đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș pierre-ansart-dialectics-and-its-object.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:10:57. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Dialectics and Its Object Author: Pierre Ansart Language: en Topics: Sociology, Dialectics, Proudhon Source: Translated by Shaun Murdock. Originally Published in: Ansart, Pierre. 1984. Proudhon. Le Livre de Poche.
Chapter 2. Dialectics and its object
Proudhon, politically opposed to conservatives, liberals, republicans,
and communists, also wanted to analyse his opponentsâ theoretical
positions (theology, statism, utopia) and put forward a way of thinking
that explains and proves his conclusions. Hence, for him, the critical
importance of an intellectual method to avoid the pitfalls of dogmatism.
His conclusions are understood only by reference to his framework of
thought: dialectics.
Dialectics
In this long investigation, whose steps can be followed from 1840 to
1848, he was aided by an impressive appetite for reading.
At the same time, he read the Bible, Fourier, Saint-Simon and the
Saint-Simonians, Sismondi, Adam Smith, Ricardo, the French economists,
and also translations or fragments of Kant, Leibniz, Fichte, Feuerbach,
Strauss, Hegel, and many others. But he never devoured these diverse
texts to
obey one school, but always to define his own method, one that, in his
view, could not be
established by theologians, bourgeois intellectuals, or socialist
utopians. Karl GrĂŒn, who dreamed of
converting him to the school of Feuerbach, linked this independent
spirit to his friendâs Franc-
Comtois origins:
âThe French say that Germans are straightforward people. Plain,
stubborn, rigid: this is also
true of the Franc-Comtois Proudhon. I will please the German
nationalists by speaking to them of
this native of the highlands... and I will draw their attention to the
pattern that Fourier, Considérant,
Muiron, Proudhon, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, all derive their origin from
the foothills of the Jura. They
are all stubborn, straightforward people.â
164/K. GRUN, Die soziale Bewegung... [The Social Movement...], C.W.
Leske, p. 40.
When he wrote his âFirst Memoirâ on property in 1839â1840, Proudhon
already had a
precise intellectual method.
His theory of social conflict was also imposed on him during his
experience as a printing
worker, and then as an independent printer, where he would face all the
difficulties of the worker
and the artisan vis-Ă -vis the owners of capital. It was in this
experience of work, bankruptcy, and
paying interest and debt, that Proudhon theorised the relationship
between capital and labour. In
this experience, the Saint-Simoniansâ assertions on the exploitation of
man by man in work and the
analyses of EugĂšne Buret on the MisĂšre des classes laborieuses...
[Poverty of the Working Classes...]
pointed the way for Proudhon to pursue the analysis of socio-economic
conflict.
Reading Kant was an important moment in this development. Besides the
theory of morality,
to which he would often return, the critical and rationalist conception
of problems confirmed his
intuitions. He would also continue to update the Kantian lesson, not
asking the classic question:
What is God? What is Property or the State? but instead asking: Where
does the idea of God come
from? How is property created? Why do we believe in the myth of the
State?
âFor him, Kant is essentially a âmoralistâ, the greatest of the
moralists, which is why he
crowns him with so many garlands. From the First Memoir, Kant appears in
Proudhonâs works as the
one who wanted to solve the âproblem of certaintyâ, and thus the
ultimate philosophical problem.
However, in 1840, he found âthe metaphysics of Reid and Kant to be still
farther removed from the
truth than that of Aristotleâ. But that did not stop him three years
later, in Creation, from presenting
himself as the successor of Kant, who came close to the âseriesâ without
reaching it: âthe illustrious
author of the Analyticâ stopped too soon on his road, though he had had
the intuition of unity in
diversity and thus anticipated the âserial lawâ through which the
âanxieties of scepticismâ could finally
be overcome. It was Kant who revealed the âlaw of antinomyâ and the âlaw
of balanceâ: he counts
âamong the profoundest philosophers of modern timesâ. [...]
It was also Kant who, rather than asking himself the classic question
What is God? had the
brilliant idea of asking himself: Why does it happen that I believe in
God? He thus ushered in a
revolution comparable to that of Descartes, and deserved âthe greatest
gloryâ possible. He is truly
âthe one whom no philosopher has ever equalled, the immortal Kantâ.
However, Kant could not free himself of the Absolute. After having
eliminated it in his
Critique of Pure Reason, he returned to it in his Practical Reason.
Nevertheless, what he sought,
wanted, called for in the best of his thought, is a âpurely humanâ, not
transcendental, absolute â in
short, the absolute that Proudhon calls Justice, and which is seated in
the human conscience. Finally,
like all the great philosophers, Kant was âessentially a moralistâ, and
while the immortal author of
Critique of Pure Reason did not understand the high morality, necessity,
divinity of war, which he
considered detestable, it did not escape him that âin the final
analysis, the only certainty about
human intelligence is that it derives from the conscienceâ.â
165/P. HAUBTMANN, Proudhon, Marx et la pensée allemande [Proudhon, Marx
and German
Thought], Presses Universitaires de Grenoble, pp. 23â24.
Reading Kant also forced him to answer the problem of mental categories,
the question of
whether dialectics is the essence of the human mind, of reason, or
whether it is an objective
dimension of reality. Proudhon rejects such a dichotomy between
rationalism and empiricism, and
likewise between spiritualism and materialism. It seems essential him to
recognise both the
objectivity of what he called âreal seriesâ, i.e. objective, ordered
divisions and distinctions, and, on
the other hand, âideal seriesâ, i.e. the systems of relations which the
mind learns from the real, but
which are not just reflections of reality. By ideal series, the mind
invents and reconstructs reality,
and can combine relations that do not exist in reality.
âThe series is natural when it is proper and specific to the object,
when it arises from its
nature and properties.
The series is artificial when it is transferred from the object which is
proper to it another
which is foreign to it. Most products of art and industry are artificial
series. [...]
In nature, each series develops according to its proper object, without
being combined or
mixed up; then comes man who, having sovereignty over the earth [...],
begins, by transposing the
natural series, a second creation within creation itself.â
166/CrĂ©ation de lâordre... [Creation of Order...], pp. 176â177.
Proudhon explains that this acquisition of âideal seriesâ, categories of
understanding and
logical structures, comes from action and in particular from labour. It
is through action that man
experiences the relations between things, corrects his ideas and invents
new relations. Philosophy
itself has been devised based on labour:
Philosophy is only a way of generalising and abstracting the results of
our experience, that is,
our work.â
167/Ibid., p. 119.
Thus, using Kantian philosophy in a very free and personal way, Proudhon
read Feuerbach
and Hegel with the same critical distance.
From Feuerbach, he takes the idea of alienation, essential to his
analysis, but by transposing
it to other objects, in particular to the critique of the State. While
for Feuerbach the alienation to be
analysed is that whereby man ascribes to God what properly belongs to
him, for Proudhon it is
specifically in the formation of Capital that this dispossession and
alienation is reproduced. But he