💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › peter-gelderloos-defying-power.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:16:09. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Defying Power
Author: Peter Gelderloos
Date: May 5th, 2018 (Part I) and June 28th, 2018 (Part II)
Language: en
Topics: the state, democracy, c4ss
Source: Retrieved on July 2, 2018 from https://c4ss.org/content/50774 and https://c4ss.org/content/50991

Peter Gelderloos

Defying Power

Part I

Since its publication, I have come across two reviews of Worshiping

Power that I would like to respond to, not to bat a discursive ball back

and forth, but to engage with the flow of conversations that form an

integral part of our interaction with the world around us. One is

William Gillis’ “The Tangled Paths of State Formation and Resistance,”

and the other is Kristian Williams’ “Mystifying: An Anarchist View of

Early State Formation.”

Much of Gillis’ review focuses on a very interesting question that I

want to save for last. First, there are a couple more technical matters.

To begin with, I would disagree with the characterization that “The

fight between authoritarianism and anti-authoritarianism is ultimately a

fight over values far more than it is a fight over particular conditions

or tools.” Later, this same affirmation resurfaces in regard to markets,

when Gillis praises the book for its accuracy about “markets not

obliging inequality, hierarchy or states”

There is a constant interplay between values, institutions, and social

organization. Agency and the strategies of specific groups play a major

role in this process, but structural inertia is also capable of carrying

the day. What’s more, there is a crucial difference between tools and

machines. Machines produce social realities, whereas tools merely

amplify agency. I’m not sure whether Gillis would say there is nothing

deterministic about technology (understood as an entire social complex

of machines and practices), but I would not.

As far as markets are concerned, Gillis’ second characterization is

accurate. Markets do not deterministically create hierarchy or states.

However, markets are without a doubt dangerous to freedom and

interesting to states.

As far as I can tell, those societies that practiced market institutions

over long periods of time, without developing strong hierarchies or

states as a result, kept a large part of social life outside of the

market and had practices that enabled the self-defense of their economic

autonomy. The quantitative logic of markets is potentially damaging to

life. It is a virus that if unleashed is capable of destroying

everything (even the market itself, if we are to follow Braudel’s

assertion that capitalism superseded and consumed market dynamics).

For markets to be made innocuous, a society needs unimpeded,

non-monetized access to their basic means of survival. Land, as well as

people’s vital activity, must be inalienable, which means they cannot be

bought or sold. In a society where the basis of existence is a healthy

commons, I believe that people can safely experiment with a wide range

of mechanisms for distributing all the other goods and services that

round out our lives. But collective mechanisms of self-defense against

accumulation, enclosure, and quantification are vital.

James C. Scott expresses the view that markets were actually troublesome

to early states. The work of merchants was harder for rulers to track

and tax, so they discouraged it at times in favor of a model of

accumulation based on landed laborers. I don’t dispute that this was a

characteristic of the land-based states of southeast Asia Scott focuses

on, at least in certain moments in their development.

But the archipelagos of the Mediterranean and the Java and Banda seas

give us quite a different model. While states in those areas did not

create commerce and markets, they did not hesitate to pursue them, to

redesign them, and then to harness them to extract unprecedented amounts

of value that led to an exponential expansion of the technologies of

social control and warfare that continues to this day.

On a more trivial level, Gillis claims I made a factual error in dating

the appearance of agriculture and plant domestication to 10,500

(actually I give a range of dates), rather than 23,000 years ago. This

comes down to a minor confusion regarding the difference between

cultivation and domestication. Cultivation, which certainly happened in

Palestine 23,000 years ago, and probably in many other places and even

earlier, is simply the sowing and harvesting of plant foods, typically

wild cereals. Contrary to the prevailing stereotypes regarding

non-civilized peoples, any hunter-gatherer community is capable of doing

this, but in most conditions, it would be a waste of their effort.

Domestication, on the other hand, requires far more dedication over a

much longer period of time, as it implies the production of new species

intentionally selected for human consumption. This is the process that

only began about 11,000 years ago.

Another observation Gillis makes regards the “hostility” I evince

towards academics. It’s a contradiction I am unable to resolve:

admiration for those whose studies have expanded my horizons or

challenged my beliefs; hatred for the institutions they work for; scorn

for those who make their paycheck fine-tuning this system. But we don’t

have to stop at the contradiction of the radical academic. Why not

include the radical writer, making a name for himself by talking about

revolution?

A certain professor, asked to write a blurb for the book, politely asked

me, “Are you sure you want me to?” At first I was surprised, until I

realized that in the book I had just written, the hatred and the scorn

for academia far outweighed the admiration.

I thank Gillis for highlighting that hostility and also the

contradictions that surround it, especially when those lead one to take

a utilitarian view of knowledge, as I do, ambiguously, by suggesting

that the pursuit of knowledge must be justified. Gillis is right to

spurn the idea that “we must interrogate every flight of investigation

and demand to know its pragmatic utility for the social order” (their

characterization). But I would argue that their interpretation misses

out on the ambiguity in my statement. I wrote, “Learning is only

worthwhile if it helps us fight, to live healthy, to live free.” They

respond:

What a terribly impoverished notion of “living free”! Surely inquiry and

creativity are themselves part and parcel of freedom, not merely

servants or tools. Is freedom just some passive state of being we’re

trying to retreat to? Or is it an active, striving, reaching sort of

thing, that necessarily includes learning for its own sake, exploring

for its own sake, dreaming for its own sake?

Actually, I haven’t provided any notion, impoverished or otherwise, of

“living free.” I leave that to the reader. And if a reader such as

Gillis requires unbridled curiosity and independent inquiry to live

free, so be it.

Gillis’ warning about a utilitarian view of learning stands. I share

those concerns. But let me add a warning about science “unleashed,” a

notion that receives praise from the dominant moralists of the day.

Museum basements across North America and Europe are filled with bones

stolen from indigenous burial grounds across the world. This was done by

trained scientists as part of their unbridled search for knowledge. And

peace-loving Albert Einstein was indispensable to the invention of the

nuclear bomb. To anyone with common sense, this would have been

predictable — the military always gets first dibs. But sometimes, highly

intelligent people can be really, really stupid.

Then there’s the recent revelation that some of Chomsky’s linguistics

works had military applications, and that the Pentagon made use of MIT

and other universities by giving scientists there the feeling that they

had absolute freedom in their work, they were simply funding free

inquiry that would benefit “humanity.”

Okay: utilitarianism is a straight-jacket for knowledge. But curiosity

is never neutral. How do we continue to practice free inquiry in the

middle of a battlefield? I don’t trust those who claim not to be on any

side, because I can see who signs their paycheck, even if they don’t

notice.

Gillis’ argument about authoritarianism below the state threshold is the

one that interests me the most, but I want to save it for last, to end

on a good note.

First, I want to quickly respond to the other review, written by a

decidedly grumpy Kristian Williams. Williams’ disapproval lies on two

foundations: that I offer no clear thesis regarding the causes of state

formation; and that I give tautological explanations for state

formation.

From the beginning, Williams uses the snarky tone that is more

fashionable among writers trying to build their career profile than

those engaged in the solidaristic project of trying to foster stronger

collective struggles. One of the many problems with such a tone is that

it looks much worse when you get your facts wrong, as all of us will

inevitably do at some point, and as Williams does repeatedly throughout

his short text. Embarrassingly for Williams, he has missed the last

fifty-odd years of anarchist research into state formation, which is a

pretty bad omission for someone writing a review on the subject.

It seems that Williams doesn’t recognize the validity of non-academic

formats. He complains that “it is not until the final chapter that we

encounter anything as definite as a thesis statement.” He says “the

approach is opaque” and lacks “any clear direction”. The thesis he

identifies, quoted from my last chapter, is that “state formation is a

multilineal process and not a teleological, progressive evolution.”

Williams is not above telling a white lie to make his point. He claims I

have no thesis until the last chapter, and while I reject his assumption

that all critical writing must follow the style of the academic paper, I

recognize that his university education might have made him a bit

small-minded. But don’t they teach kids not to deliberately misrepresent

a source?

Here’s a quote from the introduction. In fact, it’s the last paragraph

of the introduction, just the place where they teach those who paid tens

of thousands of dollars to certify their brains to look for and find a

thesis statement. (Hey Gillis, there’s that hostility again. What should

I do about it?)

It is now undeniable that there are multiple pathways in the evolution

of states. I will not offer a single cause nor a single evolutionary

model. There are several models we could consider, building off the work

of a great many specialists. However, within each model, I find more

particularities than similarities. As such, throughout the following

chapters, which are divided thematically, I highlight the basic models

when they appear, but place the weight of the narrative on the

particularities of each case. This may not be the best format for rapid

summarizing, but its advantage is in avoiding potentially dogmatic

simplifications.

Hmmm. That looks pretty damn similar to the thesis that Williams claims

I don’t express until the last chapter of the book. It also looks like I

explain what my approach will be, and what direction I’ll be going in.

Williams might have been comforted by a chronological organization to

the book, instead of my “wandering” thematic approach, but I explained

that too in the introduction. Putting all the emphasis on the original

states props up the “Pandora’s Box” fallacy of state superiority, and a

progressive telling of history tends towards white supremacist

mythologizing backed by the fallacy of a unilineal history.

History unfolds in loops and spirals, full of backtracking or sudden

changes in trajectory, far more often than in a progressive series of

A-B-C… It also unfolds simultaneously on all continents. A truly

chronological telling is impossible. Many historians have created such a

narrative by ignoring non-European populations until the West invaded

and conquered them. These historians’ perspective follows the hegemonic

center and ignores the margins, to the point of completely dismembering

history and making it impossible to perceive relations of influence and

evolution. I could have been more explicit on this last point, but I

guess I wasn’t expecting such bad faith readings, and from an anarchist

no less.

What about the other shortcoming Williams picks up on? His perceived

tautology is as follows:

Gelderloos slides toward a kind of cultural determinism, and

disastrously pushes the notion to the point of outright tautology:

“Placed in the same adverse situation, a society with

anti-authoritarian, cooperative, and reciprocal values will find an

anti-authoritarian solution, while a society that values hierarchy may

likely form a state.” On that same page, he puts it more strongly, adds

in primitive accumulation, and reverses the cause and effect: “economic

accumulation is inconceivable without the hierarchical structures and

spiritual values that states and proto-states create.

Both of my statements are in line with Clastres’ groundbreaking studies

in the sixties and seventies and reconfirmed in detail by James C.

Scott’s current work. Williams is looking for a materialist explanation

for the State, but he has arrived half a century too late. I recommend

Engels’ The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State, which

was discredited ages ago. The materialists offered a mechanical

explanation for state formation, which is appealing to the scientific

mind. But their hypothesis is simply not born out by the historical

record. It gives us a theoretically useful lens for studying certain

moments of state formation, but it fails to take into full account the

political and spiritual production of that which is considered material

and natural.

Williams’ bemoans my failure to provide explanations for how a

state-forming culture might emerge. Sadly, he missed that too. Every

single chapter contains historical examples of how state-forming

cultures were strengthened, sometimes as a product of social evolution,

sometimes as the result of strategic decisions by would-be elites.

Every. Single. Chapter.

Perhaps Williams is looking for a single, tidy, deterministic cause that

brought state-forming cultures out of a smooth, egalitarian,

prelapsarian past. Maybe, the temperature and rainfall levels at which

such a culture forms, or the specific components and fuel source of the

authoritarian culture machine. But state formation is not that simple,

nor was there ever an innocent human past free of power dynamics.

For those who like it simple, I suggest the following exercise. Spend a

day with your housemates, trying to come up with all the ways that you

could make the street you live on more prestigious than the next street

over, and also ways that it might become more prestigious by chance,

without you lifting a finger. Now imagine you had years, generations, to

do this. If you think, at the end of the exercise, that there would be a

common thread linking all of your devious plans, or one external factor

that would determine their success or failure, then you are inferior

specimens of human creativity. Such nefarious creativity is hard to

contain within a tidy theoretical model.

Anyone can have a bad day and write a stupid article. Lord knows I have.

I just hope that’s the case with Kristian, and that his future writing

is as good as Our Enemies in Blue.

The most interesting question, I have saved for last, but it will have

to wait until the next installment: William Gillis’ question about

hierarchies that thrive below the state threshold. In Part II: how to

confront the kind of authoritarianism that could exist in non-state

societies, post-state societies, and even our own countercultures…

Part II

In Part I of this article, I responded to William Gillis’ review of

Worshiping Power: An Anarchist Vision of Early State Formation. I wanted

to give special attention to what I found to be his most interesting

critique.

Gillis takes me to task for focusing too much on the anthropological

definition of the state, analyzing how societies cross the threshold

from having hierarchies that don’t constitute a state to having stronger

hierarchies that do.

This focus on a very specific subsection of power structures is

interesting but it leads to a conclusion a little far afield from

anarchism’s concerns. What’s the most critical element to starting

multi-tier coercive administrations? The creation of values that enable

universal centralization. This is certainly true as far as it goes, but

the more interesting and anarchist question is what leads to domination

at all, in any flavor or organizational structure?

It’s a good point. And one that led me to imagine adding another chapter

to the book, one which I’ll outline here:

Defying Power: An Anarchist Vision of Active Statelessness

I could start by voicing an enthusiastic, “What he said,” regarding

James C. Scott’s research (The Weapons of the Weak, The Art of Not Being

Governed…) into the characteristics of populations in resistance to

state authority in Southeast Asia, particularly as regards food

production, kinship, geography, and heterodox religion. However, I would

like to add to some of these areas, discuss a couple others, and also

open the field to consider hierarchy below the state threshold both in

our movements today and in a hypothetical post-state future.

It might help to start by specifying what we mean by hierarchy. At an

analytical level, hierarchy is not any situation of inequality or

ranking. It is a ranking system capable of reproducing itself, in which

what is ranked is access to power. Curiously, the term’s original

meaning is “rule by a high priest.”

What is the opposite of hierarchy? Liberal concepts of freedom have

little to offer, as they are based in a mythical social contract, the

guarantee of rights that have little to do with quality of life and

access to power, and the achievement of an ill defined equality. No

human group enjoys anything approaching perfect equality, which makes

sense, as the latter is a mathematical concept that maps poorly onto

social relations. The tension between sameness and difference defines

human communities, and those that have rejected hierarchy do so not by

eliminating difference but by making impossible the unification and

centralization of power, such that difference simply cannot fuel a

hierarchical social relation.

If we understand that power is everywhere, then a social practice of

non-hierarchical power would require the non-alienation of power. Power

would always reside within the human activities that create it, rather

than being controlled and redistributed by self-reproducing

institutions. The power of the gardener would remain in her hands, and

if she ever did decide to form part of an association of gardeners for

the coordination of work and the sharing of materials, she might blend

her power with others, but would not lose legitimate recourse to that

power, as in the case of a guild that holds a monopoly over a certain

kind of productive activity and which is governed by an internal group

of leaders with privileged access to the product.

Another property of non-hierarchical power is that it is not

commutative. One kind of power cannot be swapped with another kind.

There is no fixed exchange rate between the power of the gardener and

the power of the healer or the storyteller. Their powers never flow

together to a central point of legitimation and control. Thus, not only

is power dispersed in such a society, it could never be centralized

because on a metaphysical level it has not been unified. We can speak of

many powers in such a society, not one power. Arriving at such a

practice requires us to entirely break with politics, the reification of

the poleis, which was the point of legitimation and centralization for a

patriarchal, contractual, and proprietary notion of power in the

militaristic slave economies of ancient Greek city-states.

Anarchist involvement in the 15M movement in Barcelona in 2011 revolved

largely around the attempt to break up unified power. This manifested as

a tension between direct democracy, which quickly evolved into an

authoritarian and bureaucratic process, and decentralized organizing and

decision-making.

Linked to the necessity of decentralization and disunity is the need for

complex as opposed to simple status. Any society in which people can be

ranked in a linear fashion is one that is prone to hierarchy, and one

that has probably undergone a severe cultural process of erasing or

belittling many of the criteria by which people can be evaluated. There

is no truly egalitarian group free of status, but it is a particular

group that only recognizes one kind of status value. Historically, this

has often involved valuing culturally masculine traits at the expense of

culturally feminine traits.

By valuing people according to an unending list of abilities and

qualities (a good singer, a good cook, a good hunter, a good mechanic, a

good mediator, a good connector, a good healer, a good fighter, a good

midwife, a good translator…), we can live a fuller life with more paths

to self-actualization, and we prevent any one kind of power from having

undue influence over the others. We could formalize many of these roles,

or not, but it requires constant effort to prevent the emergence of a

calcified value hierarchy that would heap disproportionate rewards on

some kinds of status and forget about others. And constant effort, over

multiple generations, usually means ritualization and inclusion within a

society’s mythos.

This brings us to the question of spirituality. Every society has a

spirituality. Ways of framing knowledge, explaining one’s relationship

with the world, and telling origin stories always surpass empirical fact

and rely on culturally subjective constructions. From an anarchist

standpoint, the most dangerous spirituality is the one that is

reproduced by a professional institution, without popular participation.

Perhaps the most dangerous subset of this type is the spirituality that

claims to be unquestionable, such as monotheism, or even worse, that

claims not even to be a spirituality, such as scientific rationalism.

Therefore, the kinds of spirituality with the most anarchistic

possibility are consciously metaphoric, flexible, and reliant on

non-professional, diffuse participation in their creation and

regeneration. Beyond the mode, the content should probably include an

emphasis on cycles of renewal, revolt, ecocentrism, freedom, community,

and reciprocity. Because spirituality is ultimately storytelling, it

also gives us a unique opportunity for remembering our history of

struggle, free from the stultifying effects of institutional

history-keepers. The folks at Otherworlds Review clearly have this in

mind.

The spirituality, as well as the ways of sharing reproductive tasks and

the kinship patterns, should be non-patriarchal. This is vital.

Patriarchy seems to be the most resilient form of hierarchy in human

history, as well as a necessary precondition for state formation. Many

cultures surviving colonization have traditional, non-patriarchal forms

of gender organization, and as part of a revolutionary process we can

develop (and are developing) social forms with no gender categories

whatsoever.

The sky is also the limit for different possible family structures.

However, there have been enough bad experiences with alternative

families within our radical movements to show how the Western notion of

freedom as “no attachments” leaves its mark and leaves, often, the most

exploited member of the failed experimental family holding the check. Or

the baby, as the case may be. This suggests that it may in fact be

necessary to have culturally inscribed expectations of responsibility

for care. (Sometimes, just sometimes, we’re not actually smarter than a

million years of human experimentation). But by no means do such

expectations need to fall solely on the biological mother or on a

heteronormative mother and father figure, as in the nuclear family

model.

The experiences of anti-authoritarian societies suggest the advantages

of multilateral kinship models. The multilateral part means that we

trace family in as many directions as possible, so that ideally,

everyone is related to everyone else. Most European languages have an

infinitesimal kinship vocabulary that shows the poverty of nuclear

families. The fact that we have only one word for “cousin,” any

horizontal relation further removed than sibling, makes us something of

a joke on the world stage. But we can build a new richness by

recognizing more forms of consanguinity and also non-sanguine family

relations (referring to whether or not someone is said to be related “by

blood”). For the latter, Christianity gives us the “god-parent,” but

such an adoptive familial relationship is by no means a Christian

invention.

In fact, different forms of adoption should have an important role in

any anti-authoritarian family model. Adoption—the explicit choice of

taking on the long-term responsibilities of the family bond—enshrines a

kinship logic based on solidarity rather than involuntary association.

Adoption allows the family to be a tool of resistance in situations of

repression and migration, taking in those who are orphaned by conflict

or by the prison system, as well as those who have to flee state effects

(like environmental destruction, war, and poverty). Adoption also

negates the Western rationalist assumption that an ethnicity is a

genetic community and therefore an essentialist and separate human

group. The normalization of widespread adoption, not just of children

but of anyone, shows that an ethnicity is the affirmation of a shared

cultural practice. And the habit of many anti-authoritarian societies to

claim belonging to multiple ethnic groups, as an extension of the

multilateral kinship logic, breaks the power of ethnicity to serve as a

motor for borders and ideas of racial superiority.

The biggest obstacle to reconstructing family through the proliferation

of more horizontal, elective, and multilateral kinship bonds is that

consumerism has made us forget how to make a commitment. People from

Generation X can’t even assemble an impoverished nuclear family, while

those who were raised on Facebook don’t properly know what a relation

is. The family bond, that had already degraded to the superficial level

of a consumer choice, is now constantly one click away from being

unfriended. Social network technologies are by nature an addiction, a

dependency-fostering medium, and addiction substitutes the family bond.

This mass-produced destruction of meaningful, solid relationships in our

society, and the celebrated immaturity that accompanies it, may be one

of the most pernicious forces for protecting hierarchies and domination

within our movements for liberation. Much of this has to do with

conflict resolution. Dependency on police and judges, as well as the

alienation and insolidarity that arise from antisocial crime or

conflicts between neighbors, make it easy for the state to rule us.

Monopolizing and institutionalizing conflict resolution and harm

reduction (usually through law codes and the logic of crime and

punishment) was an important task for early states.

Many anti-authoritarian societies traditionally had specialists in

conflict resolution and mediation, usually older people who could claim

neutrality by being equally related to all people involved (imagine that

a grandparent has an equal familial relation to all their grandchildren,

in the case of a conflict between cousins). And mediation is both a

calling, dependent on a certain sensibility, and a skill that requires a

great deal of practice. In anti-authoritarian societies, one of the most

important elements seems to be that the mediators have no specialized

enforcers. They are not allowed to own the conflict the way a judge

does, nor force their verdict on anyone. People in the conflict choose

to accept their intervention (suggesting the need for many different

mediators, so there is an actual choice), and the resolutions they

propose have to win community support.

In other words, people never surrender their autonomy or their own

judgment, not those directly involved in the conflict or harmful

situation, and not those around them. Curiously, the conflict resolution

and accountability strategies that most anarchists have opted for never

disassemble the logic of the prison system. Rather than denying the

authoritarian logic that someone has an absolute claim to the truth,

they simply change who is allowed to exercise that power.

Unsurprisingly, the power gets abused.

Another important element in this kind of conflict mediation is the lack

of a written law code. People’s actual needs take precedence. The needs

of the person harmed, the needs of the person who harmed, the needs of

disputing parties unable to solve a conflict on their own, the needs of

the rest of the community who allowed harm to take place, who are being

affected by the conflict. A law code replaces respect for people’s needs

with obedience to authority, and it allows a small group—those who have

the most power in the process, of writing it—to shape their society’s

morals. Without a written code, everyone can be constantly involved in

shaping and challenging the common ethos. If it’s an unending debate,

everyone is empowered to participate. The moment the debate ends, people

trick themselves into thinking they’ve discovered final solutions and

have no more need for personal or collective growth, and they have

created the specter of obedience.

Then there’s the question of punishment and response. I believe that

punishment is an authoritarian practice that institutionalizes community

power to do harm and seeks to justify, a priori, doing harm to those who

do not have community support. Subsequently, the community has no

ethical arguments against doing harm, no moral superiority over those it

punishes, and therefore it locks itself into a dynamic of “might makes

right,” a judicial arms race. What’s more, punishment dehumanizes the

person who is punished, and in the case that they have actually harmed

anyone and not just broken some written law, punishment prevents them

from the growth and healing they need to go through not to harm other

people. It’s been pretty well demonstrated by now that prison systems

and other punishment regimes reproduce the harms they supposedly are

meant to stop. This makes perfect sense for a state, because states

thrive off of interpersonal violence. But how does it make sense for

anarchists, feminists, and other radicals? I think people who posture as

wanting to go really hard against those who cause harm within our

circles should be unmasked as merely reproducing the harm that they get

power from opposing. We should instead be valuing the long, thankless,

and difficult process of accompanying those who have been harmed and

those who have caused harm as they go through their healing process.

These processes are very different. The former requires loving support

and regaining power over one’s life, and the latter requires strong

criticism and an emphasis on learning empathy. But both are necessary

for restoring a healthy community.

At this point, though, I would make a distinction between punishment and

vengeance. Vengeance, such an ugly word in statist society, is

retribution that is not sanctioned by the broader community or society.

It’s not punishment, because it doesn’t make higher claims to objective

justice. At most, it seeks to satisfy a fully individualized justice. I

think Bash Back! showed how vengeance can be a vital form of healing, in

case Frantz Fanon hadn’t already made that clear. Vengeance is an

important way of ensuring that we never surrender our freedom of action

to the community, and it also makes sure that those who harm the least

powerful—those who are excluded by majority morality—or those with a

talent for winning over mediators and public opinion, can still face

consequences for their actions. Some societies combine mediation and

accountability mechanisms with semi- or fully normalized practices of

vengeance. A combination of compassion, collective healing, and direct

action is probably a good idea: when the vengeance tradition becomes

more powerful than any mechanism for mediation, then you have systematic

feuding, which can get pretty gnarly and isn’t terribly conducive to

personal or collective growth. So it’s not a technique without its

dangers.

Perhaps the most dangerous power of accountability mechanisms is the

power to ostracize. Ostracism—fully excluding someone from their social

group—is basically social murder. And it seems that stateless societies

around the world traditionally recognized this. They reserved ostracism

as an absolute last resort, only for the most extreme and incorrigible

cases. In a communal society, ostracism is rightly seen as being just as

bad as killing someone.

But in our internet society, ostracism is a first resort. It’s common

practice. If someone rubs you the wrong way, you troll them, you drag

them, you get them excluded, and then you block them. This practice has

extended to social movements. Anyone who treats ostracism lightly is

fighting against any possibility of liberation in our lifetimes.

On the other hand, practices of critique and ridicule—especially against

those with more power and status—are very common in traditional

anti-authoritarian societies. Those can have a place in our own

movements, but only if our bonds of solidarity are stronger. The ideal

conclusion to ridicule is that the object of the critique blushes, they

shut up for a while, maybe they storm off and pout, but eventually they

come back to again share their gifts with us, and we welcome them back

warmly. The purpose is to give those in the peanut gallery the power to

intervene, not to permanently silence anyone or to break the social

bond. Of course, this means that practices of critique and ridicule need

to be accompanied by intense practices of caring.

Ridicule without caring is dangerous because it can lead to

stigmatization, the horizontal creation of a value hierarchy in which

some members of the group are permanently scorned or belittled. Such a

practice can serve as a motor for the production of ever worse kinds of

hierarchy.

In fact, so much comes down to questions of emotional maturity or

manipulation, that it seems vital to encourage a culture of personal and

collective growth, and the best possible practices of education and

child-rearing, in which children are given both autonomy and

encouragement to learn, along with every possibility to self-actualize.

I would also strongly favor combative over idyllic child-rearing

strategies. Children shouldn’t grow up in a perfect, peaceful world.

They should learn the absolute necessity of self-defense. There will be

no utopia. Humans will always have the capacity to treat one another

poorly, and children need to learn how to protect themselves and assert

their limits as a part of growing up.

There’s also the question of the relationship between society and the

youth. Rather than the boy scout model of harnessing children into a

patriotic corps that mindlessly supports the community project,

over-structuring childhood so that the young have an easy time of

finding “their place,” children should be left in an antagonistic

position with respect to their community. This means to a certain extent

that they need their own space, a space partially outside the community.

If they have autonomy, are given respect, and are taught the basics of

self-defense (which also means parents defending themselves against

their children when they enter the little dictator phase), they will not

fail to see the forms of complacency and hypocrisy creeping into their

society, and fight against them.

I’ll end talking by about alienation, land, and relationships. A society

that doesn’t want to go down the road of the authoritarian apocalypse

should never treat the land or other aspects of nature as things that

can just be bought and sold. Relationships of domination with nature

prefigure relationships of domination in human society, and they also

provide the possibility for regimes of exploitation and accumulation

that permit a nascent elite to construct the weapons and fund the war

against all the rest of us. And the more degraded our natural

environment is, the harder it is to turn to it as a refuge when we

attempt to escape state power, a guerrilla base when we attempt to

destroy state power, and a shrine when we realize the need to develop an

anti-authoritarian, ecocentric spirituality.

If we understand that we are a part of nature, then it is easier to see

how social relationships are just an extension of natural relationships.

Because it’s vital to find a balance between social mobility and the

sanctity of relationships. It’s easier to deal with stress and conflict

if we’re able to move around and find our place—or find the patterns of

nomadism that suit us—rather than being stuck within a society. However,

mobility should not mean alienation and rootlessness, as it does under

capitalism. We live through our relationships. They should be

inalienable.