 1890, in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Selected
Correspondence, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1965, p. 415.)
The problem, I think, comes from the fact that Marx and Engels use the
word âdeterminesâ in two different, but not clearly delineated, ways,
and that they shift back and forth between them without so indicating
and without, I suspect,even being aware that they are doing so. On the
one hand,they use âdeterminesâ to mean âgreatly influences or
conditionsâ; on the other, they use it to mean âuniquely causesâ orâis
uniquely responsible for.â But these two meanings are, in fact,
qualitatively different. It is one thing to say that a given force or
âfactorâ conditions or helps, along with other forces or factors, to
cause a given social event or development, even if that one factor is
overwhelmingly dominant. It is another thing to claim that that one
force or factor is necessarilyâsolely and uniquelyâresponsible for that
event or development. I suspect that many people would agree that
economic processes, taken broadly, that is, the way a given society is
organized and functions socio-economically, what happens in the economy,
etc., greatly influence or condition how people in that society think
and act and, in so doing, shape history.Yet, very few would sign on to
the notion that these socio-economic processes uniquely cause or are
responsible for peopleâs consciousness and social evolution as a whole.
To pose all this somewhat more broadly, the ambiguity of the word
âdetermines,â as used by Marx and Engels implies, as we mentioned above,
two entirely different types of theory. To say that a given force or
factor participates, along with other forces or factors, in shaping
particular events reflects a theory of âcontingency,â according to which
the outcome of a given process is not predictable beforehand but is
explainable after the fact. On the other hand, to say that a given force
or factor uniquely determines specific events reflects a theory of
necessity or inevitability, according to which the outcome is
predictable, at least if the precise state of the antecedent conditions
is known. Thus, the Marxist conception of history embraces
(uncomfortably) and vacillates between a contingent theory of history
and a theory of historical necessity.
The two meanings of the term âdeterminesâ reflect, I think,the fact that
Marx and Engels were pulled in two different directions concerning the
subject matter they were dealing with. As serious intellectuals and
students of history, they knew that historical events are
extraordinarily complex, that history is the outcome of a multitude of
events, processes, and influences (including the consciousness of its
participants),and that a unidimensional, monofactoral interpretation of
history could not do justice to this complexity. At the same time,they
were concerned to develop and defend a theory of history that they
believed to be scientific, one that reduces history to an analog of a
natural process. This ambiguityâthis contradiction, to use Marxist
phraseologyâis the counterpart of the two variants or modes of Marxism
we discussed above:Marxism as a method of investigation/interpretation
versus Marxism as predictive. As interpreters of history (and
contemporary developments), Marx and Engels wished to develop
sophisticated analyses that did justice to the complexity of events and,
consequently, encompassed a multiplicity of factorsâeconomic, social,
political, ideological. Yet, as proponents of âscientific socialism,â
they wanted their theory to be predictive. This requires that one
âfactorâ be deemed deter-mining, so that the line of historical
development is traceable.
In other words, the two types of theory served two different purposes in
the Marxian worldview but were not really integrated; nor could they be.
As a result, the deterministic theory seems simplistic and âmechanicalâ
when applied to historical interpretation. If the economic base uniquely
determines the superstructure, how do you explain, for example, the fact
that the various Greek city states, presumably sharing the same
technology, organized their economies differently and had different
types of government? Or that modern capitalist societies have
experienced different types of government:presidential republics,
parliamentary republics, various types of dictatorships, etc.? Or that,
more arcanely, different tribes in Papua New Guinea, sharing the same
technology but each living in a deep gorge separated from the others by
impassable mountains, developed completely different types of number
systems? (See What Counts, by Brian Butterworth, The Free Press, New
York, 1999.) Or that some individualsâsay, workers of the same age, from
the same ethnic group, with similar educations and background
experiences, working in the same factory, etc., might have entirely
different political outlooks? Sophisticated answers to these questions
require a lot more than the claim that the base uniquely determines the
superstructure, and that âsocial existence determines consciousness.â
Obviously, the superstructure is influenced/conditioned by the base and,
over any period of time, needs to be appropriate or adequate to it if a
particular society is to survive, but to say that the superstructure is
uniquely determined by, and reducible to the dynamics of,the base is
absurd. It leads to a kind of historical reduction-ism which so many
Marxists articulate and of which Marxism as a whole is often accused.
On the other hand, if history is indeed multifactoral and contingent,
how can one maintain the claim to be able to base a socialist program on
the projected future evolution of society? To be able to predict future
social developments requires both that one facet of the social structure
(for Marxism, the economic, the material base, the mode of production)
be the determining element in historical evolution and that its own
evolution be predictable. In the case of the socialist revolution, Marx
locates the determining factor as the internal dynamics of capitalist
development, the so-called âcontradictions of capital,â and purports to
delineate,through an analysis of these contradictions, the specific
circumstancesâthe growth of the forces of production and the rapid
technological change it entails, the expansion of the world market, the
concentration and centralization of capital, the elimination of the
middle class, the ever-increasing size of the industrial working class,
and the supposedly concomitant development of internationalist
revolutionary socialist consciousnessâthat point toward the socialist
revolution, that make it, in a word they use so frequently,inevitable.
But if history is truly multidimensional and contingent, for example, if
some apparent accident of history,some autonomous phenomenon within the
superstructure,can unpredictably change historyâs course, how can such a
projection of social trends be possible?
Marxists have engaged in various efforts to bridge the gap between these
two poles of their outlook. Yet, none is successful. One is to hide
behind the âdialecticalâ nature of the relation between base and
superstructure. âDialecticalâ in this sense means that two or more
aspects of a given social process are, despite their apparently distinct
identities, integrally connected, totally intertwined, both conflicting
and mutually reinforcing and determining; indeed, they can only be
distinguished analytically. But if the relationship between two aspects
of a contradictory process is truly dialectical, then neither can be
said to be determinant vis a vis the other. If one aspect/factor
determines the other, the process is not truly dialectical.
Another way Marxists have attempted to finesse this and other
contradictions in their world-view is by claiming that Marxism is simply
a method. (See Eric Hobsbawm, Revolutionaries, Abacus, London, 1999.)
But they never say precisely what this method consists of, nor do they
distinguish it from the other aspects of Marxism. Clearly, historical
materialism is more than a method; it makes very strong claims about
society, history and the nature of humanity, as well as proclaiming
programmatic goals. For Marxists, the alleged method actually assumes as
true the other tenets/contentions of their worldview, e.g., that social
existence determines consciousness, that the base determines the
superstructure, etc. In other words, it assumes that Marxism as a whole
is true. But by insisting that Marxism is only a method, Marxists
attempt to evade responsibility for demonstrating the truth of those
other propositions.
For his part, Engels often tries to square the circle through the use of
the words âultimatelyâ and âfinally.â As in: âAccording to the
materialist conception of history, the ultimately determining element in
history is the production and reproduction of real lifeâ (emphasis in
originalâRT); and âamid all the endless host of accidents...the economic
movement finally asserts itself as necessaryâ; and âWe make our history
our-selves, but, in the first place, under very definite assumptions and
conditions. Among these the economic ones are ultimately decisive.â But
who determines when this âultimatelyâ andâfinallyâ actually occurs? What
this comes down to is that when analyzing any given event or period of
history, Marx and Engels and Marxists in general tend to concede
autonomy to the non-material spheres of social life, i.e., the
superstructure, and therefore to a contingent theory of history whose
outcome is not determined nor determinable. But arbitrarily,that is,
when it matters to them, when, for example, it is a question of
analyzing the transition from one mode of production to another, and
specifically, the transition from capitalism to socialism, they assert
that the material/economic dynamic is âultimatelyâ decisive. This way
they can have their cake (a sophisticated multidimensional analysis) and
eat it too(maintain their claims of the predictive character of their
theory and the scientific nature of their program).
The unresolved and in fact unconscious contradiction in the Marxian
outlook we have been discussing is apparent in all of Marx and Engelsâ
attempts to explain themselves. Perhaps the most famous of these is
Engelsâ letter to J. Bloch, of September21-22, 1890 (Selected
Correspondence, as above, pp. 417â419),from which the above quotations
were taken. In this letter,Engels comes close to recognizing the
contradiction in the theory,but never quite gets there. He writes: âMarx
and I are ourselves partly to blame for the fact that the younger people
sometimes lay more stress on the economic side than is due it.We had to
emphasize the main principle vis a vis our adversaries, who denied it,
and we had not always the time, the place or the opportunity to give due
to the other elements involved in the interaction. But when it came to
presenting a section of history, that is, to making a practical
application, it was a different matter and there no error was
permitted.â (Selected Correspondence, as above, pp. 418â419.)
The problems Marxism has had in attempting to integrate certain social
phenomena, such as racism/white supremacy,sexism/the patriarchy,
nationalism, religion, etc., into its theory reflect this ambiguity in
the Marxist conception. Are these phenomena part of the superstructure
or part of the base? Can they be explained in terms of, and hence be
reducible to,questions of (economic/social) class? If class and the
class division of society are fundamental, why hasnât class
consciousness come to predominate among the workers, as Marxism
predicts? Where is the international proletarian solidarity Marxism
exalts? Why are the workers so prone to racism, sexism, national
chauvinism and religious sectarianism? Why, indeed, have we not
experienced the international socialist revolution and the establishment
of global communism? Over the decades, many Marxists have ascribed the
failure of socialist revolutions (either to occur or to be successful)to
problems with the workersâ consciousness, such as their contamination
with racism, sexism, nationalism and religious ideas. In such
explanations, these phenomena outweigh questions of class. But if these
factors are truly super-structural and hence secondary, why do they
appear to be determinant? Here, as elsewhere, Marxism is caught between
its desire for interpretive sophistication, what might be called its
empirical scruples, and its dogma, its desire to maintain the predictive
nature of its theory and the specifics (the inevitability of
socialism,the proletariat as the revolutionary class, the need for a
dictatorship of the proletariat, nationalization of the means of
production, etc.) of its revolutionary program.
The contradictory nature of Marxian theory can also be discerned in
Marxistsâ attempts to explain consciousness within in any given
social/historical situation (leaving aside the fact that Marx and Engels
never even try to explain the precise mechanisms by which economic
processes create ideas or thought in general). As weâve seen, according
to Marxist theory, âsocial existence determines consciousness.â This
might suggest, for example, that under capitalism, all members of
capitalist society, including the working class, would have bourgeois or
capitalist consciousness, since their social existence is bourgeois.
Yet, Marxism simultaneously insists that the working class, at least
after a certain point in capitalist development, will be revolutionary,
that is, that its consciousness will be militantly anti-capitalist and
socialist. Presumably, the new, revolutionary consciousness reflects
new, material characteristics of capitalism, but Marx never quite says
what these are. Marxists often contend that the working class becomes
revolutionary when the contradictions of capitalism become greatly
intensified, but intensity is a quantitative determination. Just how
intense do they have to become? Marxâs exposition of his theory in the
preface to A Contribution to a Critique of Political Economy implies
that the contradictions of capitalism will reach a qualitative point
when the relations of production turn from beings forms of development
of the forces of production into their fetters, but when precisely did
this occur, or hasnât it yet occurred? Here, too, Marx is not specific.
At times, it seems as if Marx and Engels believed that this qualitative
stage in capitalist development would manifest itself as a virtually
permanent state of economic crisis, but Marxâs analysis of capitalism
doesnât actually demonstrate the necessity or inevitability of this.
The result, it seems to me, is that for any given social class in any
given society at any given state of development, different,even
opposite, forms of consciousness can be explained consistently by
Marxist theory. When and where the working class is revolutionary, this
just reflects the working classâs central position in capitalist society
and the intensified contradictions of the system at that stage in its
development. When and where the working class is not revolutionary, this
might reflect the âhegemonyâ of the capitalist class (in the language of
the Italian Marxist, Antonio Gramsci), or the influence of the labor
aristocracy or opportunist âmisleadersâ of labor over the rest of the
workers (as Lenin might say), or the effects of racism, sexism or
national chauvinism, the role of religion or,more generally, the
cultural history of the country in question. All these interpretations
of the workersâ consciousness are consistent with the Marxian conception
of history, specifically the claim that social existence determines
social consciousness. But taken together, they add up to the fact that
social existence does not actually determine social consciousness after
all.
This problem with Marxist theory is apparent even in Marx and Engelsâ
broader theoretical considerations. For example,they considered Great
Britain to be the model for capitalist economic development, while
France to them was the epitome of political developments. But how can
this be if social existence determines consciousness? The logic of the
theory is that the country that is the model for capitalist economic
development ought to be the model for its political development. If one
refers to the concrete historical circumstances and cultural traditions,
etc., that have made Great Britain a different country from France, as
Marx and Engels do, one is tacitly admitting that the basic claim of the
theory, that social existence determines consciousness, canât be
sustained.
In sum, Marxist theory is so broad, so vague and so ambiguous that it is
capable of generating entirely opposite interpretations of any given
social phenomenon. All that is required is that the terminology be used
correctly, that a variety of factors be considered and that the economic
and social structure of society and the class struggle be accorded a
central role in the analysis, in terms of which the other factors are
explained.However useful a heuristic device the Marxist theory of
history may be, scientific it is not.
Letâs summarize some of the points Iâve made about the Marxian theory of
history and draw some other conclusions about the theory as a whole.
First, the Marxist theory of history, despite superficial appearances,
is extremely imprecise, the opposite of a scientific theory.
Second, despite its claims to represent a unified outlook, it straddles
two different standpoints that are philosophically distinct, even
opposedâan interpretive, contingent one; and a predictive, deterministic
oneâbetween which Marxists shift when applying or defending their
outlook.
Third,the theory is an abstract construct that does not standup to
factual scrutiny. Definitions and categories are stretched and fudged
depending upon what is analyzed, while those facts that cannot be
crammed into the theory are ignored. Plausible claims (that economic
factors affects consciousness and are influential in historical
processes) are stretched and âabsolutizedâ into contentions (that social
existence uniquely determines consciousness) that are not, and cannot
be, substantiated.As I have argued in other articles, the theory is in
fact idealist, without identifying itself as such or even being aware of
it. Despite its claims to be materialist, it really argues that the
fundamental, meaningful and determining facets of history are its own
definitions and categories, along with theâlaws of motionâ that these
definitions and categories, when set in motion according to the precepts
of the theory, create.Even the factors it believes to be material are
abstractions, that is, idealist categories: labor, the forces and
relations of production, etc.
Fourth, as I have suggested, the definitions, categories and various
tenets of the theory make most sense, and most accurately fit the facts,
when applied to the capitalist society of Marx and Engelsâ day: the
definition of class, the centrality of the class struggle, the
distinction between the economic and the political/ideological realms,
the apparent determining role of the economic, the growth of the forces
of production (technology on the one hand and the working class on the
other) as underlying propulsive dynamic of society. What this suggests
(and this tends to be confirmed when looking at some of Marxâs early
writings, particularly the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of
1844, is that the theory was developed by analyzing what Marxists call
the transition from feudalism to capitalism and then generalizing
forward (to the predicted transition from capitalism to socialism), and
back-ward (to the entire history of humanity). In the Manuscripts,Marx
explains that the internal logic of the concept of private property
leads, when elaborated, to the development of all the categories of
political economy, that is, the structure and internal dynamics of
capitalism. If we change the concept ofâprivate propertyâ to the concept
of âlaborâ and project the theory backward (into the past) and forward
(into the future), we get the Marxist theory in a nutshell. Marxâs
conception then, interpreted in terms of itself but in contradiction to
its other claims, represents the standpoint of competitive capitalism,
the system in which it was developed. The theory is,by this judgment,
bourgeois rather than proletarian.
Fifth, the Marxist conception of history is Eurocentric. History is
described as if it were simply the âhistory of Western Civilization,â a
teleological conception in which the direction, goal and purpose of
history is the emergence and flowering of Western Europeanâand its
offshoot, North Americanâsociety. Everything that can be is explained in
terms of this development, while everything that cannot is discarded as
not meaningful (non-historic) or ignored altogether. Most of us have
heard all this before, in our high school and college history classes.
Although Marx and Engels claimed to have transcended the historical
outlook of the Western Europe and North American bourgeoisie, their
theory is merely another version of the same thing, only with the claim
that the bourgeoisie and its economic system, capital-ism, will
themselves be transcended. For Marxism, the proletariat and socialism
are really the fruition, the true culmination,of Western Civilization.
Beyond reflecting this general, almost classical, West European
standpoint, Marx and Engelsâ historical conception,like much else in the
Marxian worldview, is directly indebted to that of Hegel. (See The
Philosophy of History, Dover Publications, New York, 1956) Hegel saw
history as representing the development of human consciousness toward
freedom, a spiritual state in which human beings recognize themselves
and each other as being embodiments of the mind/spirit of God, the
Absolute. This evolution goes through distinct stages, which are
represented by distinct forms of society. Each type of society embodies
a characteristic ethos, or ethnic/cultural worldview or âspirit,â which
in turn contains internal contradictions that impel it to evolve and,
except for the last stage,to transcend itself. Meanwhile, the actual
agents of history are so-called âworld historicâ individuals, such as
Alexander the Great, Napoleon, etc., who embody the specific cultural
ethos of their societies. In Hegelâs schema, there are three stages in
this evolution, each stage representing a different conception of
freedom. In the first of these, embodied in the societies of what Hegel
called the Eastâthe societies of the Tigris-Euphrates Valley, Persia and
Egyptâonly one man is free: the king, presumed to be or to represent
God. In the second,embodied by the Athenian and Roman republics, some
men are free. In the third and final stage, represented by the Prussian
monarchy of Hegelâs day, or at least as he thought or hoped it would
evolve, all men are free. For Hegel, this society was a dialectical
combination of unity and plurality. It was a kind of corporate state
structure, with an internal differentiation of classes and sectors,
dialectically pursuing both their self-interest and that of the nation
as a whole, that reflected the unity-in-difference/difference-in-unity
that characterizes Hegelâs idea of freedom and the Absolute (God)
itself. (Hegelâs Philosophy of Right, Oxford University Press, London,
Oxford,New York, 1967.) In Hegelâs conception, not only do we see an
upward progression, essentially, from slavery to freedom,through a
dialectical process, we also see that the political (or material) form
of each society reflects the particular notion of freedom on which it is
based. Not least, we can also discern the implication that only the
history of some societies, those encompassed in this schema, is
philosophically significant.The others fall outside the scope of ârealâ
history.
Here we can clearly see how much Marx and Engelsâ conception owes to
Hegelâs. History goes through distinct stages,these stages occur in an
order of ascending progress, this evolution occurs through a dialectical
process, and the outcome of this evolution is human freedom. Moreover,
as in Hegelâs conception, this evolution traverses a series of distinct
levels of freedom, in which the material (for Hegel, political; for
Marx, economic) and the spiritual forms correspond. But unlike the
avowedly idealist construct of Hegel, in which each stage embodies an
ever broader idea of freedom and corresponding political structure, for
Marx and Engels, each type of society (mode of production) is based upon
a distinct form of labor, which (aside from primitive communism),
rep-resents a stage in laborâs progressive emancipation. Thus, we first
have slave-labor, in which human beings are fully bound to the means of
production and are seen as being part of the means of production; then
serf labor, in which the laborers are partially tied to the means of
production, the land, and are therefore partly free; then capitalist
labor relations, under which the workers are juridically free and
totally divorced from the means of production, but still subordinated to
them,then; finally, the socialist mode of production, under which the
laborers are fully and truly free; as a freely
associating,self-consciously cooperating group, they dominate and
control the means of production themselves. Not least, the Marxist
conception of history embodies the same Eurocentric outlook as Hegelâs.
The history that matters, the only history that is truly significant, is
the history that is encompassed in the Marxian schema:primitive
communism, slavery, feudal-ism,capitalism, socialism. Everything that
falls outside its scope is dismissed as meaningless and ultimately
irrelevant.
This latter thesis was given concrete form in a series of articles by
Engels, written during the revolutions of 1848. In these pieces,whose
purpose was to explain why the south Slavic peoples, the peoples of the
Balkans, i.e., Slovenes,Serbs, Croats, Montenegrins, Albanians etc.,
played what he considered to be a reactionary role in the events of
1848â49,and to argue against their demands for national rights and
independence, Engels referred to these ethnic groups as ânon-historic.â
(For a fuller discussion of this, see Roman Rosdolsky, Engels and the
âNon-historicâ Peoples: The National Question in the Revolution of 1848,
Critique Books, Glasgow,1986.) In other words, they were outside the
main (and meaningful) course of human history, and their history (and
political demands), didnât matter. Elsewhere, Marx, for similar reasons,
referred to these people as âethnic trash.â
As I see it (and as Iâve discussed in previous articles),Marxism is a
type or variant of Hegelianism. To both Hegel and Marx, history, at
bottom, is a logical process that leads, via a series of contradictions,
through various stages to human freedom. Where Hegel saw this as
occurring through the dialectical development of human consciousness
toward its recognition that all human beings, indeed, all reality, are
manifestations of the mind or spirit of God, Marx sees it as occurring
through the dialectical evolution of human labor and its dialectical
interaction with human consciousness (as in the contradictions between
base and superstructure),toward a fully cooperative society, in which
humanity comes to control both the products of its labor and its own
destiny,and in which all human beings recognize and treat each other as
brothers/sisters. In both theories, history is progressive: it has a
meaning, a direction and a goal; it occurs dialectically and through
defined stages. Moreover, the goal/out-come of history is present,
although implicitly, at the beginning,as the underlying logic of a
fundamental principle or category: for Hegel, human consciousness; for
Marx, labor.In both theories, humanity has an essence, a kind of
philosophical substance,whose trajectory underlies and defines history.
For Hegel, this essence is consciousness or spirit(itself a piece or
manifestation of the mind or spirit of God),which creates the material
conditions of our lives and history. For Marx, the essence of humanity
is labor, which gives rise to consciousness. But the apparent opposition
between Marx and Hegel on this point is more apparent than real,because
the Marxian essence, labor, is just as much a category of thought, an
abstraction, as consciousness. It just seems to be, or can be claimed to
be, material. For Marx, labor is a logical category, almost a metaphor,
that has a life of its own.This is Idealism. It may not be a
self-conscious form of idealism, and its central category may seem, in
contrast to explicit forms of idealism, relatively poverty stricken,
that is, lacking internal differentiation (despite Marxâs efforts), but
it is idealism none the less.
As I discussed earlier, Marxismâs claims that its theory of history is
materialist were meant to give the theory scientific credentials, to
eliminate socialismâs utopian character, to make it more than an
abstract moral appeal for social justice. Hegel also considered his
philosophy to be scientific, but he meant it more in the sense of true,
logically consistent and complete,rather than in the sense of conforming
to the natural sciences,which he saw as mechanical, one-sided, and
lacking in self-awareness. But Marx and Engels were anxious to develop a
theory that was scientific in the sense of being analogous to the
natural sciences, a quest that was stimulated by Darwinâs theory of
evolution. Since they considered the natural sciences to be materialist,
they attempted to develop a materialist theory of socialism, which in
turn required materialist theories of history and capitalism, etc. Hence
their attempt to meld together, as they often admitted, French
socialism, British political economy, and Hegelian philosophy, under the
philosophical banner of materialism. Despite their efforts, their
conception remained merely a restatement, in materialist terms, of
Hegelian philosophy.
Of course, where Marxism is different from Hegelianism,where its claim
to be materialist expresses itself most palpably,is in its insistence
that social reality be radically transformed,that a totally just and
liberated societyâthe true kingdom of Heaven on Earthâactually be
established on Earth. For Hegel, freedom is only partially realizable in
social/material terms; to him, true freedom is a spiritual state. For
Marx, freedom was to be fully achievable in material reality. This, I
believe, is to Marxismâs credit. But while Marxism gains some-thing in
its attempt to restate Hegelian philosophy in materialist terms, it also
loses something.
To see this, it is necessary to recognize that Hegelian philosophy is,
at its core, a philosophical restatement of Christianity. Hegel saw his
philosophy as the truth of the Christian out-look, an
exposition/explanation of Christianity in its true, philosophical,form.
To him, Christianity, as a theology and an organized religion, is merely
a metaphorical or picturesque representation, designed to appeal to
ordinary people, of a deeper philosophical truth, of which his
philosophy is the true rendition. The Holy Trinity, to Hegel, is a
metaphor for the fundamental triadic structure of the cosmos, conceived
meta-physically: subject, object and the unity of the two that
simultaneously preserves the distinction between them; Creator, created
and their dialectical unity-in-difference/difference-in-unity. The
Absolute, which, as self-consciousness, requires another
consciousness,creates the Other, which then comes to recognize itself as
one with the Absolute. Father, Son, Holy Spirit. In this light, human
history represents the Cosmic Spirit or Mind reemerging through the
development of human consciousness to recognize spirit/mind in the
universe and itself as a part of that spirit/mind. The telos or goal of
history is thus this developing self-recognition of spirit or the cosmic
consciousness. This is why Hegelâs philosophy, both its method and its
content, takes a triadic form, and it is why, in his Lectures on the
Philosophy of Religion, Hegel places Christianity at the apex of
religious development, as âConsummate Religion.â
Yet, something is lost in Hegelâs version of Christianity. This is much
of its emotional content: God/Jesus as love. Hegel, as a philosopher
(and as a certain type of individual), celebrated thinking, and
especially philosophical speculation, as the highest form of existence.
As a result, his philosophy has a highly cerebral character. Although
Hegel talks about love, it is quite clear that he considers love, as an
emotion and hence pre-reflective, to be inferior to consciousness. This
is why, for Hegel, philosophy, which is an act and a reflection of
consciousness, is for an elite, while religion, picturesque and
emotional as it is, is for ordinary people, the masses. Despite this
denigration of love (and the emotions in general), love remains as an
element, albeit very subdued, almost repressed,in Hegelâs philosophy.
But in Marxism, this love or spiritual content is virtually
eliminated,banished, and exchanged for the soullessness of a would-be
materialism. The underlying philosophy remains idealist, since, at
bottom, labor functions as a category or concept whose development in a
(dialectically) logical manner underlies and determines human history.
Yet, the idealism is denied and the spiritual contentâclearly present,
although in attenuated form, in its Hegelian progenitorâis repressed
even further. This is not to deny that Marxism has emotional content,
that it is inspired by concern for, or even love of, humanity.But in
Marxism, this emotional content coexists very uneasily with its
insistence on its scientific character. As would-be materialists,
Marxists are vehement in their denial that fundamental reality is
spiritual or has a soul. To them,âsoulâ or âspiritâ (words with which,
as atheists, they are very uncomfortable) are primitive and picturesque
substitutions for âconsciousness,â which itself is secondary phenomenon,
a reflection of the real stuff of the universe, matter. Marxism thus is
a kind of soulless idealism. Despite its materialist pretensions, its
fundamental reality is made of up abstract categoriesâlabor, social
classes, modes of production, laws of motion, etc. But these categories
are without spirit, blind and pitiless. This combination of idealism and
soullessness is one of the reasons, I think, why Marxism tends to think
about and be concerned with humanity in the abstract, as Humanity,rather
than with human beings in the concrete, why social classes are seen as
more fundamental than specific human beings, and why individuals have
been treated as so expend-able (literally) by Marxist practitioners,
especially when they do not belong to the right class or have the
appropriate consciousness (that is, the âcorrectâ politics). It is this
unconscious idealism that makes Marxism and Marxists so uncomfortable
with the concreteness, the âgrittinessâ of history. Like Hegelianism,
Marxism seeks to unify the concrete phenomena of history (the uniqueness
of specific events, the quirkiness of individual personalities), with
the noumena of its supposedly underlying laws, logic and hence meaning.
But despite Hegel and Marx and their respective dialectics, this canât
be done. The result, for both Marxism and Hegel, is to subordinate the
concrete, the unique, the individual, to the lawfulness and the logic.
The laws and logic of history become more important than the events; the
categories of theory become more important than the phenomena they are
meant to explain. Marxism and Hegelianism are thus both reductionist;
they seek to reduce the concreteness of reality to the smooth, logical
and ultimately comfortable laws of history.
As this discussion suggests, Hegelianism and Marxism are expressions, in
somewhat different forms, of the Judeo-Christian view of history and
outlook on the world. In this worldview, in contrast to others, such as
many of those from the East, history has a beginning, an end or goal
toward which it is heading, and therefore a meaning. If anything,
Hegelianism, with its spiritual, other-worldly con-tent, its insistence
on the supremacy of thought and its belief that true
reconciliation/unity with God occurs in spirit, is the more Christian
variant (at least as Christianity has comedown to us, rather than in
what may have been its original,and probably more revolutionary,
version). For its part,Marxism, with its materialist claims and
this-worldly character, its stress on the supremacy of matter and its
insistence that the transformation required by the goal of history
actually occur in reality, not just in thought, is the more Judaic.
More specifically, Marxism, as others have suggested, is are statement,
in modern, secular terms, of the Messianic vision of Judaism, with the
proletariat as the Messiah, the fully human (although anointed by God),
savior of the Jews and all humanity, and with Marx and, by extension,
the Marxists, as the prophets of the coming apocalypse. Marxismâs
emergence reflects the secularization of the modern world, brought about
by, among other things, the Scientific and Industrial Revolutions and
the development of modern capitalist society, which called into question
the tenets of the historic religions of the West. Despite this
secularization, which affected intellectuals more than others, the basic
Judeo-Christian out-look remained, and stills remains, as a kind of
âdeepâ structure, a sort of primordial collective consciousness, of
modern culture and psychology. The effects of two thousand years of
history do not disappear overnight. Thus, most people find it hard to
exist in a world that has no meaning. They need to believe that humanity
and our history are significant, that we and our story are not just
minuscule accidents in a vast cosmos that is indifferent to us. This
includes intellectuals, many of whom find the dogmas and mythologies of
traditional religion quaint, somewhat embarrassing and in conflict with
science. So, filling the need for certainty in an increasingly secular
world were radical ideologies that preserved the broad, underlying
assumptions of the Judeo-Christian outlook, while recasting them in
modern,purportedly scientific terms. Marxism is one of these.
One of the things that remained of the old religions, but without the
humility that is at least taught as required of created beings, is the
sense of certainty that so often accompanies dogmatic beliefs: we are
right and everybody else is wrong. This sense of certainty is very
apparent in (indeed, is an almost defining characteristic of), the
Marxist movement. Marx and Engels engaged in the most strident polemics
with all those who dared take issue with them, and this practice has
continued throughout the history of Marxism. Opponents are denounced in
the most vicious terms. To Lenin, let alone Stalin, political opponents,
even (or especially) within the Marxist movement, represented the âclass
enemy,â non-proletarian, pro-capitalist elements infecting the working
class and subverting its movement, and therefore worthy of destruction.
And where Marxists have held state power, theyâve used the coercive
instruments of the state to their utmost to effect this; virtually all
opponents are jailed,sent to labor camps or âliquidated.â Although Marx
insisted that his personal motto was âDoubt everything,â this doubt does
not actually exist within, that is, truly internal to, the Marxian
worldview; it remains private, as a drive to continually prove the
validity of Marxism, where it exists at all.Marxism has an almost
Kabbalistic character, in the sense of being a kind of esoteric
knowledge that unlocks the secrets of the cosmos, which only a few, the
true elect, are able to understand. Most Marxists secretly enjoy this
sense of superiority, even when they themselves have not read, let alone
mastered, the crucial texts. I suspect that not many members of the
Communist Parties of the 1930s and 40s actually read Capital, let alone
understood it. But even those who didnât knew that it was true.
This belief that they hold the key to the mysteries of the uni-verse,
the answer to all the philosophical questions that have bothered humans
from the beginning of our existence, gives Marxists a tremendous
arrogance and often results in unbridled fanaticism. It was such
fanaticism that characterized the ethos of the Bolshevik Party and led,
via the establishment of a massive, all-powerful state, to the
unspeakable atrocities of Stalinism, which so many well-intentioned
Marxists supported, excused and justified, and to the decades of
repression and violence that have always been the products of Communist
regimes, down to Castroâs Cuba today.
This sense of certainty often leads Marxists to adopt a Messianic
self-conception, especially when it becomes clear that the proletariat
does not respond as Marxist theory predicts. When the workers are not
revolutionary, or when they do not specifically embrace Marxist
policies, Marxists denounce them as being infected with petty bourgeois
ideas,or even, as Lenin did when faced with the revolt of the sailors of
Kronstadt and the general strike of the workers of Petrograd in early
1921, as not really being proletarians at all. From being prophets of
the coming proletarian Messiah, Marxists take on the Messianic role
themselves. As carriers of the Kabbalistic mysteries, they become the
saviors of humanity. This substitutionalism, in which Marxists think and
act int he supposed interests and name of the proletariat, emerges,as
almost a logical implication of Marxist theory itself, under
circumstances in which key Marxist prognistications (that the
proletariat will be revolutionary), are not borne out.
In contrast to what Marxists believe, Marxism does not represent the
true consciousness of the working class. Most workers, like most people
in society, are not ideologists; they do not think in consistently
ideological terms. Ideologies are primarily diseases of intellectuals.
Marxism as a worldview is an outlook of sections of the radical (mostly
middle-class) intelligentsia, alienated from contemporary society, angry
at its injustices, and frustrated by their own powerlessness. Without
property and without power to influence the world, they identify
themselves with the proletariat, (or at least Marxismâs image of it),
which is also without property and power.Longing to escape this
condition, they embrace a theory that ascribes the future and the power
to create it to the proletariat and, by extension, to themselves as
representatives of the proletariat and as embodiments of its âtrueâ
consciousness. Marxism is therefore not the worldview, the supposed true
consciousness, of the working class. It is the worldview of
intellectuals who wish to reorganize society along what they consider to
be more rational, and more just, lines; who hope,in fact, that they or
people like them, might rule society in the name of reason and social
justice, and who see in the proletariat or some other large social class
the vehicle through which they might achieve this goal.
This character of Marxism explains why so many Marxists are not truly
committed to democracy. To Marxists, democracy has more of an
instrumental than a substantive value. Despite their protestations, they
generally value democracy only insofar as it facilitates their activity,
their ability to fight for their program. When they or other Marxists
with whom they agree seize control of the state, democracy no longer
matters; once they, who have the âcorrectâ politics and are the âgoodâ
people, are in power, democracy can only be a vehicle for
counterrevolution. Yet, here, too, Marxists delude themselves. They
believe that they are the true democrats and define their own rule as
inherently, intrinsically democratic. âWhen you have the substance of
democracyâ (meaning their own rule), their argument usually goes, âthe
forms are unnecessary.â It is for this reason that the brutal,
dictatorial nature of self-pro-claimed socialist regimes has never
prevented Marxists from supporting them. Beneath the rhetoric, Marxists
really donât believe the majority of people, at least as presently
constituted, are able to run their own lives and govern society. (If
they were, they would all be Marxists and wouldnât be duped by
capitalist propaganda.) Instead, they need a political and moral elite,
in possession of the true nature of society, history and the universe,
to make those decisions for them, at least until after a long
transitional period during which they are taught (by that elite) how to
do so.
The elitist nature of Marxism is occasionally clearly expressed in the
writings of Marxists themselves. In his book, The Crisis in Historical
Materialism (University of Minnesota Press,Minneapolis, 1981, 1990), a
rather desperate attempt to save Marxism by jettisoning a great deal of
it, Stanley Aronowitz is much concerned with what he calls the question
of âagency,âin other words, who (what social class or group), is to
carryout the socialist transformation of society. Specifically,
Aronowitz believes that Marx was wrong to âprivilegeâ the working class
as the agent of the socialist revolution. To me, Aronowitzâs very
language (his use of the term âagencyâ)inadvertently reveals what
Marxism really is. It is the outlook of certain radical intellectuals,
painfully aware of their own powerlessness, looking for some social
grouping that possess-es the requisite muscle (an âagencyâ) to implement
their worldview.
Of course, this characteristic of Marxism is fundamental to all forms of
utopian thought, including anarchism. They all rep-resent the
consciousnessâthe projected hopes, visions and dreamsâof socially
powerless intellectuals. This is why all utopian ideas contain the
potential for totalitarianism, the drive to impose a social schema on
recalcitrant individuals. But Marxism is particularly dangerous form of
utopianism,for several reasons. One is its self-deluded character: it
denies that it is utopian at all. Marxism, Marxists insist, is
scientific,and therefore true. The socialist revolution has been
scientifically predicted and ordained. Marxism and Marxists represent
History. Like the religious utopians that preceded them in history,
although without realizing it, Marxists believe that they are doing
Godâs will. Ironically, they who think they have access to the truth, as
opposed to those who suffer fromâfalseâ consciousness, are the most
deluded. To put it in Marxist terms,they become the victims of the
fetishism of theory.
Another reason why Marxism is so dangerous is its commitment to the use
of the state (indeed, a state whose power has been exponentially
expanded by its nationalization of the means of production and its
monopolization of the means of the exchange of ideas), and its virtually
unlimited capacity for violence and coercion, to realize its vision.
Yet, here, too,Marxists are taken in by their own theory: they believe
that the state they aim to use to transform society, the so-called
dictatorship of the proletariat, is not really a state (it is no longer
a state âin the proper sense of the termâ ) and is destined, moreover,
to wither away. But the dictatorship of the proletariat is a myth and a
contradiction in terms. Where society is truly, radically democratic,
where the vast majority of people actually do govern themselves, there
will be no state.And where there is a state, whatever it may be called,
society is not governed by its members. Communist regimes are not,and
never have been, proletarian dictatorships. They are, and have always
been, dictatorships of tiny elites claiming to rule in the name of the
proletariat. And Marxistsâ belief that their rule represents that of the
proletariat, and therefore the interests of all humanity, and the
specific nature of the regimes that Marxism mandates that they
establishâcharacterized by the nationalization of property and the
repression of all opponents as inherently bourgeois and
counterrevolutionaryâvirtually guarantees that such dictatorships will
be totalitarian and brutal.
Yet a third reason for Marxismâs perilous character is its radical
opposition to all forms of traditional morality. Although Marxism is
extremely moralistic, its worldview studded with good and evil
(individuals, classes, social systems and ideologies), and is itself
rooted in the Judeo-Christian worldview, its insistence on its
scientific character forces it to deny or repress this aspect of its
outlook and to denounce traditional morality as an illusion and as a
tool of ruling classes (like religion as a whole). To Marxists, true
morality is the historic process itself,as they understand it. The moral
thing to do is to further that process. If that means the liquidation of
entire social classes, as the historic process ordains, then the moral
thing to do is to encourage that outcome, however difficult that might
be to oneâs conscience (a hangover from oneâs upbringing
under-capitalism). Engels himself said it (quoting Hegel): âFreedom is
the recognition of necessity.â As a result, the demands of traditional
morality go out the window, or, to put it more technically,are subsumed
under the exigencies of the laws of history.As many have charged,
Marxism does insist that the end justifies the means.But for many who
make this accusation, this is hypocritical. In fact, most people in the
political world, and particularly those at the head of governments or
with other access to powers of coercion, believe that the end does
justify the means and act accordingly. But they are usually constrained
by their own public commitment to traditional morality, by their own
limited power, and by the relatively limited nature of their goals. What
makes Marxism different is that:(1) it militantly repudiates traditional
morality; (2) it advocates the establishment of a state whose power is
virtually unlimited; and (3) for it,the stakes are always set at the
highest level. The goal of Marxism is to save humanity. Where this is
the issue, what weight can a few lies, the repression of dissent and the
jailing of some recalcitrant (undoubtedly petty-bourgeois) individuals,
or even the killing of a few million people really have. These things
become, as some Marxists have described them, mere âbureaucratic
excessesâ or âdistortions,â unfortunate âbirth pangsâ in the emergence
of the future communist society.
The totalitarian potential of utopianism does not mean we should eschew
all utopian thought. In fact, utopias are necessary, as visions and
goals toward which we would like society to develop, and as guides for
our day-to-day activity and behavior. Without utopias, we would have
nothing but tepid liberalism, which accepts the brutal realities of
capitalism,wishing only to ameliorate its most egregious aspects (and
even liberalism is guided by a utopian vision, however attenuated it may
be), or, even worse, conservatism, which objects to much of the
achievements in material progress and the growth of civil liberties that
have been made. But we must be aware of the dangers of utopian thinking,
particularly the tendency to wish to impose utopian schemes on
individuals who do not accept them. As an essential part of this, we
vehemently reject the use of the state and other vehicles of mass
coercion as instruments to promote our desired goals. We should aim to
lead primarily by example, not by coercion or deception.