đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş shawn-p-wilbur-antinomies-of-democracy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:08:21. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Antinomies of Democracy Author: Shawn P. Wilbur Date: July 20th, 2017 Language: en Topics: criticism and critique, critique, democracy, Direct Democracy, a reply, C4SS Source: https://c4ss.org/content/49638 Notes: This piece is the twenty-sixth essay in the https://c4ss.org/content/49206][June C4SS Mutual Exchange Symposium]]: âAnarchy and Democracy.â It is written in reply to [[https://c4ss.org/content/49379][contributions by Nathan Goodman,]] [[https://c4ss.org/content/49295 and Wayne Price.
I thought I had pretty well had my say on the subject of democracy and
anarchy, but comparing the material Iâve written to the contributions
Iâve submitted, I see a couple of responses languishing among the
drafts. I also find that the real impasse in my exchanges with Wayne
Price leaves me considerably less than satisfied. So I want to take a
final opportunity to respond to what seems most and least promising in
the arguments for âanarchist democracyâ and then, in the hopes of making
my original position a bit clearer, I want to attempt a Proudhonian
defense of what seems defensible in âdemocratic practices.â
Several contributors to the exchange have made a point of talking about
the dangers of overreacting to the language of âdemocracyâ or leaning
too heavily on etymology. Those are obviously useful cautions. Most of
us are familiar with the quibbles by which authoritarians of various
sorts attempt to use etymology against anarchism and expand the envelope
of âanarchyâ to include their pet archisms. Precisely because those
rhetorical maneuvers are so familiar, it doesnât seem unreasonable to
expect a bit of precision and theoretical substance from the advocates
of âanarchist democracy.â And those of us who see âdemocracy,â as we
understand it, across a very important divide from anarchy, may perhaps
be forgiven for a certain degree of caution and skepticism.
Clarity in the exchange requires dealing with both matters of principle
and matters of rhetoric. If âdemocracyâ and âanarchyâ are to represent
compatible projects, then it has to be clear how that worksâand then it
seems necessary to explain why retaining the language of âdemocracyâ to
describe anarchic relations is useful. I think that the exchange has
demonstrated that it is not particularly easy to do both.
In âAnarchism as Radical Liberalism,â Nathan Goodman makes an
interesting appeal for political and economic systems characterized by
âopenness.â Using the work of Don Lavoie, he makes a brief but
intriguing case for glasnost as the defining quality of a âradicalized
democracy.â As I understand what is proposed, it seems this is a path to
anarchy of the sort I have rejected in my initial essay, but it seems to
be a good-faith proposal. Also the path from âopennessâ to anarchy seems
to have fewer clear obstacles than other nominally âdemocraticâ options.
This seems to be a principled position with possibilities worth
exploring, but its âdemocraticâ character seems in large part to be an
accident of the Cold War context. Goodman even quotes Lavoie as saying:
âThe Russian word translates better into âopennessâ than it does into
âdemocracy.ââ
I think Kevin Carson ends up in a similar place, though by a somewhat
different path. In his lead essay, âOn Democracy as a Necessary
Anarchist Value,â he quickly dispatches the question of opposing
principles by simply equating âdemocracyâ and âanarchy,â going on to
emphasize the goal of maximizing human agency. I can certainly agree
that at least one of the goals of anarchists should be to maximize
individual agency (although, given my emphasis on Proudhonâs theory of
collective force, itâs not hard to anticipate the complications I
expect), but, even with Carsonâs lengthy explanation, I have a hard time
making any sense of the impulse to call anarchy âdemocracy.â
With his references to David Graeberâs work, I think that Carson
provides various pieces of an inclusive narrative according to which
âdemocracyâ stands for something that is âas old as history, as human
intelligence itselfââand perhaps that something is even somewhat
anarchistic in its character. I understand the impulse behind Graeberâs
defense of a âdemocracyâ that is not narrowly defined by a Western
philosophical canon. But, honestly, Graeberâs rhetoric is not
reassuring. When he claims that that âdemocratic assemblies can be
attested in all times and places,â or that âall social systems, even
economic systems like capitalism, have always been built on top of a
bedrock of actually-existing communism,â I canât help but think that the
keywords have been stretched close to the point of meaninglessness. And
itâs not because I think any particular political tradition has a
monopoly on useful political concepts and principles. It is rather
because my experience is that there are very few well-defined concepts
or well-wrought principles that are unchanging over time (let alone
stable through translation) and clear without substantial
contextualization and unitary in application. The socialism of 1834 and
the socialism of 1848, to take one example, were worlds apart. The
mutualism of 1865 and the mutualism of 1881 were perhaps just as
distinct. But la dĂŠmocratie in France in 1848 and la DĂŠmocratie in the
same time and place were also distinct, the various organizations and
institutions that invoked the name of one or both were diverse in their
values, and the norms of a new chapter of political discourse were being
worked out on the fly, often in very close connection with the rapidly
changing fortunes of the Second Republic. I donât know many political
terms that have not represented substantially different practices over
relatively short periods of time, and it seems to me that the twists and
turns of Graeberâs argument testify to the difficulties of claiming
âdemocracyâ for this perennial (and possibly anarchistic) something.
Perhaps because it has not, in general, been thought of as something
that one practiced, anarchy seems bright, shiny and clearly defined in
contrast with virtually all of these other potential keywords. If there
is as much confusion about anarchy in many circles as there is about
democracy (or any number of other political concepts), the source of the
uncertainty seems different. After all, even the theoretically
sophisticated treatments of anarchy tend to differentiate the concept
from its popular connotations of chaos and uncertainty by attempting to
show what has been considered chaotic and uncertain in a different
light. Anarchist thinkers as diverse as Proudhon, Bellegarrigue,
Kropotkin and Labadie have all played with the relationships between
âanarchyâ and âorder,â most often suggesting that existing conceptions
might be flipped. But a reversal is different from an uncoupling of the
two notions and when we say that âanarchy is orderâ it is order, and not
anarchy, that we are asking people to redefine. So it is likely that
when we talk about anarchy, most people really know what weâre talking
about, but lack our positive feelings about the notionâand our critique
of the alternativesâand our optimistic sense of where it all might lead.
That poses a particular set of problems for those of us who want to
promote anarchy as a political ideal, which I am happy to take on, but
Iâm not sure what advantage is gained by adding the different set of
problems posed by this vague, ubiquitous reconstruction of âdemocracy.â
In both of these cases however, while I disagree with the rhetorical
framing, I am at least sympathetic to the stated goals. I expect that
the societies envisioned are, in both cases, rather distant from my own
ideal, but both involve healthy progress in a decidedly libertarian
direction. If âdemocracyâ is the best we can doâand even the sorts of
democracy proposed here seem pretty far removed at the momentâthen these
are proposals that seem to glean what is best from democratic tradition
(broadly defined).
I wish I could say the same about my other democratic interlocutor,
Wayne Price, but his âLast Responseâ is not the sort of thing that
inspires confidence. I might seem ungrateful to take exception to its
agreeable tone. Price begins with what seems to be a mix of conciliation
and praise:
Shawn Wilbur is correct, I think, when he writes, âPrice and I have
enough in common to have a useful conversation about anarchy and
democracy, and that we could start with something very close to a shared
political language.â Since I have a great deal of respect for Shawn as
an interpreter of Proudhon, let me try to state what may be common in
our views:
Unfortunately, what I actually said was this:
This ought to mean that Price and I have enough in common to have a
useful conversation about anarchy and democracy, and that we could start
with something very close to a shared political language. That we
obviously have not had a useful conversation requires some explainingâŚ
And that paragraph was immediately preceded by this one, which explains
the âshared political languageâ in rather different terms than Priceâs
attempt:
It seems to me that Price has made his own position clear. He envisions
a democracy in which minorities will, in fact, be subject to the
decisions of majorities. The silver lining he offers is that the
minorities will not be static, so we will not see the same sort of
oppression we see in more conventionally hierarchical societies. He
seems to see this relationship as just and legitimate, although it is
not clear whether he believes there is a political duty to assent to
some âwill of the peopleâ or whether he believes that there is some more
utilitarian justification. What seems clear enough, however, is that
this majority rule is not a failure in his mind. Given that apparent
fact, it does not seem out of line to attribute to Price some sort of
(still not precisely clarified) democratic principleâand one that
occupies a place on the political map awfully close to the one I
assigned it in my own account.
Itâs hard to know what to make of the rest of Priceâs response. He
spends a third of it speculating about âwhether Shawn is saying that
this means that I am not a real anarchist,â lumping himself together
with a group of people for whom âradical democracyâ does not seem to
have a uniform meaning, but not actually responding to my
characterization of his position.
Looking back over his contributions, however, it seems to me that my
characterization is fair enough and that, rather than shifting the
language of âdemocracyâ onto relations governed by other relations
(openness, glasnost, maximizing agency, etc.), Price seems intent on
applying the language of âanarchyâ to relations that are hierarchical
and governmentalist in principle. He is correct, of course, that we both
believe that â[a]t times it will be necessary to make collective
decisions using democratic procedures,â at least in the short run. But
the nature of his responseâthe mangled quotation, the failure to
clarify, etc.âmake that âdemocraticâ eventuality seem even more dire to
me. This is not, to be just a bit blunt, the sort of interaction you
want to have with someone whose pitch is basically âweâll take turns
oppressing each other a little.â
But letâs not leave things there.
Letâs acknowledge that the points of agreement and disagreement among
the contributors here are complicated. For example, the âdemocratic
practicesâ that Price seems to approve, and I anticipate with some
dread, do not seem to be the characteristic practices of Graeberâs
perennial and ubiquitous âdemocracy,â and it might not be too great a
stretch to associate them, in that context, with âfailureâ in the sense
that I have done in my contributions. As the market advocates among us
are almost certainly aware, it is a common trope among Graeber-inspired
anarchists that people only turn to counting and calculation as a means
of organizing themselves when society (characterized in this view by a
basis in communism and informal democracy) begins to break down. And
that reading seems generally faithful to Graeberâs variety of social
anarchism, at the core of which is a faith that people can work things
out without recourse to mechanisms like market valuation or vote-taking.
When we shift our focus away from the questions of vocabulary and
rhetoric, our divisions look different. In order to wrap up my
contributions to this exchange, I would like to redraw the lines between
us in a way that acceptsâwithin clearly defined limitsâWayne Priceâs
contention that we are in agreement about the practical side of things.
Having proposed this new divide, I then want to undertake a limited
defense of democratic practices, including voting, in a way that draws
on Proudhonâs later works and, in a sense, completes the argument
against the democratic principle. This move is not just consistent with
the Proudhonian analysis Iâve been making, but is probably required by
any very serious application.
I want to avoid getting too bogged down in the details of Proudhonâs
final works, where we can find his own unfinished attempts to reimagine
institutions like universal suffrage and constitutionalism in
anarchistic terms. Those who are familiar with the approach in Theory of
Property will recognize that the recuperation of democracy is the
logical complement to the recuperation of property. For those unfamiliar
with that work, here is a key passage:
We have finally understood that the opposition of two absolutes
[property, the governmental State]âone of which, alone, would be
unpardonably reprehensible and both of which, together, would be
rejected, if they worked separatelyâis the very cornerstone of social
economy and public right: but it falls to us to govern it and to make it
act according to the laws of logic.
The âNew Theoryâ of property depends on the recognition âthat the
reasons [motifs, motives, impetus, justification] for property, and thus
its legitimacy, must be sought, not in its principle or its origin, but
in its aims.â On the basis of principle, property remains âtheft,â
absolutist and âunpardonably reprehensible.â But as early as 1842, in
the Arguments Presented to the Public Prosecutor Regarding the Right of
Property, Proudhon had been exploring the possibility that the
equalization of property and the limitation of its scope might allow its
effects to be generally neutralized. As he embraced the notion of
antimony, and it became clear that this sort of counterbalancing was
perhaps the most promising means of at least neutralizing authority, the
doors were thrown wide open for the consideration of what other
institutions might serve as social counterweights. And it should be no
surprise that universal suffrage, constitutionalism and other existing
democratic practices were subject to similar attempts at recuperation in
Proudhonâs final works.
But in what sense could such a theory be anarchic or anarchistic?
Obviously, this is not the simple anarchy, identified as a perpetual
desideratum in The Principle of Federation, but if the effect is indeed
to balance and thus neutralize the authoritarian or absolutist elements
in various institutionsâall of them still considered suspect in
principleâthen perhaps we have anarchy as a resultant. It may not be
immediately obvious how a âgovernedâ opposition becomes the âvery
cornerstone of social economy and public right,â but it should be very
easy for us to identify anarchy with the combined effects of various
opposing forces or tendencies. The principle of anarchy is not
compromised by the fact that anarchy is inseparable from conflict. Like
the principle of authority, it is a response to that fact.
If any of this seems unfamiliar or outlandish, consider that what
Proudhon proposed for âpropertyâ was not significantly different from
Bakuninâs treatment of âauthorityâ in âGod and the State.��� In the
context of his quite thorough rejection of the principle of authority,
the way to avoiding âspurning every [individual] authorityâ is to treat
expertise as a matter of difference between individuals and not of
social hierarchy, and then to neutralize the potentially authoritarian
effects of that difference by balancing expertise against expertise.
It would be easy, at this point, to expand the analysis of Proudhonâs
final works and trace his own work towards the recuperation of at least
certain democratic practices, which we should probably understand as
complementary to the recuperation of property. But that would be a long
and convoluted tale. Instead, I would simply like to pick out one aspect
of Proudhonâs theoryâhis frequent use of the English term
self-government among the synonyms for anarchyâand propose the bare
outline how anarchic self-government might function in practice.
Letâs figure out how we might build a road, or undertake similar
projects, using the principle of federation and the sociology of
collective force. Readers can then determine whether the distinctions
that I have been proposing do or do not actually make a difference. Iâll
structure the sketch around four basic observations about social
organization:
organizational structures to the organization of a free society is
almost certainly overestimated. If we are considering building a road,
then there are all sorts of technical questions to be answered. We need
to know about potential users, routes, construction methods, ecological
impacts, etc.âand the answers to all of these questions will
significantly narrow the range of possible proposals. We need to make
sure that the plans which seem to serve specific local needs can be met
with local resources, which will further narrow the possibilities. And
in a non-governmental society, there can be no right to coerce
individuals in the name of âthe People,â nor can there be any obligation
for individuals to give way to the will of the majorityâand this absence
of democratic rights and duties must, I think, be recognized, if the
society is to be considered even vaguely anarchisticâso new limitations
are likely to appear when individuals feel that their interests are not
represented by proposals.
The simplest sort of self-government, where individuals simply pursue a
combination of their own interestsâincluding, of course, their interests
as members of various social collectivitiesâand the knowledge necessary
to serve them, will either lead to proposals that are acceptable to all
the interested parties or they will encounter some obstacle that this
sort of simple self-government appears unable to overcome. This second
case is presumably the point at which a vote and the imposition of the
will of the majority might seem useful. But what is obvious is that such
a resolution does not solve the problem facing this particular polity.
This sort of democracy is what happens when the simplest sort of
self-governmentâwhich is probably not worth calling government at
allâbreaks down, and it involves relations that seem difficult to
reconcile with the notion of self-government.
But perhaps this very simple self-government revolves around the wrong
sort of self.
individual, nor âthe People,â understood abstractly, but some real
social collectivity. The vast majority of Proudhonâs sociological
writings actually relate to the analysis of how unity-collectivities,
organized social groups with a unified character, emerge and dissolve in
society, but what is key for us to note here is that we are not talking
about abstract notions like âthe People.â Instead, if we are talking
about a sort of social self-government, it would seem that the avoidance
of exploitation and oppression is going to depend on carefully
identifying real collectivities to which various interested parties
belong. While âthe Peopleâ may find their mutual dependence a rather
abstract matter, the more precisely we can identify and clarify the
workings of specific collectivities, the less chance there should be
that purely individual interests undercut negotiations among the members
of those collectivities.
One of the important elements of Proudhonâs sociology is his recognition
that collectivities may have different interests than the strictly
individual interests of the persons of which they are composed. That
means that individuals may find themselves forced to recognize their own
interests as complex and perhaps in conflicts, depending on the scale
and focus of analysis. This may mean, for example, that there will be
hard choices between the direct satisfaction of individual desires and
various indirect, social satisfactions. But it should also mean that the
more strictly individual sorts of satisfaction cannot be neglected when
members are thinking about the health and success of the group. To the
extent that real collectivities can be identified, and decisions
regarding them limited to the members of those collectivities,
negotiations can be structured quite explicitly around the likely
trade-offs. To the extent that the health and success of the
collectivity depends on lively forms of conflict among the members (and
Proudhon made complexity and intensity of internal relations one of the
markers of the healthâand the freedomâof these entities), then the more
conscious all members must be of the need to maintain balance without
resorting to some winner-take-all scenario.
It will, of course, not always be possible to resolve conflict by
bringing together a single collectivity. There will be issues that can
be resolved through additional fact-finding or compromises within the
group, but there will be others that call for the identification of
other groups of interested parties, whether in parallel with the
existing groups, addressing different sorts of shared interests, at a
smaller scale, addressing interests that can be addressed separately
from the present context, or on a larger scale, addressing issues shared
by the given group and other groups as well. We can already see how this
analysis leads to federalism as an organizing principle, but perhaps it
is not quite clear how and why these various groups might be
constituted.
problem or convergence of interests. One of the consequences of breaking
with the governmental principle ought to be the abandonment of the
worldview that sees society always present as âthe People,â a
fundamentally governmental collectivity always present to intervene in
the affairs of individual persons. While there might be a few
institutions of self-government that enjoy a perpetual existence,
anarchists should almost certainly break with the notion that that each
individual is obliged to stand as a citizen of some general polity
whenever called to account for themselves.
Instead, the principle of voluntary association and careful attention to
real relations of interdependence ought to be our guides. And the rich
sort of self-interest weâve been exploring here ought to serve us well
in that regard. To abandon the assumptions of governmentalism and take
on the task of self-government is going to be extremely demanding in
some cases, so we might expect that individuals will desire to keep
their relations simple where they can, coming together to form explicit
associations only when circumstances demand itâand then dissolving those
association when circumstances allow.
Where existing relations seem inadequate to meet our needs and desires,
then some new form of association is always an optionâand with practice
hopefully we will learn to take on the complex responsibilities
involved. Where existing relations seem to bind us in ways that stand in
the way of our needs and desires, weâll learn to distinguish between
those existing associations which simply do not serve and those of a
more fundamental, inescapable sortâand hopefully we will grow into those
large-scale responsibilities from which we cannot extricate ourselves.
Conventions for the use of property, the distribution of revenue and
products, the mechanics of exchange, etc. can probably be approached in
much the same way we would approach the formation of a new workgroup,
the extension of a roadway, the establishment of sustainable waste or
stormwater disposal, etc.
which we identifyâor extricateâspecific social âselves,â on the one
hand, or establish their involvement in larger-scale collectivities, on
the other, and establish the narrow confines within which various
âdemocraticâ practices might come into play. If we are organized in
anarchistic federations, then we can expect that organization to be not
just bottom-up, but very specifically up from the problems, up from the
local needs and desires, up from the material constraints, with the
larger-scale collectivities only emerging on the basis of converging
interests. Beyond the comparatively temporary nature of the federated
collectivities, we should probably specify that we are talking about a
largely consultative federalism, within which individuals strive to
avoid circumstances in which decision among options is likely to become
a clear loss for any of the interested parties. If we are forced by
circumstances to resort to mechanisms like a majority vote, then we will
want to contain the damage as much as possible. But I suspect we will
often find that the local decisions that are both sufficiently
collective and divisive to require something worth calling âdemocratic
practices,â but also sufficiently serious to push us to confrontations
within local groups may find solutions through consultation with other,
similar groups. Alternately, if the urgency is not simply localâif, for
example, ecological concerns are a factorâthey may find themselves
âsolved,â not by local desires at all, but by consideration of the
effects elsewhere.
Taking these various observations together, it should be clear that I do
indeed believe that sometimes we will be required to fall back on
familiar sorts of democratic practices, but I hope it is also clear why,
in very practical terms, I believe that this will constitute a failure
within an anarchist society.
I would be remiss if I did not very briefly return to Proudhonâs Theory
of Property and the proposal there, according to which âthe opposition
of two absolutes,â each objectionable on principle, becomes âthe very
cornerstone of social economy and public right.â In the previous section
I have obviously been attempting to sketch out a federated society in
which the balances struck would be between less objectionable and
absolute elements, suggesting a fairly well developed sort of anarchy,
in the context of which, a complex sort of consensus is the ideal. But,
as Iâve suggested, this is a demanding standard and other sorts of
balances might be struck. The clues in Proudhonâs late work suggest that
perhaps his recuperation of universal suffrage would have functioned in
a similar way to his recuperation of domain, and perhaps that it is not
simply the anarchistic âcitizen-stateâ that would have functioned as a
counterweight to property. My reservations about Proudhonâs late theory
of property arise from the fact that domain is potentially a very
formidable power within society, but it is at least presented in those
works as a largely defensive element. My reservations about democratic
practices is that they are much more likely to be invasive and that, in
the presence of that potentially invasive power, various defensive
counterweights would likely have to be strengthened, if a real balance
was to be struck.