💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-post-scarcity-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:33:03. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Post-Scarcity Anarchism
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: December 1968
Language: en
Topics: post-scarcity, anarchism, ecology, dialectics
Source: First chapter of the book by the same name. https://libcom.org/files/Post-Scarcity%20Anarchism%20-%20Murray%20Bookchin.pdf
Notes: This is the essay/pamphlet entitled *Post-Scarcity Anarchism*, https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/murray-bookchin-post-scarcity-anarchism-1.

Murray Bookchin

Post-Scarcity Anarchism

Preconditions and Possibilities

All the successful revolutions of the past have been particularistic

revolutions of minority classes seeking to assert their specific

interests over those of society as a whole. The great bourgeois

revolutions of modern times offered an ideology of sweeping political

reconstitution, but in reality they merely certified the social

dominance of the bourgeoisie, giving formal political expression to the

economic ascendancy of capital. The lofty notions of the "nation," the

"free citizen," of equality before the law," concealed the mundane

reality of the centralized state, the atomized isolated man, the

dominance of bourgeois interest. Despite their sweeping ideological

claims, the particularistic revolutions replaced the rule of one class

by another, one system of exploitation by another, one system of toil by

another, and one system of psychological repression by another.

What is unique about our era is that the particularistic revolution has

now been subsumed by the possibility of the generalized

revolution—complete and totalistic. Bourgeois society, if it achieved

nothing else, revolutionized the means of production on a scale

unprecedented in history. This technological revolution, culminating in

cybernation, has created the objective, quantitative basis for a world

without class rule, exploitation, toil or material want. The means now

exist for the development of the rounded man, the total man, freed of

guilt and the workings of authoritarian modes of training, and given

over to desire and the sensuous apprehension of the marvelous. It is now

possible to conceive of man's future experience in terms of a coherent

process in which the bifurcations of thought and activity, mind and

sensuousness, discipline and spontaneity, individuality and community,

man and nature, town and country, education and life, work and play are

all resolved, harmonized, and organically wedded in a qualitatively new

realm of freedom. Just as the particularized revolution produced a

particularized, bifurcated society, so the generalized revolution can

produce an organically unified, many-sided community. The great wound

opened by propertied society in the form of the "social question" can

now be healed.

That freedom must be conceived of in human terms, not in animal terms—in

terms of life, not of survival—is clear enough. Men do not remove their

ties of bondage and become fully human merely by divesting themselves of

social domination and obtaining freedom in its abstract form. They must

also be free concretely: free from material want, from toil, from the

burden of devoting the greater part of their time—indeed, the greater

part of their lives—to the struggle with necessity. To have seen these

material preconditions for human freedom, to have emphasized that

freedom presupposes free time and the material abundance for abolishing

free time as a social privilege, is the great contribution of Karl Marx

to modern revolutionary theory.

By the same token, the preconditions for freedom must not be mistaken

for the conditions of freedom. The possibility of liberation does not

constitute its reality. Along with its positive aspects, technological

advance has a distinctly negative, socially regressive side. If it is

true that technological progress enlarges the historical potentiality

for freedom, it is also true that the bourgeois control of technology

reinforces the established organization of society and everyday life.

Technology and the resources of abundance furnish capitalism with the

means for assimilating large sections of society to the established

system of hierarchy and authority. They provide the system with the

weaponry, the detecting devices and the propaganda media for the threat

as well as the reality of massive repression. By their centralistic

nature, the resources of abundance reinforce the monopolistic,

centralistic and bureaucratic tendencies in the political apparatus. In

short, they furnish the state with historically unprecedented means for

manipulating and mobilizing the entire environment of life—and for

perpetuating hierarchy, exploitation and unfreedom.

It must be emphasized, however, that this manipulation and mobilization

of the environment is extremely problematical and laden with crises. Far

from leading to pacification (one can hardly speak, here, of

harmonization), the attempt of bourgeois society to control and exploit

its environment, natural as well as social, has devastating

consequences. Volumes have been written on the pollution of the

atmosphere and waterways, on the destruction of tree cover and soil, and

on toxic materials in foods and liquids. Even more threatening in their

final results are the pollution and destruction of the very ecology

required for a complex organism like man. The concentration of

radioactive wastes in living things is a menace to the health and

genetic endowment of nearly all species. Worldwide contamination by

pesticides that inhibit oxygen production in plankton or by the

near-toxic level of lead from gasoline exhaust are examples of an

enduring pollution that threatens the biological integrity of all

advanced lifeforms—including man.

No less alarming is the fact that we must drastically revise our

traditional notions of what constitutes an environmental pollutant. A

few decades ago it would have been absurd to describe carbon dioxide and

heat as pollutants in the customary sense of the term. Yet both may well

rank among the most serious sources of future ecological imbalance and

may pose major threats to the viability of the planet. As a result of

industrial and domestic combustion activities, the quantity of carbon

dioxide in the atmosphere has increased by roughly twenty-five percent

in the past one hundred years, and may well double by the end of the

century. The famous "greenhouse effect" which the increasing quantity of

the gas is expected to produce has been widely discussed in the media;

eventually, it is supposed, the gas will inhibit the dissipation of the

world's heat into space, causing a rise in overall temperatures which

will melt the polar ice caps and result in the inundation of vast

coastal areas. Thermal pollution, the result mainly of warm water

discharged by nuclear and conventional power plants, has had disastrous

effects on the ecology of lakes, rivers and estuaries. Increases in

water temperature not only damage the physiological and reproductive

activities of the fish, they also promote the great blooms of algae that

have become such formidable problems in waterways.

Ecologically, bourgeois exploitation and manipulation are undermining

the very capacity of the earth to sustain advanced forms of life. The

crisis is being heightened by massive increases in air and water

pollution; by a mounting accumulation of nondegradable wastes, lead

residues, pesticide residues and toxic additives in food; by the

expansion of cities into vast urban belts; by increasing stresses due to

congestion, noise and mass living; and by the wanton scarring of the

earth as a result of mining operations, lumbering, and real estate

speculation. As a result, the earth has been despoiled in a few decades

on a scale that is unprecedented in the entire history of human

habitation of the planet. Socially, bourgeois exploitation and

manipulation have brought everyday life to the most excruciating point

of vacuity and boredom. As society has been converted into a factory and

a marketplace, the very rationale of life has been reduced to production

for its own sake—and consumption for its own sake.[1]

The Redemptive Dialectic

Is there a redemptive dialectic that can guide the social development in

the direction of an anarchic society where people will attain full

control over their daily lives? Or does the social dialectic come to an

end with capitalism, its possibilities sealed off by the use of a highly

advanced technology for repressive and co-optative purposes? We must

learn here from the limits of Marxism, a project which, understandably

in a period of material scarcity, anchored the social dialectic and the

contradictions of capitalism in the economic realm. Marx, it has been

emphasized, examined the preconditions for liberation, not the

conditions of liberation. The Marxian critique is rooted in the past, in

the era of material want and relatively limited technological

development. Even its humanistic theory of alienation turns primarily on

the issue of work and man's alienation from the product of his labor.

Today, however, capitalism is a parasite on the future, a vampire that

survives on the technology and resources of freedom.

The industrial capitalism of Marx's time organized its commodity

relations around a prevailing system of material scarcity; the state

capitalism of our time organizes its commodity relations around a

prevailing system of material abundance. A century ago, scarcity had to

be endured; today, it has to be enforced—hence the importance of the

state in the present era. It is not that modern capitalism has resolved

its contradictions[2] and annulled the social dialectic, but rather that

the social dialectic and the contradictions of capitalism have expanded

from the economic to the hierarchical realms of society, from the

abstract "historic" domain to the concrete minutiae of everday

experience, from the arena of survival to the arena of life.

The dialectic of bureaucratic state capitalism originates in the

contradiction between the repressive character of commodity society and

the enormous potential freedom opened by technological advance. This

contradiction also opposes the exploitative organization of society to

the natural world—a world that includes not only the natural

environment, but also man's "nature"—his Eros-derived impulses. The

contradiction between the exploitative organization of society and the

natural environment is beyond co-optation: the atmosphere, the

waterways, the soil and the ecology required for human survival are not

redeemable by reforms, concessions, or modifications of strategic

policy. There is no technology that can reproduce atmospheric oxygen in

sufficient quantities to sustain life on this planet. There is no

substitute for the hydrological systems of the earth. There is no

technique for removing massive environmental pollution by radioactive

isotopes, pesticides, lead and petroleum wastes. Nor is there the

faintest evidence that bourgeois society will relent at any time in the

foreseeable future in its disruption of vital ecological processes, in

its exploitation of natural resources, in its use of the atmosphere and

waterways as dumping areas for wastes, or in its cancerous mode of

urbanization and land abuse.

Even more immediate is the contradiction between the exploitative

organization of society and man's Eros-derived impulses—a contradiction

that manifests itself as the banalization and impoverishment of

experience in a bureaucratically manipulated, impersonal mass society.

The Eros-derived impulses in man can be repressed and sublimated, but

they can never be eliminated. They are renewed with every birth of a

human being and with every generation of youth. It is not surprising

today that the young, more than any economic class or stratum,

articulate the life-impulses in humanity's nature—the urgings of desire,

sensuousness, and the lure of the marvelous. Thus, the biological

matrix, from which hierarchical society emerged ages ago, reappears at a

new level with the era that marks the end of hierarchy, only now this

matrix is saturated with social phenomena. Short of manipulating

humanity's germplasm, the life-impulses can be annulled only with the

annihilation of man himself.

The contradictions within bureaucratic state capitalism permeate all the

hierarchical forms developed and overdeveloped by bourgeois society. The

hierarchical forms which nurtured propertied society for ages and

promoted its development—the state, city, centralized economy,

bureaucracy, patriarchal family, and marketplace—have reached their

historic limits. They have exhausted their social functions as modes of

stabilization. It is not a question of whether these hierarchical forms

were ever "progressive" in the Marxian sense of the term. As Raoul

Vaneigem has observed: "Perhaps it isn't enough to say that hierarchical

power has preserved humanity for thousands of years as alcohol preserves

a fetus, by arresting either growth or decay." Today these forms

constitute the target of all the revolutionary forces that are generated

by modern capitalism, and whether one sees their outcome as nuclear

catastrophe or ecological disaster they now threaten the very survival

of humanity.

With the development of hierarchical forms into a threat to the very

existence of humanity, the social dialectic, far from being annulled,

acquires a new dimension. It poses the "social question" in an entirely

new way. If man had to acquire the conditions of survival in order to

live (as Marx emphasized), now he must acquire the conditions of life in

order to survive. By this inversion of the relationship between survival

and life, revolution acquires a new sense of urgency. No longer are we

faced with Marx's famous choice of socialism or barbarism; we are

confronted with the more drastic alternatives of anarchism or

annihilation. The problems of necessity and survival have become

congruent with the problems of freedom and life. They cease to require

any theoretical mediation, "transitional" stages, or centralized

organizations to bridge the gap between the existing and the possible.

The possible, in fact, is all that can exist. Hence, the problems of

"transition," which occupied the Marxists for nearly a century, are

eliminated not only by the advance of technology, but by the social

dialectic itself. The problems of social reconstruction have been

reduced to practical tasks that can be solved spontaneously by

self-liberatory acts of society.

Revolution, in fact, acquires not only a new sense of urgency, but a new

sense of promise. In the hippies' tribalism, in the drop-out lifestyles

and free sexuality of millions of youth, in the spontaneous affinity

groups of the anarchists, we find forms of affirmation that follow from

acts of negation. With the inversion of the "social question" there is

also an inversion of the social dialectic; a "yea" emerges automatically

and simultaneously with a "nay."

The solutions take their point of departure from the problems. When the

time has arrived in history that the state, the city, bureaucracy, the

centralized economy, the patriarchal family and the marketplace have

reached their historic limits, what is posed is no longer a change in

form but the absolute negation of all hierarchical forms as such. The

absolute negation of the state is anarchism—a situation in which men

liberate not only "history," but all the immediate circumstances of

their everyday lives. The absolute negation of the city is community— a

community in which the social environment is decentralized into rounded,

ecologically balanced communes. The absolute negation of bureaucracy is

immediate as distinguished from mediated relations—a situation in which

representation is replaced by face-to-face relations in a general

assembly of free individuals. The absolute negation of the centralized

economy is regional ecotechnology— a situation in which the instruments

of production are molded to the resources of an ecosystem. The absolute

negation of the patriarchal family is liberated sexuality—in which all

forms of sexual regulation are transcended by the spontaneous,

untrammeled expression of eroticism among equals. The absolute negation

of the marketplace is communism—in which collective abundance and

cooperation transform labor into play and need into desire.

Spontaneity and Utopia

It is not accidental that at a point in history when hierarchical power

and manipulation have reached their most threatening proportions, the

very concepts of hierarchy, power and manipulation are being brought

into question. The challenge to these concepts comes from a rediscovery

of the importance of spontaneity—a rediscovery nourished by ecology, by

a heightened conception of self-development, and by a new understanding

of the revolutionary process in society.

What ecology has shown is that balance in nature is achieved by organic

variation and complexity, not by homogeneity and simplification. For

example, the more varied the flora and fauna of an ecosystem, the more

stable the population of a potential pest. The more environmental

diversity is diminished, the greater will the population of a potential

pest fluctuate, with the probability that it will get out of control.

Left to itself, an ecosystem tends spontaneously toward organic

differentiation, greater variety of flora and fauna, and diversity in

the number of prey and predators. This does not mean that interference

by man must be avoided. The need for a productive agriculture—itself a

form of interference with nature—must always remain in the foreground of

an ecological approach to food cultivation and forest management. No

less important is the fact that man can often produce changes in an

ecosystem that would vastly improve its ecological quality.

But these efforts require insight and understanding, not the exercise of

brute power and manipulation.

This concept of management, this new regard for the importance of

spontaneity, has far-reaching applications for technology and

community—indeed, for the social image of man in a liberated society. It

challenges the capitalist ideal of agriculture as a factory operation,

organized around immense, centrally controlled land-holdings, highly

specialized forms of monoculture, the reduction of the terrain to a

factory floor, the substitution of chemical for organic processes, the

use of gang-labor, etc. If food cultivation is to be a mode of

cooperation with nature rather than a contest between opponents, the

agriculturist must become thoroughly familiar with the ecology of the

land; he must acquire a new sensitivity to its needs and possibilities.

This presupposes the reduction of agriculture to a human scale, the

restoration of moderate-sized agricultural units, and the

diversification of the agricultural situation; in short, it presupposes

a decentralized, ecological system of food cultivation.

The same reasoning applies to pollution control. The development of

giant factory complexes and the use of single or dual-energy sources are

responsible for atmospheric pollution. Only by developing smaller

industrial units and diversifying energy sources by the extensive use of

clean power (solar, wind and water power) will it be possible to reduce

industrial pollution. The means for this radical technological change

are now at hand. Technologists have developed miniaturized substitutes

for large-scale industrial operation—small versatile machines and

sophisticated methods for converting solar, wind and water energy into

power usable in industry and the home. These substitutes are often more

productive and less wasteful than the large-scale facilities that exist

today.[3]

The implications of small-scale agriculture and industry for a community

are obvious: if humanity is to use the principles needed to manage an

ecosystem, the basic communal unit of social life must itself become an

ecosystem—an ecocommunity. It too must become diversified, balanced and

well-rounded. By no means is this concept of community motivated

exclusively by the need for a lasting balance between man and the

natural world; it also accords with the Utopian ideal of the rounded

man, the individual whose sensibilities, range of experience and

lifestyle are nourished by a wide range of stimuli, by a diversity of

activities, and by a social scale that always remains within the

comprehension of a single human being. Thus the means and conditions of

survival become the means and conditions of life; need becomes desire

and desire becomes need. The point is reached where the greatest social

decomposition provides the source of the highest form of social

integration, bringing the most pressing ecological necessities into a

common focus with the highest Utopian ideals.

If it is true, as Guy Debord observes, that "daily life is the measure

of everything: of the fulfillment or rather the non-fulfillment of human

relationships, of the use we make of our time," a question arises: Who

are "we whose daily lives are to be fulfilled? And how does the

liberated self emerge that is capable of turning time into life, space

into community, and human relationships into the marvelous? The

liberation of the self involves, above all, a social process. In a

society that has shriveled the self into a commodity—into an object

manufactured for exchange—there can be no fulfilled self. There can only

be the beginnings of selfhood, the emergence of a self that seeks

fulfillment—a self that is largely defined by the obstacles it must

overcome to achieve realization. In a society whose belly is distended

to the bursting point with revolution, whose chronic state is an

unending series of labor pains, whose real condition is a mounting

emergency, only one thought and act is relevant—giving birth. Any

environment, private or social, that does not make this fact the center

of human experience is a sham and diminishes whatever self remains to us

after we have absorbed our daily poison of everyday life in bourgeois

society.

It is plain that the goal of revolution today must be the liberation of

daily life. Any revolution that fails to achieve this goal is

counterrevolution. Above all, it is we who have to be liberated, our

daily lives, with all their moments, hours and days, and not universals

like "History" and "Society."[4]

The self must always be identifiable in the revolution, not overwhelmed

by it. The self must always be perceivable in the revolutionary process,

not submerged by it. There is no word that is more sinister in the

"revolutionary" vocabulary than "masses." Revolutionary liberation must

be a self-liberation that reaches social dimensions, not "mass

liberation" or "class liberation" behind which lurks the rule of an

elite, a hierarchy and a state. If a revolution fails to produce a new

society by the self-activity and self-mobilization of revolutionaries,

if it does not involve the forging of a self in the revolutionary

process, the revolution will once again circumvent those whose lives are

to be lived every day and leave daily life unaffected. Out of the

revolution must emerge a self that takes full possession of daily life,

not a daily life that once again takes full possession of the self. The

most advanced form of class consciousness thus becomes

self-consciousness—the concretization in daily life of the great

liberating universals.

If for this reason alone, the revolutionary movement is profoundly

concerned with lifestyle. It must try to live the revolution in all its

totality, not only participate in it. It must be deeply concerned with

the way the revolutionist lives, his relations with the surrounding

environment, and his degree of self-emancipation. In seeking to change

society, the revolutionist cannot avoid changes in himself that demand

the reconquest of his own being. Like the movement in which he

participates, the revolutionist must try to reflect the conditions of

the society he is trying to achieve—at least to the degree that this is

possible today.

The treacheries and failures of the past half century have made it

axiomatic that there can be no separation of the revolutionary process

from the revolutionary goal. A society whose fundamental aim is

self-administration in all facets of life can be achieved only by

self-activity. This implies a mode of administration that is always

possessed by the self. The power of man over man can be destroyed only

by the very process in which man acquires power over his own life and in

which he not only "discovers" himself but, more meaningfully, in which

he formulates his selfhood in all its social dimensions.

A libertarian society can be achieved only by a libertarian revolution.

Freedom cannot be "delivered" to the individual as the "end-product" of

a "revolution"; the assembly and community cannot be legislated or

decreed into existence. A revolutionary group can seek, purposively and

consciously, to promote the creation of these forms, but if assembly and

community are not allowed to emerge organically, if their growth is not

matured by the process of demassification, by self-activity and by

self-realization, they will remain nothing but forms, like the Soviets

in postrevolutionary Russia. Assembly and community must arise within

the revolutionary process; indeed, the revolutionary process must be the

formation of assembly and community, and also the destruction of power,

property, hierarchy and exploitation.

Revolution as self-activity is not unique to our time. It is the

paramount feature of all the great revolutions in modern history. It

marked the journees of the sansculottes in 1792 and 1793, the famous

"Five Days" of February 1917 in Petrograd, the uprising of the Barcelona

proletariat in 1936, the early days of the Hungarian Revolution in 1956,

and the May-June events in Paris in 1968. Nearly every revolutionary

uprising in the history of our time has been initiated spontaneously by

the self-activity of "masses"—often in flat defiance of the hesitant

policies advanced by the revolutionary organizations. Every one of these

revolutions has been marked by extraordinary individuation, by a

joyousness and solidarity that turned everyday life into a festival.

This surreal dimension of the revolutionary process, with its explosion

of deep-seated libidinal forces, grins irascibly through the pages of

history like the face of a satyr on shimmering water. It is not without

reason that the Bolshevik commissars smashed the wine bottles in the

Winter Palace on the night of November 7, 1917.

The puritanism and work ethic of the traditional left stem from one of

the most powerful forces opposing revolution today—the capacity of the

bourgeois environment to infiltrate the revolutionary framework. The

origins of this power lie in the commodity nature of man under

capitalism, a quality that is almost automatically transferred to the

organized group—and which the group, in turn, reinforces in its members.

As the late Josef Weber emphasized, all organized groups "have the

tendency to render themselves autonomous, i.e., to alienate themselves

from their original aim and to become an end in themselves in the hands

of those administering them." This phenomenon is as true of

revolutionary organizations as it is of state and semi-state

institutions, official parties and trade unions.

The problem of alienation can never be completely resolved apart from

the revolutionary process itself, but it can be guarded against by an

acute awareness that the problem exists, and partly solved by a

voluntary but drastic remaking of the revolutionary and his group. This

remaking can only begin when the revolutionary group recognizes that it

is a catalyst in the revolutionary process, not a "vanguard." The

revolutionary group must clearly see that its goal is not the seizure of

power but the dissolution of power—indeed, it must see that the entire

problem of power, of control from below and control from above, can be

solved only if there is no above or below.

Above all, the revolutionary group must divest itself of the forms of

power—statutes, hierarchies, property, prescribed opinions, fetishes,

paraphernalia, official etiquette—and of the subtlest as well as the

most obvious of bureaucratic and bourgeois traits that consciously and

unconsciously reinforce authority and hierarchy. The group must remain

open to public scrutiny not only in its formulated decisions but also in

their very formulation. It must be coherent in the profound sense that

its theory is its practice and its practice its theory. It must do away

with all commodity relations in its day-to-day existence and constitute

itself along the decentralizing organizational principles of the very

society it seeks to achieve—community, assembly, spontaneity. It must,

in Josef Weber's superb words, be "marked always by simplicity and

clarity, always thousands of unprepared people can enter and direct it,

always it remains transparent to and controlled by all." Only then, when

the revolutionary movement is congruent with the decentralized community

it seeks to achieve, can it avoid becoming another elitist obstacle to

the social development and dissolve into the revolution like surgical

thread into a healing wound.

Prospect

The most important process going on in America today is the sweeping

de-institutionalization of the bourgeois social structure. A basic,

far-reaching disrespect and a profound disloyalty are developing toward

the values, the forms, the aspirations and, above all, the institutions

of the established order. On a scale unprecedented in American history,

millions of people are shedding their commitment to the society in which

they live. They no longer believe in its claims. They no longer respect

its symbols. They no longer accept its goals, and, most significantly,

they refuse almost intuitively to live by its institutional and social

codes. This growing refusal runs very deep. It extends from an

opposition to war into a hatred of political manipulation in all its

forms. Starting from a rejection of racism, it brings into question the

very existence of hierarchical power as such. In its detestation of

middle-class values and lifestyles it rapidly evolves into a rejection

of the commodity system; from an irritation with environmental

pollution, it passes into a rejection of the American city and modern

urbanism. In short, it tends to transcend every particularistic critique

of the society and to evolve into a generalized opposition to the

bourgeois order on an ever broadening scale.

In this respect, the period in which we live closely resembles the

revolutionary Enlightenment that swept through France in the eighteenth

century—a period that completely reworked French consciousness and

prepared the conditions for the Great Revolution of 1789. Then as now,

the old institutions were slowly pulverized by molecular action from

below long before they were toppled by mass revolutionary action. This

molecular movement creates an atmosphere of general lawlessness: a

growing personal day-to-day disobedience, a tendency not to "go along"

with the existing system, a seemingly "petty" but nevertheless critical

attempt to circumvent restriction in every facet of daily life. The

society, in effect, becomes disorderly, undisciplined, Dionysian—a

condition that reveals itself most dramatically in an increasing rate of

official crimes. A vast critique of the system develops—the actual

Enlightenment itself, two centuries ago, and the sweeping critique that

exists today—which seeps downward and accelerates the molecular movement

at the base. Be it an angry gesture, a "riot" or a conscious change in

lifestyle, an ever-increasing number of people—who have no more of a

commitment to an organized revolutionary movement than they have to

society itself—begin spontaneously to engage in their own defiant

propaganda of the deed.

In its concrete details, the disintegrating social process is nourished

by many sources. The process develops with all the unevenness, indeed

with all the contradictions, that mark every revolutionary trend. In

eighteenth century France, radical ideology oscillated between a rigid

scientism and a sloppy romanticism. Notions of freedom were anchored in

a precise, logical ideal of self-control, and also a vague, instinctive

norm of spontaneity. Rousseau stood at odds with d'Holbach, Diderot at

odds with Voltaire, yet in retrospect we can see that one not only

transcended but also presupposed the other in a cumulative development

toward revolution.

The same uneven, contradictory and cumulative development exists today,

and in many cases it follows a remarkably direct course. The "beat"

movement created the most important breach in the solid, middle-class

values of the 1950s, a breach that was widened enormously by the

illegalities of pacifists, civil-rights workers, draft resisters and

longhairs. Moreover, the merely reactive response of rebellious American

youth has produced invaluable forms of libertarian and Utopian

affirmation—the right to make love without restriction, the goal of

community, the disavowal of money and commodities, the belief in mutual

aid, and a new respect for spontaneity. Easy as it is for

revolutionaries to criticize certain pitfalls within this orientation of

personal and social values, the fact remains that it has played a

preparatory role of decisive importance in forming the present

atmosphere of indiscipline, spontaneity, radicalism and freedom.

A second parallel between the revolutionary Enlightenment and our own

period is the emergence of the crowd, the so-called "mob," as a major

vehicle of social protest. The typical institutionalized forms of public

dissatisfaction—in our own day, they are orderly elections,

demonstration and mass meetings—tend to give way to direct action by

crowds. This shift from predictable, highly organized protests within

the institutionalized framework of the existing society to sporadic,

spontaneous, near-insurrectionary assaults from outside (and even

against) socially acceptable forms reflects a profound change in popular

psychology. The "rioter" has begun to break, however partially and

intuitively, with those deep-seated norms of behavior which

traditionally weld the "masses" to the established order. He actively

sheds the internalized structure of authority, the long-cultivated body

of conditioned reflexes, and the pattern of submission sustained by

guilt that tie one to the system even more effectively than any fear of

police violence and juridical reprisal. Contrary to the views of social

psychologists, who see in these modes of direct action the submission of

the individual to a terrifying collective entity called the "mob," the

truth is that "riots" and crowd actions represent the first gropings of

the mass toward individuation. The mass tends to become demassified in

the sense that it begins to assert itself against the really massifying

automatic responses produced by the bourgeois family, the school and the

mass media. By the same token, crowd actions involve the rediscovery of

the streets and the effort to liberate them. Ultimately, it is in the

streets that power must be dissolved: for the streets, where daily life

is endured, suffered and eroded, and where power is confronted and

fought, must be turned into the domain where daily life is enjoyed,

created and nourished. The rebellious crowd marked the beginning not

only of a spontaneous transmutation of private into social revolt, but

also of a return from the abstractions of social revolt to the issues of

everyday life.

Finally, as in the Enlightenment, we are seeing the emergence of an

immense and ever-growing stratum of declasses, a body of lumpenized

individuals drawn from every stratum of society. The chronically

indebted and socially insecure middle classes of our period compare

loosely with the chronically insolvent and flighty nobility of

prerevolutionary France. A vast flotsam of educated people emerged then

as now, living at loose ends, without fixed careers or established

social roots. At the bottom of both structures we find a large number of

chronic poor- vagabonds, drifters, people with part-time jobs or no jobs

at all, threatening, unruly sans-culottes— surviving on public aid and

on the garbage thrown off by society, the poor of the Parisian slums,

the blacks of the American ghettoes. But here all the parallels end. The

French Enlightenment belongs to a period of revolutionary transition

from feudalism to capitalism—both societies based on economic scarcity,

class rule, exploitation, social hierarchy and state power. The

day-to-day popular resistance which marked the eighteenth century and

culminated in open revolution was soon disciplined by the newly emerging

industrial order—as well as by naked force. The vast mass of declasses

and sans-culottes was largely absorbed into the factory system and tamed

by industrial discipline. Formerly rootless intellectuals and footloose

nobles found secure places in the economic, political, social and

cultural hierarchy of the new bourgeois order. From a socially and

culturally fluid condition, highly generalized in its structure and

relations, society hardened again into rigid, particularized class and

institutional forms—the classical Victorian era appeared not only in

England but, to one degree or another, in all of Western Europe and

America. Critique was consolidated into apologia, revolt into reform,

declasses into clearly defined classes and "mobs" into political

constituencies. "Riots" became the well-behaved processionals we call

"demonstrations," and spontaneous direct action turned into electoral

rituals.

Our own era is also a transitional one, but with a profound and new

difference. In the last of their great insurrections, the sans-culottes

of the French Revolution rose under the fiery cry: "Bread and the

Constitution of '93!" The black sans-culottes of the American ghettoes

rise under the slogan: "Black is beautiful!" Between these two slogans

lies a development of unprecedented importance. The declasses of the

eighteenth century were formed during a slow transition from an

agricultural to an industrial era; they were created out of a pause in

the historical transition from one regime of toil to another. The demand

for bread could have been heard at any time in the evolution of

propertied society. The new declasses of the twentieth century are being

created as a result of the bankruptcy of all social forms based on toil.

They are the end products of the process of propertied society itself

and of the social problems of material survival. In the era when

technological advances and cybernation have brought into question the

exploitation of man by man, toil, and material want in any form

whatever, the cry "Black is beautiful" or "Make love, not war" marks the

transformation of the traditional demand for survival into a

historically new demand for life.[5]

What underpins every social conflict in the United States today is the

demand for the realization of all human potentialities in a fully

rounded, balanced, totalistic way of life. In short, the potentialities

for revolution in America are now anchored in the potentialities of man

himself.

What we are witnessing is the breakdown of a century and a half of

embourgeoisement and a pulverization of all bourgeois institutions at a

point in history when the boldest concepts of Utopia are realizable. And

there is nothing that the present bourgeois order can substitute for the

destruction of its traditional institutions but bureaucratic

manipulation and state capitalism. This process is unfolding most

dramatically in the United States. Within a period of little more than

two decades, we have seen the collapse of the "American Dream," or what

amounts to the same thing, the steady destruction in the United States

of the myth that material abundance, based on commodity relations

between men, can conceal the inherent poverty of bourgeois life. Whether

this process will culminate in revolution or in annihilation will depend

in great part on the ability of revolutionists to extend social

consciousness and defend the spontaneity of the revolutionary

development from authoritarian ideologies, both of the "left" and of the

right.

[1] It is worth noting here that the emergence of the "consumer society"

provides us with remarkable evidence of the difference between the

industrial capitalism of Marx's time and state capitalism today. In

Marx's view, capitalism as a system organized around "production for the

sake of production" results in the economic immiseration of the

proletariat. "Production for the sake of production" is paralleled today

by "consumption for the sake of consumption," in which immiseration

takes a spiritual rather than an economic form—it is starvation of life.

[2] The economic contradictions of capitalism have not disappeared, but

the system can plan to such a degree that they no longer have the

explosive characteristics they had in the past.

[3] For a detailed discussion of this "miniaturized" technology see

"Towards a Liberatory Technology."

[4] Despite its lip service to the dialectic, the traditional left has

yet to take Hegel's "concrete universal" seriously and see it not merely

as a philosophical concept but as a social program. This has been done

only in Marx's early writings, in the writings of the great Utopians

(Fourier and William Morris) and, in our time, by the drop-out youth.

[5] The above lines were written in 1966. Since then, we have seen the

graffiti on the walls of Paris, during the May-June revolution: "All

power to the imagination"; "I take my desires to be reality, because I

believe in the reality of my desires"; "Never work"; "The more I make

love, the more I want to make revolution"; "Life without dead times";

"The more you consume, the less you live"; "Culture is the inversion of

life"; "One does not buy happiness, one steals it"; "Society is a

carnivorous flower." These are not graffiti, they are a program for life

and desire.