💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › william-morris-signs-of-change.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:47:05. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Signs of Change
Author: William Morris
Date: 1888
Language: en
Topics: art, Arts and Crafts, democracy, libertarian socialist, socialism, United Kingdom, work
Source: Retrieved on 17 April 2011 from http://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/3053/pg3053.html

William Morris

Signs of Change

How We Live and How We Might Live

The word Revolution, which we Socialists are so often forced to use, has

a terrible sound in most people’s ears, even when we have explained to

them that it does not necessarily mean a change accompanied by riot and

all kinds of violence, and cannot mean a change made mechanically and in

the teeth of opinion by a group of men who have somehow managed to seize

on the executive power for the moment. Even when we explain that we use

the word revolution in its etymological sense, and mean by it a change

in the basis of society, people are scared at the idea of such a vast

change, and beg that you will speak of reform and not revolution. As,

however, we Socialists do not at all mean by our word revolution what

these worthy people mean by their word reform, I can’t help thinking

that it would be a mistake to use it, whatever projects we might conceal

beneath its harmless envelope. So we will stick to our word, which means

a change of the basis of society; it may frighten people, but it will at

least warn them that there is something to be frightened about, which

will be no less dangerous for being ignored; and also it may encourage

some people, and will mean to them at least not a fear, but a hope.

Fear and Hope — those are the names of the two great passions which rule

the race of man, and with which revolutionists have to deal; to give

hope to the many oppressed and fear to the few oppressors, that is our

business; if we do the first and give hope to the many, the few must be

frightened by their hope; otherwise we do not want to frighten them; it

is not revenge we want for poor people, but happiness; indeed, what

revenge can be taken for all the thousands of years of the sufferings of

the poor?

However, many of the oppressors of the poor, most of them, we will say,

are not conscious of their being oppressors (we shall see why

presently); they live in an orderly, quiet way themselves, as far as

possible removed from the feelings of a Roman slave-owner or a Legree;

they know that the poor exist, but their sufferings do not present

themselves to them in a trenchant and dramatic way; they themselves have

troubles to bear, and they think doubtless that to bear trouble is the

lot of humanity, nor have they any means of comparing the troubles of

their lives with those of people lower in the social scale; and if ever

the thought of those heavier troubles obtrudes itself upon them, they

console themselves with the maxim that people do get used to the

troubles they have to bear, whatever they may be.

Indeed, as far as regards individuals at least, that is but too true, so

that we have as supporters of the present state of things, however bad

it may be, first those comfortable unconscious oppressors who think that

they have everything to fear from any change which would involve more

than the softest and most gradual of reforms, and secondly those poor

people who, living hard and anxiously as they do, can hardly conceive of

any change for the better happening to them, and dare not risk one

tittle of their poor possessions in taking any action towards a possible

bettering of their condition; so that while we can do little with the

rich save inspire them with fear, it is hard indeed to give the poor any

hope. It is, then, no less than reasonable that those whom we try to

involve in the great struggle for a better form of life than that which

we now lead should call on us to give them at least some idea of what

that life may be like.

A reasonable request, but hard to satisfy, since we are living under a

system that makes conscious effort towards reconstruction almost

impossible: it is not unreasonable on our part to answer, “There are

certain definite obstacles to the real progress of man; we can tell you

what these are; take them away, and then you shall see.”

However, I purpose now to offer myself as a victim for the satisfaction

of those who consider that as things now go we have at least got

something, and are terrified at the idea of losing their hold of that,

lest they should find they are worse off than before, and have nothing.

Yet in the course of my endeavour to show how we might live, I must more

or less deal in negatives. I mean to say I must point out where in my

opinion we fall short in our present attempts at decent life. I must ask

the rich and well-to-do what sort of a position it is which they are so

anxious to preserve at any cost? and if, after all, it will be such a

terrible loss to them to give it up? and I must point out to the poor

that they, with capacities for living a dignified and generous life, are

in a position which they cannot endure without continued degradation.

How do we live, then, under our present system? Let us look at it a

little.

And first, please to understand that our present system of Society is

based on a state of perpetual war. Do any of you think that this is as

it should be? I know that you have often been told that the competition,

which is at present the rule of all production, is a good thing, and

stimulates the progress of the race; but the people who tell you this

should call competition by its shorter name of war if they wish to be

honest, and you would then be free to consider whether or no war

stimulates progress, otherwise than as a mad bull chasing you over your

own garden may do. War or competition, whichever you please to call it,

means at the best pursuing your own advantage at the cost of some one

else’s loss, and in the process of it you must not be sparing of

destruction even of your own possessions, or you will certainly come by

the worse in the struggle. You understand that perfectly as to the kind

of war in which people go out to kill and be killed; that sort of war in

which ships are commissioned, for instance, “to sink, burn, and

destroy;” but it appears that you are not so conscious of this waste of

goods when you are only carrying on that other war called commerce;

observe, however, that the waste is there all the same.

Now let us look at this kind of war a little closer, run through some of

the forms of it, that we may see how the “burn, sink, and destroy” is

carried on in it.

First, you have that form of it called national rivalry, which in good

truth is nowadays the cause of all gunpowder and bayonet wars which

civilized nations wage. For years past we English have been rather shy

of them, except on those happy occasions when we could carry them on at

no sort of risk to ourselves, when the killing was all on one side, or

at all events when we hoped it would be. We have been shy of gunpowder

war with a respectable enemy for a long while, and I will tell you why:

It is because we have had the lion’s-share of the world-market; we

didn’t want to fight for it as a nation, for we had got it; but now this

is changing in a most significant, and, to a Socialist, a most cheering

way; we are losing or have lost that lion’s share; it is now a desperate

“competition” between the great nations of civilization for the

world-market, and to-morrow it may be a desperate war for that end. As a

result, the furthering of war (if it be not on too large a scale) is no

longer confined to the honour-and-glory kind of old Tories, who if they

meant anything at all by it meant that a Tory war would be a good

occasion for damping down democracy; we have changed all that, and now

it is quite another kind of politician that is wont to urge us on to

“patriotism” as ‘tis called. The leaders of the Progressive Liberals, as

they would call themselves, long-headed persons who know well enough

that social movements are going on, who are not blind to the fact that

the world will move with their help or without it; these have been the

Jingoes of these later days. I don’t mean to say they know what they are

doing: politicians, as you well know, take good care to shut their eyes

to everything that may happen six months ahead; but what is being done

is this: that the present system, which always must include national

rivalry, is pushing us into a desperate scramble for the markets on more

or less equal terms with other nations, because, once more, we have lost

that command of them which we once had. Desperate is not too strong a

word. We shall let this impulse to snatch markets carry us whither it

will, whither it must. To-day it is successful burglary and disgrace,

to-morrow it may be mere defeat and disgrace.

Now this is not a digression, although in saying this I am nearer to

what is generally called politics than I shall be again. I only want to

show you what commercial war comes to when it has to do with foreign

nations, and that even the dullest can see how mere waste must go with

it. That is how we live now with foreign nations, prepared to ruin them

without war if possible, with it if necessary, let alone meantime the

disgraceful exploiting of savage tribes and barbarous peoples, on whom

we force at once our shoddy wares and our hypocrisy at the cannon’s

mouth.

Well, surely Socialism can offer you something in the place of all that.

It can; it can offer you peace and friendship instead of war. We might

live utterly without national rivalries, acknowledging that while it is

best for those who feel that they naturally form a community under one

name to govern themselves, yet that no community in civilization should

feel that it had interests opposed any other, their economical condition

being at any rate similar; so that any citizen of one community could

fall to work and live without disturbance of his life when he was in a

foreign country, and would fit into his place quite naturally; so that

all civilized nations would form one great community, agreeing together

as to the kind and amount of production and distribution needed; working

at such and such production where it could be best produced; avoiding

waste by all means. Please to think of the amount of waste which they

would avoid, how much such a revolution would add to the wealth of the

world! What creature on earth would be harmed by such a revolution? Nay,

would not everybody be the better for it? And what hinders it? I will

tell you presently.

Meantime let us pass from this “competition” between nations to that

between “the organizers of labour,” great firms, joint-stock companies;

capitalists in short, and see how competition “stimulates production”

among them: indeed it does do that; but what kind of production? Well,

production of something to sell at a profit, or say production of

profits: and note how war commercial stimulates that: a certain market

is demanding goods; there are, say, a hundred manufacturers who make

that kind of goods, and every one of them would if he could keep that

market to himself; and struggles desperately to get as much of it as he

can, with the obvious result that presently the thing is overdone, and

the market is glutted, and all that fury of manufacture has to sink into

cold ashes. Doesn’t that seem something like war to you? Can’t you see

the waste of it — waste of labour, skill, cunning, waste of life in

short? Well, you may say, but it cheapens the goods. In a sense it does;

and yet only apparently, as wages have a tendency to sink for the

ordinary worker in proportion as prices sink; and at what a cost do we

gain this appearance of cheapness! Plainly speaking, at the cost of

cheating the consumer and starving the real producer for the benefit of

the gambler, who uses both consumer and producer as his milch cows. I

needn’t go at length into the subject of adulteration, for every one

knows what kind of a part it plays in this sort of commerce; but

remember that it is an absolutely necessary incident to the production

of profit out of wares, which is the business of the so-called

manufacturer; and this you must understand, that, taking him in the

lump, the consumer is perfectly helpless against the gambler; the goods

are forced on him by their cheapness, and with them a certain kind of

life which that energetic, that aggressive cheapness determines for him:

for so far-reaching is this curse of commercial war that no country is

safe from its ravages; the traditions of a thousand years fall before it

in a month; it overruns a weak or semi-barbarous country, and whatever

romance or pleasure or art existed there, is trodden down into a mire of

sordidness and ugliness; the Indian or Javanese craftsman may no longer

ply his craft leisurely, working a few hours a day, in producing a maze

of strange beauty on a piece of cloth: a steam-engine is set a-going at

Manchester, and that victory over nature and a thousand stubborn

difficulties is used for the base work of producing a sort of plaster of

china-clay and shoddy, and the Asiatic worker, if he is not starved to

death outright, as plentifully happens, is driven himself into a factory

to lower the wages of his Manchester brother worker, and nothing of

character is left him except, most like, an accumulation of fear and

hatred of that to him most unaccountable evil, his English master. The

South Sea Islander must leave his canoe-carving, his sweet rest, and his

graceful dances, and become the slave of a slave: trousers, shoddy, rum,

missionary, and fatal disease — he must swallow all this civilization in

the lump, and neither himself nor we can help him now till social order

displaces the hideous tyranny of gambling that has ruined him.

Let those be types of the consumer: but now for the producer; I mean the

real producer, the worker; how does this scramble for the plunder of the

market affect him? The manufacturer, in the eagerness of his war, has

had to collect into one neighbourhood a vast army of workers, he has

drilled them till they are as fit as may be for his special branch of

production, that is, for making a profit out of it, and with the result

of their being fit for nothing else: well, when the glut comes in that

market he is supplying, what happens to this army, every private in

which has been depending on the steady demand in that market, and

acting, as he could not choose but act, as if it were to go on for ever?

You know well what happens to these men: the factory door is shut on

them; on a very large part of them often, and at the best on the reserve

army of labour, so busily employed in the time of inflation. What

becomes of them? Nay, we know that well enough just now. But what we

don’t know, or don’t choose to know, is, that this reserve army of

labour is an absolute necessity for commercial war; if our manufacturers

had not got these poor devils whom they could draft on to their machines

when the demand swelled, other manufacturers in France, or Germany, or

America, would step in and take the market from them.

So you see, as we live now, it is necessary that a vast part of the

industrial population should be exposed to the danger of periodical

semi-starvation, and that, not for the advantage of the people in

another part of the world, but for their degradation and enslavement.

Just let your minds run for a moment on the kind of waste which this

means, this opening up of new markets among savage and barbarous

countries which is the extreme type of the force of the profit-market on

the world, and you will surely see what a hideous nightmare that

profit-market is: it keeps us sweating and terrified for our livelihood,

unable to read a book, or look at a picture, or have pleasant fields to

walk in, or to lie in the sun, or to share in the knowledge of our time,

to have in short either animal or intellectual pleasure, and for what?

that we may go on living the same slavish life till we die, in order to

provide for a rich man what is called a life of ease and luxury; that is

to say, a life so empty, unwholesome, and degraded, that perhaps, on the

whole, he is worse off than we the workers are: and as to the result of

all this suffering, it is luckiest when it is nothing at all, when you

can say that the wares have done nobody any good; for oftenest they have

done many people harm, and we have toiled and groaned and died in making

poison and destruction for our fellow-men.

Well, I say all this is war, and the results of war, the war this time,

not of competing nations, but of competing firms or capitalist units:

and it is this war of the firms which hinders the peace between nations

which you surely have agreed with me in thinking is so necessary; for

you must know that war is the very breath of the nostrils of these

fighting firms, and they have now, in our times, got into their hands

nearly all the political power, and they band together in each country

in order to make their respective governments fulfil just two functions:

the first is at home to act as a strong police force, to keep the ring

in which the strong are beating down the weak; the second is to act as a

piratical body-guard abroad, a petard to explode the doors which lead to

the markets of the world: markets at any price abroad, uninterfered-with

privilege, falsely called laissez-faire, [1] at any price at home, to

provide these is the sole business of a government such as our

industrial captains have been able to conceive of. I must now try to

show you the reason of all this, and what it rests on, by trying to

answer the question, Why have the profit-makers got all this power, or

at least why are they able to keep it?

That takes us to the third form of war commercial: the last, and, the

one which all the rest is founded on. We have spoken first of the war of

rival nations; next of that of rival firms: we have now to speak of

rival men. As nations under the present system are driven to compete

with one another for the markets of the world, and as firms or the

captains of industry have to scramble for their share of the profits of

the markets, so also have the workers to compete with each other — for

livelihood; and it is this constant competition or war amongst them

which enables the profit-grinders to make their profits, and by means of

the wealth so acquired to take all the executive power of the country

into their hands. But here is the difference between the position of the

workers and the profit-makers: to the latter, the profit-grinders, war

is necessary; you cannot have profit-making without competition,

individual, corporate, and national; but you may work for a livelihood

without competing; you may combine instead of competing.

I have said war was the life-breath of the profit-makers; in like

manner, combination is the life of the workers. The working-classes or

proletariat cannot even exist as a class without combination of some

sort. The necessity which forced the profit-grinders to collect their

men first into workshops working by the division of labour, and next

into great factories worked by machinery, and so gradually to draw them

into the great towns and centres of civilization, gave birth to a

distinct working-class or proletariat: and this it was which gave them

their mechanical existence, so to say. But note, that they are indeed

combined into social groups for the production of wares, but only as yet

mechanically; they do not know what they are working at, nor whom they

are working for, because they are combining to produce wares of which

the profit of a master forms an essential part, instead of goods for

their own use: as long as they do this, and compete with each other for

leave to do it, they will be, and will feel themselves to be, simply a

part of those competing firms I have been speaking of; they will be in

fact just a part of the machinery for the production of profit; and so

long as this lasts it will be the aim of the masters or profit-makers to

decrease the market value of this human part of the machinery; that is

to say, since they already hold in their hands the labour of dead men in

the form of capital and machinery, it is their interest, or we will say

their necessity, to pay as little as they can help for the labour of

living men which they have to buy from day to day: and since the workmen

they employ have nothing but their labour-power, they are compelled to

underbid one another for employment and wages, and so enable the

capitalist to play his game.

I have said that, as things go, the workers are a part of the competing

firms, an adjunct of capital. Nevertheless, they are only so by

compulsion; and, even without their being conscious of it, they struggle

against that compulsion and its immediate results, the lowering of their

wages, of their standard of life; and this they do, and must do, both as

a class and individually: just as the slave of the great Roman lord,

though he distinctly felt himself to be a part of the household, yet

collectively was a force in reserve for its destruction, and

individually stole from his lord whenever he could safely do so. So,

here, you see, is another form of war necessary to the way we live now,

the war of class against class, which, when it rises to its height, and

it seems to be rising at present, will destroy those other forms of war

we have been speaking of; will make the position of the profit-makers,

of perpetual commercial war, untenable; will destroy the present system

of competitive privilege, or commercial war.

Now observe, I said that to the existence of the workers it was

combination, not competition, that was necessary, while to that of the

profit-makers combination was impossible, and war necessary. The present

position of the workers is that of the machinery of commerce, or in

plainer words its slaves; when they change that position and become

free, the class of profit-makers must cease to exist; and what will then

be the position of the workers? Even as it is they are the one necessary

part of society, the life-giving part; the other classes are but

hangers-on who live on them. But what should they be, what will they be,

when they, once for all, come to know their real power, and cease

competing with one another for livelihood? I will tell you: they will be

society, they will be the community. And being society — that is, there

being no class outside them to contend with — they can then regulate

their labour in accordance with their own real needs.

There is much talk about supply and demand, but the supply and demand

usually meant is an artificial one; it is under the sway of the gambling

market; the demand is forced, as I hinted above, before it is supplied;

nor, as each producer is working against all the rest, can the producers

hold their hands, till the market is glutted and the workers, thrown out

on the streets, hear that there has been over-production, amidst which

over-plus of unsaleable goods they go ill-supplied with even

necessaries, because the wealth which they themselves have created is

“ill-distributed,” as we call it — that is, unjustly taken away from

them.

When the workers are society they will regulate their labour, so that

the supply and demand shall be genuine, not gambling; the two will then

be commensurate, for it is the same society which demands that also

supplies; there will be no more artificial famines then, no more poverty

amidst over-production, amidst too great a stock of the very things

which should supply poverty and turn it into well-being. In short, there

will be no waste and therefore no tyranny.

Well, now, what Socialism offers you in place of these artificial

famines, with their so-called over-production, is, once more, regulation

of the markets; supply and demand commensurate; no gambling, and

consequently (once more) no waste; not overwork and weariness for the

worker one month, and the next no work and terror of starvation, but

steady work and plenty of leisure every month; not cheap market wares,

that is to say, adulterated wares, with scarcely any good in them, mere

scaffold-poles for building up profits; no labour would be spent on such

things as these, which people would cease to want when they ceased to be

slaves. Not these, but such goods as best fulfilled the real uses of the

consumers, would labour be set to make; for profit being abolished,

people could have what they wanted, instead of what the profit-grinders

at home and abroad forced them to take.

For what I want you to understand is this: that in every civilized

country at least there is plenty for all — is, or at any rate might be.

Even with labour so misdirected as it is at present, an equitable

distribution of the wealth we have would make all people comparatively

comfortable; but that is nothing to the wealth we might have if labour

were not misdirected.

Observe, in the early days of the history of man he was the slave of his

most immediate necessities; Nature was mighty and he was feeble, and he

had to wage constant war with her for his daily food and such shelter as

he could get. His life was bound down and limited by this constant

struggle; all his morals, laws, religion, are in fact the outcome and

the reflection of this ceaseless toil of earning his livelihood. Time

passed, and little by little, step by step, he grew stronger, till now

after all these ages he has almost completely conquered Nature, and one

would think should now have leisure to turn his thoughts towards higher

things than procuring to-morrow’s dinner. But, alas! his progress has

been broken and halting; and though he has indeed conquered Nature and

has her forces under his control to do what he will with, he still has

himself to conquer, he still has to think how he will best use those

forces which he has mastered. At present he uses them blindly,

foolishly, as one driven by mere fate. It would almost seem as if some

phantom of the ceaseless pursuit of food which was once the master of

the savage was still hunting the civilized man; who toils in a dream, as

it were, haunted by mere dim unreal hopes, borne of vague recollections

of the days gone by. Out of that dream he must wake, and face things as

they really are. The conquest of Nature is complete, may we not say? and

now our business is, and has for long been, the organization of man, who

wields the forces of Nature. Nor till this is attempted at least shall

we ever be free of that terrible phantom of fear of starvation which,

with its brother devil, desire of domination, drives us into injustice,

cruelty, and dastardliness of all kinds: to cease to fear our fellows

and learn to depend on them, to do away with competition and build up

co-operation, is our one necessity.

Now, to get closer to details; you probably know that every man in

civilization is worth, so to say, more than his skin; working, as he

must work, socially, he can produce more than will keep himself alive

and in fair condition; and this has been so for many centuries, from the

time, in fact, when warring tribes began to make their conquered enemies

slaves instead of killing them; and of course his capacity of producing

these extras has gone on increasing faster and faster, till to-day one

man will weave, for instance, as much cloth in a week as will clothe a

whole village for years: and the real question of civilization has

always been what are we to do with this extra produce of labour — a

question which the phantom, fear of starvation, and its fellow, desire

of domination, has driven men to answer pretty badly always, and worst

of all perhaps in these present days, when the extra produce has grown

with such prodigious speed. The practical answer has always been for man

to struggle with his fellow for private possession of undue shares of

these extras, and all kinds of devices have been employed by those who

found themselves in possession of the power of taking them from others

to keep those whom they had robbed in perpetual subjection; and these

latter, as I have already hinted, had no chance of resisting this

fleecing as long as they were few and scattered, and consequently could

have little sense of their common oppression. But now that, owing to the

very pursuit of these undue shares of profit, or extra earnings, men

have become more dependent on each other for production, and have been

driven, as I said before, to combine together for that end more

completely, the power of the workers — that is to say, of the robbed or

fleeced class — has enormously increased, and it only remains for them

to understand that they have this power. When they do that they will be

able to give the right answer to the question what is to be done with

the extra products of labour over and above what will keep the labourer

alive to labour: which answer is, that the worker will have all that he

produces, and not be fleeced at all: and remember that he produces

collectively, and therefore he will do effectively what work is required

of him according to his capacity, and of the produce of that work he

will have what he needs; because, you see, he cannot use more than he

needs — he can only waste it.

If this arrangement seems to you preposterously ideal, as it well may,

looking at our present condition, I must back it up by saying that when

men are organized so that their labour is not wasted, they will be

relieved from the fear of starvation and the desire of domination, and

will have freedom and leisure to look round and see what they really do

need.

Now something of that I can conceive for my own self, and I will lay my

ideas before you, so that you may compare them with your own, asking you

always to remember that the very differences in men’s capacities and

desires, after the common need of food and shelter is satisfied, will

make it easier to deal with their desires in a communal state of things.

What is it that I need, therefore, which my surrounding circumstances

can give me — my dealings with my fellow-men — setting aside inevitable

accidents which co-operation and forethought cannot control, if there be

such?

Well, first of all I claim good health; and I say that a vast proportion

of people in civilization scarcely even know what that means. To feel

mere life a pleasure; to enjoy the moving one’s limbs and exercising

one’s bodily powers; to play, as it were, with sun and wind and rain; to

rejoice in satisfying the due bodily appetites of a human animal without

fear of degradation or sense of wrong-doing: yes, and therewithal to be

well formed, straight-limbed, strongly knit, expressive of countenance —

to be, in a word, beautiful — that also I claim. If we cannot have this

claim satisfied, we are but poor creatures after all; and I claim it in

the teeth of those terrible doctrines of asceticism, which, born of the

despair of the oppressed and degraded, have been for so many ages used

as instruments for the continuance of that oppression and degradation.

And I believe that this claim for a healthy body for all of us carries

with it all other due claims: for who knows where the seeds of disease

which even rich people suffer from were first sown: from the luxury of

an ancestor, perhaps; yet often, I suspect, from his poverty. And for

the poor: a distinguished physicist has said that the poor suffer always

from one disease — hunger; and at least I know this, that if a man is

overworked in any degree he cannot enjoy the sort of health I am

speaking of; nor can he if he is continually chained to one dull round

of mechanical work, with no hope at the other end of it; nor if he lives

in continual sordid anxiety for his livelihood, nor if he is ill-housed,

nor if he is deprived of all enjoyment of the natural beauty of the

world, nor if he has no amusement to quicken the flow of his spirits

from time to time: all these things, which touch more or less directly

on his bodily condition, are born of the claim I make to live in good

health; indeed, I suspect that these good conditions must have been in

force for several generations before a population in general will be

really healthy, as I have hinted above; but also I doubt not that in the

course of time they would, joined to other conditions, of which more

hereafter, gradually breed such a population, living in enjoyment of

animal life at least, happy therefore, and beautiful according to the

beauty of their race. On this point I may note that the very variations

in the races of men are caused by the conditions under which they live,

and though in these rougher parts of the world we lack some of the

advantages of climate and surroundings, yet, if we were working for

livelihood and not for profit, we might easily neutralize many of the

disadvantages of our climate, at least enough give due scope to the full

development of our race.

Now the next thing I claim is education. And you must not say that every

English child is educated now; that sort of education will not answer my

claim, though I cheerfully admit it is something: something, and yet

after all only class education. What I claim is liberal education;

opportunity, that is, to have my share of whatever knowledge there is in

the world according to my capacity or bent of mind, historical or

scientific; and also to have my share of skill of hand which is about in

the world, either in the industrial handicrafts or in the fine arts;

picture-painting, sculpture, music, acting, or the like: I claim to be

taught, if I can be taught, more than one craft to exercise for the

benefit of the community. You may think this a large claim, but I am

clear it is not too large a claim if the community is to have any gain

out of my special capacities, if we are not all to be beaten down to a

dull level of mediocrity as we are now, all but the very strongest and

toughest of us.

But also I know that this claim for education involves one for public

advantages in the shape of public libraries, schools, and the like, such

as no private person, not even the richest, could command: but these I

claim very confidently, being sure that no reasonable community could

bear to be without such helps to a decent life.

Again, the claim for education involves a claim for abundant leisure,

which once more I make with confidence; because when once we have shaken

off the slavery of profit, labour would be organized so unwastefully

that no heavy burden would be laid on the individual citizens; every one

of whom as a matter of course would have to pay his toll of some

obviously useful work. At present you must note that all the amazing

machinery which we have invented has served only to increase the amount

of profit-bearing wares; in other words, to increase the amount of

profit pouched by individuals for their own advantage, part of which

profit they use as capital for the production of more profit, with ever

the same waste attached to it; and part as private riches or means for

luxurious living, which again is sheer waste — is in fact to be looked

on as a kind of bonfire on which rich men burn up the product of the

labour they have fleeced from the workers beyond what they themselves

can use. So I say that, in spite of our inventions, no worker works

under the present system an hour the less on account of those

labour-saving machines, so-called. But under a happier state of things

they would be used simply for saving labour, with the result of a vast

amount of leisure gained for the community to be added to that gained by

the avoidance of the waste of useless luxury, and the abolition of the

service of commercial war.

And I may say that as to that leisure, as I should in no case do any

harm to any one with it, so I should often do some direct good to the

community with it, by practising arts or occupations for my hands or

brain which would give pleasure to many of the citizens; in other words,

a great deal of the best work done would be done in the leisure time of

men relieved from any anxiety as to their livelihood, and eager to

exercise their special talent, as all men, nay, all animals are.

Now, again, this leisure would enable me to please myself and expand my

mind by travelling if I had a mind to it: because, say, for instance,

that I were a shoemaker; if due social order were established, it by no

means follows that I should always be obliged to make shoes in one

place; a due amount of easily conceivable arrangement would enable me to

make shoes in Rome, say, for three months, and to come back with new

ideas of building, gathered from the sight of the works of past ages,

amongst other things which would perhaps be of service in London.

But now, in order that my leisure might not degenerate into idleness and

aimlessness, I must set up a claim for due work to do. Nothing to my

mind is more important than this demand, and I must ask your leave to

say something about it. I have mentioned that I should probably use my

leisure for doing a good deal of what is now called work; but it is

clear that if I am a member of a Socialist Community I must do my due

share of rougher work than this — my due share of what my capacity

enables me to do, that is; no fitting of me to a Procrustean bed; but

even that share of work necessary to the existence of the simplest

social life must, in the first place, whatever else it is, be reasonable

work; that is, it must be such work as a good citizen can see the

necessity for; as a member of the community, I must have agreed to do

it.

To take two strong instances of the contrary, I won’t submit to be

dressed up in red and marched off to shoot at my French or German or

Arab friend in a quarrel that I don’t understand; I will rebel sooner

than do that.

Nor will I submit to waste my time and energies in making some trifling

toy which I know only a fool can desire; I will rebel sooner than do

that.

However, you may be sure that in a state of social order I shall have no

need to rebel against any such pieces of unreason; only I am forced to

speak from the way we live to the way we might live.

Again, if the necessary reasonable work be of a mechanical kind, I must

be helped to do it by a machine, not to cheapen my labour, but so that

as little time as possible may be spent upon it, and that I may be able

to think of other things while am tending the machine. And if the work

be specially rough or exhausting, you will, I am sure, agree with me in

saying that I must take turns in doing it with other people; I mean I

mustn’t, for instance, be expected to spend my working hours always at

the bottom of a coal-pit. I think such work as that ought to be largely

volunteer work, and done, as I say, in spells. And what I say of very

rough work I say also of nasty work. On the other hand, I should think

very little of the manhood of a stout and healthy man who did not feel a

pleasure in doing rough work; always supposing him to work under the

conditions I have been speaking of — namely, feeling that it was useful

(and consequently honoured), and that it was not continuous or hopeless,

and that he was really doing it of his own free will.

The last claim I make for my work is that the places I worked in,

factories or workshops, should be pleasant, just as the fields where our

most necessary work is done are pleasant. Believe me there is nothing in

the world to prevent this being done, save the necessity of making

profits on all wares; in other words, the wares are cheapened at the

expense of people being forced to work in crowded, unwholesome, squalid,

noisy dens: that is to say, they are cheapened at the expense of the

workman’s life.

Well, so much for my claims as to my necessary work, my tribute to the

community. I believe people would find, as they advanced in their

capacity for carrying on social order, that life so lived was much less

expensive than we now can have any idea of; and that, after a little,

people would rather be anxious to seek work than to avoid it; that our

working hours would rather be merry parties of men and maids, young men

and old enjoying themselves over their work, than the grumpy weariness

it mostly is now. Then would come the time for the new birth of art, so

much talked of, so long deferred; people could not help showing their

mirth and pleasure in their work, and would be always wishing to express

it in a tangible and more or less enduring form, and the workshop would

once more be a school of art, whose influence no one could escape from.

And, again, that word art leads me to my last claim, which is that the

material surroundings of my life should be pleasant, generous, and

beautiful; that I know is a large claim, but this I will say about it,

that if it cannot be satisfied, if every civilized community cannot

provide such surroundings for all its members, I do not want the world

to go on; it is a mere misery that man has ever existed. I do not think

it possible under the present circumstances to speak too strongly on

this point. I feel sure that the time will come when people will find it

difficult to believe that a rich community such as ours, having such

command over external Nature, could have submitted to live such a mean,

shabby, dirty life as we do.

And once for all, there is nothing in our circumstances save the hunting

of profit that drives us into it. It is profit which draws men into

enormous unmanageable aggregations called towns, for instance; profit

which crowds them up when they are there into quarters without gardens

or open spaces; profit which won’t take the most ordinary precautions

against wrapping a whole district in a cloud of sulphurous smoke; which

turns beautiful rivers into filthy sewers; which condemns all but the

rich to live in houses idiotically cramped and confined at the best, and

at the worst in houses for whose wretchedness there is no name.

I say it is almost incredible that we should bear such crass stupidity

as this; nor should we if we could help it. We shall not bear it when

the workers get out of their heads that they are but an appendage to

profit-grinding, that the more profits that are made the more employment

at high wages there will be for them, and that therefore all the

incredible filth, disorder, and degradation of modern civilization are

signs of their prosperity. So far from that, they are signs of their

slavery. When they are no longer slaves they will claim as a matter of

course that every man and every family should be generously lodged; that

every child should be able to play in a garden close to the place his

parents live in; that the houses should by their obvious decency and

order be ornaments to Nature, not disfigurements of it; for the decency

and order above-mentioned when carried to the due pitch would most

assuredly lead to beauty in building. All this, of course, would mean

the people — that is, all society — duly organized, having in its own

hands the means of production, to be owned by no individual, but used by

all as occasion called for its use, and can only be done on those terms;

on any other terms people will be driven to accumulate private wealth

for themselves, and thus, as we have seen, to waste the goods of the

community and perpetuate the division into classes, which means

continual war and waste.

As to what extent it may be necessary or desirable for people under

social order to live in common, we may differ pretty much according to

our tendencies towards social life. For my part I can’t see why we

should think it a hardship to eat with the people we work with; I am

sure that as to many things, such as valuable books, pictures, and

splendour of surroundings, we shall find it better to club our means

together; and I must say that often when I have been sickened by the

stupidity of the mean idiotic rabbit warrens that rich men build for

themselves in Bayswater and elsewhere, I console myself with visions of

the noble communal hall of the future, unsparing of materials, generous

in worthy ornament, alive with the noblest thoughts of our time, and the

past, embodied in the best art which a free and manly people could

produce; such an abode of man as no private enterprise could come

anywhere near for beauty and fitness, because only collective thought

and collective life could cherish the aspirations which would give birth

to its beauty, or have the skill and leisure to carry them out. I for my

part should think it much the reverse of a hardship if I had to read my

books and meet my friends in such a place; nor do I think I am better

off to live in a vulgar stuccoed house crowded with upholstery that I

despise, in all respects degrading to the mind and enervating to the

body to live in, simply because I call it my own, or my house.

It is not an original remark, but I make it here, that my home is where

I meet people with whom I sympathise, whom I love.

Well, that is my opinion as a middle-class man. Whether a working-class

man would think his family possession of his wretched little room better

than his share of the palace of which I have spoken, I must leave to his

opinion, and to the imaginations of the middle class, who perhaps may

sometimes conceive the fact that the said worker is cramped for space

and comfort — say on washing-day.

Before I leave this matter of the surroundings of life, I wish to meet a

possible objection. I have spoken of machinery being used freely for

releasing people from the more mechanical and repulsive part of

necessary labour; and I know that to some cultivated people, people of

the artistic turn of mind, machinery is particularly distasteful, and

they will be apt to say you will never get your surroundings pleasant so

long as you are surrounded by machinery. I don’t quite admit that; it is

the allowing machines to be our masters and not our servants that so

injures the beauty of life nowadays. In other words, it is the token of

the terrible crime we have fallen into of using our control of the

powers of Nature for the purpose of enslaving people, we careless

meantime of how much happiness we rob their lives of.

Yet for the consolation of the artists I will say that I believe indeed

that a state of social order would probably lead at first to a great

development of machinery for really useful purposes, because people will

still be anxious about getting through the work necessary to holding

society together; but that after a while they will find that there is

not so much work to do as they expected, and that then they will have

leisure to reconsider the whole subject; and if it seems to them that a

certain industry would be carried on more pleasantly as regards the

worker, and more effectually as regards the goods, by using hand-work

rather than machinery, they will certainly get rid of their machinery,

because it will be possible for them to do so. It isn’t possible now; we

are not at liberty to do so; we are slaves to the monsters which we have

created. And I have a kind of hope that the very elaboration of

machinery in a society whose purpose is not the multiplication of

labour, as it now is, but the carrying on of a pleasant life, as it

would be under social order — that the elaboration of machinery, I say,

will lead the simplification of life, and so once more to the limitation

of machinery.

Well, I will now let my claims for decent life stand as I have made

them. To sum them up in brief, they are: First, a healthy body; second,

an active mind in sympathy with the past, the present, and the future;

thirdly, occupation fit for a healthy body and an active mind; and

fourthly, a beautiful world to live in.

These are the conditions of life which the refined man of all ages has

set before him as the thing above all others to be attained. Too often

he has been so foiled in their pursuit that he has turned longing eyes

backward to the days before civilization, when man’s sole business was

getting himself food from day to day, and hope was dormant in him, or at

least could not be expressed by him.

Indeed, if civilization (as many think) forbids the realization of the

hope to attain such conditions of life, then civilization forbids

mankind to be happy; and if that be the case, then let us stifle all

aspirations towards progress — nay, all feelings of mutual good-will and

affection between men — and snatch each one of us what we can from the

heap of wealth that fools create for rogues to grow fat on; or better

still, let us as speedily as possible find some means of dying like men,

since we are forbidden to live like men.

Rather, however, take courage, and believe that we of this age, in spite

of all its torment and disorder, have been born to a wonderful heritage

fashioned of the work of those that have gone before us; and that the

day of the organization of man is dawning. It is not we who can build up

the new social order; the past ages have done the most of that work for

us; but we can clear our eyes to the signs of the times, and we shall

then see that the attainment of a good condition of life is being made

possible for us, and that it is now our business to stretch out our

hands to take it.

And how? Chiefly, I think, by educating people to a sense of their real

capacities as men, so that they may be able to use to their own good the

political power which is rapidly being thrust upon them; to get them to

see that the old system of organizing labour for individual profit is

becoming unmanageable, and that the whole people have now got to choose

between the confusion resulting from the break up of that system and the

determination to take in hand the labour now organized for profit, and

use its organization for the livelihood of the community: to get people

to see that individual profit-makers are not a necessity for labour but

an obstruction to it, and that not only or chiefly because they are the

perpetual pensioners of labour, as they are, but rather because of the

waste which their existence as a class necessitates. All this we have to

teach people, when we have taught ourselves; and I admit that the work

is long and burdensome; as I began by saying, people have been made so

timorous of change by the terror of starvation that even the unluckiest

of them are stolid and hard to move. Hard as the work is, however, its

reward is not doubtful. The mere fact that a body of men, however small,

are banded together as Socialist missionaries shows that the change is

going on. As the working-classes, the real organic part of society, take

in these ideas, hope will arise in them, and they will claim changes in

society, many of which doubtless will not tend directly towards their

emancipation, because they will be claimed without due knowledge of the

one thing necessary to claim, equality of condition; but which

indirectly will help to break up our rotten sham society, while that

claim for equality of condition will be made constantly and with growing

loudness till it must be listened to, and then at last it will only be a

step over the border and the civilized world will be socialized; and,

looking back on what has been, we shall be astonished to think of how

long we submitted to live as we live now.

Whigs, Democrats, and Socialists Read at the Conference convened by

the Fabian Society at South Place Institute, June 11, 1886.

What is the state of parties in England to-day? How shall we enumerate

them? The Whigs, who stand first on the list in my title, are considered

generally to be the survival of an old historical party once looked on

as having democratic tendencies, but now the hope of all who would stand

soberly on the ancient ways. Besides these, there are Tories also, the

descendants of the stout defenders of Church and State and the divine

right of kings.

Now, I don’t mean to say but that at the back of this ancient name of

Tory there lies a great mass of genuine Conservative feeling, held by

people who, if they had their own way, would play some rather fantastic

tricks, I fancy; nay, even might in the course of time be somewhat rough

with such people as are in this hall at present. [2] But this feeling,

after all, is only a sentiment now; all practical hope has died out of

it, and these worthy people cannot have their own way. It is true that

they elect members of Parliament, who talk very big to please them, and

sometimes even they manage to get a Government into power that nominally

represents their sentiment, but when that happens the said Government is

forced, even when its party has a majority in the House of Commons, to

take a much lower standpoint than the high Tory ideal; the utmost that

the real Tory party can do, even when backed by the Primrose League and

its sham hierarchy, is to delude the electors to return Tories to

Parliament to pass measures more akin to Radicalism than the Whigs durst

attempt, so that, though there are Tories, there is no Tory party in

England.

On the other hand, there is a party, which I can call for the present by

no other name than Whig, which is both numerous and very powerful, and

which does, in fact, govern England, and to my mind will always do so as

long as the present constitutional Parliament lasts. Of course, like all

parties it includes men of various shades of opinion, from the

Tory-tinted Whiggery of Lord Salisbury to the Radical-tinted Whiggery of

Mr. Chamberlain’s present tail. Neither do I mean to say that they are

conscious of being a united party; on the contrary, the groups will

sometimes oppose each other furiously at elections, and perhaps the more

simple-minded of them really think that it is a matter of importance to

the nation which section of them may be in power; but they may always be

reckoned upon to be in their places and vote against any measure which

carries with it a real attack on our constitutional system; surely very

naturally, since they are there for no other purpose than to do so. They

are, and always must be, conscious defenders of the present system,

political and economical, as long as they have any cohesion as Tories,

Whigs, Liberals, or even Radicals. Not one of them probably would go

such a very short journey towards revolution as the abolition of the

House of Lords. A one-chamber Parliament would seem to them an impious

horror, and the abolition of the monarchy they would consider a serious

inconvenience to the London tradesman.

Now this is the real Parliamentary Party, at present divided into

jarring sections under the influence of the survival of the party

warfare of the last few generations, but which already shows signs of

sinking its differences so as to offer a solid front of resistance to

the growing instinct which on its side will before long result in a

party claiming full economical as well as political freedom for the

whole people.

But is there nothing in Parliament, or seeking entrance to it, except

this variously tinted Whiggery, this Harlequin of Reaction? Well, inside

Parliament, setting aside the Irish party, which is, we may now well

hope, merely temporarily there, there is not much. It is not among

people of “wealth and local influence,” who I see are supposed to be the

only available candidates for Parliament of a recognized party, that you

will find the elements of revolution. We will grant that there are some

few genuine Democrats there, and let them pass. But outside there are

undoubtedly many who are genuine Democrats, and who have it in their

heads that it is both possible and desirable to capture the

constitutional Parliament and turn it into a real popular assembly,

which, with the people behind it, might lead us peaceably and

constitutionally into the great Revolution which all thoughtful men

desire to bring about; all thoughtful men, that is, who do not belong to

the consciously cynical Tories, i.e., men determined, whether it be just

or unjust, good for humanity or bad for it, to keep the people down as

long as they can, which they hope, very naturally, will be as long as

they live.

To capture Parliament and turn it into a popular but constitutional

assembly is, I must conclude, the aspiration of the genuine Democrats

wherever they may be found; that is their idea of the first step of the

Democratic policy. The questions to be asked of this, as of all other

policies, are first, What is the end proposed by it? and secondly, Are

they likely to succeed? As to the end proposed, I think there is much

difference of opinion. Some Democrats would answer from the merely

political point of view, and say: Universal suffrage, payment of

members, annual Parliaments, abolition of the House of Lords, abolition

of the monarchy, and so forth. I would answer this by saying: After all,

these are not ends, but means to an end; and passing by the fact that

the last two are not constitutional measures, and so could not be

brought about without actual rebellion, I would say if you had gained

all these things, and more, all you would have done would have been to

establish the ascendancy of the Democratic party; having so established

it, you would then have to find out by the usual party means what that

Democratic party meant, and you would find that your triumph in mere

politics would lead you back again exactly to the place you started

from. You would be Whigs under a different name. Monarchy, House of

Lords, pensions, standing army, and the rest of it, are only supports to

the present social system — the privilege based on the wages and capital

system of production — and are worth nothing except as supports to it.

If you are determined to support that system, therefore, you had better

leave these things alone. The real masters of Society, the real tyrants

of the people, are the Landlords and Capitalists, whom your political

triumph would not interfere with.

Then, as now, there would be a proletariat and a moneyed class. Then, as

now, it would be possible sometimes for a diligent, energetic man, with

his mind set wholly on such success, to climb out of the proletariat

into the moneyed class, there to sweat as he once was sweated; which, my

friends, is, if you will excuse the word, your ridiculous idea of

freedom of contract.

The sole and utmost success of your policy would be that it might raise

up a strong opposition to the condition of things which it would be your

function to uphold; but most probably such opposition would still be

outside Parliament, and not in it; you would have made a revolution,

probably not without bloodshed, only to show people the necessity for

another revolution the very next day.

Will you think the example of America too trite? Anyhow, consider it! A

country with universal suffrage, no king, no House of Lords, no

privilege as you fondly think; only a little standing army, chiefly used

for the murder of red-skins; a democracy after your model; and with all

that, a society corrupt to the core, and at this moment engaged in

suppressing freedom with just the same reckless brutality and blind

ignorance as the Czar of all the Russias uses. [3]

But it will be said, and certainly with much truth, that not all the

Democrats are for mere political reform. I say that I believe that this

is true, and it is a very important truth too. I will go farther, and

will say that all those Democrats who can be distinguished from Whigs do

intend social reforms which they hope will somewhat alter the relations

of the classes towards each other; and there is, generally speaking,

amongst Democrats a leaning towards a kind of limited State-Socialism,

and it is through that that they hope to bring about a peaceful

revolution, which, if it does not introduce a condition of equality,

will at least make the workers better off and contented with their lot.

They hope to get a body of representatives elected to Parliament, and by

them to get measure after measure passed which will tend towards this

goal; nor would some of them, perhaps most of them, be discontented if

by this means we could glide into complete State-Socialism. I think that

the present Democrats are widely tinged with this idea, and to me it is

a matter of hope that it is so; whatever of error there is in it, it

means advance beyond the complete barrenness of the mere political

programme.

Yet I must point out to these semi-Socialist Democrats that in the first

place they will be made the cat’s-paw of some of the wilier of the

Whigs. There are several of these measures which look to some

Socialistic, as, for instance, the allotments scheme, and other schemes

tending toward peasant proprietorship, co-operation, and the like, but

which after all, in spite of their benevolent appearance, are really

weapons in the hands of reactionaries, having for their real object the

creation of a new middle-class made out of the working-class and at

their expense; the raising, in short, of a new army against the attack

of the disinherited.

There is no end to this kind of dodge, nor will be apparently till there

is an end of the class which tries it on; and a great many of the

Democrats will be amused and absorbed by it from time to time. They call

this sort of nonsense “practical;” it seems like doing something, while

the steady propaganda of a principle which must prevail in the end is,

according to them, doing nothing, and is unpractical. For the rest, it

is not likely to become dangerous, further than as it clogs the wheels

of the real movement somewhat, because it is sometimes a mere piece of

reaction, as when, for instance, it takes the form of peasant

proprietorship, flying right in the face of the commercial development

of the day, which tends ever more and more towards the aggregation of

capital, thereby smoothing the way for the organized possession of the

means of production by the workers when the true revolution shall come:

while, on the other hand, when this attempt to manufacture a new

middle-class takes the form of co-operation and the like, it is not

dangerous, because it means nothing more than a slightly altered form of

joint-stockery, and everybody almost is beginning to see this. The greed

of men stimulated by the spectacle of profit-making all around them, and

also by the burden of the interest on the money which they have been

obliged to borrow, will not allow them even to approach a true system of

co-operation. Those benefited by the transaction presently become eager

shareholders in a commercial speculation, and if they are working-men,

as they often are, they are also capitalists. The enormous commercial

success of the great co-operative societies, and the absolute no-effect

of that success on the social conditions of the workers, are sufficient

tokens of what this non-political co-operation must come to: “Nothing —

it shall not be less.”

But again, it may be said, some of the Democrats go farther than this;

they take up actual pieces of Socialism, and are more than inclined to

support them. Nationalization of the land, or of railways, or cumulative

taxation on incomes, or limiting the right of inheritance, or new

factory laws, or the restriction by law of the day’s labour — one of

these, or more than one sometimes, the Democrats will support, and see

absolute salvation in these one or two planks of the platform. All this

I admit, and once again say it is a hopeful sign, and yet once again I

say there is a snare in it — a snake lies lurking in the grass.

Those who think that they can deal with our present system in this

piecemeal way very much underrate the strength of the tremendous

organization under which we live, and which appoints to each of us his

place, and if we do not chance to fit it, grinds us down till we do.

Nothing but a tremendous force can deal with this force; it will not

suffer itself to be dismembered, nor to lose anything which really is

its essence without putting forth all its force in resistance; rather

than lose anything which it considers of importance, it will pull the

roof of the world down upon its head. For, indeed, I grant these

semi-Socialist Democrats that there is one hope for their tampering

piecemeal with our Society; if by chance they can excite people into

seriously, however blindly, claiming one or other of these things in

question, and could be successful in Parliament in driving it through,

they would certainly draw on a great civil war, and such a war once let

loose would not end but either with the full triumph of Socialism or its

extinction for the present; it would be impossible to limit the aim of

the struggle; nor can we even guess at the course which it would take,

except that it could not be a matter of compromise. But suppose the

Democratic party peaceably successful on this new basis of semi-State

Socialism, what would it all mean? Attempts to balance the two classes

whose interests are opposed to each other, a mere ignoring of this

antagonism which has led us through so many centuries to where we are

now, and then, after a period of disappointment and disaster, the naked

conflict once more; a revolution made, and another immediately necessary

on its morrow!

Yet, indeed, it will not come to that; for, whatever may be the aims of

the Democrats, they will not succeed in getting themselves into a

position from whence they could make the attempt to realize them. I have

said there are Tories and yet no real Tory party; so also it seems to me

that there are Democrats but no Democratic party; at present they are

used by the leaders of the parliamentary factions, and also kept at a

distance by them from any real power. If they by hook or crook managed

to get a number of members into Parliament, they would find out their

differences very speedily under the influence of party rule; in point of

fact, the Democrats are not a party; because they have no principles

other than the old Whig-Radical ones, extended in some cases so as to

take in a little semi-Socialism which the march of events has forced on

them — that is, they gravitate on one side to the Whigs and on the other

to the Socialists. Whenever, if ever, they begin to be a power in the

elections and get members in the House, the temptation to be members of

a real live party which may have the government of the country in its

hands, the temptation to what is (facetiously, I suppose) called

practical politics, will be too much for many, even of those who

gravitate towards Socialism; a quasi-Democratic parliamentary party,

therefore, would probably be merely a recruiting ground, a nursery for

the left wing of the Whigs; though it would indeed leave behind some

small nucleus of opposition, the principles of which, however, would be

vague and floating, so that it would be but a powerless group after all.

The future of the constitutional Parliament, therefore, it seems to me,

is a perpetual Whig Rump, which will yield to pressure when mere

political reforms are attempted to be got out of it, but will be quite

immovable towards any real change in social and economical matters; that

is to say, so far as it may be conscious of the attack; for I grant that

it may be betrayed into passing semi-State-Socialistic measures, which

will do this amount of good, that they will help to entangle commerce in

difficulties, and so add to discontent by creating suffering; suffering

of which the people will not understand the causes definitely, but which

their instinct will tell them truly is brought about by government, and

that, too, the only kind of government which they can have so long as

the constitutional Parliament lasts.

Now, if you think I have exaggerated the power of the Whigs, that is, of

solid, dead, unmoving resistance to progress, I must call your attention

to the events of the last few weeks. Here has been a measure of

pacification proposed; at the least and worst an attempt to enter upon a

pacification of a weary and miserable quarrel many centuries old. The

British people, in spite of their hereditary prejudice against the

Irish, were not averse to the measure; the Tories were, as usual,

powerless against it; yet so strong has been the vis inertiae of

Whiggery that it has won a notable victory over common-sense and

sentiment combined, and has drawn over to it a section of those hitherto

known as Radicals, and probably would have drawn all Radicals over but

for the personal ascendancy of Mr. Gladstone. The Whigs, seeing, if but

dimly, that this Irish Independence meant an attack on property, have

been successful in snatching the promised peace out of the people’s

hands, and in preparing all kinds of entanglement and confusion for us

for a long while in their steady resistance to even the beginnings of

revolution.

This, therefore, is what Parliament looks to me: a solid central party,

with mere nebulous opposition on the right hand and on the left. The

people governed; that is to say, fair play amongst themselves for the

money-privileged classes to make the most of their privilege, and to

fight sturdily with each other in doing so; but the government concealed

as much as possible, and also as long as possible; that is to say, the

government resting on an assumed necessary eternity of privilege to

monopolize the means of the fructification of labour.

For so long as that assumption is accepted by the ignorance of the

people, the Great Whig Rump will remain inexpugnable, but as soon as the

people’s eyes are opened, even partially — and they begin to understand

the meaning of the words, the Emancipation of Labour — we shall begin to

have an assured hope of throwing off the basest and most sordid tyranny

which the world has yet seen, the tyranny of so-called

Constitutionalism.

How, then, are the people’s eyes to be opened? By the force evolved from

the final triumph and consequent corruption of Commercial Whiggery,

which force will include in it a recognition of its constructive

activity by intelligent people on the one hand, and on the other

half-blind instinctive struggles to use its destructive activity on the

part of those who suffer and have not been allowed to think; and, to

boot, a great deal that goes between those two extremes.

In this turmoil, all those who can be truly called Socialists will be

involved. The modern development of the great class-struggle has forced

us to think, our thoughts force us to speak, and our hopes force us to

try to get a hearing from the people. Nor can one tell how far our words

will carry, so to say. The most moderate exposition of our principles

will bear with it the seeds of disruption; nor can we tell what form

that disruption will take.

One and all, then, we are responsible for the enunciation of Socialist

principles and of the consequences which may flow from their general

acceptance, whatever that may be. This responsibility no Socialist can

shake off by declarations against physical force and in favour of

constitutional methods of agitation; we are attacking the Constitution

with the very beginnings, the mere lispings, of Socialism.

Whiggery, therefore, in its various forms, is the representative of

Constitutionalism — is the outward expression of monopoly and consequent

artificial restraints on labour and life; and there is only one

expression of the force which will destroy Whiggery, and that is

Socialism; and on the right hand and on the left Toryism and Radicalism

will melt into Whiggery — are doing so now — and Socialism has got to

absorb all that is not Whig in Radicalism.

Then comes the question, What is the policy of Socialism? If Toryism and

Democracy are only nebulous masses of opposition to the solid centre of

Whiggery, what can we call Socialism?

Well, at present, in England at least, Socialism is not a party, but a

sect. That is sometimes brought against it as a taunt; but I am not

dismayed by it; for I can conceive of a sect — nay, I have heard of one

— becoming a very formidable power, and becoming so by dint of its long

remaining a sect. So I think it is quite possible that Socialism will

remain a sect till the very eve of the last stroke that completes the

revolution, after which it will melt into the new Society. And is it not

sects, bodies of definite, uncompromising principles, that lead us into

revolutions? Was it not so in the Cromwellian times? Nay, have not the

Fenian sect, even in our own days, made Home Rule possible? They may

give birth to parties, though not parties themselves. And what should a

sect like we are have to do in the parliamentary struggle — we who have

an ideal to keep always before ourselves and others, and who cannot

accept compromise; who can see nothing that can give us rest for a

minute save the emancipation of labour, which will be brought about by

the workers gaining possession of all the means of the fructification of

labour; and who, even when that is gained, shall have pure Communism

ahead to strive for?

What are we to do, then? Stand by and look on? Not exactly. Yet we may

look on other people doing their work while we do ours. They are already

beginning, as I have said, to stumble about with attempts at State

Socialism. Let them make their experiments and blunders, and prepare the

way for us by so doing. And our own business? Well, we — sect or party,

or group of self-seekers, madmen, and poets, which you will — are at

least the only set of people who have been able to see that there is and

has been a great class-struggle going on. Further, we can see that this

class-struggle cannot come to an end till the classes themselves do: one

class must absorb the other. Which, then? Surely the useful one, the one

that the world lives by, and on. The business of the people at present

is to make it impossible for the useless, non-producing class to live;

while the business of Constitutionalism is, on the contrary, to make it

possible for them to live. And our business is to help to make the

people conscious of this great antagonism between the people and

Constitutionalism; and meantime to let Constitutionalism go on with its

government unhelped by us at least, until it at last becomes conscious

of its burden of the people’s hate, of the people’s knowledge that it is

disinherited, which we shall have done our best to further by any means

that we could.

As to Socialists in Parliament, there are two words about that. If they

go there to take a part in carrying on Constitutionalism by palliating

the evils of the system, and so helping our rulers to bear their burden

of government, I for one, and so far as their action therein goes,

cannot call them Socialists at all. But if they go there with the

intention of doing what they can towards the disruption of Parliament,

that is a matter of tactics for the time being; but even here I cannot

help seeing the danger of their being seduced from their true errand,

and I fear that they might become, on the terms above mentioned, simply

supporters of the very thing they set out to undo.

I say that our work lies quite outside Parliament, and it is to help to

educate the people by every and any means that may be effective; and the

knowledge we have to help them to is threefold — to know their own, to

know how to take their own, and to know how to use their own.

Feudal England

It is true that the Norman Conquest found a certain kind of feudality in

existence in England — a feudality which was developed from the customs

of the Teutonic tribes with no admixture of Roman law; and also that

even before the Conquest this country was slowly beginning to be mixed

up with the affairs of the Continent of Europe, and that not only with

the kindred nations of Scandinavia, but with the Romanized countries

also. But the Conquest of Duke William did introduce the complete Feudal

system into the country; and it also connected it by strong bonds to the

Romanized countries, and yet by so doing laid the first foundations of

national feeling in England. The English felt their kinship with the

Norsemen or the Danes, and did not suffer from their conquests when they

had become complete, and when, consequently, mere immediate violence had

disappeared from them; their feeling was tribal rather than national;

but they could have no sense of tribal unity with the varied populations

of the provinces which mere dynastical events had strung together into

the dominion, the manor, one may say, of the foreign princes of Normandy

and Anjou; and, as the kings who ruled them gradually got pushed out of

their French possessions, England began to struggle against the

domination of men felt to be foreigners, and so gradually became

conscious of her separate nationality, though still only in a fashion,

as the manor of an English lord.

It is beyond the scope of this piece to give anything like a connected

story, even of the slightest, of the course of events between the

conquest of Duke William and the fully developed mediaeval period of the

fourteenth century, which is the England that I have before my eyes as

Mediaeval or Feudal. That period of the fourteenth century united the

developments of the elements which had been stirring in Europe since the

final fall of the Roman Empire, and England shared in the general

feeling and spirit of the age, although, from its position, the course

of its history, and to a certain extent the lives of its people, were

different. It is to this period, therefore, that I wish in the long run

to call your attention, and I will only say so much about the earlier

period as may be necessary to explain how the people of England got into

the position in which they were found by the Statute of Labourers

enacted by Edward III., and the Peasants’ Rebellion in the time of his

grandson and successor, Richard II.

Undoubtedly, then, the Norman Conquest made a complete break in the

continuity of the history of England. When the Londoners after the

Battle of Hastings accepted Duke William for their king, no doubt they

thought of him as occupying much the same position as that of the newly

slain Harold; or at any rate they looked on him as being such a king of

England as Knut the Dane, who had also conquered the country; and

probably William himself thought no otherwise; but the event was quite

different; for on the one hand, not only was he a man of strong

character, able, masterful, and a great soldier in the modern sense of

the word, but he had at his back his wealthy dukedom of Normandy, which

he had himself reduced to obedience and organized; and, on the other

hand, England lay before him, unorganized, yet stubbornly rebellious to

him; its very disorganization and want of a centre making it more

difficult to deal with by merely overrunning it with an army levied for

that purpose, and backed by a body of house-carles or guards, which

would have been the method of a Scandinavian or native king in dealing

with his rebellious subjects. Duke William’s necessities and instincts

combined led him into a very different course of action, which

determined the future destiny of the country. What he did was to quarter

upon England an army of feudal vassals drawn from his obedient dukedom,

and to hand over to them the lordship of the land of England in return

for their military service to him, the suzerain of them all.

Thenceforward, it was under the rule of these foreign landlords that the

people of England had to develop.

The development of the country as a Teutonic people was checked and

turned aside by this event. Duke William brought, in fact, his Normandy

into England, which was thereby changed from a Teutonic people

(Old-Norse theod), with the tribal customary law still in use among

them, into a province of Romanized Feudal Europe, a piece of France, in

short; and though in time she did grow into another England again, she

missed for ever in her laws, and still more in her language and her

literature, the chance of developing into a great homogeneous Teutonic

people infused usefully with a mixture of Celtic blood.

However, this step which Duke William was forced to take further

influenced the future of the country by creating the great order of the

Baronage, and the history of the early period of England is pretty much

that of the struggle of the king with the Baronage and the Church. For

William fixed the type of the successful English mediaeval king, of whom

Henry II. and Edward I. were the most notable examples afterwards. It

was, in fact, with him that the struggle towards monarchical bureaucracy

began, which was checked by the barons, who extorted Magna Charta from

King John, and afterwards by the revolt headed by Simon de Montfort in

Henry III.‘s reign; was carried on vigorously by Edward I., and finally

successfully finished by Henry VII. after the long faction-fight of the

Wars of the Roses had weakened the feudal lords so much that they could

no longer assert themselves against the monarchy.

As to the other political struggle of the Middle Ages, the contest

between the Crown and the Church, two things are to be noted; first,

that at least in the earlier period the Church was on the popular side.

Thomas Beckett was canonized, it is true, formally and by regular

decree; but his memory was held so dear by the people that he would

probably have been canonized informally by them if the holy seat at Rome

had refused to do so. The second thing to be noted about the dispute is

this, that it was no contest of principle. According to the mediaeval

theory of life and religion, the Church and the State were one in

essence, and but separate manifestations of the Kingdom of God upon

earth, which was part of the Kingdom of God in heaven. The king was an

officer of that realm and a liegeman of God. The doctor of laws and the

doctor of physic partook in a degree of the priestly character. On the

other hand, the Church was not withdrawn from the every-day life of men;

the division into a worldly and spiritual life, neither of which had

much to do with the other, was a creation of the protestantism of the

Reformation, and had no place in the practice at least of the mediaeval

Church, which we cannot too carefully remember is little more

represented by modern Catholicism than by modern Protestantism. The

contest, therefore, between the Crown and the Church was a mere

bickering between two bodies, without any essential antagonism between

them, as to how far the administration of either reached; neither

dreamed of subordinating one to the other, far less of extinguishing one

by the other.

The history of the Crusades, by-the-way, illustrates very emphatically

this position of the Church in the Middle Ages. The foundation of that

strange feudal kingdom of Jerusalem, whose very coat of arms was a

solecism in heraldry, whose king had precedence, in virtue of his place

as lord of the centre of Christianity, over all other kings and princes;

the orders of men-at-arms vowed to poverty and chastity, like the

Templars and Knights of St. John; and above all the unquestioning sense

of duty that urged men of all classes and kinds into the holy war, show

how strongly the idea of God’s Kingdom on the earth had taken hold of

all men’s minds in the early Middle Ages. As to the result of the

Crusades, they certainly had their influence on the solidification of

Europe and the great feudal system, at the head of which, in theory at

least, were the Pope and the Kaiser. For the rest, the intercourse with

the East gave Europe an opportunity of sharing in the mechanical

civilization of the peoples originally dominated by the Arabs, and

infused by the art of Byzantium and Persia, not without some tincture of

the cultivation of the latter classical period.

The stir and movement also of the Crusades, and the necessities in which

they involved the princes and their barons, furthered the upward

movement of the classes that lay below the feudal vassals, great and

little; the principal opportunity for which movement, however, in

England, was given by the continuous struggle between the Crown and the

Church and Baronage.

The early Norman kings, even immediately after the death of the

Conqueror, found themselves involved in this struggle, and were forced

to avail themselves of the help of what had now become the inferior

tribe — the native English, to wit. Henry I., an able and ambitious man,

understood this so clearly that he made a distinct bid for the favour of

the inferior tribe by marrying an English princess; and it was by means

of the help of his English subjects that he conquered his Norman

subjects, and the field of Tenchebray, which put the coping-stone on his

success, was felt by the English people as an English victory over the

oppressing tribe with which Duke William had overwhelmed the English

people. It was during this king’s reign and under these influences that

the trading and industrial classes began to rise somewhat. The merchant

gilds were now in their period of greatest power, and had but just

begun, in England at least, to develop into the corporations of the

towns; but the towns themselves were beginning to gain their freedom and

to become an important element in the society of the time, as little by

little they asserted themselves against the arbitrary rule of the feudal

lords, lay or ecclesiastical: for as to the latter, it must be

remembered that the Church included in herself the orders or classes

into which lay society was divided, and while by its lower clergy of the

parishes and by the friars it touched the people, its upper clergy were

simply feudal lords; and as the religious fervour of the higher clergy,

which was marked enough in the earlier period of the Middle Ages (in

Anselm, for example), faded out, they became more and more mere

landlords, although from the conditions of their landlordism, living as

they did on their land and amidst of their tenants, they were less

oppressive than the lay landlords.

The order and progress of Henry I.‘s reign, which marks the transition

from the mere military camp of the Conqueror to the mediaeval England I

have to dwell upon, was followed by the period of mere confusion and

misery which accompanied the accession of the princes of Anjou to the

throne of England. In this period the barons widely became mere violent

and illegal robbers; and the castles with which the land was dotted, and

which were begun under the auspices of the Conqueror as military posts,

became mere dens of strong-thieves.

No doubt this made the business of the next able king, Henry II., the

easier. He was a staunch man of business, and turned himself with his

whole soul towards the establishment of order and the consolidation of

the monarchy, which accordingly took a great stride under him towards

its ultimate goal of bureaucracy. He would probably have carried the

business still farther, since in his contest with the Church, in spite

of the canonization of Beckett and the king’s formal penance at his

tomb, he had in fact gained a victory for the Crown which it never

really lost again; but in his days England was only a part of the vast

dominion of his House, which included more than half of France, and his

struggle with his feudatories and the French king, which sowed the seed

of the loss of that dominion to the English Crown, took up much of his

life, and finally beat him.

His two immediate successors, Richard I. and John, were good specimens

of the chiefs of their line, almost all of whom were very able men,

having even a touch of genius in them, but therewithal were such wanton

blackguards and scoundrels that one is almost forced to apply the

theological word “wickedness” to them. Such characters belong specially

to their times, fertile as they were both of great qualities and of

scoundrelism, and in which our own special vice of hypocrisy was

entirely lacking. John, the second of these two pests, put the

coping-stone on the villany of his family, and lost his French dominion

in the lump.

Under such rascals as these came the turn of the Baronage; and they, led

by Stephen Langton, the archbishop who had been thrust on the unwilling

king by the Pope, united together and forced from him his assent to

Magna Charta, the great, thoroughly well-considered deed, which is

conventionally called the foundation of English Liberty, but which can

only claim to be so on the ground that it was the confirmation and seal

of the complete feudal system in England, and put the relations between

the vassals, the great feudatories, and the king on a stable basis;

since it created, or at least confirmed, order among these privileged

classes, among whom, indeed, it recognized the towns to a certain extent

as part of the great feudal hierarchy: so that even by this time they

had begun to acquire status in that hierarchy.

So John passed away, and became not long after an almost mythical

personage, the type of the bad king. There are still ballads, and prose

stories deduced from these ballads, in existence, which tell the tale of

this strange monster as the English people imagined it.

As they belong to the literature of the fourteenth century, the period I

have undertaken to tell you about specially, I will give you one of the

latter of these concerning the death of King John, for whom the people

imagined a more dramatic cause of death than mere indigestion, of which

in all probability he really died; and you may take it for a specimen of

popular literature of the fourteenth century.

I can here make bold to quote from memory, without departing very widely

from the old text, since the quaint wording of the original, and the

spirit of bold and blunt heroism which it breathes, have fixed it in my

mind for ever.

The king, you must remember, had halted at Swinestead Abbey, in

Lincolnshire, in his retreat from the hostile barons and their French

allies, and had lost all his baggage by the surprise of the advancing

tide in the Wash; so that he might well be in a somewhat sour mood.

Says the tale: So the king went to meat in the hall, and before him was

a loaf; and he looked grimly on it and said, ‘For how much is such a

loaf sold in this realm?’

‘Sir, for one penny,’ said they.

Then the king smote the board with his fist and said, ‘By God, if I live

for one year such a loaf shall be sold for twelve pence!’

That heard one of the monks who stood thereby, and he thought and

considered that his hour and time to die was come, and that it would be

a good deed to slay so cruel a king and so evil a lord.

So he went into the garden and plucked plums and took out of them the

steles [stalks], and did venom in them each one; and he came before the

king and sat on his knee, and said:

‘Sir, by St. Austin, this is fruit of our garden.’

Then the king looked evilly on him and said, ‘Assay them, monk!’

So the monk took and ate thereof, nor changed countenance any whit: and

the king ate thereafter.

But presently afterwards the monk swelled and turned blue, and fell down

and died before the king: then waxed the king sick at heart, and he also

swelled and died, and so he ended his days.

For a while after the death of John and the accession of Henry III. the

Baronage, strengthened by the great Charter and with a weak and wayward

king on the throne, made their step forward in power and popularity, and

the first serious check to the tendency to monarchical bureaucracy, a

kind of elementary aristocratic constitution, was imposed upon the

weakness of Henry III. Under this movement of the barons, who in their

turn had to seek for the support of the people, the towns made a fresh

step in advance, and Simon de Montfort, the leader of what for want of a

better word must be called the popular party, was forced by his

circumstances to summon to his Parliament citizens from the boroughs.

Earl Simon was one of those men that come to the front in violent times,

and he added real nobility of character to strength of will and

persistence. He became the hero of the people, who went near to

canonizing him after his death. But the monarchy was too strong for him

and his really advanced projects, which by no means squared with the

hopes of the Baronage in general: and when Prince Edward, afterwards

Edward I., grown to his full mental stature, came to the help of the

Crown with his unscrupulous business ability, the struggle was soon

over; and with Evesham field the monarchy began to take a new stride,

and the longest yet taken, towards bureaucracy.

Edward I. is remembered by us chiefly for the struggle he carried on

with the Scotch Baronage for the feudal suzerainty of that kingdom, and

the centuries of animosity between the two countries which that struggle

drew on. But he has other claims to our attention besides this.

At first, and remembering the ruthlessness of many of his acts,

especially in the Scotch war, one is apt to look upon him as a somewhat

pedantic tyrant and a good soldier, with something like a dash of

hypocrisy beyond his time added. But, like the Angevine kings I was

speaking of just now, he was a completely characteristic product of his

time. He was not a hypocrite probably, after all, in spite of his tears

shed after he had irretrievably lost a game, or after he had won one by

stern cruelty. There was a dash of real romance in him, which mingled

curiously with his lawyer-like qualities. He was, perhaps, the man of

all men who represented most completely the finished feudal system, and

who took it most to heart. His law, his romance, and his religion, his

self-command, and his terrible fury were all a part of this innate

feudalism, and exercised within its limits; and we must suppose that he

thoroughly felt his responsibility as the chief of his feudatories,

while at the same time he had no idea of his having any responsibilities

towards the lower part of his subjects. Such a man was specially suited

to carrying on the tendency to bureaucratic centralization, which

culminated in the Tudor monarchy. He had his struggle with the Baronage,

but hard as it was, he was sure not to carry it beyond the due limits of

feudalism; to that he was always loyal. He had slain Earl Simon before

he was king, while he was but his father’s general; but Earl Simon’s

work did not die with him, and henceforward, while the Middle Ages and

their feudal hierarchy lasted, it was impossible for either king or

barons to do anything which would seriously injure each other’s

position; the struggle ended in his reign in a balance of power in

England which, on the one hand, prevented any great feudatory becoming a

rival of the king, as happened in several instances in France, and on

the other hand prevented the king lapsing into a mere despotic monarch.

I have said that bureaucracy took a great stride in Edward’s reign, but

it reached its limits under feudalism as far as the nobles were

concerned. Peace and order was established between the different powers

of the governing classes; henceforward, the struggle is between them and

the governed; that struggle was now to become obvious; the lower tribe

was rising in importance; it was becoming richer for fleecing, but also

it was beginning to have some power; this led the king first, and

afterwards the barons, to attack it definitely; it was rich enough to

pay for the trouble of being robbed, and not yet strong enough to defend

itself with open success, although the slower and less showy success of

growth did not fail it. The instrument of attack in the hands of the

barons was the ordinary feudal privilege, the logical carrying out of

serfdom; but this attack took place two reigns later. We shall come to

that further on. The attack on the lower tribe which was now growing

into importance was in this reign made by the king; and his instrument

was — Parliament.

I have told you that Simon de Montfort made some attempt to get the

burgesses to sit in his Parliament, but it was left to Edward I. to lay

the foundations firmly of parliamentary representation, which he used

for the purpose of augmenting the power of the Crown and crushing the

rising liberty of the towns, though of course his direct aim was simply

at — money.

The Great Council of the Realm was purely feudal; it was composed of the

feudatories of the king, theoretically of all of them, practically of

the great ones only. It was, in fact, the council of the conquering

tribe with their chief at its head; the matters of the due feudal

tribute, aids, reliefs, fines, scutage, and the like — in short, the

king’s revenue due from his men — were settled in this council at once

and in the lump. But the inferior tribe, though not represented there,

existed, and, as aforesaid, was growing rich, and the king had to get

their money out of their purses directly; which, as they were not

represented at the council, he had to do by means of his officers (the

sheriffs) dealing with them one after another, which was a troublesome

job; for the men were stiff-necked and quite disinclined to part with

their money; and the robbery having to be done on the spot, so to say,

encountered all sorts of opposition: and, in fact, it was the money

needs both of baron, bishop, and king which had been the chief

instrument in furthering the progress of the towns. The towns would be

pressed by their lords, king, or baron, or bishop, as it might be, and

they would see their advantage and strike a bargain. For you are not to

imagine that because there was a deal of violence going on in those

times there was no respect for law; on the contrary, there was a quite

exaggerated respect for it if it came within the four corners of the

feudal feeling, and the result of this feeling of respect was the

constant struggle for status on the part of the townships and other

associations throughout the Middle Ages.

Well, the burghers would say, “‘Tis hard to pay this money, but we will

put ourselves out to pay it if you will do something for us in return;

let, for example, our men be tried in our own court, and the verdict be

of one of compurgation instead of wager of battle,” and so forth, and so

forth.

All this sort of detailed bargaining was, in fact, a safeguard for the

local liberties, so far as they went, of the towns and shires, and did

not suit the king’s views of law and order at all; and so began the

custom of the sheriff (the king’s officer, who had taken the place of

the earl of the Anglo-Saxon period) summoning the burgesses to the

council, which burgesses you must understand were not elected at the

folkmotes of the town, or hundred, but in a sort of hole-and-corner way

by a few of the bigger men of the place. What the king practically said

was this: “I want your money, and I cannot be for ever wrangling with

you stubborn churles at home there, and listening to all your stories of

how poor you are, and what you want; no, I want you to be represented.

Send me up from each one of your communes a man or two whom I can bully

or cajole or bribe to sign away your substance for you.”

Under these circumstances it is no wonder that the towns were not very

eager in the cause of representation. It was no easy job to get them to

come up to London merely to consult as to the kind of sauce with which

they were to be eaten. However, they did come in some numbers, and by

the year 1295 something like a shadow of our present Parliament was on

foot. Nor need there be much more said about this institution; as time

went on its functions got gradually extended by the petition for the

redress of grievances accompanying the granting of money, but it was

generally to be reckoned on as subservient to the will of the king, who

down to the later Tudor period played some very queer tunes on this

constitutional instrument.

Edward I. gave place to his son, who again was of the type of king who

had hitherto given the opportunity to the barons for their turn of

advancement in the constitutional struggle; and in earlier times no

doubt they would have taken full advantage of the circumstances; as it

was they had little to gain. The king did his best to throw off the

restraint of the feudal constitution, and to govern simply as an

absolute monarch. After a time of apparent success he failed, of course,

and only succeeded in confirming the legal rights of feudalism by

bringing about his own formal deposition at the hands of the Baronage,

as a chief who, having broken the compact with his feudatories, had

necessarily forfeited his right. If we compare his case with that of

Charles I. we shall find this difference in it, besides the obvious one

that Edward was held responsible to his feudatories and Charles towards

the upper middle classes, the squirearchy, as represented by Parliament;

that Charles was condemned by a law created for the purpose, so to say,

and evolved from the principle of the representation of the propertied

classes, while Edward’s deposition was the real logical outcome of the

confirmed feudal system, and was practically legal and regular.

The successor of the deposed king, the third Edward, ushers in the

complete and central period of the Middle Ages in England. The feudal

system is complete: the life and spirit of the country has developed

into a condition if not quite independent, yet quite forgetful, on the

one hand of the ideas and customs of the Celtic and Teutonic tribes, and

on the other of the authority of the Roman Empire. The Middle Ages have

grown into manhood; that manhood has an art of its own, which, though

developed step by step from that of Old Rome and New Rome, and embracing

the strange mysticism and dreamy beauty of the East, has forgotten both

its father and its mother, and stands alone triumphant, the loveliest,

brightest, and gayest of all the creations of the human mind and hand.

It has a literature of its own too, somewhat akin to its art, yet

inferior to it, and lacking its unity, since there is a double stream in

it. On the one hand is the court poet, the gentleman, Chaucer, with his

Italianizing metres, and his formal recognition of the classical

stories; on which, indeed, he builds a superstructure of the quaintest

and most unadulterated mediaevalism, as gay and bright as the

architecture which his eyes beheld and his pen pictured for us, so

clear, defined, and elegant it is; a sunny world even amidst its

violence and passing troubles, like those of a happy child, the worst of

them an amusement rather than a grief to the onlookers; a world that

scarcely needed hope in its eager life of adventure and love, amidst the

sunlit blossoming meadows, and green woods, and white begilded

manor-houses. A kindly and human muse is Chaucer’s, nevertheless,

interested in and amused by all life, but of her very nature devoid of

strong aspirations for the future; and that all the more, since, though

the strong devotion and fierce piety of the ruder Middle Ages had by

this time waned, and the Church was more often lightly mocked at than

either feared or loved, still the habit of looking on this life as part

of another yet remained: the world is fair and full of adventure; kind

men and true and noble are in it to make one happy; fools also to laugh

at, and rascals to be resisted, yet not wholly condemned; and when this

world is over we shall still go on living in another which is a part of

this. Look at all the picture, note all and live in all, and be as merry

as you may, never forgetting that you are alive and that it is good to

live.

That is the spirit of Chaucer’s poetry; but alongside of it existed yet

the ballad poetry of the people, wholly untouched by courtly elegance

and classical pedantry; rude in art but never coarse, true to the

backbone; instinct with indignation against wrong, and thereby

expressing the hope that was in it; a protest of the poor against the

rich, especially in those songs of the Foresters, which have been called

the mediaeval epic of revolt; no more gloomy than the gentleman’s

poetry, yet cheerful from courage, and not content. Half a dozen stanzas

of it are worth a cartload of the whining introspective lyrics of

to-day; and he who, when he has mastered the slight differences of

language from our own daily speech, is not moved by it, does not

understand what true poetry means nor what its aim is.

There is a third element in the literature of this time which you may

call Lollard poetry, the great example of which is William Langland’s

“Piers Plowman.” It is no bad corrective to Chaucer, and in form at

least belongs wholly to the popular side; but it seems to me to show

symptoms of the spirit of the rising middle class, and casts before it

the shadow of the new master that was coming forward for the workman’s

oppression. But I must leave what more I have to say on this subject of

the art and literature of the fourteenth century for another occasion.

In what I have just said, I only wanted to point out to you that the

Middle Ages had by this time come to the fullest growth; and that they

could express in a form which was all their own, the ideas and life of

the time.

That time was in a sense brilliant and progressive, and the life of the

worker in it was better than it ever had been, and might compare with

advantage with what it became in after periods and with what it is now;

and indeed, looking back upon it, there are some minds and some moods

that cannot help regretting it, and are not particularly scared by the

idea of its violence and its lack of accurate knowledge of scientific

detail.

However, one thing is clear to us now, the kind of thing which never is

clear to most people living in such periods — namely, that whatever it

was, it could not last, but must change into something else.

The complete feudalism of the fourteenth century fell, as systems always

fall, by its own corruption, and by development of the innate seeds of

change, some of which indeed had lain asleep during centuries, to wake

up into activity long after the events which had created them were

forgotten.

The feudal system was naturally one of open war; and the alliances,

marriages, and other dealings, family with family, made by the king and

potentates, were always leading them into war by giving them legal

claims, or at least claims that could be legally pleaded, to the domains

of other lords, who took advantage of their being on the spot, of their

strength in men or money, or their popularity with the Baronage, to give

immediate effect to their claims. Such a war was that by which Edward I.

drew on England the enmity of the Scotch; and such again was the great

war which Edward III. entered into with France. You must not suppose

that there was anything in this war of a national, far less of a race,

character. The last series of wars before this time I am now speaking

of, in which race feelings counted for much, was the Crusades. This

French war, I say, was neither national, racial, or tribal; it was the

private business of a lord of the manor, claiming what he considered his

legal rights of another lord, who had, as he thought, usurped them; and

this claim his loyal feudatories were bound to take up for him; loyalty

to a feudal superior, not patriotism to a country, was the virtue which

Edward III.‘s soldiers had to offer, if they had any call to be virtuous

in that respect.

This war once started was hard to drop, partly because of the success

that Edward had in it, falling as he did on France with the force of a

country so much more homogeneous than it; and no doubt it was a war very

disastrous to both countries, and so may be reckoned as amongst the

causes which broke up the feudal system.

But the real causes of that break-up lay much deeper than that. The

system was not capable of expansion in production; it was, in fact, as

long as its integrity remained untouched, an army fed by slaves, who

could not be properly and closely exploited; its free men proper might

do something else in their leisure, and so produce art and literature,

but their true business as members of a conquering tribe, their

concerted business, was to fight. There was, indeed, a fringe of people

between the serf and the free noble who produced the matters of

handicraft which were needed for the latter, but deliberately, and, as

we should now think, wastefully; and as these craftsmen and traders

began to grow into importance and to push themselves, as they could not

help doing, into the feudal hierarchy, as they acquired status, so the

sickness of the feudal system increased on it, and the shadow of the

coming commercialism fell upon it.

That any set of people who could claim to be other than the property of

free men should not have definite rights differentiated sharply from

those of other groups, was an idea that did not occur to the Middle

Ages; therefore, as soon as men came into existence that were not serfs

and were not nobles, they had to struggle for status by organizing

themselves into associations that should come to be acknowledged members

of the great feudal hierarchy; for indefinite and negative freedom was

not allowed to any person in those days; if you had not status you did

not exist except as an outlaw.

This is, briefly speaking, the motive power of necessity that lay behind

the struggle of the town corporations and craft-gilds to be free, a

struggle which, though it was to result in the breaking up of the

mediaeval hierarchy, began by an appearance of strengthening it by

adding to its members, increasing its power of production, and so making

it more stable for the time being.

About this struggle, and the kind of life which accompanied it, I may

have to write another time, and so will not say more about it here.

Except this, that it was much furthered by the change that gradually

took place between the landlords and the class on whom all society

rested, the serfs. These at first were men who had no more rights than

chattel slaves had, except that mostly, as part of the stock of the

manor, they could not be sold off it; they had to do all the work of the

manor, and to earn their own livelihood off it as they best could. But

as the power of production increased, owing to better methods of

working, and as the country got to be more settled, their task-work

became easier of performance and their own land more productive to them;

and that tendency to the definition and differentiation of rights,

moreover, was at work for their benefit, and the custom of the manor

defined what their services were, and they began to acquire rights. From

that time they ceased to be pure serfs, and began to tend towards

becoming tenants, at first paying purely and simply service for their

holdings, but gradually commuting that service for fines and money

payment — for rent, in short.

Towards the close of the fourteenth century, after the country had been

depopulated by the Black Death, and impoverished by the long war, the

feudal lords of these copyholders and tenants began to regret the

slackness with which their predecessors had exploited their property,

the serfs, and to consider that under the new commercial light which had

begun to dawn upon them they could do it much better if they only had

their property a little more in hand; but it was too late, for their

property had acquired rights, and therewithal had got strange visions

into their heads of a time much better than that in which they lived,

when even those rights should be supplanted by a condition of things in

which the assertion of rights for any one set of men should no longer be

needed, since all men should be free to enjoy the fruits of their own

labour.

Of that came the great episode of the Peasants’ War, led by men like Wat

Tyler, Jack Straw, and John Ball, who indeed, with those they led,

suffered for daring to be before their time, for the revolt was put down

with cruelty worthy of an Irish landlord or a sweating capitalist of the

present day; but, nevertheless, serfdom came to an end in England, if

not because of the revolt, yet because of the events that made it, and

thereby a death-wound was inflicted on the feudal system.

From that time onward the country, passing through the various troubles

of a new French war of Henry V.‘s time, and the War of the Roses, did

not heed these faction fights much.

The workmen grew in prosperity, but also they began to rise into a new

class, and a class beneath them of mere labourers who were not serfs

began to form, and to lay the foundations of capitalistic production.

England got carried into the rising current of commercialism, and the

rich men and landlords to turn their attention to the production of

profit instead of the production of livelihood; the gild-less journeyman

and the landless labourer slowly came into existence; the landlord got

rid of his tenants all he could, turned tillage into pasture, and

sweated the pastures to death in his eagerness for wool, which for him

meant money and the breeding of money; till at last the place of the

serf, which had stood empty, as it were, during a certain transition

period, during which the non-capitalistic production was expanding up to

its utmost limit, was filled by the proletarian working for the service

of a master in a new fashion, a fashion which exploited and (woe worth

the while!) exploits him very much more completely than the customs of

the manor of the feudal period.

The life of the worker and the production of goods in this transition

period, when Feudal society was sickening for its end, is a difficult

and wide subject that requires separate treatment; at present I will

leave the mediaeval workman at the full development of that period which

found him a serf bound to the manor, and which left him generally a

yeoman or an artisan sharing the collective status of his gild.

The workman of to-day, if he could realize the position of his

forerunner, has some reason to envy him: the feudal serf worked hard,

and lived poorly, and produced a rough livelihood for his master;

whereas the modern workman, working harder still, and living little if

any better than the serf, produces for his master a state of luxury of

which the old lord of the manor never dreamed. The workman’s powers of

production are multiplied a thousandfold; his own livelihood remains

pretty much where it was. The balance goes to his master and the crowd

of useless, draggled-tailed knaves and fools who pander to his idiotic

sham desires, and who, under the pretentious title of the intellectual

part of the middle classes, have in their turn taken the place of the

mediaeval jester.

Truly, if the Positivist motto, “Live for others,” be taken in stark

literality, the modern workman should be a good and wise man, since he

has no chance of living for himself!

And yet, I wish he were wiser still; wise enough to make an end of the

preaching of “Live on others,” which is the motto set forth by

commercialism to her favoured children.

Yet in one thing the modern proletarian has an advantage over the

mediaeval serf, and that advantage is a world in itself. Many a century

lay between the serf and successful revolt, and though he tried it many

a time and never lost heart, yet the coming change which his martyrdom

helped on was not to be for him yet, but for the new masters of his

successors. With us it is different. A few years of wearisome struggle

against apathy and ignorance; a year or two of growing hope — and then

who knows? Perhaps a few months, or perhaps a few days of the open

struggle against brute force, with the mask off its face, and the sword

in its hand, and then we are over the bar.

Who knows, I say? Yet this we know, that ahead of us, with nothing

betwixt us except such incidents as are necessary to its development,

lies the inevitable social revolution, which will bring about the end of

mastery and the triumph of fellowship.

The Hopes of Civilization

Every age has had its hopes, hopes that look to something beyond the

life of the age itself, hopes that try to pierce into the future; and,

strange to say, I believe that those hopes have been stronger not in the

heyday of the epoch which has given them birth, but rather in its

decadence and times of corruption: in sober truth it may well be that

these hopes are but a reflection in those that live happily and

comfortably of the vain longings of those others who suffer with little

power of expressing their sufferings in an audible voice: when all goes

well the happy world forgets these people and their desires, sure as it

is that their woes are not dangerous to them the wealthy: whereas when

the woes and grief of the poor begin to rise to a point beyond the

endurance of men, fear conscious or unconscious falls upon the rich, and

they begin to look about them to see what there may be among the

elements of their society which may be used as palliatives for the

misery which, long existing and ever growing greater among the slaves of

that society, is now at last forcing itself on the attention of the

masters. Times of change, disruption, and revolution are naturally times

of hope also, and not seldom the hopes of something better to come are

the first tokens that tell people that revolution is at hand, though

commonly such tokens are no more believed than Cassandra’s prophecies,

or are even taken in a contrary sense by those who have anything to

lose; since they look upon them as signs of the prosperity of the times,

and the long endurance of that state of things which is so kind to them.

Let us then see what the hopes of civilization are like to-day: for

indeed I purpose speaking of our own times chiefly, and will leave for

the present all mention of that older civilization which was destroyed

by the healthy barbarism out of which our present society has grown.

Yet a few words may be necessary concerning the birth of our present

epoch and the hopes it gave rise to, and what has become of them: that

will not take us very far back in history; as to my mind our modern

civilization begins with the stirring period about the time of the

Reformation in England, the time which in the then more important

countries of the Continent is known as the period of the Renaissance,

the so-called new-birth of art and learning.

And first remember that this period includes the death-throes of

feudalism, with all the good and evil which that system bore with it.

For centuries past its end was getting ready by the gradual weakening of

the bonds of the great hierarchy which held men together: the

characteristics of those bonds were, theoretically at least, personal

rights and personal duties between superior and inferior all down the

scale; each man was born, so to say, subject to these conditions, and

the mere accidents of his life could not free him from them: commerce,

in our sense of the word, there was none; capitalistic manufacture,

capitalistic exchange was unknown: to buy goods cheap that you might

sell them dear was a legal offence (forestalling): to buy goods in the

market in the morning and to sell them in the afternoon in the same

place was not thought a useful occupation and was forbidden under the

name of regrating; usury, instead of leading as now directly to the

highest offices of the State, was thought wrong, and the profit of it

mostly fell to the chosen people of God: the robbery of the workers,

thought necessary then as now to the very existence of the State, was

carried out quite crudely without any concealment or excuse by arbitrary

taxation or open violence: on the other hand, life was easy, and common

necessaries plenteous; the holidays of the Church were holidays in the

modern sense of the word, downright play-days, and there were ninety-six

obligatory ones: nor were the people tame and sheep-like, but as

rough-handed and bold a set of good fellows as ever rubbed through life

under the sun.

I remember three passages, from contemporary history or gossip, about

the life of those times which luck has left us, and which illustrate

curiously the change that has taken place in the habits of Englishmen. A

lady writing from Norfolk 400 years ago to her husband in London, amidst

various commissions for tapestries, groceries, and gowns, bids him also

not to forget to bring back with him a good supply of cross-bows and

bolts, since the windows of their hall were too low to be handy for

long-bow shooting. A German traveller, writing quite at the end of the

mediaeval period, speaks of the English as the laziest and proudest

people and the best cooks in Europe. A Spanish ambassador about the same

period says, “These English live in houses built of sticks and mud, [4]

but therein they fare as plenteously as lords.”

Indeed, I confess that it is with a strange emotion that I recall these

times and try to realize the life of our forefathers, men who were named

like ourselves, spoke nearly the same tongue, lived on the same spots of

earth, and therewithal were as different from us in manners, habits,

ways of life and thought, as though they lived in another planet. The

very face of the country has changed; not merely I mean in London and

the great manufacturing centres, but through the country generally;

there is no piece of English ground, except such places as Salisbury

Plain, but bears witness to the amazing change which 400 years has

brought upon us.

Not seldom I please myself with trying to realize the face of mediaeval

England; the many chases and great woods, the stretches of common

tillage and common pasture quite unenclosed; the rough husbandry of the

tilled parts, the unimproved breeds of cattle, sheep, and swine;

especially the latter, so lank and long and lathy, looking so strange to

us; the strings of packhorses along the bridle-roads, the scantiness of

the wheel-roads, scarce any except those left by the Romans, and those

made from monastery to monastery: the scarcity of bridges, and people

using ferries instead, or fords where they could; the little towns, well

bechurched, often walled; the villages just where they are now (except

for those that have nothing but the church left to tell of them), but

better and more populous; their churches, some big and handsome, some

small and curious, but all crowded with altars and furniture, and gay

with pictures and ornament; the many religious houses, with their

glorious architecture; the beautiful manor-houses, some of them castles

once, and survivals from an earlier period; some new and elegant; some

out of all proportion small for the importance of their lords. How

strange it would be to us if we could be landed in fourteenth century

England; unless we saw the crest of some familiar hill, like that which

yet bears upon it a symbol of an English tribe, and from which, looking

down on the plain where Alfred was born, I once had many such

ponderings, we should not know into what country of the world we were

come: the name is left, scarce a thing else.

And when I think of this it quickens my hope of what may be: even so it

will be with us in time to come; all will have changed, and another

people will be dwelling here in England, who, although they may be of

our blood and bear our name, will wonder how we lived in the nineteenth

century.

Well, under all that rigidly ordered caste society of the fourteenth

century, with its rough plenty, its sauntering life, its cool acceptance

of rudeness and violence, there was going on a keen struggle of classes

which carried with it the hope of progress of those days: the serfs

gradually getting freed, and becoming some of them the town population,

the first journeymen, or “free-labourers,” so called, some of them the

copyholders of agricultural land: the corporations of the towns gathered

power, the craft-gilds grew into perfection and corruption, the power of

the Crown increased, attended with nascent bureaucracy; in short, the

middle class was forming underneath the outward show of feudalism still

intact: and all was getting ready for the beginning of the great

commercial epoch in whose latter days I would fain hope we are living.

That epoch began with the portentous change of agriculture which meant

cultivating for profit instead of for livelihood, and which carried with

it the expropriation of the people from the land, the extinction of the

yeoman, and the rise of the capitalist farmer; and the growth of the

town population, which, swelled by the drift of the landless vagabonds

and masterless men, grew into a definite proletariat or class of

free-workmen; and their existence made that of the embryo

capitalist-manufacturer also possible; and the reign of commercial

contract and cash payment began to take the place of the old feudal

hierarchy, with its many-linked chain of personal responsibilities. The

latter half of the seventeenth century, the reign of Charles II., saw

the last blow struck at this feudal system, when the landowners’

military service was abolished, and they became simple owners of

property that had no duties attached to it save the payment of a

land-tax.

The hopes of the early part of the commercial period may be read in

almost every book of the time, expressed in various degrees of dull or

amusing pedantry, and show a naif arrogance and contempt of the times

just past through which nothing but the utmost simplicity of ignorance

could have attained to. But the times were stirring, and gave birth to

the most powerful individualities in many branches of literature, and

More and Campanella, at least from the midst of the exuberant triumph of

young commercialism, gave to the world prophetic hopes of times yet to

come when that commercialism itself should have given place to the

society which we hope will be the next transform of civilization into

something else; into a new social life.

This period of early and exuberant hopes passed into the next stage of

sober realization of many of them, for commerce grew and grew, and

moulded all society to its needs: the workman of the sixteenth century

worked still as an individual with little co-operation, and scarce any

division of labour: by the end of the seventeenth he had become only a

part of a group which by that time was in the handicrafts the real unit

of production; division of labour even at that period had quite

destroyed his individuality, and the worker was but part of a machine:

all through the eighteenth century this system went on progressing

towards perfection, till to most men of that period, to most of those

who were in any way capable of expressing their thoughts, civilization

had already reached a high stage of perfection, and was certain to go on

from better to better.

These hopes were not on the surface of a very revolutionary kind, but

nevertheless the class struggle still went on, and quite openly too; for

the remains of feudality, aided by the mere mask and grimace of the

religion, which was once a real part of the feudal system, hampered the

progress of commerce sorely, and seemed a thousandfold more powerful

than it really was; because in spite of the class struggle there was

really a covert alliance between the powerful middle classes who were

the children of commerce and their old masters the aristocracy; an

unconscious understanding between them rather, in the midst of their

contest, that certain matters were to be respected even by the advanced

party: the contest and civil war between the king and the commons in

England in the seventeenth century illustrates this well: the caution

with which privilege was attacked in the beginning of the struggle, the

unwillingness of all the leaders save a few enthusiasts to carry matters

to their logical consequences, even when the march of events had

developed the antagonism between aristocratic privilege and middle-class

freedom of contract (so called); finally, the crystallization of the new

order conquered by the sword of Naseby into a mongrel condition of

things between privilege and bourgeois freedom, the defeat and grief of

the purist Republicans, and the horror at and swift extinction of the

Levellers, the pioneers of Socialism in that day, all point to the fact

that the “party of progress,” as we should call it now, was determined

after all that privilege should not be abolished further than its own

standpoint.

The seventeenth century ended in the great Whig revolution in England,

and, as I said, commerce throve and grew enormously, and the power of

the middle classes increased proportionately and all things seemed going

smoothly with them, till at last in France the culminating corruption of

a society, still nominally existing for the benefit of the privileged

aristocracy, forced their hand: the old order of things, backed as it

was by the power of the executive, by that semblance of overwhelming

physical force which is the real and only cement of a society founded on

the slavery of the many — the aristocratic power, seemed strong and

almost inexpugnable: and since any stick will do to beat a dog with, the

middle classes in France were forced to take up the first stick that lay

ready to hand if they were not to give way to the aristocrats, which

indeed the whole evolution of history forbade them to do. Therefore, as

in England in the seventeenth century, the middle classes allied

themselves to religious and republican, and even communistic

enthusiasts, with the intention, firm though unexpressed, to keep them

down when they had mounted to power by their means, so in France they

had to ally themselves with the proletariat; which, shamefully oppressed

and degraded as it had been, now for the first time in history began to

feel its power, the power of numbers: by means of this help they

triumphed over aristocratic privilege, but, on the other hand, although

the proletariat was speedily reduced again to a position not much better

than that it had held before the revolution, the part it played therein

gave a new and terrible character to that revolution, and from that time

forward the class struggle entered on to a new phase; the middle classes

had gained a complete victory, which in France carried with it all the

outward signs of victory, though in England they chose to consider a

certain part of themselves an aristocracy, who had indeed little signs

of aristocracy about them either for good or for evil, being in very few

cases of long descent, and being in their manners and ideas unmistakably

bourgeois.

So was accomplished the second act of the great class struggle with

whose first act began the age of commerce; as to the hopes of this

period of the revolution we all know how extravagant they were; what a

complete regeneration of the world was expected to result from the

abolition of the grossest form of privilege; and I must say that, before

we mock at the extravagance of those hopes, we should try to put

ourselves in the place of those that held them, and try to conceive how

the privilege of the old noblesse must have galled the respectable

well-to-do people of that time. Well, the reasonable part of those hopes

were realized by the revolution; in other words, it accomplished what it

really aimed at, the freeing of commerce from the fetters of sham

feudality; or, in other words, the destruction of aristocratic

privilege. The more extravagant part of the hopes expressed by the

eighteenth century revolution were vague enough, and tended in the

direction of supposing that the working classes would be benefited by

what was to the interest of the middle class in some way quite

unexplained — by a kind of magic, one may say — which welfare of the

workers, as it was never directly aimed at, but only hoped for by the

way, so also did not come about by any such magical means, and the

triumphant middle classes began gradually to find themselves looked upon

no longer as rebellious servants, but as oppressive masters.

The middle class had freed commerce from her fetters of privilege, and

had freed thought from her fetters of theology, at least partially; but

it had not freed, nor attempted to free, labour from its fetters. The

leaders of the French Revolution, even amidst the fears, suspicions and

slaughter of the Terror, upheld the rights of “property” so called,

though a new pioneer or prophet appeared in France, analogous in some

respects to the Levellers of Cromwell’s time, but, as might be expected,

far more advanced and reasonable than they were. Gracchus Babeuf and his

fellows were treated as criminals, and died or suffered the torture of

prison for attempting to put into practice those words which the

Republic still carried on its banners, and Liberty, Fraternity, and

Equality were interpreted in a middle-class, or if you please a

Jesuitical, sense, as the rewards of success for those who could

struggle into an exclusive class; and at last property had to be

defended by a military adventurer, and the Revolution seemed to have

ended with Napoleonism.

Nevertheless, the Revolution was not dead, nor was it possible to say

thus far and no further to the rising tide. Commerce, which had created

the propertyless proletariat throughout civilization had still another

part to play, which is not yet played out; she had and has to teach the

workers to know what they are; to educate them, to consolidate them, and

not only to give them aspirations for their advancement as a class, but

to make means for them to realize those aspirations. All this she did,

nor loitered in her work either; from the beginning of the nineteenth

century the history of civilization is really the history of the last of

the class-struggles which was inaugurated by the French Revolution; and

England, who all through the times of the Revolution and the Caesarism

which followed it appeared to be the steady foe of Revolution, was

really as steadily furthering it; her natural conditions, her store of

coal and minerals, her temperate climate, extensive sea-board and many

harbours, and lastly her position as the outpost of Europe looking into

America across the ocean, doomed her to be for a time at least the

mistress of the commerce of the civilized world, and its agent with

barbarous and semi-barbarous countries. The necessities of this destiny

drove her into the implacable war with France, a war which, nominally

waged on behalf of monarchical principles, was really, though doubtless

unconsciously, carried on for the possession of the foreign and colonial

markets. She came out victorious from that war, and fully prepared to

take advantage of the industrial revolution which had been going on the

while, and which I now ask you to note.

I have said that the eighteenth century perfected the system of labour

which took the place of the mediaeval system, under which a workman

individually carried his piece of work all through its various stages

from the first to the last.

This new system, the first change in industrial production since the

Middle Ages, is known as the system of division of labour, wherein, as I

said, the unit of labour is a group, not a man; the individual workman

in this system is kept life-long at the performance of some task quite

petty in itself, and which he soon masters, and having mastered it has

nothing more to do but to go on increasing his speed of hand under the

spur of competition with his fellows, until he has become the perfect

machine which it is his ultimate duty to become, since without attaining

to that end he must die or become a pauper. You can well imagine how

this glorious invention of division of labour, this complete destruction

of individuality in the workman, and his apparent hopeless enslavement

to his profit-grinding master, stimulated the hopes of civilization;

probably more hymns have been sung in praise of division of labour, more

sermons preached about it, than have done homage to the precept, “do

unto others as ye would they should do unto you.”

To drop all irony, surely this was one of those stages of civilization

at which one might well say that, if it was to stop there, it was a pity

that it had ever got so far. I have had to study books and methods of

work of the eighteenth century a good deal, French chiefly; and I must

say that the impression made on me by that study is that the eighteenth

century artisan must have been a terrible product of civilization, and

quite in a condition to give rise to hopes — of the torch, the pike, and

the guillotine.

However, civilization was not going to stop there; having turned the man

into a machine, the next stage for commerce to aim at was to contrive

machines which would widely dispense with human labour; nor was this aim

altogether disappointed.

Now, at first sight it would seem that having got the workman into such

a plight as he was, as the slave of division of labour, this new

invention of machines which should free him from a part of his labour at

least, could be nothing to him but an unmixed blessing. Doubtless it

will prove to have been so in the end, when certain institutions have

been swept away which most people now look on as eternal; but a longish

time has passed during which the workman’s hopes of civilization have

been disappointed, for those who invented the machines, or rather who

profited by their invention, did not aim at the saving of labour in the

sense of reducing the labour which each man had to do, but, first taking

it for granted that every workman would have to work as long as he could

stand up to it, aimed, under those conditions of labour, at producing

the utmost possible amount of goods which they could sell at a profit.

Need I dwell on the fact that, under these circumstances, the invention

of the machines has benefited the workman but little even to this day?

Nay, at first they made his position worse than it had been: for, being

thrust on the world very suddenly, they distinctly brought about an

industrial revolution, changing everything suddenly and completely;

industrial productiveness was increased prodigiously, but so far from

the workers reaping the benefit of this, they were thrown out of work in

enormous numbers, while those who were still employed were reduced from

the position of skilled artisans to that of unskilled labourers: the

aims of their masters being, as I said, to make a profit, they did not

trouble themselves about this as a class, but took it for granted that

it was something that couldn’t be helped and didn’t hurt them; nor did

they think of offering to the workers that compensation for harassed

interests which they have since made a point of claiming so loudly for

themselves.

This was the state of things which followed on the conclusion of

European peace, and even that peace itself rather made matters worse

than better, by the sudden cessation of all war industries, and the

throwing on to the market many thousands of soldiers and sailors: in

short, at no period of English history was the condition of the workers

worse than in the early years of the nineteenth century.

There seem during this period to have been two currents of hope that had

reference to the working classes: the first affected the masters, the

second the men.

In England, and, in what I am saying of this period, I am chiefly

thinking of England, the hopes of the richer classes ran high; and no

wonder; for England had by this time become the mistress of the markets

of the world, and also, as the people of that period were never weary of

boasting, the workshop of the world: the increase in the riches of the

country was enormous, even at the early period I am thinking of now —

prior to ‘48, I mean — though it increased much more speedily in times

that we have all seen: but part of the jubilant hopes of this newly rich

man concerned his servants, the instruments of his fortune: it was hoped

that the population in general would grow wiser, better educated,

thriftier, more industrious, more comfortable; for which hope there was

surely some foundation, since man’s mastery over the forces of Nature

was growing yearly towards completion; but you see these benevolent

gentlemen supposed that these hopes would be realized perhaps by some

unexplained magic as aforesaid, or perhaps by the working-classes, at

their own expense, by the exercise of virtues supposed to be specially

suited to their condition, and called, by their masters, “thrift” and

“industry.” For this latter supposition there was no foundation: indeed,

the poor wretches who were thrown out of work by the triumphant march of

commerce had perforce worn thrift threadbare, and could hardly better

their exploits in that direction; while as to those who worked in the

factories, or who formed the fringe of labour elsewhere, industry was no

new gospel to them, since they already worked as long as they could work

without dying at the loom, the spindle, or the stithy. They for their

part had their hopes, vague enough as to their ultimate aim, but

expressed in the passing day by a very obvious tendency to revolt: this

tendency took various forms, which I cannot dwell on here, but settled

down at last into Chartism: about which I must speak a few words: but

first I must mention, I can scarce do more, the honoured name of Robert

Owen, as representative of the nobler hopes of his day, just as More was

of his, and the lifter of the torch of Socialism amidst the dark days of

the confusion consequent on the reckless greed of the early period of

the great factory industries.

That the conditions under which man lived could affect his life and his

deeds infinitely, that not selfish greed and ceaseless contention, but

brotherhood and co-operation were the bases of true society, was the

gospel which he preached and also practised with a single-heartedness,

devotion, and fervour of hope which have never been surpassed: he was

the embodied hope of the days when the advance of knowledge and the

sufferings of the people thrust revolutionary hope upon those thinkers

who were not in some form or other in the pay of the sordid masters of

society.

As to the Chartist agitation, there is this to be said of it, that it

was thoroughly a working-class movement, and it was caused by the

simplest and most powerful of all causes — hunger. It is noteworthy that

it was strongest, especially in its earlier days, in the Northern and

Midland manufacturing districts — that is, in the places which felt the

distress caused by the industrial revolution most sorely and directly;

it sprang up with particular vigour in the years immediately following

the great Reform Bill; and it has been remarked that disappointment of

the hopes which that measure had cherished had something to do with its

bitterness. As it went on, obvious causes for failure were developed in

it; self-seeking leadership; futile discussion of the means of making

the change, before organization of the party was perfected; blind fear

of ultimate consequences on the part of some, blind disregard to

immediate consequences on the part of others; these were the surface

reasons for its failure: but it would have triumphed over all these and

accomplished revolution in England, if it had not been for causes deeper

and more vital than these. Chartism differed from mere Radicalism in

being a class movement; but its aim was after all political rather than

social. The Socialism of Robert Owen fell short of its object because it

did not understand that, as long as there is a privileged class in

possession of the executive power, they will take good care that their

economical position, which enables them to live on the unpaid labour of

the people, is not tampered with: the hopes of the Chartists were

disappointed because they did not understand that true political freedom

is impossible to people who are economically enslaved: there is no first

and second in these matters, the two must go hand in hand together: we

cannot live as we will, and as we should, as long as we allow people to

govern us whose interest it is that we should live as they will, and by

no means as we should; neither is it any use claiming the right to

manage our own business unless we are prepared to have some business of

our own: these two aims united mean the furthering of the class struggle

till all classes are abolished — the divorce of one from the other is

fatal to any hope of social advancement.

Chartism therefore, though a genuine popular movement, was incomplete in

its aims and knowledge; the time was not yet come and it could not

triumph openly; but it would be a mistake to say that it failed utterly:

at least it kept alive the holy flame of discontent; it made it possible

for us to attain to the political goal of democracy, and thereby to

advance the cause of the people by the gain of a stage from whence could

be seen the fresh gain to be aimed at.

I have said that the time for revolution had not then come: the great

wave of commercial success went on swelling, and though the capitalists

would if they had dared have engrossed the whole of the advantages

thereby gained at the expense of their wage slaves, the Chartist revolt

warned them that it was not safe to attempt it. They were forced to try

to allay discontent by palliative measures. They had to allow Factory

Acts to be passed regulating the hours and conditions of labour of women

and children, and consequently of men also in some of the more important

and consolidated industries; they were forced to repeal the ferocious

laws against combination among the workmen; so that the Trades Unions

won for themselves a legal position and became a power in the labour

question, and were able by means of strikes and threats of strikes to

regulate the wages granted to the workers, and to raise the standard of

livelihood for a certain part of the skilled workmen and the labourers

associated with them: though the main part of the unskilled, including

the agricultural workmen, were no better off than before.

Thus was damped down the flame of a discontent vague in its aims, and

passionately crying out for what, if granted, it could not have used:

twenty years ago any one hinting at the possibility of serious class

discontent in this country would have been looked upon as a madman; in

fact, the well-to-do and cultivated were quite unconscious (as many

still are) that there was any class distinction in this country other

than what was made by the rags and cast clothes of feudalism, which in a

perfunctory manner they still attacked.

There was no sign of revolutionary feeling in England twenty years ago:

the middle class were so rich that they had no need to hope for anything

— but a heaven which they did not believe in: the well-to-do working men

did not hope, since they were not pinched and had no means of learning

their degraded position: and lastly, the drudges of the proletariat had

such hope as charity, the hospital, the workhouse, and kind death at

last could offer them.

In this stock-jobbers’ heaven let us leave our dear countrymen for a

little, while I say a few words about the affairs of the people on the

continent of Europe. Things were not quite so smooth for the fleecer

there: Socialist thinkers and writers had arisen about the same time as

Robert Owen; St. Simon, Proudhon, Fourier and his followers kept up the

traditions of hope in the midst of a bourgeois world. Amongst these

Fourier is the one that calls for most attention: since his doctrine of

the necessity and possibility of making labour attractive is one which

Socialism can by no means do without. France also kept up the

revolutionary and insurrectionary tradition, the result of something

like hope still fermenting amongst the proletariat: she fell at last

into the clutches of a second Caesarism developed by the basest set of

sharpers, swindlers, and harlots that ever insulted a country, and of

whom our own happy bourgeois at home made heroes and heroines: the

hideous open corruption of Parisian society, to which, I repeat, our

respectable classes accorded heartfelt sympathy, was finally swept away

by the horrors of a race war: the defeats and disgraces of this war

developed, on the one hand, an increase in the wooden implacability and

baseness of the French bourgeois, but on the other made way for

revolutionary hope to spring again, from which resulted the attempt to

establish society on the basis of the freedom of labour, which we call

the Commune of Paris of 1871. Whatever mistakes or imprudences were made

in this attempt, and all wars blossom thick with such mistakes, I will

leave the reactionary enemies of the people’s cause to put forward: the

immediate and obvious result was the slaughter of thousands of brave and

honest revolutionists at the hands of the respectable classes, the loss

in fact of an army for the popular cause: but we may be sure that the

results of the Commune will not stop there: to all Socialists that

heroic attempt will give hope and ardour in the cause as long as it is

to be won; we feel as though the Paris workman had striven to bring the

day-dawn for us, and had lifted us the sun’s rim over the horizon, never

to set in utter darkness again: of such attempts one must say, that

though those who perished in them might have been put in a better place

in the battle, yet after all brave men never die for nothing, when they

die for principle.

Let us shift from France to Germany before we get back to England again,

and conclude with a few words about our hopes at the present day. To

Germany we owe the school of economists, at whose head stands the name

of Karl Marx, who have made modern Socialism what it is: the earlier

Socialist writers and preachers based their hopes on man being taught to

see the desirableness of co-operation taking the place of competition,

and adopting the change voluntarily and consciously, and they trusted to

schemes more or less artificial being tried and accepted, although such

schemes were necessarily constructed out of the materials which

capitalistic society offered: but the new school, starting with an

historical view of what had been, and seeing that a law of evolution

swayed all events in it, was able to point out to us that the evolution

was still going on, and that, whether Socialism be desirable or not, it

is at least inevitable. Here then was at last a hope of a different kind

to any that had gone before it; and the German and Austrian workmen were

not slow to learn the lesson founded on this theory; from being one of

the most backward countries in Europe in the movement, before Lassalle

started his German workman’s party in 1863, Germany soon became the

leader in it: Bismarck’s repressive law has only acted on opinion there,

as the roller does to the growing grass — made it firmer and stronger;

and whatever vicissitudes may be the fate of the party as a party, there

can be no doubt that Socialistic opinion is firmly established there,

and that when the time is ripe for it that opinion will express itself

in action.

Now, in all I have been saying, I have been wanting you to trace the

fact that, ever since the establishment of commercialism on the ruins of

feudality, there has been growing a steady feeling on the part of the

workers that they are a class dealt with as a class, and in like manner

to deal with others; and that as this class feeling has grown, so also

has grown with it a consciousness of the antagonism between their class

and the class which employs it, as the phrase goes; that is to say,

which lives by means of its labour.

Now it is just this growing consciousness of the fact that as long as

there exists in society a propertied class living on the labour of a

propertyless one, there must be a struggle always going on between those

two classes — it is just the dawning knowledge of this fact which should

show us what civilization can hope for — namely, transformation into

true society, in which there will no longer be classes with their

necessary struggle for existence and superiority: for the antagonism of

classes which began in all simplicity between the master and the chattel

slave of ancient society, and was continued between the feudal lord and

the serf of mediaeval society, has gradually become the contention

between the capitalist developed from the workman of the last-named

period, and the wage-earner: in the former struggle the rise of the

artisan and villenage tenant created a new class, the middle class,

while the place of the old serf was filled by the propertyless labourer,

with whom the middle class, which has absorbed the aristocracy, is now

face to face: the struggle between the classes therefore is once again a

simple one, as in the days of the classical peoples; but since there is

no longer any strong race left out of civilization, as in the time of

the disruption of Rome, the whole struggle in all its simplicity between

those who have and those who lack is within civilization.

Moreover, the capitalist or modern slave-owner has been forced by his

very success, as we have seen, to organize his slaves, the wage-earners,

into a co-operation for production so well arranged that it requires

little but his own elimination to make it a foundation for communal

life: in the teeth also of the experience of past ages, he has been

compelled to allow a modicum of education to the propertyless, and has

not even been able to deprive them wholly of political rights; his own

advance in wealth and power has bred for him the very enemy who is

doomed to make an end of him.

But will there be any new class to take the place of the present

proletariat when that has triumphed, as it must do, over the present

privileged class? We cannot foresee the future, but we may fairly hope

not: at least we cannot see any signs of such a new class forming. It is

impossible to see how destruction of privilege can stop short of

absolute equality of condition; pure Communism is the logical deduction

from the imperfect form of the new society, which is generally

differentiated from it as Socialism.

Meantime, it is this simplicity and directness of the growing contest

which above all things presents itself as a terror to the conservative

instinct of the present day. Many among the middle class who are

sincerely grieved and shocked at the condition of the proletariat which

civilization has created, and even alarmed by the frightful inequalities

which it fosters, do nevertheless shudder back from the idea of the

class struggle, and strive to shut their eyes to the fact that it is

going on. They try to think that peace is not only possible, but

natural, between the two classes, the very essence of whose existence is

that each can only thrive by what it manages to force the other to yield

to it. They propose to themselves the impossible problem of raising the

inferior or exploited classes into a position in which they will cease

to struggle against the superior classes, while the latter will not

cease to exploit them. This absurd position drives them into the

concoction of schemes for bettering the condition of the working classes

at their own expense, some of them futile, some merely fantastic; or

they may be divided again into those which point out the advantages and

pleasures of involuntary asceticism, and reactionary plans for importing

the conditions of the production and life of the Middle Ages (wholly

misunderstood by them, by the way) into the present system of the

capitalist farmer, the great industries, and the universal world-market.

Some see a solution of the social problem in sham co-operation, which is

merely an improved form of joint-stockery: others preach thrift to

(precarious) incomes of eighteen shillings a week, and industry to men

killing themselves by inches in working overtime, or to men whom the

labour-market has rejected as not wanted: others beg the proletarians

not to breed so fast; an injunction the compliance with which might be

at first of advantage to the proletarians themselves in their present

condition, but would certainly undo the capitalists, if it were carried

to any lengths, and would lead through ruin and misery to the violent

outbreak of the very revolution which these timid people are so anxious

to forego.

Then there are others who, looking back on the past, and perceiving that

the workmen of the Middle Ages lived in more comfort and self- respect

than ours do, even though they were subjected to the class rule of men

who were looked on as another order of beings than they, think that if

those conditions of life could be reproduced under our better political

conditions the question would be solved for a time at least. Their

schemes may be summed up in attempts, more or less preposterously

futile, to graft a class of independent peasants on our system of wages

and capital. They do not understand that this system of independent

workmen, producing almost entirely for the consumption of themselves and

their neighbours, and exploited by the upper classes by obvious taxes on

their labour, which was not otherwise organized or interfered with by

the exploiters, was what in past times took the place of our system, in

which the workers sell their labour in the competitive market to masters

who have in their hands the whole organization of the markets, and that

these two systems are mutually destructive.

Others again believe in the possibility of starting from our present

workhouse system, for the raising of the lowest part of the working

population into a better condition, but do not trouble themselves as to

the position of the workers who are fairly above the condition of

pauperism, or consider what part they will play in the contest for a

better livelihood. And, lastly, quite a large number of well-intentioned

persons belonging to the richer classes believe, that in a society that

compels competition for livelihood, and holds out to the workers as a

stimulus to exertion the hope of their rising into a monopolist class of

non-producers, it is yet possible to “moralize” capital (to use a slang

phrase of the Positivists): that is to say, that a sentiment imported

from a religion which looks upon another world as the true sphere of

action for mankind, will override the necessities of our daily life in

this world. This curious hope is founded on the feeling that a sentiment

antagonistic to the full development of commercialism exists and is

gaining ground, and that this sentiment is an independent growth of the

ethics of the present epoch. As a matter of fact, admitting its

existence, as I think we must do, it is the birth of the sense of

insecurity which is the shadow cast before by the approaching

dissolution of modern society founded on wage-slavery.

The greater part of these schemes aim, though seldom with the

consciousness of their promoters, at the creation of a new middle-class

out of the wage-earning class, and at their expense, just as the present

middle-class was developed out of the serf-population of the early

Middle Ages. It may be possible that such a further development of the

middle-class lies before us, but it will not be brought about by any

such artificial means as the abovementioned schemes. If it comes at all,

it must be produced by events, which at present we cannot foresee,

acting on our commercial system, and revivifying for a little time,

maybe, that Capitalist Society which now seems sickening towards its

end.

For what is visible before us in these days is the competitive

commercial system killing itself by its own force: profits lessening,

businesses growing bigger and bigger, the small employer of labour

thrust out of his function, and the aggregation of capital increasing

the numbers of the lower middle-class from above rather than from below,

by driving the smaller manufacturer into the position of a mere servant

to the bigger. The productivity of labour also increasing out of all

proportion to the capacity of the capitalists to manage the market or

deal with the labour supply: lack of employment therefore becoming

chronic, and discontent therewithal.

All this on the one hand. On the other, the workmen claiming everywhere

political equality, which cannot long be denied; and education

spreading, so that what between the improvement in the education of the

working-class and the continued amazing fatuity of that of the upper

classes, there is a distinct tendency to equalization here; and, as I

have hinted above, all history shows us what a danger to society may be

a class at once educated and socially degraded: though, indeed, no

history has yet shown us — what is swiftly advancing upon us — a class

which, though it shall have attained knowledge, shall lack utterly the

refinement and self-respect which come from the union of knowledge with

leisure and ease of life. The growth of such a class may well make the

“cultured” people of to-day tremble.

Whatever, therefore, of unforeseen and unconceived-of may lie in the

womb of the future, there is nothing visible before us but a decaying

system, with no outlook but ever-increasing entanglement and blindness,

and a new system, Socialism, the hope of which is ever growing clearer

in men’s minds — a system which not only sees how labour can be freed

from its present fetters, and organized unwastefully, so as to produce

the greatest possible amount of wealth for the community and for every

member of it, but which bears with it its own ethics and religion and

aesthetics: that is the hope and promise of a new and higher life in all

ways. So that even if those unforeseen economical events above spoken of

were to happen, and put off for a while the end of our Capitalist

system, the latter would drag itself along as an anomaly cursed by all,

a mere clog on the aspirations of humanity.

It is not likely that it will come to that: in all probability the

logical outcome of the latter days of Capitalism will go step by step

with its actual history: while all men, even its declared enemies, will

be working to bring Socialism about, the aims of those who have learned

to believe in the certainty and beneficence of its advent will become

clearer, their methods for realizing it clearer also, and at last ready

to hand. Then will come that open acknowledgment for the necessity of

the change (an acknowledgment coming from the intelligence of

civilization) which is commonly called Revolution. It is no use

prophesying as to the events which will accompany that revolution, but

to a reasonable man it seems unlikely to the last degree, or we will say

impossible, that a moral sentiment will induce the proprietary classes —

those who live by owning the means of production which the unprivileged

classes must needs use — to yield up this privilege uncompelled; all one

can hope is that they will see the implicit threat of compulsion in the

events of the day, and so yield with a good grace to the terrible

necessity of forming part of a world in which all, including themselves,

will work honestly and live easily.

The Aims of Art

In considering the Aims of Art, that is, why men toilsomely cherish and

practise Art, I find myself compelled to generalize from the only

specimen of humanity of which I know anything; to wit, myself. Now, when

I think of what it is that I desire, I find that I can give it no other

name than happiness. I want to be happy while I live; for as for death,

I find that, never having experienced it, I have no conception of what

it means, and so cannot even bring my mind to bear upon it. I know what

it is to live; I cannot even guess what it is to be dead. Well, then, I

want to be happy, and even sometimes, say generally, to be merry; and I

find it difficult to believe that that is not the universal desire: so

that, whatever tends towards that end I cherish with all my best

endeavour. Now, when I consider my life further, I find out, or seem to,

that it is under the influence of two dominating moods, which for lack

of better words I must call the mood of energy and the mood of idleness:

these two moods are now one, now the other, always crying out in me to

be satisfied. When the mood of energy is upon me, I must be doing

something, or I become mopish and unhappy; when the mood of idleness is

on me, I find it hard indeed if I cannot rest and let my mind wander

over the various pictures, pleasant or terrible, which my own experience

or my communing with the thoughts of other men, dead or alive, have

fashioned in it; and if circumstances will not allow me to cultivate

this mood of idleness, I find I must at the best pass through a period

of pain till I can manage to stimulate my mood of energy to take its

place and make me happy again. And if I have no means wherewith to rouse

up that mood of energy to do its duty in making me happy, and I have to

toil while the idle mood is upon me, then am I unhappy indeed, and

almost wish myself dead, though I do not know what that means.

Furthermore, I find that while in the mood of idleness memory amuses me,

in the mood of energy hope cheers me; which hope is sometimes big and

serious, and sometimes trivial, but that without it there is no happy

energy. Again, I find that while I can sometimes satisfy this mood by

merely exercising it in work that has no result beyond the passing hour

— in play, in short — yet that it presently wearies of that and gets

languid, the hope therein being too trivial, and sometimes even scarcely

real; and that on the whole, to satisfy my master the mood, I must

either be making something or making believe to make it.

Well, I believe that all men’s lives are compounded of these two moods

in various proportions, and that this explains why they have always,

with more or less of toil, cherished and practised art.

Why should they have touched it else, and so added to the labour which

they could not choose but do in order to live? It must have been done

for their pleasure, since it has only been in very elaborate

civilizations that a man could get other men to keep him alive merely to

produce works of art, whereas all men that have left any signs of their

existence behind them have practised art.

I suppose, indeed, that nobody will be inclined to deny that the end

proposed by a work of art is always to please the person whose senses

are to be made conscious of it. It was done for some one who was to be

made happier by it; his idle or restful mood was to be amused by it, so

that the vacancy which is the besetting evil of that mood might give

place to pleased contemplation, dreaming, or what you will; and by this

means he would not so soon be driven into his workful or energetic mood:

he would have more enjoyment, and better.

The restraining of restlessness, therefore, is clearly one of the

essential aims of art, and few things could add to the pleasure of life

more than this. There are, to my knowledge, gifted people now alive who

have no other vice than this of restlessness, and seemingly no other

curse in their lives to make them unhappy: but that is enough; it is

“the little rift within the lute.” Restlessness makes them hapless men

and bad citizens.

But granting, as I suppose you all will do, that this is a most

important function for art to fulfil, the question next comes, at what

price do we obtain it? I have admitted that the practice of art has

added to the labour of mankind, though I believe in the long run it will

not do so; but in adding to the labour of man has it added, so far, to

his pain? There always have been people who would at once say yes to

that question; so that there have been and are two sets of people who

dislike and contemn art as an embarrassing folly. Besides the pious

ascetics, who look upon it as a worldly entanglement which prevents men

from keeping their minds fixed on the chances of their individual

happiness or misery in the next world; who, in short, hate art, because

they think that it adds to man’s earthly happiness — besides these,

there are also people who, looking on the struggle of life from the most

reasonable point that they know of, contemn the arts because they think

that they add to man’s slavery by increasing the sum of his painful

labour: if this were the case, it would still, to my mind, be a question

whether it might not be worth the while to endure the extra pain of

labour for the sake of the extra pleasure added to rest; assuming, for

the present, equality of condition among men. But it seems to me that it

is not the case that the practice of art adds to painful labour; nay

more, I believe that, if it did, art would never have arisen at all,

would certainly not be discernible, as it is, among peoples in whom only

the germs of civilization exist. In other words, I believe that art

cannot be the result of external compulsion; the labour which goes to

produce it is voluntary, and partly undertaken for the sake of the

labour itself, partly for the sake of the hope of producing something

which, when done, shall give pleasure to the user of it. Or, again, this

extra labour, when it is extra, is undertaken with the aim of satisfying

that mood of energy by employing it to produce something worth doing,

and which, therefore, will keep before the worker a lively hope while he

is working; and also by giving it work to do in which there is absolute

immediate pleasure. Perhaps it is difficult to explain to the

non-artistic capacity that this definite sensuous pleasure is always

present in the handiwork of the deft workman when he is working

successfully, and that it increases in proportion to the freedom and

individuality of the work. Also you must understand that this production

of art, and consequent pleasure in work, is not confined to the

production of matters which are works of art only, like pictures,

statues, and so forth, but has been and should be a part of all labour

in some form or other: so only will the claims of the mood of energy be

satisfied.

Therefore the Aim of Art is to increase the happiness of men, by giving

them beauty and interest of incident to amuse their leisure, and prevent

them wearying even of rest, and by giving them hope and bodily pleasure

in their work; or, shortly, to make man’s work happy and his rest

fruitful. Consequently, genuine art is an unmixed blessing to the race

of man.

But as the word “genuine” is a large qualification, I must ask leave to

attempt to draw some practical conclusions from this assertion of the

Aims of Art, which will, I suppose, or indeed hope, lead us into some

controversy on the subject; because it is futile indeed to expect any

one to speak about art, except in the most superficial way, without

encountering those social problems which all serious men are thinking

of; since art is and must be, either in its abundance or its barrenness,

in its sincerity or its hollowness, the expression of the society

amongst which it exists.

First, then, it is clear to me that, at the present time, those who look

widest at things and deepest into them are quite dissatisfied with the

present state of the arts, as they are also with the present condition

of society. This I say in the teeth of the supposed revivification of

art which has taken place of late years: in fact, that very excitement

about the arts amongst a part of the cultivated people of to-day does

but show on how firm a basis the dissatisfaction above mentioned rests.

Forty years ago there was much less talk about art, much less practice

of it, than there is now; and that is specially true of the

architectural arts, which I shall mostly have to speak about now. People

have consciously striven to raise the dead in art since that time, and

with some superficial success. Nevertheless, in spite of this conscious

effort, I must tell you that England, to a person who can feel and

understand beauty, was a less grievous place to live in then than it is

now; and we who feel what art means know well, though we do not often

dare to say so, that forty years hence it will be a more grievous place

to us than it is now if we still follow up the road we are on. Less than

forty years ago — about thirty — I first saw the city of Rouen, then

still in its outward aspect a piece of the Middle Ages: no words can

tell you how its mingled beauty, history, and romance took hold on me; I

can only say that, looking back on my past life, I find it was the

greatest pleasure I have ever had: and now it is a pleasure which no one

can ever have again: it is lost to the world for ever. At that time I

was an undergraduate of Oxford. Though not so astounding, so romantic,

or at first sight so mediaeval as the Norman city, Oxford in those days

still kept a great deal of its earlier loveliness: and the memory of its

grey streets as they then were has been an abiding influence and

pleasure in my life, and would be greater still if I could only forget

what they are now — a matter of far more importance than the so-called

learning of the place could have been to me in any case, but which, as

it was, no one tried to teach me, and I did not try to learn. Since then

the guardians of this beauty and romance so fertile of education, though

professedly engaged in “the higher education” (as the futile system of

compromises which they follow is nick-named), have ignored it utterly,

have made its preservation give way to the pressure of commercial

exigencies, and are determined apparently to destroy it altogether.

There is another pleasure for the world gone down the wind; here, again,

the beauty and romance have been uselessly, causelessly, most foolishly

thrown away.

These two cases are given simply because they have been fixed in my

mind; they are but types of what is going on everywhere throughout

civilization: the world is everywhere growing uglier and more

commonplace, in spite of the conscious and very strenuous efforts of a

small group of people towards the revival of art, which are so obviously

out of joint with the tendency of the age that, while the uncultivated

have not even heard of them, the mass of the cultivated look upon them

as a joke, and even that they are now beginning to get tired of.

Now, if it be true, as I have asserted, that genuine art is an unmixed

blessing to the world, this is a serious matter; for at first sight it

seems to show that there will soon be no art at all in the world, which

will thus lose an unmixed blessing; it can ill afford to do that, I

think.

For art, if it has to die, has worn itself out, and its aim will be a

thing forgotten; and its aim was to make work happy and rest fruitful.

Is all work to be unhappy, all rest unfruitful, then? Indeed, if art is

to perish, that will be the case, unless something is to take its place

— something at present unnamed, undreamed of.

I do not think that anything will take the place of art; not that I

doubt the ingenuity of man, which seems to be boundless in the direction

of making himself unhappy, but because I believe the springs of art in

the human mind to be deathless, and also because it seems to me easy to

see the causes of the present obliteration of the arts.

For we civilized people have not given them up consciously, or of our

free will; we have been forced to give them up. Perhaps I can illustrate

that by the detail of the application of machinery to the production of

things in which artistic form of some sort is possible. Why does a

reasonable man use a machine? Surely to save his labour. There are some

things which a machine can do as well as a man’s hand, plus a tool, can

do them. He need not, for instance, grind his corn in a hand-quern; a

little trickle of water, a wheel, and a few simple contrivances will do

it all perfectly well, and leave him free to smoke his pipe and think,

or to carve the handle of his knife. That, so far, is unmixed gain in

the use of a machine — always, mind you, supposing equality of condition

among men; no art is lost, leisure or time for more pleasurable work is

gained. Perhaps a perfectly reasonable and free man would stop there in

his dealings with machinery; but such reason and freedom are too much to

expect, so let us follow our machine-inventor a step farther. He has to

weave plain cloth, and finds doing so dullish on the one hand, and on

the other that a power-loom will weave the cloth nearly as well as a

hand-loom: so, in order to gain more leisure or time for more

pleasurable work, he uses a power-loom, and foregoes the small advantage

of the little extra art in the cloth. But so doing, as far as the art is

concerned, he has not got a pure gain; he has made a bargain between art

and labour, and got a makeshift as a consequence. I do not say that he

may not be right in so doing, but that he has lost as well as gained.

Now, this is as far as a man who values art and is reasonable would go

in the matter of machinery as long as he was free — that is, was not

forced to work for another man’s profit; so long as he was living in a

society that had accepted equality of condition. Carry the machine used

for art a step farther, and he becomes an unreasonable man, if he values

art and is free. To avoid misunderstanding, I must say that I am

thinking of the modern machine, which is as it were alive, and to which

the man is auxiliary, and not of the old machine, the improved tool,

which is auxiliary to the man, and only works as long as his hand is

thinking; though I will remark, that even this elementary form of

machine has to be dropped when we come to the higher and more intricate

forms of art. Well, as to the machine proper used for art, when it gets

to the stage above dealing with a necessary production that has

accidentally some beauty about it, a reasonable man with a feeling for

art will only use it when he is forced to. If he thinks he would like

ornament, for instance, and knows that the machine cannot do it

properly, and does not care to spend the time to do it properly, why

should he do it at all? He will not diminish his leisure for the sake of

making something he does not want unless some man or band of men force

him to it; so he will either go without the ornament, or sacrifice some

of his leisure to have it genuine. That will be a sign that he wants it

very much, and that it will be worth his trouble: in which case, again,

his labour on it will not be mere trouble, but will interest and please

him by satisfying the needs of his mood of energy.

This, I say, is how a reasonable man would act if he were free from

man’s compulsion; not being free, he acts very differently. He has long

passed the stage at which machines are only used for doing work

repulsive to an average man, or for doing what could be as well done by

a machine as a man, and he instinctively expects a machine to be

invented whenever any product of industry becomes sought after. He is

the slave to machinery; the new machine must be invented, and when

invented he must — I will not say use it, but be used by it, whether he

likes it or not.

But why is he the slave to machinery? Because he is the slave to the

system for whose existence the invention of machinery was necessary.

And now I must drop, or rather have dropped, the assumption of the

equality of condition, and remind you that, though in a sense we are all

the slaves of machinery, yet that some men are so directly without any

metaphor at all, and that these are just those on whom the great body of

the arts depends — the workmen. It is necessary for the system which

keeps them in their position as an inferior class that they should

either be themselves machines or be the servants to machines, in no case

having any interest in the work which they turn out. To their employers

they are, so far as they are workmen, a part of the machinery of the

workshop or the factory; to themselves they are proletarians, human

beings working to live that they may live to work: their part of

craftsmen, of makers of things by their own free will, is played out.

At the risk of being accused of sentimentality, I will say that since

this is so, since the work which produces the things that should be

matters of art is but a burden and a slavery, I exult in this at least,

that it cannot produce art; that all it can do lies between stark

utilitarianism and idiotic sham.

Or indeed is that merely sentimental? Rather, I think, we who have

learned to see the connection between industrial slavery and the

degradation of the arts have learned also to hope for a future for those

arts; since the day will certainly come when men will shake off the

yoke, and refuse to accept the mere artificial compulsion of the

gambling market to waste their lives in ceaseless and hopeless toil; and

when it does come, their instincts for beauty and imagination set free

along with them, will produce such art as they need; and who can say

that it will not as far surpass the art of past ages as that does the

poor relics of it left us by the age of commerce?

A word or two on an objection which has often been made to me when I

have been talking on this subject. It may be said, and is often, You

regret the art of the Middle Ages (as indeed I do), but those who

produced it were not free; they were serfs, or gild-craftsmen surrounded

by brazen walls of trade restrictions; they had no political rights, and

were exploited by their masters, the noble caste, most grievously. Well,

I quite admit that the oppression and violence of the Middle Ages had

its effect on the art of those days, its shortcomings are traceable to

them; they repressed art in certain directions, I do not doubt that; and

for that reason I say, that when we shake off the present oppression as

we shook off the old, we may expect the art of the days of real freedom

to rise above that of those old violent days. But I do say that it was

possible then to have social, organic, hopeful progressive art; whereas

now such poor scraps of it as are left are the result of individual and

wasteful struggle, are retrospective and pessimistic. And this hopeful

art was possible amidst all the oppression of those days, because the

instruments of that oppression were grossly obvious, and were external

to the work of the craftsman. They were laws and customs obviously

intended to rob him, and open violence of the highway-robbery kind. In

short, industrial production was not the instrument used for robbing the

“lower classes;” it is now the main instrument used in that honourable

profession. The mediaeval craftsman was free in his work, therefore he

made it as amusing to himself as he could; and it was his pleasure and

not his pain that made all things beautiful that were made, and lavished

treasures of human hope and thought on everything that man made, from a

cathedral to a porridge-pot. Come, let us put it in the way least

respectful to the mediaeval craftsman, most polite to the modern “hand:”

the poor devil of the fourteenth century, his work was of so little

value that he was allowed to waste it by the hour in pleasing himself —

and others; but our highly-strung mechanic, his minutes are too rich

with the burden of perpetual profit for him to be allowed to waste one

of them on art; the present system will not allow him — cannot allow him

— to produce works of art.

So that there has arisen this strange phenomenon, that there is now a

class of ladies and gentlemen, very refined indeed, though not perhaps

as well informed as is generally supposed, and of this refined class

there are many who do really love beauty and incident — i.e., art, and

would make sacrifices to get it; and these are led by artists of great

manual skill and high intellect, forming altogether a large body of

demand for the article. And yet the supply does not come. Yes, and

moreover, this great body of enthusiastic demanders are no mere poor and

helpless people, ignorant fisher-peasants, half-mad monks,

scatter-brained sansculottes — none of those, in short, the expression

of whose needs has shaken the world so often before, and will do yet

again. No, they are of the ruling classes, the masters of men, who can

live without labour, and have abundant leisure to scheme out the

fulfilment of their desires; and yet I say they cannot have the art

which they so much long for, though they hunt it about the world so

hard, sentimentalizing the sordid lives of the miserable peasants of

Italy and the starving proletarians of her towns, now that all the

picturesqueness has departed from the poor devils of our own

country-side, and of our own slums. Indeed, there is little of reality

left them anywhere, and that little is fast fading away before the needs

of the manufacturer and his ragged regiment of workers, and before the

enthusiasm of the archaeological restorer of the dead past. Soon there

will be nothing left except the lying dreams of history, the miserable

wreckage of our museums and picture-galleries, and the carefully guarded

interiors of our aesthetic drawing-rooms, unreal and foolish, fitting

witnesses of the life of corruption that goes on there, so pinched and

meagre and cowardly, with its concealment and ignoring, rather than

restraint of, natural longings; which does not forbid the greedy

indulgence in them if it can but be decently hidden.

The art then is gone, and can no more be “restored” on its old lines

than a mediaeval building can be. The rich and refined cannot have it

though they would, and though we will believe many of them would. And

why? Because those who could give it to the rich are not allowed by the

rich to do so. In one word, slavery lies between us and art.

I have said as much as that the aim of art was to destroy the curse of

labour by making work the pleasurable satisfaction of our impulse

towards energy, and giving to that energy hope of producing something

worth its exercise.

Now, therefore, I say, that since we cannot have art by striving after

its mere superficial manifestation, since we can have nothing but its

sham by so doing, there yet remains for us to see how it would be if we

let the shadow take care of itself and try, if we can, to lay hold of

the substance. For my part I believe, that if we try to realize the aims

of art without much troubling ourselves what the aspect of the art

itself shall be, we shall find we shall have what we want at last:

whether it is to be called art or not, it will at least be life; and,

after all, that is what we want. It may lead us into new splendours and

beauties of visible art; to architecture with manifolded magnificence

free from the curious incompleteness and failings of that which the

older times have produced — to painting, uniting to the beauty which

mediaeval art attained the realism which modern art aims at; to

sculpture, uniting the beauty of the Greek and the expression of the

Renaissance with some third quality yet undiscovered, so as to give us

the images of men and women splendidly alive, yet not disqualified from

making, as all true sculpture should, architectural ornament. All this

it may do; or, on the other hand, it may lead us into the desert, and

art may seem to be dead amidst us; or feebly and uncertainly to be

struggling in a world which has utterly forgotten its old glories.

For my part, with art as it now is, I cannot bring myself to think that

it much matters which of these dooms awaits it, so long as each bears

with it some hope of what is to come; since here, as in other matters,

there is no hope save in Revolution. The old art is no longer fertile,

no longer yields us anything save elegantly poetical regrets; being

barren, it has but to die, and the matter of moment now is, as to how it

shall die, whether with hope or without it.

What is it, for instance, that has destroyed the Rouen, the Oxford of my

elegant poetic regret? Has it perished for the benefit of the people,

either slowly yielding to the growth of intelligent change and new

happiness? or has it been, as it were, thunderstricken by the tragedy

which mostly accompanies some great new birth? Not so. Neither

phalangstere nor dynamite has swept its beauty away, its destroyers have

not been either the philanthropist or the Socialist, the co-operator or

the anarchist. It has been sold, and at a cheap price indeed: muddled

away by the greed and incompetence of fools who do not know what life

and pleasure mean, who will neither take them themselves nor let others

have them. That is why the death of that beauty wounds us so: no man of

sense or feeling would dare to regret such losses if they had been paid

for by new life and happiness for the people. But there is the people

still as it was before, still facing for its part the monster who

destroyed all that beauty, and whose name is Commercial Profit.

I repeat, that every scrap of genuine art will fall by the same hands if

the matter only goes on long enough, although a sham art may be left in

its place, which may very well be carried on by dilettanti fine

gentlemen and ladies without any help from below; and, to speak plainly,

I fear that this gibbering ghost of the real thing would satisfy a great

many of those who now think themselves lovers of art; though it is not

difficult to see a long vista of its degradation till it shall become at

last a mere laughing-stock; that is to say, if the thing were to go on:

I mean, if art were to be for ever the amusement of those whom we now

call ladies and gentlemen.

But for my part I do not think it will go on long enough to reach such

depths as that; and yet I should be hypocritical if I were to say that I

thought that the change in the basis of society, which would enfranchise

labour and make men practically equal in condition, would lead us by a

short road to the splendid new birth of art which I have mentioned,

though I feel quite certain that it would not leave what we now call art

untouched, since the aims of that revolution do include the aims of art

— viz., abolishing the curse of labour.

I suppose that this is what is likely to happen; that machinery will go

on developing, with the purpose of saving men labour, till the mass of

the people attain real leisure enough to be able to appreciate the

pleasure of life; till, in fact, they have attained such mastery over

Nature that they no longer fear starvation as a penalty for not working

more than enough. When they get to that point they will doubtless turn

themselves and begin to find out what it is that they really want to do.

They would soon find out that the less work they did (the less work

unaccompanied by art, I mean), the more desirable a dwelling-place the

earth would be; they would accordingly do less and less work, till the

mood of energy, of which I began by speaking, urged them on afresh: but

by that time Nature, relieved by the relaxation of man’s work, would be

recovering her ancient beauty, and be teaching men the old story of art.

And as the Artificial Famine, caused by men working for the profit of a

master, and which we now look upon as a matter of course, would have

long disappeared, they would be free to do as they chose, and they would

set aside their machines in all cases where the work seemed pleasant or

desirable for handiwork; till in all crafts where production of beauty

was required, the most direct communication between a man’s hand and his

brain would be sought for. And there would be many occupations also, as

the processes of agriculture, in which the voluntary exercise of energy

would be thought so delightful, that people would not dream of handing

over its pleasure to the jaws of a machine.

In short, men will find out that the men of our days were wrong in first

multiplying their needs, and then trying, each man of them, to evade all

participation in the means and processes whereby those needs are

satisfied; that this kind of division of labour is really only a new and

wilful form of arrogant and slothful ignorance, far more injurious to

the happiness and contentment of life than the ignorance of the

processes of Nature, of what we sometimes call science, which men of the

earlier days unwittingly lived in.

They will discover, or rediscover rather, that the true secret of

happiness lies in the taking a genuine interest in all the details of

daily life, in elevating them by art instead of handing the performance

of them over to unregarded drudges, and ignoring them; and that in cases

where it was impossible either so to elevate them and make them

interesting, or to lighten them by the use of machinery, so as to make

the labour of them trifling, that should be taken as a token that the

supposed advantages gained by them were not worth the trouble and had

better be given up. All this to my mind would be the outcome of men

throwing off the burden of Artificial Famine, supposing, as I cannot

help supposing, that the impulses which have from the first glimmerings

of history urged men on to the practice of Art were still at work in

them.

Thus and thus only can come about the new birth of Art, and I think it

will come about thus. You may say it is a long process, and so it is;

but I can conceive of a longer. I have given you the Socialist or

Optimist view of the matter. Now for the Pessimist view.

I can conceive that the revolt against Artificial Famine or Capitalism,

which is now on foot, may be vanquished. The result will be that the

working class — the slaves of society — will become more and more

degraded; that they will not strive against overwhelming force, but,

stimulated by that love of life which Nature, always anxious about the

perpetuation of the race, has implanted in us, will learn to bear

everything — starvation, overwork, dirt, ignorance, brutality. All these

things they will bear, as, alas! they bear them too well even now; all

this rather than risk sweet life and bitter livelihood, and all sparks

of hope and manliness will die out of them.

Nor will their masters be much better off: the earth’s surface will be

hideous everywhere, save in the uninhabitable desert; Art will utterly

perish, as in the manual arts so in literature, which will become, as it

is indeed speedily becoming, a mere string of orderly and calculated

ineptitudes and passionless ingenuities; Science will grow more and more

one-sided, more incomplete, more wordy and useless, till at last she

will pile herself up into such a mass of superstition, that beside it

the theologies of old time will seem mere reason and enlightenment. All

will get lower and lower, till the heroic struggles of the past to

realize hope from year to year, from century to century, will be utterly

forgotten, and man will be an indescribable being — hopeless,

desireless, lifeless.

And will there be deliverance from this even? Maybe: man may, after some

terrible cataclysm, learn to strive towards a healthy animalism, may

grow from a tolerable animal into a savage, from a savage into a

barbarian, and so on; and some thousands of years hence he may be

beginning once more those arts which we have now lost, and be carving

interlacements like the New Zealanders, or scratching forms of animals

on their cleaned blade-bones, like the pre-historic men of the drift.

But in any case, according to the pessimist view, which looks upon

revolt against Artificial Famine as impossible to succeed, we shall

wearily trudge the circle again, until some accident, some unforeseen

consequence of arrangement, makes an end of us altogether.

That pessimism I do not believe in, nor, on the other hand, do I suppose

that it is altogether a matter of our wills as to whether we shall

further human progress or human degradation; yet, since there are those

who are impelled towards the Socialist or Optimistic side of things, I

must conclude that there is some hope of its prevailing, that the

strenuous efforts of many individuals imply a force which is thrusting

them on. So that I believe that the “Aims of Art” will be realized,

though I know that they cannot be, so long as we groan under the tyranny

of Artificial Famine. Once again I warn you against supposing, you who

may specially love art, that you will do any good by attempting to

revivify art by dealing with its dead exterior. I say it is the aims of

art that you must seek rather than the art itself; and in that search we

may find ourselves in a world blank and bare, as the result of our

caring at least this much for art, that we will not endure the shams of

it.

Anyhow, I ask you to think with me that the worst which can happen to us

is to endure tamely the evils that we see; that no trouble or turmoil is

so bad as that; that the necessary destruction which reconstruction

bears with it must be taken calmly; that everywhere — in State, in

Church, in the household — we must be resolute to endure no tyranny,

accept no lie, quail before no fear, although they may come before us

disguised as piety, duty, or affection, as useful opportunity and

good-nature, as prudence or kindness. The world’s roughness, falseness,

and injustice will bring about their natural consequences, and we and

our lives are part of those consequences; but since we inherit also the

consequences of old resistance to those curses, let us each look to it

to have our fair share of that inheritance also, which, if nothing else

come of it, will at least bring to us courage and hope; that is, eager

life while we live, which is above all things the Aim of Art.

Useful Work Versus Useless Toil

The above title may strike some of my readers as strange. It is assumed

by most people nowadays that all work is useful, and by most well-to-to

people that all work is desirable. Most people, well-to-do or not,

believe that, even when a man is doing work which appears to be useless,

he is earning his livelihood by it — he is “employed,” as the phrase

goes; and most of those who are well-to-do cheer on the happy worker

with congratulations and praises, if he is only “industrious” enough and

deprives himself of all pleasure and holidays in the sacred cause of

labour. In short, it has become an article of the creed of modern

morality that all labour is good in itself — a convenient belief to

those who live on the labour of others. But as to those on whom they

live, I recommend them not to take it on trust, but to look into the

matter a little deeper.

Let us grant, first, that the race of man must either labour or perish.

Nature does not give us our livelihood gratis; we must win it by toil of

some sort or degree. Let us see, then, if she does not give us some

compensation for this compulsion to labour, since certainly in other

matters she takes care to make the acts necessary to the continuance of

life in the individual and the race not only endurable, but even

pleasurable.

You may be sure that she does so, that it is of the nature of man, when

he is not diseased, to take pleasure in his work under certain

conditions. And, yet, we must say in the teeth of the hypocritical

praise of all labour, whatsoever it may be, of which I have made

mention, that there is some labour which is so far from being a blessing

that it is a curse; that it would be better for the community and for

the worker if the latter were to fold his hands and refuse to work, and

either die or let us pack him off to the workhouse or prison — which you

will.

Here, you see, are two kinds of work — one good, the other bad; one not

far removed from a blessing, a lightening of life; the other a mere

curse, a burden to life.

What is the difference between them, then? This: one has hope in it, the

other has not. It is manly to do the one kind of work, and manly also to

refuse to do the other.

What is the nature of the hope which, when it is present in work, makes

it worth doing?

It is threefold, I think — hope of rest, hope of product, hope of

pleasure in the work itself; and hope of these also in some abundance

and of good quality; rest enough and good enough to be worth having;

product worth having by one who is neither a fool nor an ascetic;

pleasure enough for all for us to be conscious of it while we are at

work; not a mere habit, the loss of which we shall feel as a fidgety man

feels the loss of the bit of string he fidgets with.

I have put the hope of rest first because it is the simplest and most

natural part of our hope. Whatever pleasure there is in some work, there

is certainly some pain in all work, the beast-like pain of stirring up

our slumbering energies to action, the beast-like dread of change when

things are pretty well with us; and the compensation for this animal

pain is animal rest. We must feel while we are working that the time

will come when we shall not have to work. Also the rest, when it comes,

must be long enough to allow us to enjoy it; it must be longer than is

merely necessary for us to recover the strength we have expended in

working, and it must be animal rest also in this, that it must not be

disturbed by anxiety, else we shall not be able to enjoy it. If we have

this amount and kind of rest we shall, so far, be no worse off than the

beasts.

As to the hope of product, I have said that Nature compels us to work

for that. It remains for us to look to it that we do really produce

something, and not nothing, or at least nothing that we want or are

allowed to use. If we look to this and use our wills we shall, so far,

be better than machines.

The hope of pleasure in the work itself: how strange that hope must seem

to some of my readers — to most of them! Yet I think that to all living

things there is a pleasure in the exercise of their energies, and that

even beasts rejoice in being lithe and swift and strong. But a man at

work, making something which he feels will exist because he is working

at it and wills it, is exercising the energies of his mind and soul as

well as of his body. Memory and imagination help him as he works. Not

only his own thoughts, but the thoughts of the men of past ages guide

his hands; and, as a part of the human race, he creates. If we work thus

we shall be men, and our days will be happy and eventful.

Thus worthy work carries with it the hope of pleasure in rest, the hope

of the pleasure in our using what it makes, and the hope of pleasure in

our daily creative skill.

All other work but this is worthless; it is slaves’ work — mere toiling

to live, that we may live to toil.

Therefore, since we have, as it were, a pair of scales in which to weigh

the work now done in the world, let us use them. Let us estimate the

worthiness of the work we do, after so many thousand years of toil, so

many promises of hope deferred, such boundless exultation over the

progress of civilization and the gain of liberty.

Now, the first thing as to the work done in civilization and the easiest

to notice is that it is portioned out very unequally amongst the

different classes of society. First, there are people — not a few — who

do no work, and make no pretence of doing any. Next, there are people,

and very many of them, who work fairly hard, though with abundant

easements and holidays, claimed and allowed; and lastly, there are

people who work so hard that they may be said to do nothing else than

work, and are accordingly called “the working classes,” as distinguished

from the middle classes and the rich, or aristocracy, whom I have

mentioned above.

It is clear that this inequality presses heavily upon the “working”

class, and must visibly tend to destroy their hope of rest at least, and

so, in that particular, make them worse off than mere beasts of the

field; but that is not the sum and end of our folly of turning useful

work into useless toil, but only the beginning of it.

For first, as to the class of rich people doing no work, we all know

that they consume a great deal while they produce nothing. Therefore,

clearly, they have to be kept at the expense of those who do work, just

as paupers have, and are a mere burden on the community. In these days

there are many who have learned to see this, though they can see no

further into the evils of our present system, and have formed no idea of

any scheme for getting rid of this burden; though perhaps they have a

vague hope that changes in the system of voting for members of the House

of Commons may, as if by magic, tend in that direction. With such hopes

or superstitions we need not trouble ourselves. Moreover, this class,

the aristocracy, once thought most necessary to the State, is scant of

numbers, and has now no power of its own, but depends on the support of

the class next below it — the middle class. In fact, it is really

composed either of the most successful men of that class, or of their

immediate descendants.

As to the middle class, including the trading, manufacturing, and

professional people of our society, they do, as a rule, seem to work

quite hard enough, and so at first sight might be thought to help the

community, and not burden it. But by far the greater part of them,

though they work, do not produce, and even when they do produce, as in

the case of those engaged (wastefully indeed) in the distribution of

goods, or doctors, or (genuine) artists and literary men, they consume

out of all proportion to their due share. The commercial and

manufacturing part of them, the most powerful part, spend their lives

and energies in fighting amongst themselves for their respective shares

of the wealth which they force the genuine workers to provide for them;

the others are almost wholly the hangers-on of these; they do not work

for the public, but a privileged class: they are the parasites of

property, sometimes, as in the case of lawyers, undisguisedly so;

sometimes, as the doctors and others above mentioned, professing to be

useful, but too often of no use save as supporters of the system of

folly, fraud, and tyranny of which they form a part. And all these we

must remember have, as a rule, one aim in view; not the production of

utilities, but the gaining of a position either for themselves or their

children in which they will not have to work at all. It is their

ambition and the end of their whole lives to gain, if not for themselves

yet at least for their children, the proud position of being obvious

burdens on the community. For their work itself in spite of the sham

dignity with which they surround it, they care nothing: save a few

enthusiasts, men of science, art or letters, who, if they are not the

salt of the earth, are at least (and oh, the pity of it!) the salt of

the miserable system of which they are the slaves, which hinders and

thwarts them at every turn, and even sometimes corrupts them.

Here then is another class, this time very numerous and all-powerful,

which produces very little and consumes enormously, and is therefore in

the main supported, as paupers are, by the real producers. The class

that remains to be considered produces all that is produced, and

supports both itself and the other classes, though it is placed in a

position of inferiority to them; real inferiority, mind you, involving a

degradation both of mind and body. But it is a necessary consequence of

this tyranny and folly that again many of these workers are not

producers. A vast number of them once more are merely parasites of

property, some of them openly so, as the soldiers by land and sea who

are kept on foot for the perpetuating of national rivalries and

enmities, and for the purposes of the national struggle for the share of

the product of unpaid labour. But besides this obvious burden on the

producers and the scarcely less obvious one of domestic servants, there

is first the army of clerks, shop-assistants, and so forth, who are

engaged in the service of the private war for wealth, which, as above

said, is the real occupation of the well-to-do middle class. This is a

larger body of workers than might be supposed, for it includes amongst

others all those engaged in what I should call competitive salesmanship,

or, to use a less dignified word, the puffery of wares, which has now

got to such a pitch that there are many things which cost far more to

sell than they do to make.

Next there is the mass of people employed in making all those articles

of folly and luxury, the demand for which is the outcome of the

existence of the rich non-producing classes; things which people leading

a manly and uncorrupted life would not ask for or dream of. These

things, whoever may gainsay me, I will for ever refuse to call wealth:

they are not wealth, but waste. Wealth is what Nature gives us and what

a reasonable man can make out of the gifts of Nature for his reasonable

use. The sunlight, the fresh air, the unspoiled face of the earth, food,

raiment and housing necessary and decent; the storing up of knowledge of

all kinds, and the power of disseminating it; means of free

communication between man and man; works of art, the beauty which man

creates when he is most a man, most aspiring and thoughtful — all things

which serve the pleasure of people, free, manly and uncorrupted. This is

wealth. Nor can I think of anything worth having which does not come

under one or other of these heads. But think, I beseech you, of the

product of England, the workshop of the world, and will you not be

bewildered, as I am, at the thought of the mass of things which no sane

man could desire, but which our useless toil makes — and sells?

Now, further, there is even a sadder industry yet, which is forced on

many, very many, of our workers — the making of wares which are

necessary to them and their brethren, because they are an inferior

class. For if many men live without producing, nay, must live lives so

empty and foolish that they force a great part of the workers to produce

wares which no one needs, not even the rich, it follows that most men

must be poor; and, living as they do on wages from those whom they

support, cannot get for their use the goods which men naturally desire,

but must put up with miserable makeshifts for them, with coarse food

that does not nourish, with rotten raiment which does not shelter, with

wretched houses which may well make a town-dweller in civilization look

back with regret to the tent of the nomad tribe, or the cave of the

pre-historic savage. Nay, the workers must even lend a hand to the great

industrial invention of the age — adulteration, and by its help produce

for their own use shams and mockeries of the luxury of the rich; for the

wage-earners must always live as the wage-payers bid them, and their

very habits of life are forced on them by their masters.

But it is waste of time to try to express in words due contempt of the

productions of the much-praised cheapness of our epoch. It must be

enough to say that this cheapness is necessary to the system of

exploiting on which modern manufacture rests. In other words, our

society includes a great mass of slaves, who must be fed, clothed,

housed and amused as slaves, and that their daily necessity compels them

to make the slave-wares whose use is the perpetuation of their slavery.

To sum up, then, concerning the manner of work in civilized States,

these States are composed of three classes — a class which does not even

pretend to work, a class which pretends to work but which produces

nothing, and a class which works, but is compelled by the other two

classes to do work which is often unproductive.

Civilization therefore wastes its own resources, and will do so as long

as the present system lasts. These are cold words with which to describe

the tyranny under which we suffer; try then to consider what they mean.

There is a certain amount of natural material and of natural forces in

the world, and a certain amount of labour-power inherent in the persons

of the men that inhabit it. Men urged by their necessities and desires

have laboured for many thousands of years at the task of subjugating the

forces of Nature and of making the natural material useful to them. To

our eyes, since we cannot see into the future, that struggle with Nature

seems nearly over, and the victory of the human race over her nearly

complete. And, looking backwards to the time when history first began,

we note that the progress of that victory has been far swifter and more

startling within the last two hundred years than ever before. Surely,

therefore, we moderns ought to be in all ways vastly better off than any

who have gone before us. Surely we ought, one and all of us, to be

wealthy, to be well furnished with the good things which our victory

over Nature has won for us.

But what is the real fact? Who will dare to deny that the great mass of

civilized men are poor? So poor are they that it is mere childishness

troubling ourselves to discuss whether perhaps they are in some ways a

little better off than their forefathers. They are poor; nor can their

poverty be measured by the poverty of a resourceless savage, for he

knows of nothing else than his poverty; that he should be cold, hungry,

houseless, dirty, ignorant, all that is to him as natural as that he

should have a skin. But for us, for the most of us, civilization has

bred desires which she forbids us to satisfy, and so is not merely a

niggard but a torturer also.

Thus then have the fruits of our victory over Nature been stolen from

us, thus has compulsion by Nature to labour in hope of rest, gain, and

pleasure been turned into compulsion by man to labour in hope — of

living to labour!

What shall we do then, can we mend it?

Well, remember once more that it is not our remote ancestors who

achieved the victory over Nature, but our fathers, nay, our very selves.

For us to sit hopeless and helpless then would be a strange folly

indeed: be sure that we can amend it. What, then, is the first thing to

be done?

We have seen that modern society is divided into two classes, one of

which is privileged to be kept by the labour of the other — that is, it

forces the other to work for it and takes from this inferior class

everything that it can take from it, and uses the wealth so taken to

keep its own members in a superior position, to make them beings of a

higher order than the others: longer lived, more beautiful, more

honoured, more refined than those of the other class. I do not say that

it troubles itself about its members being positively long lived,

beautiful or refined, but merely insists that they shall be so

relatively to the inferior class. As also it cannot use the labour-

power of the inferior class fairly in producing real wealth, it wastes

it wholesale in the production of rubbish.

It is this robbery and waste on the part of the minority which keeps the

majority poor; if it could be shown that it is necessary for the

preservation of society that this should be submitted to, little more

could be said on the matter, save that the despair of the oppressed

majority would probably at some time or other destroy Society. But it

has been shown, on the contrary, even by such incomplete experiments,

for instance, as Co-operation (so called), that the existence of a

privileged class is by no means necessary for the production of wealth,

but rather for the “government” of the producers of wealth, or, in other

words, for the upholding of privilege.

The first step to be taken then is to abolish a class of men privileged

to shirk their duties as men, thus forcing others to do the work which

they refuse to do. All must work according to their ability, and so

produce what they consume — that is, each man should work as well as he

can for his own livelihood, and his livelihood should be assured to him;

that is to say, all the advantages which society would provide for each

and all of its members.

Thus, at last, would true Society be founded. It would rest on equality

of condition. No man would be tormented for the benefit of another —

nay, no one man would be tormented for the benefit of Society. Nor,

indeed, can that order be called Society which is not upheld for the

benefit of every one of its members.

But since men live now, badly as they live, when so many people do not

produce at all, and when so much work is wasted, it is clear that, under

conditions where all produced and no work was wasted, not only would

every one work with the certain hope of gaining a due share of wealth by

his work, but also he could not miss his due share of rest. Here, then,

are two out of the three kinds of hope mentioned above as an essential

part of worthy work assured to the worker. When class robbery is

abolished, every man will reap the fruits of his labour, every man will

have due rest — leisure, that is. Some Socialists might say we need not

go any further than this; it is enough that the worker should get the

full produce of his work, and that his rest should be abundant. But

though the compulsion of man’s tyranny is thus abolished, I yet demand

compensation for the compulsion of Nature’s necessity. As long as the

work is repulsive it will still be a burden which must be taken up

daily, and even so would mar our life, even though the hours of labour

were short. What we want to do is to add to our wealth without

diminishing our pleasure. Nature will not be finally conquered till our

work becomes a part of the pleasure of our lives.

That first step of freeing people from the compulsion to labour

needlessly will at least put us on the way towards this happy end; for

we shall then have time and opportunities for bringing it about. As

things are now, between the waste of labour-power in mere idleness and

its waste in unproductive work, it is clear that the world of

civilization is supported by a small part of its people; when all were

working usefully for its support, the share of work which each would

have to do would be but small, if our standard of life were about on the

footing of what well-to-do and refined people now think desirable. We

shall have labour-power to spare, and shall, in short, be as wealthy as

we please. It will be easy to live. If we were to wake up some morning

now, under our present system, and find it “easy to live,” that system

would force us to set to work at once and make it hard to live; we

should call that “developing our resources,” or some such fine name. The

multiplication of labour has become a necessity for us, and as long as

that goes on no ingenuity in the invention of machines will be of any

real use to us. Each new machine will cause a certain amount of misery

among the workers whose special industry it may disturb; so many of them

will be reduced from skilled to unskilled workmen, and then gradually

matters will slip into their due grooves, and all will work apparently

smoothly again; and if it were not that all this is preparing

revolution, things would be, for the greater part of men, just as they

were before the new wonderful invention.

But when revolution has made it “easy to live,” when all are working

harmoniously together and there is no one to rob the worker of his time,

that is to say, his life; in those coming days there will be no

compulsion on us to go on producing things we do not want, no compulsion

on us to labour for nothing; we shall be able calmly and thoughtfully to

consider what we shall do with our wealth of labour-power. Now, for my

part, I think the first use we ought to make of that wealth, of that

freedom, should be to make all our labour, even the commonest and most

necessary, pleasant to everybody; for thinking over the matter carefully

I can see that the one course which will certainly make life happy in

the face of all accidents and troubles is to take a pleasurable interest

in all the details of life. And lest perchance you think that an

assertion too universally accepted to be worth making, let me remind you

how entirely modern civilization forbids it; with what sordid, and even

terrible, details it surrounds the life of the poor, what a mechanical

and empty life she forces on the rich; and how rare a holiday it is for

any of us to feel ourselves a part of Nature, and unhurriedly,

thoughtfully, and happily to note the course of our lives amidst all the

little links of events which connect them with the lives of others, and

build up the great whole of humanity.

But such a holiday our whole lives might be, if we were resolute to make

all our labour reasonable and pleasant. But we must be resolute indeed;

for no half measures will help us here. It has been said already that

our present joyless labour, and our lives scared and anxious as the life

of a hunted beast, are forced upon us by the present system of producing

for the profit of the privileged classes. It is necessary to state what

this means. Under the present system of wages and capital the

“manufacturer” (most absurdly so called, since a manufacturer means a

person who makes with his hands) having a monopoly of the means whereby

the power to labour inherent in every man’s body can be used for

production, is the master of those who are not so privileged; he, and he

alone, is able to make use of this labour-power, which, on the other

hand, is the only commodity by means of which his “capital,” that is to

say, the accumulated product of past labour, can be made productive to

him. He therefore buys the labour-power of those who are bare of capital

and can only live by selling it to him; his purpose in this transaction

is to increase his capital, to make it breed. It is clear that if he

paid those with whom he makes his bargain the full value of their

labour, that is to say, all that they produced, he would fail in his

purpose. But since he is the monopolist of the means of productive

labour, he can compel them to make a bargain better for him and worse

for them than that; which bargain is that after they have earned their

livelihood, estimated according to a standard high enough to ensure

their peaceable submission to his mastership, the rest (and by far the

larger part as a matter of fact) of what they produce shall belong to

him, shall be his property to do as he likes with, to use or abuse at

his pleasure; which property is, as we all know, jealously guarded by

army and navy, police and prison; in short, by that huge mass of

physical force which superstition, habit, fear of death by starvation —

ignorance, in one word, among the propertyless masses enables the

propertied classes to use for the subjection of — their slaves.

Now, at other times, other evils resulting from this system may be put

forward. What I want to point out now is the impossibility of our

attaining to attractive labour under this system, and to repeat that it

is this robbery (there is no other word for it) which wastes the

available labour-power of the civilized world, forcing many men to do

nothing, and many, very many more to do nothing useful; and forcing

those who carry on really useful labour to most burdensome over-work.

For understand once for all that the “manufacturer” aims primarily at

producing, by means of the labour he has stolen from others, not goods

but profits, that is, the “wealth” that is produced over and above the

livelihood of his workmen, and the wear and tear of his machinery.

Whether that “wealth” is real or sham matters nothing to him. If it

sells and yields him a “profit” it is all right. I have said that, owing

to there being rich people who have more money than they can spend

reasonably, and who therefore buy sham wealth, there is waste on that

side; and also that, owing to there being poor people who cannot afford

to buy things which are worth making, there is waste on that side. So

that the “demand” which the capitalist “supplies” is a false demand. The

market in which he sells is “rigged” by the miserable inequalities

produced by the robbery of the system of Capital and Wages.

It is this system, therefore, which we must be resolute in getting rid

of, if we are to attain to happy and useful work for all. The first step

towards making labour attractive is to get the means of making labour

fruitful, the Capital, including the land, machinery, factories, &c.,

into the hands of the community, to be used for the good of all alike,

so that we might all work at “supplying” the real “demands” of each and

all — that is to say, work for livelihood, instead of working to supply

the demand of the profit market — instead of working for profit — i.e.,

the power of compelling other men to work against their will.

When this first step has been taken and men begin to understand that

Nature wills all men either to work or starve, and when they are no

longer such fools as to allow some the alternative of stealing, when

this happy day is come, we shall then be relieved from the tax of waste,

and consequently shall find that we have, as aforesaid, a mass of

labour-power available, which will enable us to live as we please within

reasonable limits. We shall no longer be hurried and driven by the fear

of starvation, which at present presses no less on the greater part of

men in civilized communities than it does on mere savages. The first and

most obvious necessities will be so easily provided for in a community

in which there is no waste of labour, that we shall have time to look

round and consider what we really do want, that can be obtained without

over-taxing our energies; for the often-expressed fear of mere idleness

falling upon us when the force supplied by the present hierarchy of

compulsion is withdrawn, is a fear which is but generated by the burden

of excessive and repulsive labour, which we most of us have to bear at

present.

I say once more that, in my belief, the first thing which we shall think

so necessary as to be worth sacrificing some idle time for, will be the

attractiveness of labour. No very heavy sacrifice will be required for

attaining this object, but some will be required. For we may hope that

men who have just waded through a period of strife and revolution will

be the last to put up long with a life of mere utilitarianism, though

Socialists are sometimes accused by ignorant persons of aiming at such a

life. On the other hand, the ornamental part of modern life is already

rotten to the core, and must be utterly swept away before the new order

of things is realized. There is nothing of it — there is nothing which

could come of it that could satisfy the aspirations of men set free from

the tyranny of commercialism.

We must begin to build up the ornamental part of life — its pleasures,

bodily and mental, scientific and artistic, social and individual — on

the basis of work undertaken willingly and cheerfully, with the

consciousness of benefiting ourselves and our neighbours by it. Such

absolutely necessary work as we should have to do would in the first

place take up but a small part of each day, and so far would not be

burdensome; but it would be a task of daily recurrence, and therefore

would spoil our day’s pleasure unless it were made at least endurable

while it lasted. In other words, all labour, even the commonest, must be

made attractive.

How can this be done? — is the question the answer to which will take up

the rest of this paper. In giving some hints on this question, I know

that, while all Socialists will agree with many of the suggestions made,

some of them may seem to some strange and venturesome. These must be

considered as being given without any intention of dogmatizing, and as

merely expressing my own personal opinion.

From all that has been said already it follows that labour, to be

attractive, must be directed towards some obviously useful end, unless

in cases where it is undertaken voluntarily by each individual as a

pastime. This element of obvious usefulness is all the more to be

counted on in sweetening tasks otherwise irksome, since social morality,

the responsibility of man towards the life of man, will, in the new

order of things, take the place of theological morality, or the

responsibility of man to some abstract idea. Next, the day’s work will

be short. This need not be insisted on. It is clear that with work

unwasted it can be short. It is clear also that much work which is now a

torment, would be easily endurable if it were much shortened.

Variety of work is the next point, and a most important one. To compel a

man to do day after day the same task, without any hope of escape or

change, means nothing short of turning his life into a prison-torment.

Nothing but the tyranny of profit-grinding makes this necessary. A man

might easily learn and practise at least three crafts, varying sedentary

occupation with outdoor — occupation calling for the exercise of strong

bodily energy for work in which the mind had more to do. There are few

men, for instance, who would not wish to spend part of their lives in

the most necessary and pleasantest of all work — cultivating the earth.

One thing which will make this variety of employment possible will be

the form that education will take in a socially ordered community. At

present all education is directed towards the end of fitting people to

take their places in the hierarchy of commerce — these as masters, those

as workmen. The education of the masters is more ornamental than that of

the workmen, but it is commercial still; and even at the ancient

universities learning is but little regarded, unless it can in the long

run be made to pay. Due education is a totally different thing from

this, and concerns itself in finding out what different people are fit

for, and helping them along the road which they are inclined to take. In

a duly ordered society, therefore, young people would be taught such

handicrafts as they had a turn for as a part of their education, the

discipline of their minds and bodies; and adults would also have

opportunities of learning in the same schools, for the development of

individual capacities would be of all things chiefly aimed at by

education, instead, as now, the subordination of all capacities to the

great end of “money-making” for oneself — or one’s master. The amount of

talent, and even genius, which the present system crushes, and which

would be drawn out by such a system, would make our daily work easy and

interesting.

Under this head of variety I will note one product of industry which has

suffered so much from commercialism that it can scarcely be said to

exist, and is, indeed, so foreign from our epoch that I fear there are

some who will find it difficult to understand what I have to say on the

subject, which I nevertheless must say, since it is really a most

important one. I mean that side of art which is, or ought to be, done by

the ordinary workman while he is about his ordinary work, and which has

got to be called, very properly, Popular Art. This art, I repeat, no

longer exists now, having been killed by commercialism. But from the

beginning of man’s contest with Nature till the rise of the present

capitalistic system, it was alive, and generally flourished. While it

lasted, everything that was made by man was adorned by man, just as

everything made by Nature is adorned by her. The craftsman, as he

fashioned the thing he had under his hand, ornamented it so naturally

and so entirely without conscious effort, that it is often difficult to

distinguish where the mere utilitarian part of his work ended and the

ornamental began. Now the origin of this art was the necessity that the

workman felt for variety in his work, and though the beauty produced by

this desire was a great gift to the world, yet the obtaining variety and

pleasure in the work by the workman was a matter of more importance

still, for it stamped all labour with the impress of pleasure. All this

has now quite disappeared from the work of civilization. If you wish to

have ornament, you must pay specially for it, and the workman is

compelled to produce ornament, as he is to produce other wares. He is

compelled to pretend happiness in his work, so that the beauty produced

by man’s hand, which was once a solace to his labour, has now become an

extra burden to him, and ornament is now but one of the follies of

useless toil, and perhaps not the least irksome of its fetters.

Besides the short duration of labour, its conscious usefulness, and the

variety which should go with it, there is another thing needed to make

it attractive, and that is pleasant surroundings. The misery and squalor

which we people of civilization bear with so much complacency as a

necessary part of the manufacturing system, is just as necessary to the

community at large as a proportionate amount of filth would be in the

house of a private rich man. If such a man were to allow the cinders to

be raked all over his drawing-room, and a privy to be established in

each corner of his dining-room, if he habitually made a dust and refuse

heap of his once beautiful garden, never washed his sheets or changed

his tablecloth, and made his family sleep five in a bed, he would surely

find himself in the claws of a commission de lunatico. But such acts of

miserly folly are just what our present society is doing daily under the

compulsion of a supposed necessity, which is nothing short of madness. I

beg you to bring your commission of lunacy against civilization without

more delay.

For all our crowded towns and bewildering factories are simply the

outcome of the profit system. Capitalistic manufacture, capitalistic

land-owning, and capitalistic exchange force men into big cities in

order to manipulate them in the interests of capital; the same tyranny

contracts the due space of the factory so much that (for instance) the

interior of a great weaving-shed is almost as ridiculous a spectacle as

it is a horrible one. There is no other necessity for all this, save the

necessity for grinding profits out of men’s lives, and of producing

cheap goods for the use (and subjection) of the slaves who grind. All

labour is not yet driven into factories; often where it is there is no

necessity for it, save again the profit-tyranny. People engaged in all

such labour need by no means be compelled to pig together in close city

quarters. There is no reason why they should not follow their

occupations in quiet country homes, in industrial colleges, in small

towns, or, in short, where they find it happiest for them to live.

As to that part of labour which must be associated on a large scale,

this very factory system, under a reasonable order of things (though to

my mind there might still be drawbacks to it), would at least offer

opportunities for a full and eager social life surrounded by many

pleasures. The factories might be centres of intellectual activity also,

and work in them might well be varied very much: the tending of the

necessary machinery might to each individual be but a short part of the

day’s work. The other work might vary from raising food from the

surrounding country to the study and practice of art and science. It is

a matter of course that people engaged in such work, and being the

masters of their own lives, would not allow any hurry or want of

foresight to force them into enduring dirt, disorder, or want of room.

Science duly applied would enable them to get rid of refuse, to

minimize, if not wholly to destroy, all the inconveniences which at

present attend the use of elaborate machinery, such as smoke, stench and

noise; nor would they endure that the buildings in which they worked or

lived should be ugly blots on the fair face of the earth. Beginning by

making their factories, buildings, and sheds decent and convenient like

their homes, they would infallibly go on to make them not merely

negatively good, inoffensive merely, but even beautiful, so that the

glorious art of architecture, now for some time slain by commercial

greed, would be born again and flourish.

So, you see, I claim that work in a duly ordered community should be

made attractive by the consciousness of usefulness, by its being carried

on with intelligent interest, by variety, and by its being exercised

amidst pleasurable surroundings. But I have also claimed, as we all do,

that the day’s work should not be wearisomely long. It may be said, “How

can you make this last claim square with the others? If the work is to

be so refined, will not the goods made be very expensive?”

I do admit, as I have said before, that some sacrifice will be necessary

in order to make labour attractive. I mean that, if we could be

contented in a free community to work in the same hurried, dirty,

disorderly, heartless way as we do now, we might shorten our day’s

labour very much more than I suppose we shall do, taking all kinds of

labour into account. But if we did, it would mean that our new-won

freedom of condition would leave us listless and wretched, if not

anxious, as we are now, which I hold is simply impossible. We should be

contented to make the sacrifices necessary for raising our condition to

the standard called out for as desirable by the whole community. Nor

only so. We should, individually, be emulous to sacrifice quite freely

still more of our time and our ease towards the raising of the standard

of life. Persons, either by themselves or associated for such purposes,

would freely, and for the love of the work and for its results —

stimulated by the hope of the pleasure of creation — produce those

ornaments of life for the service of all, which they are now bribed to

produce (or pretend to produce) for the service of a few rich men. The

experiment of a civilized community living wholly without art or

literature has not yet been tried. The past degradation and corruption

of civilization may force this denial of pleasure upon the society which

will arise from its ashes. If that must be, we will accept the passing

phase of utilitarianism as a foundation for the art which is to be. If

the cripple and the starveling disappear from our streets, if the earth

nourish us all alike, if the sun shine for all of us alike, if to one

and all of us the glorious drama of the earth — day and night, summer

and winter — can be presented as a thing to understand and love, we can

afford to wait awhile till we are purified from the shame of the past

corruption, and till art arises again amongst people freed from the

terror of the slave and the shame of the robber.

Meantime, in any case, the refinement, thoughtfulness, and deliberation

of labour must indeed be paid for, but not by compulsion to labour long

hours. Our epoch has invented machines which would have appeared wild

dreams to the men of past ages, and of those machines we have as yet

made no use.

They are called “labour-saving” machines — a commonly used phrase which

implies what we expect of them; but we do not get what we expect. What

they really do is to reduce the skilled labourer to the ranks of the

unskilled, to increase the number of the “reserve army of labour” — that

is, to increase the precariousness of life among the workers and to

intensify the labour of those who serve the machines (as slaves their

masters). All this they do by the way, while they pile up the profits of

the employers of labour, or force them to expend those profits in bitter

commercial war with each other. In a true society these miracles of

ingenuity would be for the first time used for minimizing the amount of

time spent in unattractive labour, which by their means might be so

reduced as to be but a very light burden on each individual. All the

more as these machines would most certainly be very much improved when

it was no longer a question as to whether their improvement would “pay”

the individual, but rather whether it would benefit the community.

So much for the ordinary use of machinery, which would probably, after a

time, be somewhat restricted when men found out that there was no need

for anxiety as to mere subsistence, and learned to take an interest and

pleasure in handiwork which, done deliberately and thoughtfully, could

be made more attractive than machine work.

Again, as people freed from the daily terror of starvation find out what

they really wanted, being no longer compelled by anything but their own

needs, they would refuse to produce the mere inanities which are now

called luxuries, or the poison and trash now called cheap wares. No one

would make plush breeches when there were no flunkies to wear them, nor

would anybody waste his time over making oleomargarine when no one was

compelled to abstain from real butter. Adulteration laws are only needed

in a society of thieves — and in such a society they are a dead letter.

Socialists are often asked how work of the rougher and more repulsive

kind could be carried out in the new condition of things. To attempt to

answer such questions fully or authoritatively would be attempting the

impossibility of constructing a scheme of a new society out of the

materials of the old, before we knew which of those materials would

disappear and which endure through the evolution which is leading us to

the great change. Yet it is not difficult to conceive of some

arrangement whereby those who did the roughest work should work for the

shortest spells. And again, what is said above of the variety of work

applies specially here. Once more I say, that for a man to be the whole

of his life hopelessly engaged in performing one repulsive and

never-ending task, is an arrangement fit enough for the hell imagined by

theologians, but scarcely fit for any other form of society. Lastly, if

this rougher work were of any special kind, we may suppose that special

volunteers would be called on to perform it, who would surely be

forthcoming, unless men in a state of freedom should lose the sparks of

manliness which they possessed as slaves.

And yet if there be any work which cannot be made other than repulsive,

either by the shortness of its duration or the intermittency of its

recurrence, or by the sense of special and peculiar usefulness (and

therefore honour) in the mind of the man who performs it freely, — if

there be any work which cannot be but a torment to the worker, what

then? Well, then, let us see if the heavens will fall on us if we leave

it undone, for it were better that they should. The produce of such work

cannot be worth the price of it.

Now we have seen that the semi-theological dogma that all labour, under

any circumstances, is a blessing to the labourer, is hypocritical and

false; that, on the other hand, labour is good when due hope of rest and

pleasure accompanies it. We have weighed the work of civilization in the

balance and found it wanting, since hope is mostly lacking to it, and

therefore we see that civilization has bred a dire curse for men. But we

have seen also that the work of the world might be carried on in hope

and with pleasure if it were not wasted by folly and tyranny, by the

perpetual strife of opposing classes.

It is Peace, therefore, which we need in order that we may live and work

in hope and with pleasure. Peace so much desired, if we may trust men’s

words, but which has been so continually and steadily rejected by them

in deeds. But for us, let us set our hearts on it and win it at whatever

cost.

What the cost may be, who can tell? Will it be possible to win peace

peaceably? Alas, how can it be? We are so hemmed in by wrong and folly,

that in one way or other we must always be fighting against them: our

own lives may see no end to the struggle, perhaps no obvious hope of the

end. It may be that the best we can hope to see is that struggle getting

sharper and bitterer day by day, until it breaks out openly at last into

the slaughter of men by actual warfare instead of by the slower and

crueller methods of “peaceful” commerce. If we live to see that, we

shall live to see much; for it will mean the rich classes grown

conscious of their own wrong and robbery, and consciously defending them

by open violence; and then the end will be drawing near.

But in any case, and whatever the nature of our strife for peace may be,

if we only aim at it steadily and with singleness of heart, and ever

keep it in view, a reflection from that peace of the future will

illumine the turmoil and trouble of our lives, whether the trouble be

seemingly petty, or obviously tragic; and we shall, in our hopes at

least, live the lives of men: nor can the present times give us any

reward greater than that.

Dawn of a New Epoch

Perhaps some of my readers may think that the above title is not a

correct one: it may be said, a new epoch is always dawning, change is

always going on, and it goes on so gradually that we do not know when we

are out of an old epoch and into a new one. There is truth in that, at

least to this extent, that no age can see itself: we must stand some way

off before the confused picture with its rugged surface can resolve

itself into its due order, and seem to be something with a definite

purpose carried through all its details. Nevertheless, when we look back

on history we do distinguish periods in the lapse of time that are not

merely arbitrary ones, we note the early growth of the ideas which are

to form the new order of things, we note their development into the

transitional period, and finally the new epoch is revealed to us bearing

in its full development, unseen as yet, the seeds of the newer order

still which shall transform it in its turn into something else.

Moreover, there are periods in which even those alive in them become

more or less conscious of the change which is always going on; the old

ideas which were once so exciting to men’s imaginations, now cease to

move them, though they may be accepted as dull and necessary platitudes:

the material circumstances of man’s life which were once only struggled

with in detail, and only according to a kind of law made manifest in

their working, are in such times conscious of change, and are only

accepted under protest until some means can be found to alter them. The

old and dying order, once silent and all-powerful, tries to express

itself violently, and becomes at once noisy and weak. The nascent order

once too weak to be conscious of need of expression, or capable of it if

it were, becomes conscious now and finds a voice. The silent sap of the

years is being laid aside for open assault; the men are gathering under

arms in the trenches, and the forlorn hope is ready, no longer trifling

with little solacements of the time of weary waiting, but looking

forward to mere death or the joy of victory.

Now I think, and some who read this will agree with me, that we are now

living in one of these times of conscious change; we not only are, but

we also feel ourselves to be living between the old and the new; we are

expecting something to happen, as the phrase goes: at such times it

behoves us to understand what is the old which is dying, what is the new

which is coming into existence? That is a question practically important

to us all, since these periods of conscious change are also, in one way

or other, times of serious combat, and each of us, if he does not look

to it and learn to understand what is going on, may find himself

fighting on the wrong side, the side with which he really does not

sympathize.

What is the combat we are now entering upon — who is it to be fought

between? Absolutism and Democracy, perhaps some will answer. Not quite,

I think; that contest was practically settled by the great French

Revolution; it is only its embers which are burning now: or at least

that is so in the countries which are not belated like Russia, for

instance. Democracy, or at least what used to be considered Democracy,

is now triumphant; and though it is true that there are countries where

freedom of speech is repressed besides Russia, as e.g., Germany and

Ireland, [5] that only happens when the rulers of the triumphant

Democracy are beginning to be afraid of the new order of things, now

becoming conscious of itself, and are being driven into reaction in

consequence. No, it is not Absolutism and Democracy as the French

Revolution understood those two words that are the enemies now: the

issue is deeper than it was; the two foes are now Mastership and

Fellowship. This is a far more serious quarrel than the old one, and

involves a much completer revolution. The grounds of conflict are really

quite different. Democracy said and says, men shall not be the masters

of others, because hereditary privilege has made a race or a family so,

and they happen to belong to such race; they shall individually grow

into being the masters of others by the development of certain qualities

under a system of authority which artificially protects the wealth of

every man, if he has acquired it in accordance with this artificial

system, from the interference of every other, or from all others

combined.

The new order of things says, on the contrary, why have masters at all?

let us be fellows working in the harmony of association for the common

good, that is, for the greatest happiness and completest development of

every human being in the community.

This ideal and hope of a new society founded on industrial peace and

forethought, bearing with it its own ethics, aiming at a new and higher

life for all men, has received the general name of Socialism, and it is

my firm belief that it is destined to supersede the old order of things

founded on industrial war, and to be the next step in the progress of

humanity.

Now, since I must explain further what are the aims of Socialism, the

ideal of the new epoch, I find that I must begin by explaining to you

what is the constitution of the old order which it is destined to

supplant. If I can make that clear to you, I shall have also made clear

to you the first aim of Socialism: for I have said that the present and

decaying order of things, like those which have gone before it, has to

be propped up by a system of artificial authority; when that artificial

authority has been swept away, harmonious association will be felt by

all men to be a necessity of their happy and undegraded existence on the

earth, and Socialism will become the condition under which we shall all

live, and it will develop naturally, and probably with no violent

conflict, whatever detailed system may be necessary: I say the struggle

will not be over these details, which will surely vary according to the

difference of unchangeable natural surroundings, but over the question,

shall it be mastership or fellowship?

Let us see then what is the condition of society under the last

development of mastership, the commercial system, which has taken the

place of the Feudal system.

Like all other systems of society, it is founded on the necessity of man

conquering his subsistence from Nature by labour, and also, like most

other systems that we know of, it presupposes the unequal distribution

of labour among different classes of society, and the unequal

distribution of the results of that labour: it does not differ in that

respect from the system which it supplanted; it has only altered the

method whereby that unequal distribution should be arranged. There are

still rich people and poor people amongst us, as there were in the

Middle Ages; nay, there is no doubt that, relatively at least to the sum

of wealth existing, the rich are richer and the poor are poorer now than

they were then. However that may be, in any case now as then there are

people who have much work and little wealth living beside other people

who have much wealth and little work. The richest are still the idlest,

and those who work hardest and perform the most painful tasks are the

worst rewarded for their labour.

To me, and I should hope to my readers, this seems grossly unfair; and I

may remind you here that the world has always had a sense of its

injustice. For century after century, while society has strenuously

bolstered up this injustice forcibly and artificially, it has professed

belief in philosophies, codes of ethics, and religions which have

inculcated justice and fair dealing between men: nay, some of them have

gone so far as to bid us bear one another’s burdens, and have put before

men the duty, and in the long run the pleasure, of the strong working

for the weak, the wise for the foolish, the helpful for the helpless;

and yet these precepts of morality have been set aside in practice as

persistently as they have been preached in theory; and naturally so,

since they attack the very basis of class society. I as a Socialist am

bound to preach them to you once more, assuring you that they are no

mere foolish dreams bidding us to do what we now must acknowledge to be

impossible, but reasonable rules of action, good for our defence against

the tyranny of Nature. Anyhow, honest men have the choice before them of

either putting these theories in practice or rejecting them altogether.

If they will but face that dilemma, I think we shall soon have a new

world of it; yet I fear they will find it hard to do so: the theory is

old, and we have got used to it and its form of words: the practice is

new, and would involve responsibilities we have not yet thought much of.

Now the great difference between our present system and that of the

feudal period is that, as far as the conditions of life are concerned,

all distinction of classes is abolished except that between rich and

poor: society is thus simplified; the arbitrary distinction is gone, the

real one remains and is far more stringent than the arbitrary one was.

Once all society was rude, there was little real difference between the

gentleman and the non-gentleman, and you had to dress them differently

from one another in order to distinguish them. But now a well-to-do man

is a refined and cultivated being, enjoying to the full his share of the

conquest over Nature which the modern world has achieved, while the poor

man is rude and degraded, and has no share in the wealth conquered by

modern science from Nature: he is certainly no better as to material

condition than the serf of the Middle Ages, perhaps he is worse: to my

mind he is at least worse than the savage living in a good climate.

I do not think that any thoughtful man seriously denies this: let us try

to see what brings it about; let us see it as clearly as we all see that

the hereditary privilege of the noble caste, and the consequent serf

slavery of the workers of the Middle Ages, brought about the peculiar

conditions of that period.

Society is now divided between two classes, those who monopolize all the

means of the production of wealth save one; and those who possess

nothing except that one, the Power of Labour. That power of labour is

useless to its possessors, and cannot be exercised without the help of

the other means of production; but those who have nothing but

labour-power — i.e., who have no means of making others work for them,

must work for themselves in order to live; and they must therefore apply

to the owners of the means of fructifying labour — i.e., the land,

machinery, &c., for leave to work that they may live. The possessing

class (as for short we will call them) are quite prepared to grant this

leave, and indeed they must grant it if they are to use the labour-power

of the non-possessing class for their own advantage, which is their

special privilege. But that privilege enables them to compel the

non-possessing class to sell them their labour-power on terms which

ensure the continuance of their monopoly. These terms are at the outset

very simple. The possessing class, or masters, allow the men just so

much of the wealth produced by their labour as will give them such a

livelihood as is considered necessary at the time, and will permit them

to breed and rear children to a working age: that is the simple

condition of the “bargain” which obtains when the labour-power required

is low in quality, what is called unskilled labour, and when the workers

are too weak or ignorant to combine so as to threaten the masters with

some form of rebellion. When skilled labour is wanted, and the labourer

has consequently cost more to produce, and is rarer to be found, the

price of the article is higher: as also when the commodity labour takes

to thinking and remembers that after all it is also men, and as

aforesaid holds out threats to the masters; in that case they for their

part generally think it prudent to give way, when the competition of the

market allows them to do so, and so the standard of livelihood for the

workers rises.

But to speak plainly, the greater part of the workers, in spite of

strikes and Trades’ Unions, do get little more than a bare subsistence

wage, and when they grow sick or old they would die outright if it were

not for the refuge afforded them by the workhouse, which is purposely

made as prison-like and wretched as possible, in order to prevent the

lower-paid workers from taking refuge in it before the time of their

industrial death.

Now comes the question as to how the masters are able to force the men

to sell their commodity labour-power so dirt-cheap without treating them

as the ancients treated their slaves — i.e., with the whip. Well, of

course you understand that the master having paid his workmen what they

can live upon, and having paid for the wear and tear of machinery and

other expenses of that kind, has for his share whatever remains over and

above, the whole of which he gets from the exercise of the labour-power

possessed by the worker: he is anxious therefore to make the most of

this privilege, and competes with his fellow-manufacturers to the utmost

in the market: so that the distribution of wares is organized on a

gambling basis, and as a consequence many more hands are needed when

trade is brisk than when it is slack, or even in an ordinary condition:

under the stimulus also of the lust for acquiring this surplus value of

labour, the great machines of our epoch were invented and are yearly

improved, and they act on labour in a threefold way: first they get rid

of many hands; next they lower the quality of the labour required, so

that skilled work is wanted less and less; thirdly, the improvement in

them forces the workers to work harder while they are at work, as

notably in the cotton-spinning industry. Also in most trades women and

children are employed, to whom it is not even pretended that a

subsistence wage is given. Owing to all these causes, the reserve army

of labour necessary to our present system of manufactures for the

gambling market, the introduction of labour-saving machines (labour

saved for the master, mind you, not the man), and the intensifying of

the labour while it lasts, the employment of the auxiliary labour of

women and children: owing to all this there are in ordinary years even,

not merely in specially bad years like the current one, [6] more workers

than there is work for them to do. The workers therefore undersell one

another in disposing of their one commodity, labour-power, and are

forced to do so, or they would not be allowed to work, and therefore

would have to starve or go to the prison called the workhouse. This is

why the masters at the present day are able to dispense with the

exercise of obvious violence which in bygone times they used towards

their slaves.

This then is the first distinction between the two great classes of

modern Society: the upper class possesses wealth, the lower lacks

wealth; but there is another distinction to which I will now draw your

attention: the class which lacks wealth is the class that produces it,

the class that possesses it does not produce it, it consumes it only. If

by any chance the so-called lower class were to perish or leave the

community, production of wealth would come to a standstill, until the

wealth-owners had learned how to produce, until they had descended from

their position, and had taken the place of their former slaves. If on

the contrary, the wealth-owners were to disappear, production of wealth

would at the worst be only hindered for awhile, and probably would go on

pretty much as it does now.

But you may say, though it is certain that some of the wealth-owners, as

landlords, holders of funds, and the like do nothing, yet there are many

of them who work hard. Well, that is true, and perhaps nothing so

clearly shows the extreme folly of the present system than this fact

that there are so many able and industrious men employed by it, in

working hard at — nothing: nothing or worse. They work, but they do not

produce.

It is true that some useful occupations are in the hands of the

privileged classes, physic, education, and the fine arts, e.g. The men

who work at these occupations are certainly working usefully; and all

that we can say against them is that they are sometimes paid too high in

proportion to the pay of other useful persons, which high pay is given

them in recognition of their being the parasites of the possessing

classes. But even as to numbers these are not a very large part of the

possessors of wealth, and, as to the wealth they hold, it is quite

insignificant compared with that held by those who do nothing useful.

Of these last, some, as we all agree, do not pretend to do anything

except amuse themselves, and probably these are the least harmful of the

useless classes. Then there are others who follow occupations which

would have no place in a reasonable condition of society, as, e.g.,

lawyers, judges, jailers, and soldiers of the higher grades, and most

Government officials. Finally comes the much greater group of those who

are engaged in gambling or fighting for their individual shares of the

tribute which their class compels the working-class to yield to it:

these are the group that one calls broadly business men, the conductors

of our commerce, if you please to call them so.

To extract a good proportion of this tribute, and to keep as much as

possible of it when extracted for oneself, is the main business of life

for these men, that is, for most well-to-do and rich people; it is

called, quite inaccurately, “money-making;” and those who are most

successful in this occupation are, in spite of all hypocritical

pretences to the contrary, the persons most respected by the public.

A word or two as to the tribute extracted from the workers as aforesaid.

It is no trifle, but amounts to at least two-thirds of all that the

worker produces; but you must understand that it is not all taken

directly from the workman by his immediate employer, but by the

employing class. Besides the tribute or profit of the direct employer,

which is in all cases as much as he can get amidst his competition or

war with other employers, the worker has also to pay taxes in various

forms, and the greater part of the wealth so extorted is at the best

merely wasted: and remember, whoever seems to pay the taxes, labour in

the long run is the only real taxpayer. Then he has to pay house-rent,

and very much heavier rent in proportion to his earnings than well-to-do

people have. He has also to pay the commission of the middle-men who

distribute the goods which he has made, in a way so wasteful that now

all thinking people cry out against it, though they are quite helpless

against it in our present society. Finally, he has often to pay an extra

tax in the shape of a contribution to a benefit society or trades’

union, which is really a tax on the precariousness of his employment

caused by the gambling of his masters in the market. In short, besides

the profit or the result of unpaid labour which he yields to his

immediate master he has to give back a large part of his wages to the

class of which his master is a part.

The privilege of the possessing class therefore consists in their living

on this tribute, they themselves either not working or working

unproductively — i.e., living on the labour of others; no otherwise than

as the master of ancient days lived on the labour of his slave, or as

the baron lived on the labour of his serf. If the capital of the rich

man consists of land, he is able to force a tenant to improve his land

for him and pay him tribute in the form of rack- rent; and at the end of

the transaction has his land again, generally improved, so that he can

begin again and go on for ever, he and his heirs, doing nothing, a mere

burden on the community for ever, while others are working for him. If

he has houses on his land he has rent for them also, often receiving the

value of the building many times over, and in the end house and land

once more. Not seldom a piece of barren ground or swamp, worth nothing

in itself, becomes a source of huge fortune to him from the development

of a town or a district, and he pockets the results of the labour of

thousands upon thousands of men, and calls it his property: or the earth

beneath the surface is found to be rich in coal or minerals, and again

he must be paid vast sums for allowing others to labour them into

marketable wares, to which labour he contributes nothing.

Or again, if his capital consists of cash, he goes into the labour

market and buys the labour-power of men, women and children, and uses it

for the production of wares which shall bring him in a profit, buying it

of course at the lowest price that he can, availing himself of their

necessities to keep their livelihood down to the lowest point which they

will bear: which indeed he must do, or he himself will be overcome in

the war with his fellow-capitalists. Neither in this case does he do any

useful work, and he need not do any semblance of it, since he may buy

the brain-power of managers at a somewhat higher rate than he buys the

hand-power of the ordinary workman. But even when he does seem to be

doing something, and receives the pompous title of “organizer of

labour,” he is not really organizing labour, but the battle with his

immediate enemies, the other capitalists, who are in the same line of

business with himself.

Furthermore, though it is true, as I have said, that the working- class

are the only producers, yet only a part of them are allowed to produce

usefully; for the men of the non-producing classes having often much

more wealth than they can use are forced to waste it in mere luxuries

and follies, that on the one hand harm themselves, and on the other

withdraw a very large part of the workers from useful work, thereby

compelling those who do produce usefully to work the harder and more

grievously: in short, the essential accompaniment of the system is

waste.

How could it be otherwise, since it is a system of war? I have mentioned

incidentally that all the employers of labour are at war with each

other, and you will probably see that, according to my account of the

relations between the two great classes, they also are at war. Each can

only gain at the others’ loss: the employing class is forced to make the

most of its privilege, the possession of the means for the exercise of

labour, and whatever it gets to itself can only be got at the expense of

the working-class; and that class in its turn can only raise its

standard of livelihood at the expense of the possessing class; it is

forced to yield as little tribute to it as it can help; there is

therefore constant war always going on between these two classes,

whether they are conscious of it or not.

To recapitulate: In our modern society there are two classes, a useful

and a useless class; the useless class is called the upper, the useful

the lower class. The useless or upper class, having the monopoly of all

the means of the production of wealth save the power of labour, can and

does compel the useful or lower class to work for its own disadvantage,

and for the advantage of the upper class; nor will the latter allow the

useful class to work on any other terms. This arrangement necessarily

means an increasing contest, first of the classes one against the other,

and next of the individuals of each class among themselves.

Most thinking people admit the truth of what I have just stated, but

many of them believe that the system, though obviously unjust and

wasteful, is necessary (though perhaps they cannot give their reasons

for their belief), and so they can see nothing for it but palliating the

worst evils of the system: but, since the various palliatives in fashion

at one time or another have failed each in its turn, I call upon them,

firstly, to consider whether the system itself might not be changed, and

secondly, to look round and note the signs of approaching change.

Let us remember first that even savages live, though they have poor

tools, no machinery, and no co-operation, in their work: but as soon as

a man begins to use good tools and work with some kind of co-operation

he becomes able to produce more than enough for his own bare

necessaries, All industrial society is founded on that fact, even from

the time when workmen were mere chattel slaves. What a strange society

then is this of ours, wherein while one set of people cannot use their

wealth, they have so much, but are obliged to waste it, another set are

scarcely if at all better than those hapless savages who have neither

tools nor co-operation! Surely if this cannot be set right, civilized

mankind must write itself down a civilized fool.

Here is the workman now, thoroughly organized for production, working

for production with complete co-operation, and through marvellous

machines; surely if a slave in Aristotle’s time could do more than keep

himself alive, the present workman can do much more — as we all very

well know that he can. Why therefore should he be otherwise than in a

comfortable condition? Simply because of the class system, which with

one hand plunders, and with the other wastes the wealth won by the

workman’s labour. If the workman had the full results of his labour he

would in all cases be comfortably off, if he were working in an

unwasteful way. But in order to work unwastefully he must work for his

own livelihood, and not to enable another man to live without producing:

if he has to sustain another man in idleness who is capable of working

for himself, he is treated unfairly; and, believe me, he will only do so

as long he is compelled to submit by ignorance and brute force. Well,

then, he has a right to claim the wealth produced by his labour, and in

consequence to insist that all shall produce who are able to do so; but

also undoubtedly his labour must be organized, or he will soon find

himself relapsing into the condition of the savage. But in order that

his labour may be organized properly he must have only one enemy to

contend with — Nature to wit, who as it were eggs him on to the conflict

against herself, and is grateful to him for overcoming her; a friend in

the guise of an enemy. There must be no contention of man with man, but

association instead; so only can labour be really organized,

harmoniously organized. But harmony cannot co-exist with contention for

individual gain: men must work for the common gain if the world is to be

raised out of its present misery; therefore that claim of the workman

(that is of every able man) must be subject to the fact that he is but a

part of a harmonious whole: he is worthless without the co-operation of

his fellows, who help him according to their capacities: he ought to

feel, and will feel when he has his right senses, that he is working for

his own interest when he is working for that of the community.

So working, his work must always be profitable, therefore no obstacle

must be thrown in the way of his work: the means whereby his

labour-power can be exercised must be free to him. The privilege of the

proprietary class must come to an end. Remember that at present the

custom is that a person so privileged is in the position of a man (with

a policeman or so to help) guarding the gate of a field which will

supply livelihood to whomsoever can work in it: crowds of people who

don’t want to die come to that gate; but there stands law and order, and

says “pay me five shillings before you go in;” and he or she that hasn’t

the five shillings has to stay outside, and die — or live in the

workhouse. Well, that must be done away with; the field must be free to

everybody that can use it. To throw aside even this transparent

metaphor, those means of the fructification of labour, the land,

machinery, capital, means of transit, &c., which are now monopolized by

those who cannot use them, but who abuse them to force unpaid labour out

of others, must be free to those who can use them; that is to say, the

workers properly organized for production; but you must remember that

this will wrong no man, because as all will do some service to the

community — i.e., as there will be no non-producing class, the organized

workers will be the whole community, there will be no one left out.

Society will thus be recast, and labour will be free from all compulsion

except the compulsion of Nature, which gives us nothing for nothing. It

would be futile to attempt to give you details of the way in which this

would be carried out; since the very essence of it is freedom and the

abolition of all arbitrary or artificial authority; but I will ask you

to understand one thing: you will no doubt want to know what is to

become of private property under such a system, which at first sight

would not seem to forbid the accumulation of wealth, and along with that

accumulation the formation of new classes of rich and poor.

Now private property as at present understood implies the holding of

wealth by an individual as against all others, whether the holder can

use it or not: he may, and not seldom he does, accumulate capital, or

the stored-up labour of past generations, and neither use it himself nor

allow others to use it: he may, and often he does, engross the first

necessity of labour, land, and neither use it himself or allow any one

else to use it; and though it is clear that in each case he is injuring

the community, the law is sternly on his side. In any case a rich man

accumulates property, not for his own use, but in order that he may

evade with impunity the law of Nature which bids man labour for his

livelihood, and also that he may enable his children to do the same,

that he and they may belong to the upper or useless class: it is not

wealth that he accumulates, well-being, well-doing, bodily and mental;

he soon comes to the end of his real needs in that respect, even when

they are most exacting: it is power over others, what our forefathers

called riches, that he collects; power (as we have seen) to force other

people to live for his advantage poorer lives than they should live.

Understand that that must be the result of the possession of riches.

Now this power to compel others to live poorly Socialism would abolish

entirely, and in that sense would make an end of private property: nor

would it need to make laws to prevent accumulation artificially when

once people had found out that they could employ themselves, and that

thereby every man could enjoy the results of his own labour: for

Socialism bases the rights of the individual to possess wealth on his

being able to use that wealth for his own personal needs, and, labour

being properly organized, every person, male or female, not in nonage or

otherwise incapacitated from working, would have full opportunity to

produce wealth and thereby to satisfy his own personal needs; if those

needs went in any direction beyond those of an average man, he would

have to make personal sacrifices in order to satisfy them; he would

have, for instance, to work longer hours, or to forego some luxury that

he did not care for in order to obtain something which he very much

desired: so doing he would at the worst injure no one: and you will

clearly see that there is no other choice for him between so doing and

his forcing some one else to forego his special desires; and this latter

proceeding by the way, when it is done without the sanction of the most

powerful part of society, is called theft; though on the big scale and

duly sanctioned by artificial laws, it is, as we have seen, the

groundwork of our present system. Once more, that system refuses

permission to people to produce unless under artificial restrictions;

under Socialism, every one who could produce would be free to produce,

so that the price of an article would be just the cost of its

production, and what we now call profit would no longer exist: thus, for

instance, if a person wanted chairs, he would accumulate them till he

had as many as he could use, and then he would stop, since he would not

have been able to buy them for less than their cost of production and

could not sell them for more: in other words, they would be nothing else

than chairs; under the present system they may be means of compulsion

and destruction as formidable as loaded rifles.

No one therefore would dispute with a man the possession of what he had

acquired without injury to others, and what he could use without

injuring them, and it would so remove temptations toward the abuse of

possession, that probably no laws would be necessary to prevent it.

A few words now as to the differentiation of reward of labour, as I know

my readers are sure to want an exposition of the Socialist views here as

to those who direct labour or who have specially excellent faculties

towards production. And, first, I will look on the super- excellent

workman as an article presumably needed by the community; and then say

that, as with other articles so with this, the community must pay the

cost of his production: for instance, it will have to seek him out, to

develop his special capacities, and satisfy any needs he may have (if

any) beyond those of an average man, so long as the satisfaction of

those needs is not hurtful to the community.

Furthermore, you cannot give him more than he can use so he will not ask

for more, and will not take it: it is true that his work may be more

special than another’s, but it is not more necessary if you have

organized labour properly; the ploughman and the fisherman are as

necessary to society as the scientist or the artist, I will not say more

necessary: neither is the difficulty of producing the more special and

excellent work at all proportionate to its speciality or excellence: the

higher workman produces his work as easily perhaps as the lower does his

work; if he does not do so, you must give him extra leisure, extra means

for supplying the waste of power in him, but you can give him nothing

more. The only reward that you can give the excellent workman is

opportunity for developing and exercising his excellent capacity. I

repeat, you can give him nothing more worth his having: all other

rewards are either illusory or harmful. I must say in passing, that our

present system of dealing with what is called a man of genius is utterly

absurd: we cruelly starve him and repress his capacity when he is young;

we foolishly pamper and flatter him and again repress his capacity when

he is middle-aged or old: we get the least out of him, not the most.

These last words concern mere rarities in the way of workmen; but in

this respect it is only a matter of degree; the point of the whole thing

is this, that the director of labour is in his place because he is fit

for it, not by a mere accident; being fit for it, he does it easier than

he would do other work, and needs no more compensation for the wear and

tear of life than another man does, and not needing it will not claim

it, since it would be no use to him; his special reward for his special

labour is, I repeat, that he can do it easily, and so does not feel it a

burden; nay, since he can do it well he likes doing it, since indeed the

main pleasure of life is the exercise of energy in the development of

our special capacities. Again, as regards the workmen who are under his

direction, he needs no special dignity or authority; they know well

enough that so long as he fulfils his function and really does direct

them, if they do not heed him it will be at the cost of their labour

being more irksome and harder. All this, in short, is what is meant by

the organization of labour, which is, in other words, finding out what

work such and such people are fittest for and leaving them free to do

that: we won’t take the trouble to do that now, with the result that

people’s best faculties are wasted, and that work is a heavy burden to

them, which they naturally shirk as much as they can; it should be

rather a pleasure to them: and I say straight out that, unless we find

some means to make all work more or less pleasurable, we shall never

escape from the great tyranny of the modern world.

Having mentioned the difference between the competitive and commercial

ideas on the subject of the individual holding of wealth and the

relative position of different groups of workmen, I will very briefly

say something on what for want of a better word I must call the

political position which we take up, or at least what we look forward to

in the long run. The substitution of association for competition is the

foundation of Socialism, and will run through all acts done under it,

and this must act as between nations as well as between individuals:

when profits can no more be made, there will be no necessity for holding

together masses of men to draw together the greatest proportion of

profit to their locality, or to the real or imaginary union of persons

and corporations which is now called a nation. What we now call a nation

is a body whose function it is to assert the special welfare of its

incorporated members at the expense of all other similar bodies: the

death of competition will deprive it of this function; since there will

be no attack there need be no defence, and it seems to me that this

function being taken away from the nation it can have no other, and

therefore must cease to exist as a political entity. On this side of the

movement opinion is growing steadily. It is clear that, quite apart from

Socialism, the idea of local administration is pushing out that of

centralized government: to take a remarkable case: in the French

Revolution of 1793, the most advanced party was centralizing: in the

latest French revolution, that of the Commune of 1871, it was

federalist. Or take Ireland, the success which is to-day attending the

struggles of Ireland for independence is, I am quite sure, owing to the

spread of this idea: it no longer seems a monstrous proposition to

liberal-minded Englishmen that a country should administer its own

affairs: the feeling that it is not only just, but also very convenient

to all parties for it to do so, is extinguishing the prejudices fostered

by centuries of oppressive and wasteful mastership. And I believe that

Ireland will show that her claim for self-government is not made on

behalf of national rivalry, but rather on behalf of genuine

independence; the consideration, on the one hand, of the needs of her

own population, and, on the other, goodwill towards that of other

localities. Well, the spread of this idea will make our political work

as Socialists the easier; men will at last come to see that the only way

to avoid the tyranny and waste of bureaucracy is by the Federation of

Independent Communities: their federation being for definite purposes:

for furthering the organization of labour, by ascertaining the real

demand for commodities, and so avoiding waste: for organizing the

distribution of goods, the migration of persons — in short, the friendly

intercommunication of people whose interests are common, although the

circumstances of their natural surroundings made necessary differences

of life and manners between them.

I have thus sketched something of the outline of Socialism, by showing

that its aim is first to get rid of the monopoly of the means of

fructifying labour, so that labour may be free to all, and its resulting

wealth may not be engrossed by a few, and so cause the misery and

degradation of the many: and, secondly, that it aims at organizing

labour so that none of it may be wasted, using as a means thereto the

free development of each man’s capacity; and, thirdly, that it aims at

getting rid of national rivalry, which in point of fact means a

condition of perpetual war, sometimes of the money-bag, sometimes of the

bullet, and substituting for this worn-out superstition a system of free

communities living in harmonious federation with each other, managing

their own affairs by the free consent of their members; yet

acknowledging some kind of centre whose function it would be to protect

the principle whose practice the communities should carry out; till at

last those principles would be recognized by every one always and

intuitively, when the last vestiges of centralization would die out.

I am well aware that this complete Socialism, which is sometimes called

Communism, cannot be realized all at once; society will be changed from

its basis when we make the form of robbery called profit impossible by

giving labour full and free access to the means of its fructification —

i.e., to raw material. The demand for this emancipation of labour is the

basis on which all Socialists may unite. On more indefinite grounds they

cannot meet other groups of politicians; they can only rejoice at seeing

the ground cleared of controversies which are really dead, in order that

the last controversy may be settled that we can at present foresee, and

the question solved as to whether or no it is necessary, as some people

think it is, that society should be composed of two groups of dishonest

persons, slaves submitting to be slaves, yet for ever trying to cheat

their masters, and masters conscious of their having no support for

their dishonesty of eating the common stock without adding to it save

the mere organization of brute force, which they have to assert for ever

in all details of life against the natural desire of man to be free.

It may be hoped that we of this generation may be able to prove that it

is unnecessary; but it will, doubt it not, take many generations yet to

prove that it is necessary for such degradation to last as long as

humanity does; and when that is finally proved we shall at least have

one hope left — that humanity will not last long.

 

[1] Falsely; because the privileged classes have at their back the force

of the Executive by means of which to compel the unprivileged to accept

their terms; if this is “free competition” there is no meaning in words.

[2] They have been “rather rough,” you may say, and have done more than

merely hold their sentimental position. Well, I still say (February

1888) that the present open tyranny which sends political opponents to

prison, both in England and Ireland, and breaks Radical heads in the

street for attempting to attend political meetings, is not Tory, but

Whig; not the old Tory “divine right of kings,” but the new Tory, i.e.,

Tory-tinted Whig, “divine right of property” made Bloody Sunday

possible. I admit that I did not expect in 1886 that we should in 1887

and 1888 be having such a brilliant example of the tyranny of a

parliamentary majority; in fact, I did not reckon on the force of the

impenetrable stupidity of the Prigs in alliance with the Whigs marching

under the rather ragged banner of sham Toryism.

[3] As true now (February 1888) as then: the murder of the Chicago

Anarchists, to wit.

[4] I suppose he was speaking of the frame houses of Kent.

[5] And the brick and mortar country London, also, it seems (Feb. 1888).

[6] 1886, to wit.