đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș martin-small-athenian-democracy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:49:42. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Athenian Democracy Author: Martin Small Date: November 1964 Language: en Topics: Ancient Greece, democracy, direct democracy, participatory democracy Source: Retrieved on 22nd September 2020 from https://libcom.org/library/athenian-democracy Notes: Originally published in Anarchy #045: Ancient Greece
THE ANARCHIST MAINTAINS THAT ALL MEN HAVE THE POWER to organise their
own lives: he maintains that this power does exist and should be usedâor
at least, using a purely aesthetic and personal rather than ethical form
of judgment, that he would find it more pleasing if they did use it. And
a situation which would demonstrate conclusively the truth of what he
maintains, is conceivable. But since he maintains only that the use of
the power which he describes is possible, his case cannot be disproved
by any demonstration of how rarely this power has been used, or of how
difficult it is to learn to use it. Since what the anarchist desires,
either as an absolute good or merely for his own private satisfaction,
can be brought about only if people believe what he says, he wishes to
be believed. But though the incredulity of others may shake his own
conviction, no amount of disbelief, no matter how far and wide the words
and deeds in which it is expressed, can refute his case: that there is a
power, and that it should be used.
Those who doubt the anarchist case may say that there is little evidence
in history that this power exists, none that it exists in all men; the
anarchist will reply that there is much evidence of the failure to use
the power of which he speaks, none that it does not exist in all men. He
will say, do we not, in effect (however many different ways of
expressing it there may be), describe and assess ourselves and each
other as having been more or less able to use this power of which I
speak, as having learnt more or less well how to use it? And when the
anarchist appeals to history, he will appeal, not so much to what has
happened, as to how men naturally think of what has happened: not in
this way to escape from an objective fact to a subjective impression,
but rather in this way to emphasise that the deeds of men through time
are the different manifestations of an endeavour which is one and the
same in all men and that all men in their different ways have been aware
of this. And, the anarchist will say, in the societies and civilisations
which they have built to contain their common life men have expressed
their feelings about this endeavour: it has been glorious, perilous,
hopeless, absurd, and every man has found himself encouraged or
discouraged in his own individual interpretation of the common endeavour
by the expectations of the society in which he lives.
Of every society it must be asked, What encouragement has it given to
that power whereby men are able to build and create their own lives, and
what provision does it make for men to learn the use of this powerâor
does it merely make provision for the failure to use this power, does it
merely ensure that the failure to use it will cause the least possible
damage to the social framework, forgetting that the social framework is
not the object of manâs common endeavour but merely an interpretation of
that object, an interpretation which may be wrong? Does this society
believe in freedom, or not? From the study of any past or present
society the anarchist cannot exactly learn anything new about the ideal
society which he has already conceived in accordance with his theory of
man. But he may be reminded of what it is that he believes, he may be
enabled to clarify his understanding and his knowledge: he will be
brought, not to any new conviction, but to a better understanding of
what has always been his conviction.
This sketch of the democracy of ancient Athens will be an attempt to
understand the theory of man upon which it was built and how it
developed: it will also attempt some examination of the theory of man in
terms of which that democracy was criticised by contemporaries. How well
did the Athenians learn the truth of the remark of their great lawgiver
Solon, that the best-policed city is âthe city where all citizens,
whether they have suffered injury or not, equally pursue and punish
injusticeâ?[1] How justified are the claims that Pericles made in a
famous speech at the height of Athensâ pride and splendour, at the end
of the first year of the war (the Peloponnesian War, 432â404) which put
an end to the Athenian empire? âOur constitution is called a democracy
because power is in the hands not of a minority but of the whole people.
When it is a question of settling private disputes, everyone is equal
before the law; when it is a question of putting one person before
another in positions of public responsibility, what counts is not
membership of a particular class, but the actual ability which the man
possesses. No one, so long as he has it in him to be of service to the
state, is kept in political obscurity because of poverty. And, just as
our political life is free and open, so is our day-to-day life in our
relations with each other ⊠Taking everything together, I declare that
our city is an education to Greece, and I declare that in my opinion
each single one of our citizens, in all the manifold aspects of life, is
able to show himself the rightful lord and owner of his own person, and
to do this, moreover, with exceptional grace and exceptional
versatility.â[2]
âAbout 1200 B.C. the secure prosperity of Mycenaean Greece was abruptly
terminated.â[3] The Mycenaeans had partially replaced and partially
taken over the Minoan civilisation of the Aegean: they now in their turn
succumbed to invasions from the mountains in the north: the invaders
were semi-nomadic tribesmen, among whom the most important were the
Dorians. The Dorians were ill-suited to the tedious business of the
Mycenaeansâ agriculture and industrious palace bureaucracy. They
preferred tribal assemblies over which the king was supreme, though
ruling by the consent of his soldiery. But in Greece during the age of
reconstruction from the twelfth to the eighth centuries the monarchical
organisation of society survived only in the north, in Macedonia. In the
rest of Greece the city-state (perhaps first brought over from Asia
Minor) came into being, a âsynoecismâ or âbringing together of
householdsâ not so much into a single conurbation as under a single
judicial and military authority, a form of political organisation which
represented the triumph of the interests of the lowland farmers and
traders over the highlanders. Most Hellenic city-statesâAthens was a
signal exception to the ruleâstarted life handicapped by a division of
the people into a body of first-class citizens, living in the city and
on the arable land adjoining it, and an outer circle of second-class
citizens descended from the subjugated highlanders; and this schism in
the community was a fruitful cause of subsequent social conflict.â[4]
â âDemosâ, the people, can mean the whole community, including everyone
within it whether the community is large or small. It can also mean, not
everyone, but the mass of the people in contrast to the privileged
classâit can have, that is, a party and not a national sense, an
ambiguity that has attacked the word for âpeopleâ in many languages.
This party sense appears in Solonâs poems side by side with the more
comprehensive sense, and it was probably in Solonâs lifetime, in the
early sixth century, that it began to have a party meaning.â[5] The
political situation with which Solon had to deal was one in which the
people (in the party sense of the word) were becoming politically
conscious and articulate, at least partly as a result of military and
economic developments of the seventh century.
The replacement of expensive bronze by cheap iron âbrought within the
means of the yeoman farmer an equipment that had previously been the
monopoly of a small aristocracy, and the consequent large increase in
the number of a city-stateâs heavy-armed fighting-men made it possible,
for the first time in the Hellenic World, to make the weight of metal
tell by substituting, for the chariot-borne champion, a phalanx of
peasant infantry, whose virtue lay not in individual physical prowess
but in drill and discipline and âesprit de corpsâ.â[6] The military
revolution brought into existence a vast new class of âhoplitesâ, that
is, âshield-bearersâ, whose effectiveness in battle depended upon their
formation, since the shield, borne on the soldierâs left arm, protected
only his left side and he depended for the protection of his right side
on the shield of the soldier at his right just as the soldier on his
left depended upon his shield for the protection of his right side. And
if class solidarity was encouraged, so was self-confidence: âWhen they
see each other in moments of danger, the rich man will no longer be able
to despise the poor man; the poor man will be lean and sunburnt, and
find himself fighting next to some rich man whose sheltered life and
superfluous flesh make him puff and blow and quite unable to cope. Wonât
he conclude that people like this are rich because their subjects are
cowards, and wonât he say to his fellows, when he meets them in private,
âThis lot are no good; theyâve had itâ?â[7]
The eighth century rise in population had made necessary, first ventures
in colonisation, and then commercial expansion. There emerged a class of
moderately prosperous merchants, who resented the hereditary privileges
of the aristocratic magistrates who in the previous centuries had
quietly usurped the functions of the kings. The nine annually elected
magistrates of Athens were called âarchonsâ: the council of retired
magistrates was the âAreopagusâ: it is not certain that election was
ever officially confined to the âEupatridaeâ aristocracy, but in
practice they controlled the machinery of government: and Solon, who was
elected archon in 594, broke their monopoly.
Solonâs âShaking off of Burdensâ cancelled all the debts of the entire
population: for the future, he prohibited the use of oneâs own body as
security for debt or the sale of oneself or oneâs children into slavery
(except that a father might sell a daughter detected in illegal sexual
relations). Having âset free the land from slaveryâ Solon sought a
political arrangement which would combine the virtues of aristocracy
with those of democracy. He divided the citizenry into four classes, a
citizenâs class depending upon the number of bushels of com or measures
of oil his land produced, i.e. upon his income. The wealthy commoners
were the most obvious beneficiaries of Solonâs reform: they (it is not
clear whether it was the top two classes which received this right, or
only the top one) became eligible for election to the archonship, though
this was not conceded by the old aristocracy without a struggle: in the
fifteen years which followed Solonâs archonship there were two years
which appeared in the records as âanarchiaiââthat is, no archon was
elected, or no election was recognised as valid. The third class (the
âzeugitaiâ, roughly the hoplite class) gained access to minor political
office; the fourth class (the âthetesâ, literally the labourers) were
confirmed in their right to attend and vote at the assembly. But the
character of this right was much changed by Solonâs reforms.
It seems that before 594 the assembly had met but seldom, which rather
restricted the practical effectiveness of the ordinary citizenâs right
to attend and vote. After 594 all legislation and all major questions of
policy had to be brought before the assembly, and it was freed from the
control of the Areopagus by Solonâs institution of a new lower council
of 400 members, for election to which the second and third classes, but
not the fourth, seem to have been eligible. But Solonâs âgreatest
achievementâ, says Sir Alfred Zimmern, âwas to âmake the people master
of the verdictâ ⊠(The Magistrates remained.) But in exceptional cases,
where the law was not clear or the decision hotly disputed. Solon
granted an appeal to a large popular court of several thousand
citizensâa sort of Grand Assize of the nation sitting under open heaven
by the market-place. The exact powers and composition of this body, the
Heliaea as it was called, are not known; we only become familiar with
popular justice when the Heliaea had been split up into the numerous
courts, consisting of several hundreds, instead of thousands, of judges
(the people acted as both judge and jury and there were no lawyers),
which we find in the time of Pericles. We do not know who decided what
cases should be submitted to it. But Solon enacted one provision which
made it quite certain that, in the case of friction, the people had the
whip-hand of their magistrates. He ordained that every magistrate when
he went out of office should give an account before the assembly of the
people of his conduct during its tenure.â[8]
Tyranny, when it came to Athens in the middle of the sixth century, came
in a far milder form than that experienced by other cities where the
violence of class conflict had not been assigned by the wisdom of a
Solon. âPeisistratusâ two failures to establish a tyranny and his
eventual triumph organised from abroad do not look like the career of a
social revolutionary leader.â[9] His government, writes the author of
the treatise on the Constitution of Athens (probably a pupil of
Aristotle rather than Aristotle himself), âwas moderate, and more
consonant with the character of a constitutional statesman than with
that of a tyrant. He was generally humane and mild, and ready to pardon
offenders; and, more especially, he pursued a policy of advancing money
to the poor to give them employment and to enable them to make a living
by farming. There were two reasons for this policy. The first was to
stop the poor from spending their time in the central city, and to
spread them out over the country-side; the second was to ensure (by
giving them a moderate competence and some business to engage their
attention) that they should have neither the desire nor the leisure to
concern themselves with public affairs.â[10] But the effect, according
to Professor Andrews, was rather different: the tyranny destroyed what
remained of âfeudalismâ (using the word in its conventional pejorative
sense), it made the mass of the people more independent of the upper
class and accustomed them to greater stability: âthe strife of
upper-class parties was a form of disturbance unfamiliar to most
Athenians when it broke out afresh, after the fall of the tyranny,
between Isagoras and Cleisthenes.â[11] âAnd Cleisthenesâ, writes
Herodotus, âfinding himself the weaker, called to his aid the common
people.â[12]
The democracy established by Cleisthenesâ reforms in 507 was âa regime
based on a property-qualification that had been reduced almost to
zero.â[13] The membership of the council was increased from 400 to 500,
to be chosen annually by lot, 50 from each of the ten tribes (âdemesâ)
with which Cleisthenes had replaced the older and more decentralised
tribal organisation of Athens: no citizen was to sit on the council for
two successive years or more than twice altogether. These provisions,
âthis simple deviceâ, as A. W. Gomme calls it, âprevented the growth of
anything like that corporate feeling which comes when men work side by
side for many years together, and which is so powerful a factor in the
creation of privilege.[14] It prevented also the concentration of
political experience in a small body of men, and at the same time spread
political experience among as large a number of citizens as possible;
and in this way worked both positively and negatively towards the
predominance of the assembly.â Like the archons councillors had to be
over thirty years of age, to take an oath and to submit individually to
preliminary scrutiny and final examination:
âIt may be conjectured that technically they had, like magistrates, to
be of at least zeugite (i.e. third class, vid. p. 332) status.â[15]
The council sat every day except on festivals, and it had a standing
sub-committee which dined every day in the city hall and whose task it
was to prepare the order paper (âprogrammaâ) for the council, which in
its turn prepared one for the assembly if it was to meetâas it did on
four days in every sub-committeeâs period of office: no decision might
be taken by the assembly except on a motion voted by the council, and
placed by the council on the agenda. The fifty members of each tribe on
the council served in turn for a tenth of the year as the councilâs
sub-committee, the sub-committee for each period being selected by lot
at the end of the preceding period: every day a new president of the
committee was chosen by lot from their number, and he also presided over
the assembly if it met. (In the fourth century another president of the
assembly was chosen by lot from among those councillors who were not on
the sub-committee.) It cannot be said that the Athenians did not take
their democracy seriously.
It may be that Cleisthenesâ intention was that the council should be the
effective governing body, only referring major and contentious issues to
the people. If that was his intention, it was not his achievement. The
people had come into their own, or so it would appear from Herodotusâ
description of the Atheniansâ successful repulse of an attempt by
Cleomenes king of Sparta to restore Isagoras: âAnd it is plain enough,
not from this instance only, but from many everywhere, that freedom is
an excellent thing; since even the Athenians, who, while they continued
under the rule of tyrants, were not a whit more valiant than any of
their neighbours, no sooner shook off the yoke than they became
decidedly the first of all. These things show that, while undergoing
oppression, they let themselves be beaten, since they worked for a
master; but so soon as they got their freedom, each man was eager to do
the best he could for himself.â[16]
Ephialtes (who was murdered in 461) and Pericles carried the democracy a
few stages further. In 462 or 461, at their instance, the Assembly
passed a bill which deprived the Areopagus (which had already lost much
of its importance, its members now being chosen by lot from the archons)
of all its powers except those of a supreme court for charges of murder:
its customary jurisdiction in moral and constitutional questions went,
respectively, to the popular jury-courts (vid. p. 332) and to the
council. A few years later the chief archonships were thrown open to the
âzeugitaiâ, and before long even the poorest class (the âthetesâ) were
accepted as candidates if they wished to standâwhich in fact they
usually didnât, since the office demanded by tradition expenditure in
excess of its meagre pay, and had some rather exacting duties, like the
choice of dramatists to compete at the Dionysia. Far more significant
was the introduction of the system of payment for the members of the
juries. For this too Pericles seems to have been responsible.
Pericles was born not long before the battle of Marathon (490) at which
the Athenians defeated the Persian invading force before the arrival of
their (the Atheniansâ) Spartan alliesâten years later the Athenian naval
contribution and the cunning of her general Themistocles were the
decisive factors in the destruction of Xerxesâ great invading fleet at
Salamis, though a Spartan commanded the allies on land and a Corinthian
commanded their sea forces. If this was an opportunity to achieve that
political unity they needed, the ancient Greeks missed it. But the
Athenian navy (on which, rather than upon any privateâor
publicâfrivolities, Themistocles had persuaded the assembly in 483 to
spend the large profit made by the state silver mines) became the
instrument of empire. When the Delian Leagueâfrom which Sparta and the
Peloponnesian League were always quite distinctâwas formed in 477
against the threat of any future Persian invasion, the allies of Athens
contributed men and ships to a common navy. But more and more did it
become the system that Athens built the ships[17] and provided the men
for their crews while her allies made monetary contributions; and as the
Persian threat receded the navy seemed to become the instrument of
purely Athenian interests and policies: the great cityâs allies began to
resent what had ceased to protect and reassure, what was now the sign,
not of their safety, but of their subjection.
After the reduction of the archons to election by lot in 487, the ten
annually elected generals remained the only chief officers of state
elected directly by majority vote. (In general direct election was
distrusted as an instrument of aristocratic rule: candidates would be
elected for their personality or private influence; but occasionally the
need for a certain technical skill reduced or at least modified this
danger and at the same time made election by lot impractical.)
âAnything like a continuous governmentâ, writes Professor Jones, âwas
only achieved when one man (or a coherent group of men) succeeded in
holding the confidence of the people over a long period, in which case
he (or they) was usually in the fifth century regularly re-elected
general.â But, he warns, âthe idea that the board of generals acted as
such as a government is manifestly false ⊠The generals were primarily
executive officers in the military and naval spheres, and their duties
were to mobilise armies and fleets on the instructions of the assembly,
and to command such armies and fleets with a view to achieving
objectives laid down, in more or less detail, by the people.â[18]
Pericles was elected general for the first time in 463 or thereabouts.
The period of his continual re-election began in 443, after 443 in all
the years until and including that of his death (429) only once did the
people of Athens fail to elect him general; and that once was in the
year of the plague which devastated Athens during the second year of the
Peloponnesian War (430: the plague lasted into the summer of 429 and
after a pause in 428 flared up for the last time in 427). But even
before 443 his influence upon Athenian policy is discernible: the
reforms which he and Ephialtes initiated have already been mentioned, so
has his introduction of payment for jury-service. In 453 Athens.
began to plant strategic settlements of her citizens (âcleruchiesâ) in
the territories of her allies, allowing a remission of their naval
contributions (or tribute) to those whose territories she used: in 447
the Athenian assembly decided that this money could legitimately be used
to rebuild those temples and other public buildings which had been
destroyed by the Persians in 480â79. For, says Plutarch, Pericles wanted
those who stayed at home to enjoy the benefits of empire as much as
those who were paid to serve in the navy: but not for doing nothing: and
so he instituted the greatest social welfare scheme of public works that
there has ever been, and among other things the Parthenon was built. And
all the while it was claimed that it was for the Delian League that this
was being done: for after all the Parthenon was Athenaâs temple, and
Athena was the patron-goddess of the League. But at the same time the
Leagueâs treasury was moved from Delos to Athens, and the periodical
League conferences lapsed.
In 451 Pericles had proposed to the assembly that Athenian citizenship
should be restricted to persons of citizen parentage on both sides: his
proposal was accepted: perhaps he made it only because if he did not
someone else wouldâand he would lose influence in the assembly. Six
years later an Egyptian prince sent Athens a gift of 30,000 bushels of
wheat. There were still people on the registers of the various wards who
were no longer citizens by the terms of the act of 451. The assembly
ordered a public scrutiny, there followed 19,000 cases of disputed
citizenship (a number, it has been estimated, equal to the total number
of adult âthetesâ claiming citizenship in the urban wards), and 5,000
names, it is said, were struck off the registers. âThe Athenian people
had becomeâeven the poorest of themâa privileged minority in the Empire.
The antithesis of Empire and democracy has never been more brutally and
clearly posed.â[19]
How far was Pericles responsible for Athenian policy during the years of
his generalship? Could he have influenced his fellow-citizens in the
direction of a different policy even if he had wanted to? What did
Pericles think he was doing? What did his fellow-citizens think he was
doing? What was he doing? What did he achieve? Professor Jones
emphasises Periclesâ continuous accountability to the people or at least
to the assembly[20], his absolute dependence upon their approval. âHe
had to persuade the people to vote for every measure that he wished to
have passed, and if they lost confidence in him they could, as they once
did, depose (sic) and fine him, and they could flout his advice, as
again they did in trying to parley with the Spartans in 430. Athenian
policyâ, he concludes, âwas really determined by mass meetings of the
citizens on the advice of anyone who could win the peopleâs ear. The
success of Athens is a testimony to the basic sense of the ordinary
Athenian citizen.â[21] Thucydides, who had the advantages of being a
contemporary, argues somewhat differently. âPericles, because of his
position, his intelligence, and his known integrity, could respect the
liberty of the people and at the same time hold them in check. It was he
who led them, rather than they who led him, and, since he never sought
power from any wrong motive, he was under no necessity of flattering
them; in fact he was so highly respected that he was able to speak
angrily to them and to contradict them. Certainly when he saw that they
were going too far in a mood of over-confidence, he would bring back to
them a sense of their dangers; and when they were discouraged for no
good reason he would restore their confidence. So, in what was nominally
a democracy, power was really in the hands of the first citizen. But his
successors, who were more on a level with each other and each of whom
aimed at occupying the first place, adopted methods of demagogy which
resulted in their losing control over the actual conduct of affairs.
Such a policy, in a great city with an empire to govern, naturally led
to a number of mistakes.â[22]
But another contemporary or near-contemporary judgment was that the
mistakes of Periclesâ successors were but the natural and inevitable
consequence of a completely wrong course taken by Pericles and the other
great Athenian statesmen of the fifth century. âThey have glutted the
state with harbours and dockyards and walls and tribute and rubbish of
that sort, regardless of the requirements of moderation and
righteousness, and when the inevitable fit of weakness supervenes the
citizens will hold their current advisers responsible, and go on
extolling Themistocles and Cimon and Pericles, the real authors of their
woes.â[23]
The counterfeit of the real art of government is pandering: âpanderingâ,
Socrates explains to Gorgias, âpays no regard to the welfare of its
object, but catches fools with the bait of ephemeral pleasure and tricks
them into holding it in the highest esteem.â All the great Athenian
statesmen have failed, they have not even tried to succeed, in the real
art of government, the only object of which is to make men better, that
is, to purify their desires and appetites by detaching them from all
merely corporeal and transient images and fixing them upon the ultimate
and unchanging reality of which these images are but the shadows.
Callicles protests that âone of the men of todayâ (the dramatic date of
the dialogue seems to be, accepting some large anachronisms, about 405;
the year before the end of the Peloponnesian War) can compare with
Themistocles, Miltiades (the general who commanded the Athenians at
Marathon), Cimon, or Pericles; and Socrates agrees that âthey seem to
have been better servants of the state than the present people, and more
able to provide the state with what it desired. But when it is a matter
of diverting menâs desires into a new channel instead of allowing them
free course, or of driving oneâs fellows by persuasion or constraint to
the adoption of measures designed for their improvement, which is the
sole duty of a good citizen, there is practically nothing to choose
between your men and their successors.â[24]
The âGorgiasâ is the earliest of Platoâs political dialogues; and, in
its contrasting of the true art of government with what merely imitates
it, it outlined what was to be the theme of all the later political
dialogues. âBorn in 427, nearly two years after Pericles died, Plato
knew only the growing disillusionment with the glories of Periclean
democracy.â[25] At first he hoped for a regeneration of public life
after the coup dâetat of the Thirty Tyrants in 404, but the violence of
their government showed him that this was not to be. The democracy was
restored in 403 and Plato was impressed by the moderation and clemency
of the returning party; but in 399 Socrates was executed, for what at
another time and in another place would have been called crimes against
the state. âThe result was that I, who had at first been full of
eagerness for a public career, as I gazed upon the whirlpool of public
life and saw the incessant movement of shifting currents, at last felt
dizzy ⊠and finally saw clearly in regard to all states now existing
that without exception their system of government is bad.â[26] Plato
decided that what was needed was a re-examination of first principles:
an inquiry into the function and purpose of government which would show
in what way contemporary constitutions were defective instruments of
government and how they might be remedied. He founded the Academy
(c.388) to promote this inquiry in the minds of others, and as the
inquiry proceeded he saw more and more clearly and convincingly the
nature of manâs common end and the necessity for educating him in order
that he may achieve it.
Platoâs objection to democracy was much more directly to an attitude of
mind than to a form of political organisation which he assumed to be so
bound up with it as to be almost identical: the form of political
organisation being either the effect of the attitude of mind or the
social evidence of its individual existence. This attitude of mind was
one of not understanding and of not caring to understand the nature of
government: above all, one of not knowing the need for education and the
need for a teacher. In âThe Republicâ democracy appears as the natural
consequence of the breakdown of an aristocratic society in which the
rulers have turned aside from the common good and pursue merely their
own private interest. âOligarchy changes into democracy because of its
lack of restraint in the pursuit of its objective of getting as rich as
possible ⊠This failure to curb extravagance in an oligarchy often
reduces to poverty men born for better things. Some of them are in debt,
some disfranchised, some both, and they settle down, armed with their
stings, and with hatred in their hearts, to plot against those who have
deprived them of their property and against the rest of society, and to
long for revolution ⊠Democracy originates when the poor win, kill or
exile their opponents, and give the rest equal rights and opportunities
of office, appointment to office being as a rule by lot ⊠In democracy
thereâs no compulsion either to exercise authority if you are capable of
it, or to submit to authority if you donât want to ⊠We said that no one
who had not exceptional gifts could grow into a good man unless he were
brought up from childhood in a good environment and given a good
training; democracy with a grandiose gesture sweeps all this away and
doesnât mind what the habits and background of its politicians are,
provided they profess themselves the peopleâs friends. Itâs an
agreeable, anarchic form of society, with plenty of variety, which
treats all men as equal, whether they are equal or not.â[27] All this
adumbrates the famous comparison of the democratic society with the ship
whose captain has been locked up in his cabin: the wine-casks have been
broached, everything is going merrily and joyfully, but those who can
see, see only disaster ahead.
âPoliticusâ (The Statesman), written between âThe Republicâ and âThe
Lawsâ, clarifies the distinction between true government and its
imitation. Rule of the one may be in accordance with the laws
(monarchy), or in defiance of them (tyranny): and similarly the rule of
the few (aristocracy or oligarchy), and the rule of the many (called
democracy in both cases). But true government is characterised, not by
any constitutional form, but by the knowledge and understanding of those
who rule: the constitutional form of the rule of those who possess âthe
art of government is unimportant.â It makes no difference whether their
subjects be willing or unwilling; they may rule with or without a code
of laws, they may be poor or wealthy. It is the same with doctors. We do
not assess the medical qualifications of a doctor by the degree of
willingness on our part to submit to his knife or cautery or other
painful treatment. Doctors are still doctors whether they work to fixed
prescriptions or without them and whether they be poor or wealthy ⊠The
one essential condition is that they act for the good of our bodies to
make them better instead of worse, and treat menâs ailments in every
case as healers acting to preserve life. We must insist that in this
disinterested scientific ability we see the distinguishing mark of true
authority in medicineâand of true authority everywhere else as well.â
Such authority will be productive of a juster social order than will a
system of written law, for âlaw can never issue an injunction binding on
all which really embodies what is best for each: it cannot prescribe
with perfect accuracy what is good and right for each member of the
community at any one time.â But where true authority is lacking, the
authority of written law is necessary to ensure the very survival of the
state: above all there is then one rule to which there must be strict
adherence. What rule is that? âThe rule that none of the citizens may
venture to do any act contrary to the laws, and that if any of them
ventures to do such act, the penalty is to be death or the utmost rigour
of punishment.â[28]
Professor G. H. Sabine claims that âThe Lawsâ (Platoâs last political
dialogue, on which he was still working when he died) âwas written in an
attempt to restore law to the place which it occupied in the moral
estimation of the Greeks and from which Plato had tried to remove
it.âBut, if this is so, then the dialogue âclosesâ, in Sabineâs words,
âon a note which is entirely out of keeping with the purpose which Plato
has been following and with the state which he has sketched in
accordance with that purpose.â[29] What happens is that Platoâs attempt
to describe âthe second-best stateâ in which the authority of written
law rather than of the ruler is supreme, breaks down before his own
realisation that it is useless to devise laws and institutions for a
society unless there are persons in it capable of understanding the
principle behind these laws and thus above the law in the sense that
they are its guardians rather than it their guardian. It is for this
reason that âThe Lawsâ concludes with a description of the âNocturnal
Councilâ, a council of elders who will see that the laws are properly
obeyed. âIn order that the map of the state may be complete, it must
provide for the presence of some body which understands, in the first
place, the true nature of the mark a statesman must keep before his
eyes, and next, the methods by which it may be attained, and the
counselsâemanating principally from the laws themselves, secondarily
from individual menâwhich make for or against it.â[30]
But if all government requires that there should be some knowledge of
its purpose possessed by those who govern, it is also necessary that
those who obey should have some sort of knowledge. The need for
education, and the kind of education necessary, is made clear by what
Socrates says in the âGorgiasâ: âWe can win happiness only by bending
all our own efforts and those of the state to the realisation of
uprightness and self-discipline, not by allowing our appetites to go
unchecked, and, in an attempt to satisfy their endless importunity,
living the life of a brigand.â[31] âOf all the great offices of state
this is the greatestâ, says Plato in âThe Lawsâ: he is speaking of the
director of education. â⊠Education is the drawing and leading of
children to the rule which has been pronounced right by the voice of the
law, and approved as truly right by the concordant experience of the
best and oldest men. That the childâs soul, then, may not learn the
habit of feeling pleasure and pain in ways contrary to the law and those
who have listened to its bidding, but keep them company, taking pleasure
and pain in the very same things as the agedâthat, I hold, proves to be
the real purpose of what we call our âsongsâ.â[32]
Aristotle (born in 385 or 384) agreed with his master Plato that the aim
of government is the control of the emotions in order that happiness
might be sought, not in transient and inconstant pleasures, but in those
which endure and are not subject to fortune. But while both believed in
the education of the individual so that his emotions might be controlled
by his reason, at the same time the political theory of the one no less
than that of the other seems to assume that there are and always will be
some people who will need to have their emotions controlled by others. A
basis of this assumption is the theory of the ânatural slaveâ as worked
out by Aristotle: âA man is by nature a slave if he is capable of
becoming the property of another, and if he participates in reason to
the extent of apprehending it in another, though destitute of it
himself.â[33]
Are there any ânatural slavesâ? asks Professor Charles OâNeil, and
answers his own question: âit is simply dishonest not to answer: yes,
there are. There simply are some men who are unable âon their ownâ to
contribute to the common good life, the common life of common political
virtue.â The principle of the political life, of the life of men living
in common, is justice, the idea that each man should have his share of
what society produces and possesses. And thus the knowledge which is
necessary to the government of a societyâthe knowledge of which
government should be merely the applicationâis the knowledge of what is
due to a man: as Professor OâNeil says, âin its innermost and most
exquisite expression, in its being, an Aristotelian âpolisâ is a knowing
of the right human thing to be done.â[34] But there are some men (this
seems to be the Platonic as well as the Aristotelian argument) who will
know what is good for a man, what is his due, better than he will know
that himself. And this is the explanation of the inadequacy, so
Aristotle says, of the democratic principle of equality. âDemocracy
arose in the strength of an opinion that those who were equal in any one
respect were equal absolutely, and in all respects ⊠Democrats seek to
widen the principle of equality until it is made to include all the
masses. What is certainly justâand expedient as well as justâis that the
principle should extend to all who are really âpeersâ.â[35] The
principle of equality which underlies the concept of justice, explains
Aristotle in the fifth book of âThe Nicomachean Ethicsâ, does not
require that every man should get an equal share in everything, but that
all should receive equally what they need of each thing[36]; similarly,
one might add, cosmic justice requires, not that everyone should possess
an equal amount of knowledge, but that each man equally should possess
that knowledge which is required by his social position: âThe soul has
naturally two elements, a ruling and a ruled; and each has its different
goodness, one belonging to the rational and ruling element, and the
other to the irrational and ruled ⊠(Similarly, the different elements
of society must share in the possession of moral goodness, possessing it
not in the same way, but each in the way appropriate to the discharge of
its separate function.) The ruler must possess moral goodness in its
full and perfect form, because his function demands a master-artificer,
and reason is such a master-artificer; but all other persons need only
possess moral goodness to the extent required of them ⊠(Slaves) need
but little goodness; only so much, in fact, as will prevent them from
falling short of their duties through intemperance or cowardice.â[37]
The nature of political knowledge is also debated in the âProtagorasâ.
Socrates asks why it is that the Athenian Assembly will listen only to
the advice of experts when the debate concerns for instance
shipbuilding, but when the debate is about questions of public policy
will listen to anyone. Protagoras replies by means of a myth. All
animals have been given some particular abilityâstrength, speed, or some
other means of self-preservation; but man has been given a general
ability to use all things and, since this alone was not enough to ensure
his survival, he was also given the ability to live together with his
fellows in cities for their mutual protection. âZeus sent Hermes to
impart to men the qualities of respect for others and a sense of
justice, so as to bring order into our cities and create a bond of
friendship and union. Hermes asked Zeus in what manner he was to bestow
these gifts on men. âShall I distribute them as the arts were
distributedâthat is, on the principle that one trained doctor suffices
for many laymen, and so with the other experts? Shall I distribute
justice and respect for their fellows in this way, or to all alike?â âTo
allâ said Zeus. âLet all have their share. There could never be cities
if only a few shared in these virtues, as in the arts. Moreover, you
must lay it down as my law that if anyone is incapable of acquiring his
share of these two virtues he shall be put to death as a plague to the
city.â â And so the Athenians listen to experts when the question before
the Assembly concerns building or some other craft. âBut when the
subject of their counsel involves political wisdom, which must always
follow the path of justice and moderation, they listen to every manâs
opinion, for they think that everyone must share in this kind of virtue;
otherwise the state could not exist.â[38]
Perhaps neither the criticisms of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle nor its
vindication by Protagoras fully appreciate the principle of democracy.
All of them understand that the guiding idea of democracy is the idea of
equality, but none of them examines the full implications of the idea,
though Aristotleâs analysis of justice provides a clue and a
starting-point. Justice is the arranging in society that every man shall
have his share of what that society has: justice provides that every man
shall have, not an equal amount of everything, but equally whatever he
needs. In order that the work of justiceâdistribution and
redistributionâmay be done, above all else knowledge is necessary:
knowledge of what justice requires. Aristotle and Plato think that this
knowledge will be possessed by a small class: Aristotle seems to think
that it would be better if the circle of knowledge could be extended as
far as possible, though he is somewhat vague and self-contradictory on
this point[39]; but Plato is certain that this knowledge is attainable
only by a few[40]. Protagoras claims that all citizens must possess
political skill if the city is to survive; but he speaks only of what is
socially convenient and not of what is absolutely desirable and possible
for all menâindeed the political skill of which he speaks seems to be
something accidental rather than essential to manâand Plato is
unconvinced.
But is the Platonic-Aristotelian idea of a ruling class ruling by virtue
of its superior insight in fact compatible with that justice in which
they themselves believe? The fact that justice deals in the material
world with the distribution of things should not mislead the observer
into thinking that it is concerned with nothing more: the real object of
justiceâthe end to which the distribution of material things is but a
meansâis the creation of a psychological state, is to give the
individual a feeling of true contentment, to show him that he is well
treated and accepted by the other individuals who make up the society in
which he lives. This is why justice must not only be done, but be seen
to be done: if it is not seen, it has not achieved the object of
justice. And that is why the sort of knowledge Plato and Aristotle
describe is not enough, if justice is to be effectively realised in the
world of human relationships and not to remain but an ideal with the
awareness of which a few may be happy: it is not enough that one or a
few men should know and do justiceâthere is not an extent appropriate to
his social function, but know and do justice equally. If justice is a
realisable social ideal, then every individual equally must have
somewhere, somehow the power of knowing and doing justice to his
fellows, and of recognising it when he himself receives it: the
realisation of this power will be the realisation of justice.
If this is what justice is, then that slavery which Athens no less than
the rest of Greece accepted and which Aristotle sought to justify cannot
be just. Indeed, Aristotleâs rationalising interpretation will be turned
on its head: while he sought to justify and explain a social and
economic situation (i.e. the use of one man by another as a tool) in
terms of a psychological condition (i.e. the inability of an individual
to do good except by allowing himself to be the instrument of another
manâs reason), the democrat will follow Marx and will denounce this same
socio-economic situation (now described as one of âalienated labourâ)
as, if not the sole cause of this psychological condition (in which the
individual does not make political and moral decisions for himself, but
allows his relations with his fellows to be determined by others), at
least dependent upon it for its existence and thus encouraging its
continuance. Slavery is, then, not a condition which is potentially
justâAristotle admits that not all legal slaves are natural slaves; and
vice versaâbut rather one which proclaims the non-realisation of
justice: both in those who are slaves, and in those who use them.
The importance of slavery in ancient Greece has been much debated: it
has been pointed out that to discuss whether Greek civilisation was
âbased onâ slavery is usually to become bogged down in unprofitable
arguments concerning just what âto be basicâ means.[41] Professor Jones
write: âIt is unlikely that any slaves were owned by two-thirds to
three-quarters of the citizen population (of Athens). The great majority
of the citizens earned their living by the work of their hands, as
peasant farmers, craftsmen, shopkeepers, seamen and labourers.â[42] But
it cannot be denied that the Athenian democracy used slavery; and it was
silver-mines worked by slavesââspeaking generally, mining was the
gravest blot on Hellenismâ[43]âthat provided the capital which brought
the Athenian imperial navy into being.
The Athenian democracy of the fifth century B.C. certainly brought to a
high pitch of development the participation of the individual citizen in
the political activity of his city: on this all contemporary witnesses,
whether hostile or favourable, agree with Pericles: the contrast between
the cityâs splendid public buildings and the miserable private dwellings
shows, says Sir Alfred Zimmem, that the fifth-century Athenian âknew
very well that a man who practises politics and ignores housekeeping,
though he may possibly starve, at least remains sane and
companionable.â[44] Slavery is one sign that Athens did not fully
understand the democracy it professed. Its acceptance of war is another.
Wars arise, says Socrates, from the desire for material things: âAll
wars are undertaken for the acquisition of wealth; and the reason why we
have to acquire wealth is the body, because we are slaves in its
service.â[45] And even if we seek merely to defend ourselves against the
unjust demands of an aggressor, it may be possible to do this only at
the expense of ceasing to be able to defend ourselves against, what is
far worse and more harmful than suffering injustice, doing
injustice.[46] The first requirement of justice is not that a man should
receive his share of those material things which are as it were the
instruments of justice (of pp.23â4), but that there should be a
willingness on the part of his fellows to give him that which is his
due. Thus, the most and indeed the only effective way in which a man can
defend himself against suffering injustice is not, as even Socrates
thought, by the use of power, but by the building up of the spirit of
justice in his fellows.
Neither the policy of the Athenian democracy nor the
Socratic-Platonic-Aristotelian criticism of it fully realised the
universal nature of the democratic principle of equality. But an
understanding of the Athenian experienceâof the slow, groping,
incoherent and never altogether complete evolution of an idea of
citizenship, together with an appreciation of the criticisms of the
great Athenian philosophers[47] (and it is important to remember that
these criticisms were in terms of an idea of citizenship fostered to a
great extent by the political development of Athens): may nonetheless
help us to understand the nature of this equality. We may accept the
philosophersâ contention that the art of government depends upon
education, that in a sense government is education, and even (some of us
at least) that education is the training of the individualâs libidinal
capacity so that he seeks after the true happiness and not after
ephemeral pleasures. But the anarchist will want to modifyâperhaps he
will claim, to clarifyâthe original picture of the ideal.
It is strange that Plato with his strong sense of the common nature and
destiny of manââthere is none so worthless whom love cannot impel, as it
were by a divine inspiration, towards virtueâ[48]âshould nonetheless
have made so sharp a distinction between those who govern and those who
obey: the explanation lies perhaps in a misconceived psychological
analogyâPlato compared the rule which rational men ought to exert over
irrational men to the rule which the rational part of the soul ought to
exert over the irrational part.[49] But the anarchist ideal of the
universal rule of reason and justice is of a rule whose instruments are
notâcannot beâthe understanding of a few or even of a majority: the idea
of justice is that all shall be saved. And the object of education is
the awakening or the bringing back to life of the power of understanding
in every man: education is education in the use of freedom, in the use
of the power of every individual man to rise above the fleeting and
insatiable pleasures of material things to the contemplation of the
divine harmony of which the spirit of justice is the earthly sign or
symbol. Justice is the achievement of freedom: where there is
understanding of freedom, there is justice, and where freedom is
obscure, unrealised, there can be no justice. And even while the
universal power of freedom remains slighted and unfulfilled, every just
man and every just act is a testimony that it is universal.
[1] Quoted by A. E. Zimmern. The Greek Commonwealth (O.U.P. 1911, 5^(th)
ed. 1931, paperback 1961), p. 133. (All my references are to the 2^(nd)
edition.)
[2] Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War (Penguin Classics
translation by Rex Warner, 1954), pp. 117 119.
[3]
G. L. Huxley, Early Sparta (Faber & Faber 1962), p. 14.
[4] Arnold J. Toynbee, Hellenism. The history of a civilisation (Home
University Library: O.U.P. 1959), p. 37.
[5]
A. Andrewes, The Greek Tyrants (Hutchinsonâs University Library, 1956),
pp. 35â6.
[6] Toynbee, op. cit., p. 64.
[7] Plato, The Republic, 556 (Penguin Classics translation by H. D. P.
Lee, 1955, pp. 328â9).
[8] Zirmmern, op. cit., pp. 134â5.
[9] Andrewes, op. cit., p. 104.
[10] Ernest Barker, The Politics of Aristotle, translated and with an
introduction (0.U.P. 1946); appendix: On the Constitution of Athens, p.
377.
[11] Andrewes, p. 114.
[12] The History of Herodotus, Book 5 chapter 66 (translated by Georg
Rawlinson, Everymanâs Library 1910, volume, p. 29).
[13] Toynbee, p. 72.
[14]
A. W. Gomme, More Essays in Greek History and Literature (Oxford:
Blackwell 1962), pp. 184â5.
[15]
A. H. M. Jones, Athenian Democracy (Oxford: Blackwell 1957). p. 105.
(The indispensable modern work on the subject.)
[16] op. cit., Book 5 chapter 78 (op. cit. volume 2, p. 35).
[17] These ships were galleys and they were rowed by Athenian citizensâa
task which was the occupation of slaves and criminals in other
civilisations.
[18] Jones, op. cit., pp. 126, 125, 124.
[19]
A. R. Burn, Pericles and Athens (London: English Universities Press
1948), p. 91.
[20] On a good day 6,000 might attend out of a citizen populationâi.e.
excluding women, slaves, children and foreignersâwhich has been
estimated to have been about 30,000 in the last quarter of the fifth
century.[50]
[21] Jones. pp. 127, 132.
[22] op. cit. (Penguin Classics tr., pp. 13 5).
[23] Plato. Gorgias, 519a (Penguin Classics translation by W. Hamilton
1960, p. 135).
[24] ibid., 464, 517 (pp. 46, 133).
[25]
J. B. Skemp, introduction to translation of Plato: The Statesman
(Politicus) (Routledge 1952, Routledge paperback 1961), p. 26.
[26] Letter 7, 325d, quoted by G. H. Sabine, A History of Political
Theory (Harrap 1937, 3^(rd) ed. 1951), p. 45.
[27] 555, 557, 558 (pp. 327, 328, 329â30).
[28] tr. Skemp, op. cit., pp. 194â5, 196, 203 (293a-b, 294b, 297e).
[29] Sabine, op. cit., pp. 71, 84.
[30] The Laws (translated by A. E. Taylor, Dent 1934), p. 357.
[31] 507 (p. 117).
[32] The Laws, Book 2: 659 (op. cit., p. 37).
[33] The Politics, Book 1 chapter 5: ¶9 (tr. Barker, p. 13).
[34]
C. J. OâNeil, Aristotleâs Natural Slave Reconsidered (The New
Scholasticism, July 1953, pp. 259, 278).
[35] The Politics, Book 5 chapter 1: ¶3; Book 5, chapter 8: ¶6 (pp. 204,
225).
[36] vid. in particular chapters 3 and 5 (Penguin Classics translation
by J. A. K. Thompson 1955, pp. 146â7, 151â4).
[37] The Politics, Book 1 chapter 13: ¶¶6 8, 12 (pp. 35â6).
[38] Protagoras, 322c-d (Penguin Classics translation by W. K. C.
Guthrie 1956, p. 54).
[39] The Politics, 6.2 ¶l, 7.14 ¶¶2â3 19, 2.11 ¶14, 3.1 ¶12 (pp. 258,
315, 319, 86, 95); of 5.8 ¶¶17â18, 6.4 ¶¶l-4. (pp. 228, 263).
[40] The Statesman 293a (tr. Skemp, p. 194).
[41]
M. I. Finley, Was Greek Civilisation Based on Slavery? (Historia 8,
1959, p. 161): reprinted in M. I. Finley (ed.), Slavery in
Classical Antiquity (Cambridge: Heffer 1960). (This collection
of essays contains a very interesting on by R. O. Schlaifer on
âGreek Theories of Slavery from Homer to Aristotleâ.)
[42] Jones, p. 17.
[43] Sir William Tarn, Hellenistic Civilisation (Edward Arnold 1927,
3^(rd) ed. 1952), p. 254: he gives some details.
[44] op. cit., p. 212 (cf. pp. 213â4, 293â4, 296).
[45] Phaedo, 66 (The Last Days of Socrates: Penguin Classics translation
by Hugh Tredennick 1954, p. 111).
[46] vid. Gorgias, 509â513, 522 (pp. 119- 25, 141â2).
[47] Both Socrates and Plato were Athenian citizens who lived and died
in Athens Socratesâ service in the Athenian army and Platoâs expeditions
to Sicily were the only time they spent away from their native city);
Aristotle neither was born or died in Athens, but spent there twenty
years in Platoâs Academy 367â347) and another thermo (335â323) in his
own.
[48] Symposium 179a 7â8 (also in Penguin Classics translation).
[49] vid. The Laws, Book 3: 689 (p. 70).