💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › james-herod-majority-rule.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:19:33. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Majority Rule
Author: James Herod
Date: January 2001
Language: en
Topics: democracy

James Herod

Majority Rule

Majority rule is just a voting procedure for resolving disagreements

within a deliberative assembly. Sometimes it might be combined with

other rules, like those requiring unanimous or two-thirds votes on

certain issues. But what voting procedures were used to select the

voting procedures? That is, what rule was used for the vote to select

majority rule? - majority rule, unanimity, two-thirds, or what? And how

was that decision made? We are clearly in an infinite regress here.

In reality, the establishment, for any assembly, of the original

procedures for voting usually happens by fiat or by revolution (given

the rarity of unanimity). Thus democracy can usually only be established

in-between regimes. In the case of the US constitution for example, the

fifty-five members of the constitutional convention decided that the

constitution would be considered adopted if nine out of the thirteen

colonies approved it, with the constitution simply being imposed by

force on the remaining four colonies. (As it happened, only two colonies

refused ratification at the time, North Carolina and Rhode Island, both

of which had ratified by 1789, and 1790 respectively.) In the case of

international treaties, the writers of the treaty usually include rules

for adoption in the treaty itself, stipulating how many countries need

to ratify the treaty before it comes into force. This works of course

only if the treaty contains enforcement powers, so that the terms of the

treaty can be imposed by force on nations who don't ratify it. In the

absence of enforcement powers, a nation can simply ignore the treaty.

National parliaments do have enforcement powers of course. A

nation-state is by definition a monopolizer of violence, so-called

legitimate violence (that is, the parliament defines its own violence as

legitimate and everyone else's as illegitimate). National governments

have armed forces, intelligence agencies, police, and secret police at

their disposal to enforce the will of the parliamentary majority on the

minority in the parliament and on everyone else in the nation. Any other

police or armed forces within the nation are declared illegal. In the

setting of the nation-state system, minorities who refuse to go along

with majority decisions have only one recourse (other than simply

disobeying and facing fines and prison) - civil war. They can attempt to

secede from the nation (from the decision-making unit), and establish a

nation of their own, with its own parliament (a separate decision making

unit).

The situation is somewhat different for sub-national organizations like

corporations and voluntary associations. Unless the decisions of these

groups can be linked to national laws, and thus be enforced by the

national government (and many decisions of capitalist corporations are),

they cannot be imposed by force, since the organizations have no

policemen to arrest and imprison those who disobey. About all they can

do is expel the disobedient from the organization, revoking their

membership. Members of an organization who come to disagree too severely

with the policies of that organization (however established, either

through majority rule or management), simply leave the organization, as

a rule. A minority can also attempt to expel the majority of course, and

this happens all the time (as in a takeover). Associations are rather

often taken over by minorities within them which contrive in one way or

another to force the majority out of the project. There are also the

numerous cases of splits within an association, wherein a minority

leaves in mass and establishes another organization. The history of

political parties, especially on the left, is replete with such splits.

The principle of majority rule can itself sometimes lead to a split.

Let's say that a small group of people get together and establish an

association in order to accomplish certain goals. They are all agreed

upon these goals (tasks, objectives), and they also agree to govern

their association by direct democracy, using majority rule to resolve

disagreements. The founders therefore are very clear about what they

want to do. But new members of course are needed, in order for the

project to grow and accomplish its objectives. So new members are

recruited, all of whom have to agree to the original objectives and

established voting procedures as a condition of being admitted as

members. Nevertheless, the recruitment and admission process is rather

different than the deep commitment to certain goals that brought the

original founders together, and over time, a majority can slowly emerge

in the project which wants to take the project in a different direction

than the one originally intended by the founders. Founders can thus find

themselves in a situation, through the principle of majority rule, of

losing their project, and all the years of effort that went into

building it. They are faced with the dilemma of either leaving this

project (the one they originally founded) and starting all over again in

a new one, or of leaving and abandoning their goals altogether, or of

staying in and working toward goals that they didn't originally endorse.

It is because of the possibility of this happening that founders of

projects sometimes eject majority rule and choose instead some kind of

elite rule, whereby the original founders of a project can keep control

of it. This is actually the predominant organizational form in our

society, in corporations and in all hierarchically organized

associations. These organizations recruit people to work on the project,

wage-earners for corporations and members for voluntary associations

(because almost all human projects require more than one or a few

persons in order to be accomplished), but control of the organization

remains in the hands of a few. In the case of corporations, majority

rule (workers control or democracy at the workplace) is obviously

anathema to capitalists because it would destroy their objective of

making profit. Even if the worker-controlled enterprise stayed in the

market and continued to make profit (rather than switch to cooperative

labor and leave the market), the profit would not go to the original

owners, but would be appropriated by all the employees. This is why

capitalists fight the movement for workplace democracy tooth and nail.

It's a life and death struggle for them.

In non-capitalist organizations, elite control may enable the founders

to keep the organization on course for quite some time, but ultimately,

it is no guarantee. Why? Because disagreements can emerge among the

original founders, as new situations and new issues arise, over what

direction the organization should take in light of these new

circumstances. So the belief that elite control of an association is a

solution to the problem of splits is ultimately an illusion. Before

long, we always end up right back at majority/minority dynamics

regarding the goals and procedures of the project.

The same process will be at work in our neighborhood assemblies. Assume

for example that at the very first meeting of a neighborhood assembly a

proposal is made for a certain set of voting procedures, and that this

proposal wins unanimous support. Every member of the assembly agrees to

resolve disagreements in this certain way and to abide by decisions made

like that. What happens then if a new member moves into the neighborhood

or a child reaches maturity and starts participating in the

deliberations of the assembly? Are the voting procedures going to be

voted on anew every time a new member comes into the assembly? Surely

not. New members will have to accept the procedures that already exist.

The assembly may decide to change them periodically, but that is a

different matter. Thus the unanimity has disappeared because new members

did not explicitly agree to abide by the procedures (although I suppose

acceptance of the procedures could be made a condition for membership).

But what if the procedures were voted on anew with the addition of every

new member? Wouldn't the unanimity eventually break down anyway? Surely

so. It's easy to see then that even if an assembly starts out unanimous,

as regards voting procedures, it is unlikely to remain that way, because

sooner or later a person will come along who will disagree (or some

original member will change their mind), and thus break the unanimity.

Original unanimity is therefore no solution to the problem of splits and

disagreement. There is no escaping disagreement, and the

minority/majority dynamics these disagreements create.

As an aside: What if a majority emerges in an assembly that doesn't like

democracy any longer, doesn't think direct democracy works very well,

doesn't like majority rule? Instead, this majority wants to elect

leaders and turn over decision making to them (or even worse, wants to

simply accept leaders without even electing them). Can a majority in

such an assembly use majority rule to abolish majority rule? Obviously

not. This would be totally contradictory, and would represent in fact a

coup, a counter-revolution, if they were able to get away with it. A

majority which favors tyranny cannot use majority rule to justify its

preference. But what if a majority in an assembly did so vote? What

then? The minority that wants to keep democracy would have to revolt,

reject the majority decision, and struggle to defeat the anti-democratic

majority.

This shows us that even if there is unanimity to begin with about

accepting majority rule as a way to resolve disagreements, this

unanimity can break down. Actually, it can break down around almost any

intensely felt opposition to a majority decision, and not just when the

majority decides to abolish majority rule. This example shows us also

that democracy, if we ever get it, will involve us in an unending

struggle to keep it, although that struggle may lessen in intensity as

we gain decades and hopefully centuries of experience with it, and

democratic values permeate deeper and deeper into our cultures and

personalities.

Let's throw another ingredient into the mix. Let's assume that our

neighborhood assembly does not have police at its disposal, so that the

majority cannot impose its will on the minority by force.

A digression: We might want to remind ourselves that the earth was

covered for tens of thousands of years with hunting and gathering tribes

of human beings, and they had no police forces. Also, for the past

several thousand years, the vast majority of humans have lived in

peasant villages, and societies comprised mostly of peasant villages,

and there were no police forces there either. The empires that were

sometimes superimposed on these peasant societies had police, tax

collectors, and soldiers whose reach extended, usually quite

superficially, down into peasant villages, but the villages themselves

were free of police, and they managed just fine.

The situation started to change rather drastically with the emergence of

capitalism in Europe nearly five hundred years ago. Capitalists required

governments which could monopolize violence through armed force, in

order to defend and enforce capitalist imperatives. So police power, and

violence, extended deeper and deeper into the society. Peasant villages

were slowly destroyed in Europe over the past several centuries. They

were nevertheless still quite prominent even as late as the second world

war, and it has only been since then that this destruction has been

carried, on a large scale, to the rest of the world, with peasant

societies disappearing almost everywhere. The last half century has seen

the final rout of the peasant world in most of Europe, with the process

well along elsewhere.

The European settler governments that formed the United States are a

somewhat different case, in that they rapidly destroyed whatever

hunting-gathering tribes and peasant villages that were already here,

while the settler society itself never had autonomous peasant villages.

This society has been capitalist from day one. US citizens then have

been living so long in a social order founded on violence that it's hard

for them to believe that there could ever be life without it. They have

never known anything else, and have no memories of a peasant society

before capitalism.

I sketched the above history just to remind us that police forces are

not an inherent, inevitable, universal feature of human life. We lived

without them once, and we can do so again. But just try to convince

someone living in the United States, for example, that we could arrange

our social life in such a way that we wouldn't need police, and see how

far you get.

To return now to the issue I had raised right before this digression: if

neighborhoods do not have police forces to impose the will of the

majority on the minority, what bearing does this have on the relations

between the majority and the minority within our assemblies?

In the absence of an armed police force to impose majority decisions

through arrest, fines, and imprisonment, we will certainly want to be

careful though to avoid the following peculiar situation: It could come

to be thought that members of an assembly who disagree with a decision

of the assembly don't have to abide by it. In other words, the decision

of the majority is not thought to be binding on the minority. Wouldn't

this embody perfectly the principle of 'self-assumed political

obligation'? - each individual will only obey those decisions which they

have personally agreed to.

But then why have an assembly at all? Why go through all the trouble and

expense of building meeting halls, gathering together, debating the

issues, and voting, if the people who vote against a proposal can ignore

it? At the core of 'self-assumed political obligation' therefore must

lie a commitment to procedures for resolving disagreements. Without this

commitment to these procedures, and the commitment to abide by decisions

that are made following these procedures, democracy is impossible. All

you have is a hall full of fanatic individualists who waste their time

discussing and voting, only to do just what they each wanted to do

anyway. There are plenty of such fanatic individualists already around,

persons who would never commit in advance to a procedure for reaching

cooperative policies, believing as they do in the absolute sovereignty

of the individual, wherein they do only what they want when they want.

Such persons are as great a threat to democracy, perhaps even a greater

threat given contemporary culture, than tyrants.

We have already seen however that a commitment to abide by a procedure

for resolving disagreements, say majority rule, can breakdown too, in

extreme cases. Certainly, if a majority decides to murder a circle of

members of the assembly, those targeted for execution are not going to

stick by their previous commitment to majority rule. It will break down

too if a majority decides to abolish democracy in favor of tyranny. In

fact, it can break down on almost any extreme rejection of a majority

decision by the minority.

In deliberative assemblies therefore, which are based on free

association and voluntary compliance rather than compulsion and

violence, what it really boils down to is that on every issue the

minority must decide whether or not to go along with the majority, even

though they may disagree. On routine matters, the decision to go along

might be assumed to be routine too. But in cases of severe disagreement,

whether or not to abide immediately comes to the fore.

There is another peculiar situation that we must avoid (which is really

the same situation, but from another angle): It could come to be thought

that the assembly must reach 'consensus' on every issue. The only

practical meaning of consensus (although this is rarely admitted by its

proponents) is unanimity. The belief that every last person in an

assembly must agree to a proposal before the assembly can act is surely

one of the most destructive and misguided beliefs to have emerged in the

opposition movements in the past few decades. What this belief often

ends up doing is holding the entire assembly hostage to a minority of

one, or a minority of a few. It also results in extreme pressure being

brought to bear on dissidents. The debate starts to become dishonest and

compulsive.

Not every person has to agree with every decision. All that is needed is

for every person to agree to go along with the decision, even though

they disagree with it. This is a much different thing, and retains an

open and honest expression of disagreement. Whereas rule by consensus,

so-called, tends to suppress such disagreements.

What is needed in our deliberative assemblies is a measure of the

intensity of opposition to any given proposal. To my knowledge, this has

almost never existed so far. Intensity varies in both degree and number.

There could be a majority of fifty-one intensely in favor, and a

minority of forty-nine mildly opposed. There could be a majority of

ninety mildly in favor and a minority of ten intensely opposed. And so

forth. It is this mix that is crucial in majority-minority dynamics in

deliberative assemblies.

We need a two-stage voting system. The first vote measures approval or

disapproval of the proposal. The second vote measures the intensity of

opposition -- disagree but willing to go along, disagree and willing to

go along with minor changes, intensely disagree and not willing to go

along, and so forth. This would give the assembly the knowledge it needs

to proceed. If it finds that there exists a small minority that

intensely disagrees and refuses to go along, then it knows that it has

to back up and rethink the proposition. It knows that it has to struggle

to compromise, and work through the issue until a proposal can be

devised that everyone can agree to go along with, even though some may

still disagree with it. This would also bring into the open any minority

that regularly blocks majority decisions, and would lead to political

struggle around this issue, with the possibility that the minority, or

majority itself, might be changed. This would be an open and honest

voting system, rather than the vague, often manipulative and dishonest,

struggle (often without even voting!) for so-called consensus.

If no compromise can be reached that an intensely opposed minority can

agree to go along with, then obviously the assembly cannot have a policy

on that issue, not without further political struggle to resolve the

disagreement. But given the imperatives of cooperative social life,

everyone will become acutely aware of the necessity of having collective

decisions, if we are to succeed in carrying out any project. It is the

rare instance when we can each do our own thing.

Democracy has been a long time coming, and will still be a long time yet

in coming. By democracy I mean, not just majority rule, but the use of

human intelligence, by everyone, to consciously shape the cultural and

social arrangements within which we live. We will never have complete

control over our social lives of course, even with the most thoroughly

direct democracy possible, because of the phenomenon of unintended

consequences. But we can move a long way in that direction.

The idea of democracy existed already in antiquity, and was practiced

briefly then. It has reappeared sporadically since then, in medieval

towns, in the guilds of the middle ages, in many peasant villages (and

undoubtedly elsewhere too, for example in the League of the Iroquois).

It was not until modern times however, with the emergence of the belief

in popular sovereignty, that democracy started to gain serious ground.

Democracy, in the sense of majority rule, has never yet been achieved on

the national level anywhere. But the parliaments of the ruling class

have been forced to steadily include more and more elements of the

population, or at least representatives of those elements, first non

propertied white males, then women, then blacks and other ethnic groups,

then young adults down to the age of eighteen, and so forth. The ideas

of democracy in general, and even of majority rule in particular, have

become widely accepted and deeply rooted in contemporary culture.

Perhaps someday we will be able to create the reality to match our

dreams.