💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › staughton-lynd-workers-democracy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:04:51. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Workers’ Democracy
Author: Staughton Lynd
Date: 2002
Language: en
Topics: democracy, syndicalism, workers’ control, Serbia, Zapatistas, Mexico
Source: Retrieved on 2nd September 2021 from https://libcom.org/library/workers-democracy-staughton-lynd
Notes: Originally appeared in WorkingUSA, vol. 5, no. 4, Spring 2002. pp. 84–94. ISSN 1089–7011.

Staughton Lynd

Workers’ Democracy

Conventional definitions of union democracy are too limited to encompass

the broad majority of people in and outside unions who are struggling

for control over their workplaces. In particular, denotation of U.S.

labor law and trade union perspectives of union democracy are far too

narrow to give workers participatory power. Thus the concept of union

democracy must be reinterpreted to include workers of all kinds

(unionized workers, nonunion workers, and farmers); protection of the

rights to strike, picket, and slow down; and the demand for

worker-community ownership. This article examines two recent examples of

workers’ democracy: the Serbian revolution of 2000 and the Zapatistas’

ongoing struggle in Chiapas, Mexico.

What kind of democracy do workers need? Those who answer, “Union

democracy,” generally mean by that term the free exercise of rights

protected by Title I of the Landrum-Griffin Act, together with the right

to elect union officers and ratify contracts by referendum vote of the

rank and file. (A referendum vote is protected by Title I only if

provided in the constitution and bylaws of the union to which the

com-plaining worker belongs.)

“Union democracy,” thus defined, is critically important for the one

worker in eight who belongs to a union. The right to speak your piece at

a meeting, to belong to a caucus without retaliation, to circulate

leaflets and petitions, and to run for office represent labor law

equivalents to many of the rights protected by the First Amendment.

Even for the worker who belongs to a union, however, union democracy

understood in First Amendment terms does not encompass all the democracy

that a worker needs. Labor law in the United States as expressed in the

National Labor Relations Act as amended (otherwise known as the Labor

Management Relations Act) has a number of features that are found in few

other countries and that are a threat to democratic values.

In the United States, federal labor law as interpreted by the National

Labor Relations Board and the courts provides that:

“exclusive” representative in collective bargaining of those who work

there.

unit, and the collective bargaining agreement negotiated by that union

so provides, all members of the unit must pay dues or equivalent fees to

the union. Typically these dues or fees are “checked off” so that the

money never passes through the worker’s hands on its way to the union.

collective bargaining agreement, workers covered by the contract are

understood to have agreed not to strike or engage in other forms of

collective self-help (whether or not that prohibition appears in the

contractual language) except, perhaps, in the case of a safety and

health problem that threatens imminent bodily harm.

members’ fundamental right to engage in “concerted activity for mutual

aid or protection” otherwise guaranteed by Section 7 of the act. Workers

who engage in strikes, slow-downs, and even picketing in disregard of

this prohibition may be discharged by the employer and will have no

legal redress. Almost all union contracts in the United States give up

for the duration of the contract at least the right to strike.

To my mind, the four constraints just enumerated take away much more

democracy than any federal law such as Landrum-Griffin can give back. It

is a sad fact that in our country the worker who does not belong to a

union or whose union has not yet achieved recognition may have more

legal protection to engage in the classic forms of working-class

self-activity—strikes, slow-downs, and picketing—than has the union

member.

Thus, “union democracy” should be understood in a much broader manner

than has been the practice of those mainly con-cerned with union

elections. Union democracy requires protection of the worker ’s right to

engage in self-activity and self-organization from below, even when

these activities are not approved or are even bitterly opposed by union

officials.

Participatory Democracy for Workers, Too

But we have thus far only scratched the surface of the worker’s need for

democracy. What does democracy mean when a company unilaterally decides

to close a plant? Labor law protects the company’s action by excluding

investment decisions from the so-called “mandatory subjects of

bargaining.” This means that a union that seeks to ensure in its

bargaining that a given workplace—or all workplaces represented by the

union—will not be closed during the duration of the contract cannot

legally insist on such language.

Moreover, like the no-strike clause present in most contracts, in almost

all contracts the union agrees to a “management prerogatives clause”

that expressly gives management the right to close plants, transfer

work, get out of any particular line of busi-ness, go to Mexico, or

whatever the company may in its infinite wisdom decide to do with the

surplus value that workers produce. (Example: The largest employer in

the Youngstown area is Delphi Packard, which makes electric assemblies

for vehicles. In 1980, the company had 15,000 workers in the Youngstown

area and no workers in Mexico. Now it has 4,800 workers in Youngstown

and 80,000 in Mexico.)

Is this democracy? What do we mean by democracy anyhow? The Port Huron

Statement adopted by the Students for a Democratic Society in 1962

advocated a “participatory democracy,” whereby the “individual [would]

share in those social decisions determining the quality and direction of

his life.” Is closing a plant such a decision? Of course it is: Ask the

young worker forced to leave his or her community of origin in order to

find work; the middle-aged worker with a mortgage, children ap-proaching

college age, and no transferable skills; or the older worker, as at

Enron, worried about whether his or her pension and (especially) health

care benefits are still there. No kind of decision in our society has a

greater impact on the lives of individuals than corporate decisions to

shut down facilities, to relo-cate production, to merge, to declare

bankruptcy, and the like. If the democracy we say we believe in is

participatory democracy, workers must have a voice in such decisions.

I am not talking about adding an international union officer to a

corporate board of directors, nor do I have in mind requir-ing the

company to give a sixty-day notice of what it has unilaterally decided

to do. Workers (and their communities) must have an effective veto. When

a company decides that it no longer wishes to make steel in, say,

Youngstown or Cleveland, the workers of that community must be given an

opportunity to do the job themselves. For such an imagined right to be

made real, there must be a public source of funds permitting public

entities to exercise the same right of “eminent domain” with respect to

an abandoned industrial facility as they routinely exercise with respect

to abandoned residential structures. In Anglo-American law, exercise of

the right to eminent domain requires payment of fair market value.

Absent the financial assistance to make such a “taking” possible, the

right itself is only a cruel hoax.

Still, we have not gone far enough. A society in which workers can

acquire the plants that their employers abandon, and run the plants

themselves, is not the society in which we presently live. Socialism in

one steel mill is not going to happen. What can happen in one steel

mill—as at Weirton Steel in West Virginia, where workers engaged in an

employee stock ownership plan—will not be socialism or workers’

democracy either. To have a society in which workers can realistically

come to view a facility as “theirs” because they mix their labor with it

over a long period of time and securely look forward to working there

until retirement, there must be deep structural changes. Democracy, it

would appear, is going to require revolution.

But what kind of revolution? And how can it happen in a way that will

not destroy democracy in the process? The twentieth century offers many

cautionary examples as well as many hopeful ones.

Democracy and Revolution, Marxism and Anarchism

The new movement for change emerging in the LacondĂłn jungle of southern

Mexico, and in the streets of Paris (in 1995), Seattle, and Quebec City,

is a movement that draws on both Marxism and anarchism. The Marx it

looks back to is the author of The Civil War in France (1990) about the

Paris Commune of 1871. The Lenin to which it relates is the author who,

in State and Revolution (1993), demanded that all power pass to

improvised central labor bodies known as soviets.

Where can we find examples of this libertarian socialism in practice?

And what is the role within it of workers’ democracy?

Serbia 2000

In fall 2000, Serbia had what can fairly be called a nonviolent

revolution. A political movement won an election. When the incumbent

regime initially refused to recognize the election results, an outraged

populace poured into the streets. On the evening of Friday, September

29, the coal miners of the Kolubara region, who produce the coal

required for half of Serbia’s out-put of electricity, declared an

indefinite general strike. The general in charge of the armed forces,

and police from the Interior Ministry, showed up at the mines on

Tuesday, October 3, and Wednesday, October 4. The miners adopted a dual

strategy. On the one hand, they removed vital parts from the mine

ma-chinery and challenged the soldiers to mine coal with bayo-nets. On

the other hand, they summoned 20,000 supporters from nearby communities.

The police held their ground but made no arrests. The next day,

Thursday, October 5, hundreds of thousands of people in Belgrade—forty

miles away—seized the parliament and the state TV station, and the

police in Kolubara melted away.

The Kolubara strike was coordinated not by a “trade union” but by a

“workers’ committee.” All over Serbia, following Vojislav Kostunica’s

accession to power, local committees of workers displaced hated factory

managers. I realize that a cynic might say that this was a transition

from socialism to capitalism, not the other way around. But surely

Serbia also shows us that fundamental social transition, revolution,

remains possible in the twenty-first century, and that neutralizing the

armed forces by mass nonviolent direct action on the part of workers and

their supporters can be a critical component of the process.

Mexico 1994 to Now

The Zapatista movement in Mexico for indigenous self-determination seems

extraordinary in at least the following ways.

1. Without participating in electoral politics, the Zapatistas have

ended seventy-one years of uninterrupted government by the Institutional

Revolutionary Party, or PRI. How have they done this? One critical

component is a vast effort at popular education. Mayan peasants, who had

never before left their native villages, traveled all over Mexico

meeting with popular organizations such as the network of independent

trade unions, the Frente Auténtico del Trabajo (FAT).

2. The Zapatistas are not nonviolent in any traditional sense. But

neither are they a traditional Latin American guerrilla movement.

Without giving up either their arms or the principle of armed struggle,

they have carried on for the last five years an essentially nonviolent

resistance.

For example, the Mexican government has sought to build roads into the

LacandĂłn jungle, which is the Zapatista strong-hold. The government

claimed that this plan was to help farmers get their produce to market.

The real reason, obviously, was to be able to move soldiers and military

gear into the area.

At the western edge of the jungle is a village named AmadĂłr. During the

summer and fall of 1999, the soldiers seeking to build the road were met

each day by a cordĂłn (a picket line) of women from AmadĂłr. Since many of

the soldiers were indigenous, the women appealed to them to recognize

their true interests and to put down their weapons. To prevent this

dialogue, the government played music through loudspeakers.

After Vicente Fox became president, he announced the abandonment of a

number of military bases in Chiapas. The first base to be abandoned was

at AmadĂłr.

3. When my wife and I briefly visited San Cristobal, Chiapas, in 1999,

we talked with Teresa Ortiz, who for years has worked with indigenous

communities in the area. She was completing a book of interviews titled

Never Again a World Without Us: Voices of Mayan Women in Chiapas, Mexico

(2001). She told us that in the 1960s, 1970s, and 1980s, three

historical forces prepared the way for Zapatismo. The first was Mayan

tradition, according to which, she said, “Everything is done through

assemblies.” The second was the Mexican Revolution of 1917, which

declared a right to land. No one was supposed to own more than a certain

amount. Poor people were authorized to form associations called “ejidos”

and to acquire land as a community that no individual could sell.

The third historical force was the Second Vatican Council and Catholic

Liberation Theology. Base communities were formed—Mayan base

communities, in which there was a “marriage of traditions.” The key

demand that emerged from this confluence of traditions (we were told)

was for autonomy, that is, self-admin-istration by the indigenous

according to traditional law, “uso de costumbre.” When Marxists showed

up in Chiapas in the mid-1980s, a movement formed by these forces was

already in exist-ence. The movement influenced the Marxists, we were

told, more than the Marxists influenced the movement.

The way it works in an individual village is as follows. The village may

be wholly “autonomous” (the word the Zapatistas use to describe

themselves), or it may have some autonomous families and some families

loyal to the PRI.

In the assembly of the autonomous, trusted individuals are asked to

perform certain full-time functions; for example, as storekeeper or as a

worker in a health clinic or a school. These persons “lead by obeying.”

Someone else cultivates their corn-fields so they can perform their new

tasks. The store, the clinic, and the school serve all the families in

the village, even those that are pro-PRI.

The Zapatista communities make joint decisions by a representative

process. Each local assembly of the “autonomous”—whether it is composed

of all or some of the families in a particular village—is open to

persons above a certain age. Each assembly comes to a consensus and

sends delegates to the next level. The delegates are bound to be

spokespersons for the decisions of the local assemblies they represent.

It is an honor to be chosen as a representative, just as it is an honor

to be chosen as a storekeeper or teacher. Consensus is sought at every

level. A “straw vote” may be taken to give par-ticipants a sense of how

widely particular outcomes are desired.

In Ortiz’s opinion, the Zapatista movement does not resemble other

guerrilla movements. The movement it most resembles is the civil rights

movement in the United States in the 1960s.

Conclusion

To respond to this new movement, to take part in it helpfully, to give

it leadership in a direction promising results, requires those

interested in workers’ democracy to start thinking outside traditional

boxes. If we pursue only traditional models—for example, waiting for

trade unions (however democratic they may become) or Marxist vanguard

parties to make the revolution—we may be waiting a long time. By

contrast, workers who act on their own initiative to refuse overtime or

to take part in a wild-cat strike speak of their sense of liberation,

their experience of literally getting “outside the box” represented by

the plant and the daily routine.

I advocate an alternative perspective that I call “solidarity unionism.”

It asks workers to reach out to other workers hori-zontally, rather than

relying on higher bureaucratic levels of the unions to which they may

belong. It proposes that workers seek ways in which they can begin to

act together without waiting for approval from their international union

or even their local union. It suggests that, as needed, they form their

own organizational structures outside of (or, as in the case of a

stewards’ council, overlapping with) traditional unions.

For example, suppose I work in a plant owned by a company that operates

another plant in which you work. The company discontinues a shift in

your plant, and you and your colleagues begin to experience layoffs. The

workers at my plant, me included, find ourselves working overtime to

compensate for the loss of production at your place.

Historically, workers confronted with such cutbacks in

production—whether or not they belonged to a union—have often resolved

to share whatever work was available, regardless of seniority. The legal

services office where I worked in the 1980s did this when President

Reagan cut our budget by 20 percent. Without touching the compensation

of secretaries, who were underpaid to begin with, all the lawyers

reduced their work-week to four days. A group of visiting nurses, whom

my wife and I helped to organize an independent union, did likewise. And

in a book Alice and I edited, The New Rank and File (2000), Mia Giunta

tells how women workers of many nationalities in a Connecticut

electronics plant that Mia helped to organize adopted the same practice.

In a shutdown or cutback situation for a fellow worker in another

workplace owned by the same employer, I can express solidarity unionism

by refusing overtime. (The collective bargaining agreement may mandate

overtime, or be silent. Each situation will present a somewhat different

tactical challenge.) Hopefully I won’t act all by myself. When our group

becomes stronger, we may be able to strike in your behalf should you

decide to hit the bricks. Our slogan then would be “If you go, we go.”

I think workers’ democracy means improvising such small steps of

resistance as workers can take without excessive danger of being fired.

I think it means trying to learn from what is going on around us. It

means, I believe, affirming with students and workers in the streets

that another world—a qualitatively different world—is possible.

References

Lenin, Vladimir Ilyich. 1993. State and Revolution, trans. Robert W.

Service. New York: Viking Penguin.

Lynd, Staughton. 1997. Living Inside Our Hope: A Steadfast Radical’s

Thoughts on Rebuilding the Movement. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Lynd, Staughton, and Alice Lynd. 2000. The New Rank and File. Ithaca:

Cornell University Press.

Marx, Karl. 1990. The Civil War in France. New York: International

Publishers.

Ortiz, Teresa. 2001. Never Again a World Without Us: Voices of Mayan

Women in Chiapas, Mexico. Washington, DC: Epica.