đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş crimethinc-from-democracy-to-freedom.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:31:21. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: From Democracy To Freedom Author: CrimethInc. Date: April 29, 2016 Language: en Topics: democracy, Freedom Source: https://crimethinc.com/2016/04/29/feature-from-democracy-to-freedom
Democracy is the most universal political ideal of our day. George Bush
invoked it to justify invading Iraq; Obama congratulated the rebels of
Tahrir Square for bringing it to Egypt; Occupy Wall Street claimed to
have distilled its pure form. From the Democratic Peopleâs Republic of
North Korea to the autonomous region of Rojava, practically every
government and popular movement calls itself democratic.
And whatâs the cure for the problems with democracy? Everyone agrees:
more democracy. Since the turn of the century, weâve seen a spate of new
movements promising to deliver real democracy, in contrast to ostensibly
democratic institutions that they describe as exclusive, coercive, and
alienating.
Is there a common thread that links all these different kinds of
democracy? Which of them is the real one? Can any of them deliver the
inclusivity and freedom we associate with the word?
Impelled by our own experiences in directly democratic movements, weâve
returned to these questions. Our conclusion is that the dramatic
imbalances in economic and political power that have driven people into
the streets from New York City to Sarajevo are not incidental defects in
specific democracies, but structural features dating back to the origins
of democracy itself; they appear in practically every example of
democratic government through the ages. Representative democracy
preserved all the bureaucratic apparatus that was originally invented to
serve kings; direct democracy tends to recreate it on a smaller scale,
even outside the formal structures of the state. Democracy is not the
same as self-determination.
To be sure, many good things are regularly described as democratic. This
is not an argument against discussions, collectives, assemblies,
networks, federations, or working with people you donât always agree
with. The argument, rather, is that when we engage in those practices,
if we understand what we are doing as democracyâas a form of
participatory government rather than a collective practice of
freedomâthen sooner or later, we will recreate all the problems
associated with less democratic forms of government. This goes for
representative democracy and direct democracy alike, and even for
consensus process.
Rather than championing democratic procedures as an end in themselves,
then, letâs return to the values that drew us to democracy in the first
place: egalitarianism, inclusivity, the idea that each person should
control her own destiny. If democracy is not the most effective way to
actualize these, what is?
As fiercer and fiercer struggles rock todayâs democracies, the stakes of
this discussion keep getting higher. If we go on trying to replace the
prevailing order with a more participatory version of the same thing,
weâll keep ending up right back where we started, and others who share
our disillusionment will gravitate towards more authoritarian
alternatives. We need a framework that can fulfill the promises
democracy has betrayed.
In the following text, we examine the common threads that connect
different forms of democracy, trace the development of democracy from
its classical origins to its contemporary representative, direct, and
consensus-based variants, and evaluate how democratic discourse and
procedures serve the social movements that adopt them. Along the way, we
outline what it would mean to seek freedom directly rather than through
democratic rule.
This project is the result of years of transcontinental dialogue. To
complement it, we are publishing case studies from participants in
movements that have been promoted as models of direct democracy: 15M in
Spain (2011), the occupation of Syntagma Square in Greece (2011), Occupy
in the United States (2011â2012), the Slovenian uprising (2012â2013),
the plenums in Bosnia (2014), and the Rojava revolution (2012â2016).
What is democracy, exactly? Most of the textbook definitions have to do
with majority rule or government by elected representatives. On the
other hand, a few radicals have argued that ârealâ democracy only takes
place outside and against the stateâs monopoly on power. Should we
understand democracy as a set of decision-making procedures with a
specific history, or as a general aspiration to egalitarian, inclusive,
and participatory politics?
âWhat is democracy?â
âWell, I was never very clear on it, myself. Like every other kind of
government, itâs got something to do with young men killing each other,
I believe.â
â Johnny Got His Gun (1971)
To pin down the object of our critique, letâs start with the term
itself. The word democracy derives from the ancient Greek dÄmokratĂa,
from dĂŞmos âpeopleâ and krĂĄtos âpower.â This formulation of rule by the
people, which has resurfaced in Latin America as poder popular, begs the
question: which people? And what kind of power?
These root words, demos and kratos, suggest two common denominators of
all democracy: a way of determining who participates in the
decision-making, and a way of enforcing decisions. Citizenship, in other
words, and policing. These are the essentials of democracy; they are
what make it a form of government. Anything short of that is more
properly described as anarchyâthe absence of government, from the Greek
an- âwithoutâ and arkhos âruler.â
Common denominators of democracy:
(demos)
(kratos)
(polis)
(oikos)
Who qualifies as demos? Some have argued that etymologically, demos
never meant all people, but only particular social classes. Even as its
partisans have trumpeted its supposed inclusivity, in practice democracy
has always demanded a way of distinguishing between included and
excluded. That could be status in the legislature, voting rights,
citizenship, membership, race, gender, age, or participation in street
assemblies; but in every form of democracy, for there to be legitimate
decisions, there have to be formal conditions of legitimacy, and a
defined group of people who meet them.
In this regard, democracy institutionalizes the provincial, chauvinist
character of its Greek origins, at the same time as it seemingly offers
a model that could involve all the world. This is why democracy has
proven so compatible with nationalism and the state; it presupposes the
Other, who is not accorded the same rights or political agency.
The focus on inclusion and exclusion is clear enough at the dawn of
modern democracy in Rousseauâs influential Of the Social Contract, in
which he emphasizes that there is no contradiction between democracy and
slavery. The more âevildoersâ are in chains, he suggests, the more
perfect the freedom of the citizens. Freedom for the wolf is death for
the lamb, as Isaiah Berlin later put it. The zero-sum conception of
freedom expressed in this metaphor is the foundation of the discourse of
rights granted and protected by the state. In other words: for citizens
to be free, the state must possess ultimate authority and the capacity
to exercise total control. The state seeks to produce sheep, reserving
the position of wolf for itself.
By contrast, if we understand freedom as cumulative, the freedom of one
person becomes the freedom of all: it is not simply a question of being
protected by the authorities, but of intersecting with each other in a
way that maximizes the possibilities for everyone. In this framework,
the more that coercive force is centralized, the less freedom there can
be. This way of conceiving freedom is social rather than
individualistic: it approaches liberty as a collectively produced
relationship to our potential, not a static bubble of private rights.[1]
Letâs turn to the other root, kratos. Democracy shares this suffix with
aristocracy, autocracy, bureaucracy, plutocracy, and technocracy. Each
of these terms describes government by some subset of society, but they
all share a common logic. That common thread is kratos, power.
What kind of power? Letâs consult the ancient Greeks once more.
In classical Greece, every abstract concept was personified by a divine
being. Kratos was an implacable Titan embodying the kind of coercive
force associated with state power. One of the oldest sources in which
Kratos appears is the play Prometheus Bound, composed by Aeschylus in
the early days of Athenian democracy. The play opens with Kratos
forcibly escorting the shackled Prometheus, who is being punished for
stealing fire from the gods to give to humanity. Kratos appears as a
jailer unthinkingly carrying out Zeusâs ordersâa brute âmade for any
tyrantâs acts.â
The sort of force personified by Kratos is what democracy has in common
with autocracy and every other form of rule. They share the institutions
of coercion: the legal apparatus, the police, and the military, all of
which preceded democracy and have repeatedly outlived it. These are the
tools âmade for any tyrantâs acts,â whether the tyrant at the helm is a
king, a class of bureaucrats, or âthe peopleâ themselves. âDemocracy
means simply the bludgeoning of the people by the people for the
people,â as Oscar Wilde put it. Muâammer al Gaddafi echoed this
approvingly a century later, without irony: âDemocracy is the
supervision of the people by the people.â
In modern-day Greek, kratos is simply the word for state. To understand
democracy, we have to look closer at government itself.
âThere is no contradiction between exercising democracy and legitimate
central administrative control according to the well-known balance
between centralization and democracy⌠Democracy consolidates relations
among people, and its main strength is respect. The strength that stems
from democracy assumes a higher degree of adherence in carrying out
orders with great accuracy and zeal.â
â Saddam Hussein, âDemocracy: A Source of Strength for the Individual
and Societyâ
âAs in absolute governments the King is law, so in free countries the
law ought to be King.â
â Thomas Paine, Common Sense
As a form of government, democracy offers a way to produce a single
order out of a cacophony of desires, absorbing the resources and
activities of the minority into policies dictated by the majority. In
any democracy, there is a legitimate space of decision-making, distinct
from the rest of life. It could be a congress in a parliament building,
or a general assembly on a sidewalk, or an app soliciting votes via
iPhone. In every case, it is not our immediate needs and desires that
are the ultimate source of legitimacy, but a particular decision-making
process and protocol. In a state, this is called âthe rule of law,â
though the principle does not necessarily require a formal legal system.
This is the essence of government: decisions made in one space determine
what can take place in all other spaces. The result is alienationâthe
friction between what is decided and what is lived.
Democracy promises to solve this problem by incorporating everyone into
the space of decision-making: the rule of all by all. âThe citizens of a
democracy submit to the law because they recognize that, however
indirectly, they are submitting to themselves as makers of the law.â But
if all those decisions were actually made by the people they impact,
there would be no need for a means of enforcing them.
âThe great difficulty lies in this: you must first enable the government
to control the governed; and in the next place oblige it to control
itself.â
â James Madison, The Federalist
What protects the minorities in this winner-take-all system? Advocates
of democracy explain that minorities will be protected by institutional
provisionsââchecks and balances.â In other words, the same structure
that holds power over them is supposed to protect them from itself.[2]
In this approach, democracy and personal freedom are conceived as
fundamentally at odds: to preserve freedom for individuals, a government
must be able to take freedom away from everyone. Yet it is optimistic
indeed to trust that institutions will always be better than the people
who maintain them. The more power we vest in government in hopes of
protecting the marginalized, the more dangerous it can be when it is
turned against them.
How much do you buy into the idea that the democratic process should
trump your own conscience and values? Letâs try a quick exercise.
Imagine yourself in a democratic republic with slavesâsay, ancient
Athens, or ancient Rome, or the United States of America until the end
of 1865. Would you obey the law and treat people as property while
endeavoring to change the laws, knowing full well that whole generations
might live and die in chains in the meantime? Or would you act according
to your conscience in defiance of the law, like Harriet Tubman and John
Brown?
If you would follow in the footsteps of Harriet Tubman, then you, too,
believe that there is something more important than the rule of law.
This is a problem for anyone who wants to make conformity with the law
or with the will of the majority into the final arbiter of legitimacy.
âCan there not be a government in which majorities do not virtually
decide right and wrong, but conscience?â
â Henry David Thoreau, Civil Disobedience
In ancient Athens, the much-touted âbirthplace of democracy,â we already
see the exclusion and coercion that have been essential features of
democratic government ever since. Only adult male citizens with military
training could vote; women, slaves, debtors, and all who lacked Athenian
blood were excluded. At the very most, democracy involved less than a
fifth of the population.
Indeed, slavery was more prevalent in ancient Athens than in other Greek
city states, and women had fewer rights relative to men. Greater
equality among male citizens apparently meant greater solidarity against
women and foreigners. The space of participatory politics was a gated
community.
We can map the boundaries of this gated community in the Athenian
opposition between public and privateâbetween polis and oikos. The
polis, the Greek city-state, was a space of public discourse where
citizens interacted as equals. By contrast, the oikos, the household,
was a hierarchical space in which male property owners ruled supremeâa
zone outside the purview of the political, yet serving as its
foundation. In this dichotomy, the oikos represents everything that
provides the resources that sustain politics, yet is taken for granted
as preceding and therefore outside it.
These categories remain with us today. The words âpoliticsâ (âthe
affairs of the cityâ) and âpoliceâ (âthe administration of the cityâ)
come from polis, while âeconomyâ (âthe management of the householdâ) and
âecologyâ (âthe study of the householdâ) derive from oikos.
Democracy is still premised on this division. As long as there is a
political distinction between public and private, everything from the
household (the gendered space of intimacy that sustains the prevailing
order with invisible and unpaid labor[3]) to entire continents and
peoples (like Africa during the colonial periodâor even blackness
itself) may be relegated outside the sphere of politics. Likewise, the
institution of property and the market economy it produces, which have
served as the substructure of democracy since its origins, are placed
beyond question at the same time as they are enforced and defended by
the political apparatus.
Fortunately, ancient Athens is not the only reference point for
egalitarian decision-making. A cursory survey of other societies reveals
plenty of other examples, many of which are not predicated on
exclusivity or coercion. But should we understand these as democracies,
too?
âAre we supposed to believe that before the Athenians, it never really
occurred to anyone, anywhere, to gather all the members of their
community in order to make joint decisions in a way that gave everyone
equal say?â
â David Graeber, Fragments of an Anarchist Anthropology
In his Fragments of an Anarchist Anthropology, David Graeber takes his
colleagues to task for identifying Athens as the origin of democracy; he
surmises that the Iroquois, Berber, Sulawezi, or Tallensi models do not
receive as much attention simply because none of them center around
voting. On one hand, Graeber is right to direct our attention to
societies that focus on building consensus rather than practicing
coercion: many of these embody the best values associated with democracy
much more than ancient Athens did. On the other hand, it doesnât make
sense for us to label these examples truly democratic while questioning
the democratic credentials of the Greeks who invented the term. This is
still ethnocentricism: affirming the value of non-Western examples by
granting them honorary status in our own admittedly inferior Western
paradigm. Instead, letâs concede that democracy, as a specific
historical practice dating from Sparta and Athens and emulated
worldwide, has not lived up to the standard set by many of these other
societies, and it does not make sense to describe them as democratic. It
would be more responsible, and more precise, to describe and honor them
in their own terms.
That leaves us with Athens as the original democracy, after all. What if
Athens became so influential not because of how free it was, but because
of how it harnessed participatory politics to the power of the state? At
the time, most societies throughout human history had been stateless;
some were hierarchical, others were horizontal, but no stateless society
had the centralized power of kratos. The states that existed, by
contrast, were hardly egalitarian. The Athenians innovated a hybrid
format in which horizontality coincided with exclusion and coercion. If
you take it for granted that the state is desirable or at least
inevitable, this sounds appealing. But if the state is the root of the
problem, then the slavery and patriarchy of ancient Athens were not
early irregularities in the democratic model, but indications of the
power imbalances coded into its DNA from the beginning.
The US government has more in common with the republic of ancient Rome
than with Athens. Rather than governing directly, Roman citizens elected
representatives to head up a complex bureaucracy. As Roman territory
expanded and wealth flooded in, small farmers lost their footing and
massive numbers of the dispossessed flooded the capital; unrest forced
the Republic to extend voting rights to wider and wider segments of the
population, yet political inclusion did little to counteract the
economic stratification of Roman society. All this sounds eerily
familiar.
The Roman Republic came to an end when Julius Caesar seized power; from
then on, Rome was ruled by emperors. Yet very little changed for the
average Roman. The bureaucracy, the military, the economy, and the
courts continued to function the same as before.
âThose persons who believe in the sharpest distinction between democracy
and monarchy can scarcely appreciate how a political institution may go
through so many transformations and yet remain the same. Yet a swift
glance must show us that in all the evolution of the English monarchy,
with all its broadenings and its revolutions, and even with its jump
across the sea into a colony which became an independent nation and then
a powerful State, the same State functions and attitudes have been
preserved essentially unchanged.â
â Randolph Bourne, The State
Fast-forward eighteen centuries to the American Revolution. Outraged
about âtaxation without representation,â North American subjects of the
British Empire rebelled and established a representative democracy of
their own,[4] soon complete with a Roman-style Senate. Yet once again,
the function of the state remained unchanged. Those who had fought to
throw off the king discovered that taxation with representation was
little different. The result was a series of uprisingsâShayâs Rebellion,
the Whisky Rebellion, Friesâs Rebellion, and moreâall of which were
brutally suppressed. The new democratic government succeeded in
pacifying the population where the British Empire had failed, thanks to
the loyalty of many who had revolted against the king: for didnât this
new government represent them?[5]
This story has been repeated time and time again. In the French
revolution of 1848, the provisional governmentâs prefect of police
entered the office vacated by the kingâs prefect of police and took up
the same papers his predecessor had just set down. In the 20th century
transitions from dictatorship to democracy in Greece, Spain, and Chile,
and more recently in Tunisia and Egypt, social movements that overthrew
dictators had to go on fighting against the very same police under the
democratic regime. This is kratos, what some have called the Deep State,
carrying over from one regime to the next.
Laws, courts, prisons, intelligence agencies, tax collectors, armies,
policeâmost of the instruments of coercive power that we consider
oppressive in a monarchy or a dictatorship operate the same way in a
democracy. Yet when weâre permitted to cast ballots about who supervises
them, weâre supposed to regard them as ours, even when theyâre used
against us. This is the great achievement of two and a half centuries of
democratic revolutions: instead of abolishing the means by which kings
governed, they rendered those means popular.
âA Constituent Assembly is the means used by the privileged classes,
when a dictatorship is not possible, either to prevent a revolution, or,
when a revolution has already broken out, to stop its progress with the
excuse of legalizing it, and to take back as much as possible of the
gains that the people had made during the insurrectional period.â
â Errico Malatesta, âAgainst the Constituent Assembly as against the
Dictatorshipâ
The transfer of power from rulers to assemblies has served to
prematurely halt revolutionary movements ever since the American
Revolution. Rather than making the changes they sought via direct
action, the rebels entrusted that task to their new representatives at
the helm of the stateâonly to see their dreams betrayed.
The state is powerful indeed, but one thing it cannot do is deliver
freedom to its subjects. It cannot, because it derives its very being
from their subjection. It can subject others, it can commandeer and
concentrate resources, it can impose dues and duties, it can dole out
rights and concessionsâthe consolation prizes of the governedâbut it
cannot offer self-determination. Kratos can dominate, but it cannot
liberate.
Instead, representative democracy promises the opportunity to rule each
other on a rotating basis: a distributed and temporary kingship as
diffuse, dynamic, and yet hierarchical as the stock market. In practice,
since this rule is delegated, there are still rulers who wield
tremendous power relative to everyone else. Usually, like the Bushes and
Clintons, they hail from a de facto ruling class. This ruling class
tends to occupy the upper echelons of all the other hierarchies of our
society, both formal and informal. Even if a politician grew up among
the plebs, the more he exercises authority, the more his interests
diverge from those of the governed. Yet the real problem is not the
intentions of politicians; it is the apparatus of the state itself.
Competing for the right to direct the coercive power of the state, the
contestants never question the value of the state itself, even if in
practice they only find themselves on the receiving end of its force.
Representative democracy offers a pressure valve: when people are
dissatisfied, they set their sights on the next elections, taking the
state itself for granted. Indeed, if you want to put a stop to corporate
profiteering or environmental devastation, isnât the state the only
instrument powerful enough to accomplish that? Never mind that it was
state that established the conditions in which those are possible in the
first place.
âFree election of masters does not abolish the masters or the slaves.
Free choice among a wide variety of goods and services does not signify
freedom if these goods and services sustain social controls over a life
of toil and fearâthat is, if they sustain alienation. And the
spontaneous reproduction of superimposed needs by the individual does
not establish autonomy; it only testifies to the efficacy of the
controls.â
â Herbert Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man
So much for democracy and political inequality. What about the economic
inequality that has attended democracy since the beginning? You would
think that a system based on majority rule would tend to reduce the
disparities between rich and poor, seeing as the poor constitute the
majority. Yet, just as in ancient Rome, the current ascendancy of
democracy is matched by enormous gulfs between the haves and the
have-nots. How can this be?
Just as capitalism succeeded feudalism in Europe, representative
democracy proved more sustainable than monarchy because it offered
mobility within the hierarchies of the state. The dollar and the ballot
are both mechanisms for distributing power hierarchically in a way that
takes pressure off the hierarchies themselves. In contrast to the
political and economic stasis of the feudal era, capitalism and
democracy ceaselessly reapportion power. Thanks to this dynamic
flexibility, the potential rebel has better odds of improving his status
within the prevailing order than of toppling it. Consequently,
opposition tends to reenergize the political system from within rather
than threatening it.
Representative democracy is to politics what capitalism is to economics.
The desires of the consumer and the voter are represented by currencies
that promise individual empowerment yet relentlessly concentrate power
at the top of the social pyramid. As long as power is concentrated
there, it is easy enough to block, buy off, or destroy anyone who
threatens the pyramid itself.
This explains why, when the wealthy and powerful have seen their
interests challenged through the institutions of democracy, they have
been able to suspend the law to deal with the problemâwitness the
gruesome fates of the brothers Gracchi in ancient Rome and Salvador
Allende in modern Chile. Within the framework of the state, property has
always trumped democracy.[6]
âIn representative democracy as in capitalist competition, everyone
supposedly gets a chance but only a few come out on top. If you didnât
win, you must not have tried hard enough! This is the same
rationalization used to justify the injustices of sexism and racism:
look, you lazy bums, you could have been Bill Cosby or Hillary Clinton
if youâd just worked harder. But thereâs not enough space at the top for
all of us, no matter how hard we work.
When reality is generated via the media and media access is determined
by wealth, elections are simply advertising campaigns. Market
competition dictates which lobbyists gain the resources to determine the
grounds upon which voters make their decisions. Under these
circumstances, a political party is essentially a business offering
investment opportunities in legislation. Itâs foolish to expect
political representatives to oppose the interests of their clientele
when they depend directly upon them for power.â
â Work
That brings us to the present. Africa and Asia are witnessing new
movements in favor of democracy; meanwhile, many people in Europe and
the Americas who are disillusioned by the failures of representative
democracy have pinned their hopes on direct democracy, shifting from the
model of the Roman Republic back to its Athenian predecessor. If the
problem is that government is unresponsive to our needs, isnât the
solution to make it more participatory, so we wield power directly
rather than delegating it to politicians?
But what does that mean, exactly? Does it mean voting on laws rather
than legislators? Or toppling the prevailing government and instituting
a government of federated assemblies in its place? Or something else?
âTrue democracy exists only through the direct participation of the
people, and not through the activity of their representatives.
Parliaments have been a legal barrier between the people and the
exercise of authority, excluding the masses from meaningful politics and
monopolizing sovereignty in their place. People are left with only a
façade of democracy, manifested in long queues to cast their election
ballots.â
â Muâammer al Gaddafi, The Green Book
On one hand, if direct democracy is just a more participatory and
time-consuming way to pilot the state, it might offer us more say in the
details of government, but it will preserve the centralization of power
that is inherent in it. There is a problem of scale here: can we imagine
219 million eligible voters directly conducting the activities of the US
government? The conventional answer is that local assemblies would send
representatives to regional assemblies, which in turn would send
representatives to a national assemblyâbut there, already, we are
speaking about representative democracy again. At best, in place of
periodically electing representatives, we can picture a ceaseless series
of referendums decreed from on high.
One of the most robust versions of that vision is digital democracy, or
e-democracy, promoted by groups like the Pirate Party. The Pirate Party
has already been incorporated into the existing political system; but in
theory, we can imagine a population linked through digital technology,
making all the decisions regarding their society via majority vote in
real time. In such an order, majoritarian government would gain a
practically irresistible legitimacy; yet the greatest power would likely
be concentrated in the hands of the technocrats who administered the
system. Coding the algorithms that determined which information and
which questions came to the fore, they would shape the conceptual
frameworks of the participants a thousand times more invasively than
election-year advertising does today.
âThe digital project of reducing the world to representation converges
with the program of electoral democracy, in which only representatives
acting through the prescribed channels may exercise power. Both set
themselves against all that is incomputable and irreducible, fitting
humanity to a Procrustean bed. Fused as electronic democracy, they would
present the opportunity to vote on a vast array of minutia, while
rendering the infrastructure itself unquestionableâthe more
participatory a system is, the more âlegitimate.ââ
â Deserting the Digital Utopia
But even if such a system could be made to work perfectlyâdo we want to
retain centralized majoritarian rule in the first place? The mere fact
of being participatory does not make a political process any less
coercive. As long as the majority has the capacity to force its
decisions on the minority, we are talking about a system identical in
spirit with the one that governs the US todayâa system that would also
require prisons, police, and tax collectors, or else other ways to
perform the same functions.
Real freedom is not a question of how participatory the process of
answering questions is, but of the extent to which we can frame the
questions ourselvesâand whether we can stop others from imposing their
answers on us. The institutions that operate under a dictatorship or an
elected government are no less oppressive when they are employed
directly by a majority without the mediation of representatives. In the
final analysis, even the most directly democratic state is better at
concentrating power than maximizing freedom.
On the other hand, not everyone believes that democracy is a means of
state governance. Some proponents of democracy have attempted to
transform the discourse, arguing that true democracy only takes place
outside the state and against its monopoly on power. For opponents of
the state, this appears to be a strategic move, in that it appropriates
all the legitimacy that has been invested in democracy across three
centuries of popular movements and self-congratulatory state propaganda.
Yet there are three fundamental problems with this approach.
âDemocracy is not, to begin with, a form of State. It is, in the first
place, the reality of the power of the people that can never coincide
with the form of a State. There will always be tension between democracy
as the exercise of a shared power of thinking and acting, and the State,
whose very principle is to appropriate this power⌠The power of citizens
is, above all, the power for them to act for themselves, to constitute
themselves into an autonomous force. Citizenship is not a prerogative
linked to the fact of being registered as an inhabitant and voter in a
country; it is, above all, an exercise that cannot be delegated.â
â Jacques Rancière
First, itâs ahistorical. Democracy originated as a form of state
government; practically all the familiar historical examples of
democracy were carried out via the state or at least by people who
aspired to govern. The positive associations we have with democracy as a
set of abstract aspirations came later.
Second, it fosters confusion. Those who promote democracy as an
alternative to the state rarely draw a meaningful distinction between
the two. If you dispense with representation, coercive enforcement, and
the rule of law, yet keep all the other hallmarks that make democracy a
means of governingâcitizenship, voting, and the centralization of
legitimacy in a single decision-making structureâyou end up retaining
the procedures of government without the mechanisms that make them
effective. This combines the worst of both worlds. It ensures that those
who approach anti-state democracy expecting it to perform the same
function as the state will inevitably be disappointed, while creating a
situation in which anti-state democracy tends to reproduce the dynamics
associated with state democracy on a smaller scale.
Finally, itâs a losing battle. If what you mean to denote by the word
democracy can only occur outside the framework of the state, it creates
considerable ambiguity to use a term that has been associated with state
politics for 2500 years.[7] Most people will assume that what you mean
by democracy is reconcilable with the state after all. This sets the
stage for statist parties and strategies to regain legitimacy in the
public eye, even after having been completely discredited. The political
parties Podemos and Syriza gained traction in the occupied squares of
Barcelona and Athens thanks to their rhetoric about direct democracy,
only to make their way into the halls of government where they are now
behaving like any other political party. Theyâre still doing democracy,
just more efficiently and effectively. Without a language that
differentiates what they are doing in parliament from what people were
doing in the squares, this process will recur again and again.
âWe must all be both rulers and ruled simultaneously, or a system of
rulers and subjects is the only alternative⌠Freedom, in other words,
can only be maintained through a sharing of political power, and this
sharing happens through political institutions.â
â Cindy Milstein, âDemocracy Is Directâ
When we identify what we are doing when we oppose the state as the
practice of democracy, we set the stage for our efforts to be reabsorbed
into larger representational structures. Democracy is not just a way of
managing the apparatus of government, but also of regenerating and
legitimizing it. Candidates, parties, regimes, and even the form of
government can be swapped out from time to time when it becomes clear
that they cannot solve the problems of their constituents. In this way,
government itselfâthe source of at least some of those problemsâis able
to persist. Direct democracy is just the latest way to rebrand it.
Even without the familiar trappings of the state, any form of government
requires some way of determining who can participate in decision-making
and on what termsâonce again, who counts as the demos. Such stipulations
may be vague at first, but they will get more concrete the older an
institution grows and the higher the stakes get. And if there is no way
of enforcing decisionsâno kratosâthe decision-making processes of
government will have no more weight than decisions people make
autonomously.[8] This is the paradox of a project that seeks government
without the state.
These contradictions are stark enough in Murray Bookchinâs formulation
of libertarian municipalism as an alternative to state governance. In
libertarian municipalism, Bookchin explained, an exclusive and avowedly
vanguardist organization governed by laws and a Constitution would make
decisions by majority vote. They would run candidates in city council
elections, with the long-term goal of establishing a confederation that
could replace the state. Once such a confederation got underway,
membership was to be binding even if participating municipalities wanted
to withdraw. Those who try to retain government without the state are
likely to end up with something like the state by another name.
The important distinction is not between democracy and the state, then,
but between government and self-determination. Government is the
exercise of authority over a given space or polity: whether the process
is dictatorial or participatory, the end result is the imposition of
control. By contrast, self-determination means disposing of oneâs
potential on oneâs own terms: when people engage in it together, they
are not ruling each other, but fostering cumulative autonomy. Freely
made agreements require no enforcement; systems that concentrate
legitimacy in a single institution or decision-making process always do.
It is strange to use the word democracy for the idea that the state is
inherently undesirable. The proper word for that idea is anarchism.
Anarchism opposes all exclusion and domination in favor of the radical
decentralization of power structures, decision-making processes, and
notions of legitimacy. It is not a matter of governing in a completely
participatory manner, but of making it impossible to impose any form of
rule.
If the common denominators of democratic government are citizenship and
policingâdemos and kratosâthe most radical democracy would expand those
categories to include the whole world: universal citizenship, community
policing. In the ideal democratic society, every person would be a
citizen,[9] and every citizen would be a policeman.[10]
At the furthest extreme of this logic, majority rule would mean rule by
consensus: not the rule of the majority, but unanimous rule. The closer
we get to unanimity, the more legitimate government is perceived to
beâso wouldnât rule by consensus be the most legitimate government of
all? Then, finally, there would be no need for anyone to play the role
of the police.
âIn the strict sense of the term, there has never been a true democracy,
and there never will be⌠One can hardly imagine that all the people
would sit permanently in an assembly to deal with public affairs.â
â Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Of the Social Contract
Obviously, this is impossible. But itâs worth reflecting on what sort of
utopia is implied by idealizing direct democracy as a form of
government. Imagine the kind of totalitarianism it would take to produce
enough cohesion to govern a society via consensus processâto get
everyone to agree. Talk about reducing things to the lowest common
denominator! If the alternative to coercion is to abolish disagreement,
surely there must be a third path.
This problem came to the fore during the Occupy movement. Some
participants understood the general assemblies as the governing bodies
of the movement; from their perspective, it was undemocratic for people
to act without unanimous authorization. Others approached the assemblies
as spaces of encounter without prescriptive authority, in which people
might exchange influence and ideas, forming fluid constellations around
shared goals to take action. The former felt betrayed when their fellow
Occupiers engaged in tactics that hadnât been agreed on in the general
assembly; the latter countered that it didnât make sense to grant veto
power to an arbitrarily convened mass including literally anyone who
happened by on the street.
Perhaps the answer is that the structures of decision-making must be
decentralized as well as consensus-based, so that universal agreement is
unnecessary. This is a step in the right direction, but it introduces
new questions. How should people be divided into polities? What dictates
the jurisdiction of an assembly or the scope of the decisions it can
make? Who determines which assemblies a person may participate in, or
who is most affected by a given decision? How are conflicts between
assemblies resolved? The answers to these questions will either
institutionalize a set of rules governing legitimacy, or prioritize
voluntary forms of association. In the former case, the rules will
likely ossify over time, as people refer to protocol to resolve
disputes. In the latter case, the structures of decision-making will
continuously shift, fracture, clash, and re-emerge in organic processes
that can hardly be described as government. When the participants in a
decision-making process are free to withdraw from it or engage in
activity that contradicts the decisions, then what is taking place is
not governmentâit is simply conversation.[11]
âDemocracy means government by discussion, but it is only effective if
you can stop people talking.â
â Clement Attlee, UK Prime Minister, 1957
From one perspective, this is a question of emphasis. Is our goal to
produce the ideal institutions, rendering them as horizontal and
participatory as possible but deferring to them as the ultimate
foundation of authority? Or is our goal to maximize freedom, in which
case any particular institution we create is subordinate to liberty and
therefore dispensable? Once moreâwhat is legitimate, the institutions or
our needs and desires?
Even at their best, institutions are just a means to an end; they have
no value in and of themselves. No one should be obliged to adhere to the
protocol of any institution that suppresses her freedom or fails to meet
her needs. If everyone were free to organize with others on a purely
voluntary basis, that would be the best way to generate social forms
that are truly in the interests of the participants: for as soon as a
structure was not working for everyone involved, they would have to
refine or replace it. This approach wonât bring all of society into
consensus, but it is the only way to guarantee that consensus is
meaningful and desirable when it does arise.
We often hear arguments for democracy on the grounds that, as the most
inclusive form of government, it is the best suited to combat the racism
and sexism of our society. Yet as long as the categories of rulers/ruled
and included/excluded are built into the structure of politics, coded as
âmajoritiesâ and âminoritiesâ even when the minorities outnumber the
majorities, imbalances of power along race and gender lines will always
be reflected as disparities in political power. This is why women, black
people, and other groups still lack political leverage proportionate to
their numbers, despite having ostensibly possessed voting rights for a
century or more.
âWe havenât benefitted from Americaâs democracy. Weâve only suffered
from Americaâs hypocrisy.â
â Malcolm X, âThe Ballot or the Bulletâ
In The Abolition of White Democracy, the late Joel Olson presents a
compelling critique of what he calls âwhite democracyââthe concentration
of democratic political power in white hands by means of a cross-class
alliance among those granted white privilege. But he takes for granted
that democracy is the most desirable system, assuming that white
supremacy is an incidental obstacle to its functioning rather than a
natural consequence thereof. If democracy is the ideal form of
egalitarian relations, why has it been implicated in structural racism
for practically its entire existence?
Where politics is constructed as a zero-sum competition, those who hold
power will be loath to share it with others. Consider the men who
opposed universal suffrage and the white people who opposed the
extension of voting rights to people of color: the structures of
democracy did not discourage their bigotry, but gave them an incentive
to institutionalize it.
Olson traces the way that the ruling class fostered white supremacy in
order to divide the working class, but he neglects the ways that
democratic structures lent themselves to this process. He argues that we
should promote class solidarity as a response to these divisions, but
(as Bakunin argued contra Marx) the difference between the governing and
the governed is itself a class differenceâthink of ancient Athens.
Racialized exclusion has always been the flip side of citizenship.
âBy erecting a slave society, America created the economic foundation
for its great experiment in democracy⌠Americaâs indispensable working
class existed as property beyond the realm of politics, leaving white
Americans free to trumpet their love of freedom and democratic values.â
â Ta-Nehisi Coates, âThe Case for Reparationsâ
So the political dimension of white supremacy isnât just a consequence
of racial disparities in economic powerâit also produces them. Ethnic
and racial divisions were ingrained in our society long before the dawn
of capitalism; the confiscation of Jewish property under the Inquisition
financed the original colonization of the Americas, and the looting of
the Americas and enslavement of Africans provided the original startup
capital to jumpstart capitalism in Europe and later North America. It is
possible that racial divisions could outlast the next massive economic
and political shift, tooâfor example, as exclusive assemblies of
predominantly white (or Jewish, or even Kurdish) citizens.
There are no easy fixes for this problem. Reformers often speak about
making our political system more âdemocratic,â by which they mean more
inclusive and egalitarian. Yet when their reforms are realized in a way
that legitimizes and strengthens the institutions of government, this
only puts more weight behind those institutions when they strike at the
targeted and marginalizedâwitness the mass incarceration of black people
since the civil rights movement. Malcolm X and other advocates of black
separatism were right that a white-founded democracy would never offer
freedom to black peopleânot because white and black people can never
coexist, but because in rendering politics a competition for centralized
political power, democratic governance creates conflicts that preclude
coexistence. If todayâs racial conflicts can ever be resolved, it will
be through the establishment of new relations on the basis of
decentralization, not by integrating the excluded into the political
order of the included.[12]
âAs long as there are police, who do you think they will harass? As long
as there are prisons, who do you think will fill them? As long as there
is poverty, who do you think will be poor? It is naĂŻve to believe we
could achieve equality in a society based on hierarchy. You can shuffle
the cards, but itâs still the same deck.â
â To Change Everything
As long as we understand what we are doing together politically as
democracyâas government by a legitimate decision-making processâwe will
see that legitimacy invoked to justify programs that are functionally
white supremacist, whether they are the policies of a state or the
decisions of a spokescouncil. (Recall, for example, the tensions between
the decision-making processes of the predominantly white general
assemblies and the less white encampments within many Occupy groups.)
Only when we dispense with the idea that any political process is
inherently legitimate will we be able to strip away the final alibi of
the racial disparities that have always characterized democratic
governance.
Turning to gender, this gives us a new perspective on why Lucy Parsons,
Emma Goldman, and other women argued that the demand for womenâs
suffrage was missing the point. Why would anyone reject the option to
participate in electoral politics, imperfect as it is? The short answer
is that they wanted to abolish government entirely, not to make it more
participatory. But looking closer, we can find some more specific
reasons why people concerned with womenâs liberation might be suspicious
of the franchise.
âThe history of the political activities of men proves that they have
given him absolutely nothing that he could not have achieved in a more
direct, less costly, and more lasting manner. As a matter of fact, every
inch of ground he has gained has been through a constant fight, a
ceaseless struggle for self-assertion, and not through suffrage. There
is no reason whatever to assume that woman, in her climb to
emancipation, has been, or will be, helped by the ballot.â
â Emma Goldman, âWomen Suffrageâ
Letâs go back to polis and oikosâthe city and the household. Democratic
systems rely on a formal distinction between public and private spheres;
the public sphere is the site of all legitimate decision-making, while
the private sphere is excluded or discounted. Throughout a wide range of
societies and eras, this division has been profoundly gendered, with men
dominating public spheresâownership, paid labor, government, management,
and street cornersâwhile women and those outside the gender binary have
been relegated to private spheres: the household, the kitchen, the
family, child-rearing, sex work, care work, other forms of invisible and
unpaid labor.
Insofar as democratic systems centralize decision-making power and
authority in the public sphere, this reproduces patriarchal patterns of
power. This is most obvious when women are formally excluded from voting
and politicsâbut even where they are not, they often face informal
obstacles in the public sphere while bearing disproportionate
responsibility in the private sphere.
The inclusion of more participants in the public sphere serves to
further legitimize a space where women and those who do not conform to
gender norms operate at a disadvantage. If âdemocratizationâ means a
shift in decision-making power from informal and private sites towards
more public political spaces, the result could even erode some forms of
womenâs power. Recall how grassroots womenâs shelters founded in the
1970s were professionalized through state funding to such an extent that
by the 1990s, the women who had founded them could never have qualified
for entry-level positions in them.
So we cannot rely on the degree of womenâs formal participation in the
public sphere as an index of liberation. Instead, we can deconstruct the
gendered distinction between public and private, validating what takes
place in relationships, families, households, neighborhoods, social
networks, and other spaces that are not recognized as part of the
political sphere. This wouldnât mean formalizing these spaces or
integrating them into a supposedly gender-neutral political practice,
but rather legitimizing multiple ways of making decisions, recognizing
multiple sites of power within society.
There are two ways to respond to male domination of the political
sphere. The first is to try to make the formal public space as
accessible and inclusive as possibleâfor example, by registering women
to vote, providing child care, setting quotas of who must participate in
decisions, weighting who is permitted to speak in discussions, or even,
as in Rojava, establishing women-only assemblies with veto power. This
strategy seeks to implement equality, but it still assumes that all
power should be vested in the public sphere. The alternative is to
identify sites and practices of decision-making that already empower
people who do not benefit from male privilege, and grant them greater
influence. This approach draws on longstanding feminist traditions that
prioritize peopleâs lives and experiences over formal structures and
ideologies, recognizing the importance of diversity and valuing
dimensions of life that are usually invisible.
These two approaches can coincide and complement each other, but only if
we dispense with the idea that all legitimacy should be concentrated in
a single institutional structure.
There are several objections to the idea that decision-making structures
should be voluntary rather than obligatory, decentralized rather than
monolithic. Weâre told that without a central mechanism for deciding
conflicts, society will degrade into civil war; that it is impossible to
defend against centralized aggressors without a central authority; that
we need the apparatus of central government to deal with oppression and
injustice.
In fact, the centralization of power is as likely to provoke strife as
to resolve it. When everyone has to gain leverage on the structures of
the state to obtain any control over the conditions of her own life,
this is bound to generate friction. In Israel/Palestine, India/Pakistan,
and other places where people of a variety of religions and ethnicities
had coexisted autonomously in relative peace, the colonially imposed
imperative to contend for political power within the framework of a
single state produced protracted ethnic violence. Such conflicts were
common in 19th century US politics, as wellâconsider the early gang
warfare around elections in Washington and Baltimore, or the fight for
Bleeding Kansas. If these struggles are no longer common in the US,
thatâs not evidence that the state has resolved all the conflicts it
generated.
Centralized government, touted as a way to conclude disputes, just
consolidates power so the victors can maintain their position through
force of arms. And when centralized structures collapse, as Yugoslavia
did during the introduction of democracy in the 1990s, the consequences
can be bloody indeed. At best, centralization only postpones strifeâlike
a debt accumulating interest.
But can decentralized networks stand a chance against centralized power
structures? If they canât, then the whole discussion is moot, as any
attempt to experiment with decentralization will be crushed by more
centralized rivals.
The answer remains to be seen, but todayâs centralized powers are by no
means sure of their own invulnerability. Already, in 2001, the RAND
Corporation was arguing that decentralized networks, rather than
centralized hierarchies, will be the power players of the 21st century.
Over the past two decades, from the so-called anti-globalization
movement to Occupy and the Kurdish experiment with autonomy in Rojava,
the initiatives that have succeeded in opening up space for new
experiments (both democratic and anarchistic) have been decentralized,
while more centralized efforts like Syriza have been co-opted almost
immediately. A wide range of scholars are now theorizing the
distinguishing features and advantages of network-based organizing.
Finally, there is the question of whether a society needs a centralized
political apparatus to be able to put a stop to oppression and
injustice. Abraham Lincolnâs first inaugural address, delivered in 1861
on the eve of the Civil War, is one of the strongest expressions of this
argument. Itâs worth quoting at length:
Plainly the central idea of secession is the essence of anarchy. A
majority held in restraint by constitutional checks and limitations, and
always changing easily with deliberate changes of popular opinions and
sentiments, is the only true sovereign of a free people. Whoever rejects
it does of necessity fly to anarchy or to despotism. Unanimity is
impossible. The rule of a minority, as a permanent arrangement, is
wholly inadmissible; so that, rejecting the majority principle, anarchy
or despotism in some form is all that is leftâŚ
Physically speaking, we cannot separate. We cannot remove our respective
sections from each other nor build an impassable wall between them. A
husband and wife may be divorced and go out of the presence and beyond
the reach of each other, but the different parts of our country cannot
do this. They cannot but remain face to face, and intercourse, either
amicable or hostile, must continue between them. Is it possible, then,
to make that intercourse more advantageous or more satisfactory after
separation than before? Can aliens make treaties easier than friends can
make laws? Can treaties be more faithfully enforced between aliens than
laws can among friends? Suppose you go to war, you cannot fight always;
and when, after much loss on both sides and no gain on either, you cease
fighting, the identical old questions, as to terms of intercourse, are
again upon you.
This country, with its institutions, belongs to the people who inhabit
it. Whenever they shall grow weary of the existing Government, they can
exercise their constitutional right of amending it or their
revolutionary right to dismember or overthrow it.
Follow this logic far enough in todayâs globalized world and you arrive
at the idea of world government: majority rule on the scale of the
entire planet. Lincoln is right, contra partisans of consensus, that
unanimous rule is impossible and that those who do not wish to be ruled
by majorities must choose between despotism and anarchy. His argument
that aliens cannot make treaties more easily than friends make laws
sounds convincing at first. But friends donât enforce laws on each
otherâlaws are made to be imposed on weaker parties, whereas treaties
are made between equals. Government is not something that takes place
between friends, any more than a free people need a sovereign. If we
have to choose between despotism, majority rule, and anarchy, anarchy is
the closest thing to freedomâwhat Lincoln calls our ârevolutionary
rightâ to overthrow governments.
Yet, in associating anarchy with the secession of the Southern states,
Lincoln was mounting a critique of autonomy that echoes to this day. If
it werenât for the Federal government, the argument goes, slavery would
never have been abolished, nor would the South have desegregated or
granted civil rights to people of color. These measures against
injustice had to be introduced at gunpoint by the armies of the Union
and, a century later, the National Guard. In this context, advocating
decentralization seems to mean accepting slavery, segregation, and the
Ku Klux Klan. Without a legitimate central governing body, what
mechanism could stop people from acting oppressively?
There are several errors here. The first mistake is obvious: of
Lincolnâs three optionsâdespotism, majority rule, and anarchyâthe
secessionists represented despotism, not anarchy. Likewise, it is naĂŻve
to imagine that the apparatus of central government will be employed
solely on the side of freedom. The same National Guard that oversaw
integration in the South used live ammunition to put down black
uprisings around the country; today, there are nearly as many black
people in US prisons as there once were slaves in the US. Finally, one
need not vest all legitimacy in a single governing body in order to act
against oppression. One may still actâone must simply do so without the
pretext of enforcing law.
Opposing the centralization of power and legitimacy does not mean
withdrawing into quietism. Some conflicts must take place; there is no
getting around them. They follow from truly irreconcilable differences,
and the imposition of a false unity only defers them. In his inaugural
address, Lincoln was pleading in the name of the state to suspend the
conflict between abolitionists and partisans of slaveryâa conflict that
was inevitable and necessary, which had already been delayed through
decades of intolerable compromise. Meanwhile, abolitionists like Nat
Turner and John Brown were able to act decisively without need of a
central political authorityâindeed, they were able to act thus only
because they did not recognize one. Were it not for the pressure
generated by autonomous actions like theirs, the federal government
would never have intervened in the South; had more people taken the
initiative the way they did, slavery would not have been possible and
the Civil War would not have been necessary.
In other words, the problem was not too much anarchy, but too little. It
was autonomous action that forced the issue of slavery, not democratic
deliberation. Whatâs more, had there been more partisans of anarchy,
rather than majority rule, it would not have been possible for Southern
whites to regain political supremacy in the South after Reconstruction.
One more anecdote bears mention. A year after his inaugural speech,
Lincoln addressed a committee of free men of color to argue that they
should emigrate to found another colony like Liberia in hopes that the
rest of black America would follow. Regarding the relation between
emancipated black people and white American citizens, he argued,
It is better for us both to be separated⌠There is an unwillingness on
the part of our people, harsh as it may be, for you free colored people
to remain with us.
So, in Lincolnâs political cosmology, the polis of white citizens cannot
separate, but as soon as the black slaves of the oikos no longer occupy
their economic role, it is better that they depart. This dramatizes
things clearly enough: the nation is indivisible, but the excluded are
disposable. Had the slaves freed after the Civil War emigrated to
Africa, they would have arrived just in time to experience the horrors
of European colonization, with a death toll of ten million in Belgian
Congo alone. The proper solution to such catastrophes is not to
integrate all the world into a single republic governed by majority
rule, but to combat all institutions that divide people into majorities
and minoritiesârulers and ruledâhowever democratic they might be.
Barring war or miracle, the legitimacy of every constituted government
is always eroding; it can only erode. Whatever the state promises,
nothing can compensate for having to cede control of our lives. Every
specific grievance underscores this systemic problem, though we rarely
see the forest for the trees.
This is where democracy comes in: another election, another government,
another cycle of optimism and disappointment.
âDemocracy is a great way of assuring the legitimacy of the government,
even when it does a bad job of delivering what the public wants. In a
functioning democracy, mass protests challenge the rulers. They donât
challenge the fundamental nature of the stateâs political system.â
â Noah Feldman, âTunisiaâs Protests Are Different This Timeâ
But this does not always pacify the population. The past decade has seen
movements and uprisings all around the worldâfrom Oaxaca to Tunis,
Istanbul to Rio de Janeiro, Kiev to Hong Kongâin which the disillusioned
and disaffected attempt to take matters into their own hands. Most of
these have rallied around the standard of more and better democracy,
though that has hardly been unanimous.
Considering how much power the market and the government wield over us,
itâs tempting indeed to imagine that we could somehow turn the tables
and govern them. Even those who do not believe that it is possible for
the people to rule the government usually end up governing the one thing
that is left to themâtheir resistance to it. Approaching protest
movements as experiments in direct democracy, they set out to prefigure
the structures of a more democratic world.
But what if prefiguring democracy is part of the problem? That would
explain why so few of these movements have been able to mount an
irreconcilable opposition to the structures that they formed to oppose.
With the arguable exceptions of Chiapas and Rojava, all of them have
been defeated (Occupy), reintegrated into the functioning of the
prevailing government (Syriza, Podemos), or, worse still, have
overthrown and replaced that government without achieving any real
change in society (Tunisia, Egypt, Libya, Ukraine).
When a movement seeks to legitimize itself on the basis of the same
principles as state democracy, it ends up trying to beat the state at
its own game. Even if it succeeds, the reward for victory is to be
coopted and institutionalizedâwhether within the existing structures of
government or by reinventing them anew. Thus movements that begin as
revolts against the state end up recreating it.
âOccasionally you rebel, but itâs only ever just to start doing the same
thing again from scratch.â
â Albert Libertad, âVoters: You Are the Real Criminalsâ
This can play out in many different ways. There are movements that
hamstring themselves by claiming to be more democratic, more
transparent, or more representative than the authorities; movements that
come to power through electoral politics, only to betray their original
goals; movements that promote directly democratic tactics that turn out
to be just as useful to those who seek state power; and movements that
topple governments, only to replace them. Letâs consider each in turn.
If we limit our movements to what the majority of participants can agree
on in advance, we may not be able to get them off the ground in the
first place. When much of the population has accepted the legitimacy of
the government and its laws, most people donât feel entitled to do
anything that could challenge the existing power structure, no matter
how badly it treats them. Consequently, a movement that makes decisions
by majority vote or consensus may have difficulty agreeing to utilize
any but the most symbolic tactics. Can you imagine the residents of
Ferguson, Missouri holding a consensus meeting to decide whether to burn
the QuikTrip store and fight off the police? And yet those were the
actions that sparked what came to be known as the Black Lives Matter
movement. People usually have to experience something new to be open to
it; it is a mistake to confine an entire movement to what is already
familiar to the majority of participants.
By the same token, if we insist on our movements being completely
transparent, that means letting the authorities dictate which tactics we
can use. In conditions of widespread infiltration and surveillance,
conducting all decision-making in public with complete transparency
invites repression on anyone who is perceived as a threat to the status
quo. The more public and transparent a decision-making body is, the more
conservative its actions are likely to be, even when this contradicts
its express reason for beingâthink of all the environmental coalitions
that have never taken a single step to halt the activities that cause
climate change. Within democratic logic, it makes sense to demand
transparency from the government, as it is supposed to represent and
answer to the people. But outside that logic, rather than demanding that
participants in social movements represent and answer to each other, we
should seek to maximize the autonomy with which they may act.
If we claim legitimacy on the grounds that we represent the public, we
offer the authorities an easy way to outmaneuver us, while opening the
way for others to coopt our efforts. Before the introduction of
universal suffrage, it was possible to maintain that a movement
represented the will of the people; but nowadays an election can draw
more people to the polls than even the most massive movement can
mobilize into the streets. The winners of elections will always be able
to claim to represent more people than can participate in movements.[13]
Likewise, movements purporting to represent the most oppressed sectors
of society can be outflanked by the inclusion of token representatives
of those sectors in the halls of power. And as long as we validate the
idea of representation, some new politician or party can use our
rhetoric to come to power. We should not claim that we represent the
peopleâwe should assert that no one has the right to rule us.
What happens when a movement comes to power through electoral politics?
The victory of Lula and his Workersâ Party in Brazil seemed to present a
best-case scenario in which a party based in grassroots radical
organizing took the helm of the state. At the time, Brazil hosted some
of the worldâs most powerful social movements, including the
1.5-million-strong land reform campaign MST (Landless Workersâ
Movement); many of these were interconnected with the Workersâ Party.
Yet after Lula took office in 2002, social movements entered a
precipitous decline that lasted until 2013. Members of the Workersâ
Party dropped out of local organizing to take positions in the
government, while the necessities of realpolitik prevented Lula from
granting concessions to the movements he had previously supported. The
MST had forced the conservative government that preceded Lula to
legalize many land occupations, but it made no headway whatsoever under
Lula. This pattern recurred all around Latin America as supposedly
radical politicians betrayed the social movements that had put them in
office. Today, the most powerful social movements in Brazil are
right-wing protests against the Workersâ Party. There are no electoral
shortcuts to freedom.
What if instead of seeking state power, we focus on promoting directly
democratic models such as neighborhood assemblies? Unfortunately, such
practices can be appropriated to serve a wide range of agendas. After
the Slovenian uprising of 2012, while self-organized neighborhood
assemblies continued to meet in Ljubljana, an NGO financed by the city
authorities began organizing assemblies in a âneglectedâ neighborhood as
a pilot project towards ârevitalizingâ the area, with the explicit
intention of drawing disaffected citizens back into dialogue with the
government. During the Ukrainian revolution of 2014, the fascist parties
Svoboda and Right Sector came to prominence via the democratic
assemblies in the occupied Maidan. In 2009, members of the Greek fascist
party Golden Dawn joined locals in the Athenian neighborhood of Agios
Panteleimonas in organizing an assembly that coordinated attacks on
immigrants and anarchists. If we want to foster inclusivity and
self-determination, it is not enough to propagate the rhetoric and
procedures of participatory democracy.[14] We need to spread a framework
that opposes the state and other forms of hierarchical power in and of
themselves.
Even explicitly revolutionary strategies can be turned to the advantage
of world powers in the name of democracy. From Venezuela to Macedonia,
we have seen state actors and vested interests channel genuine popular
dissent into ersatz social movements in order to shorten the electoral
cycle. Usually, the goal is to force the ruling party to resign in order
to replace it with a more âdemocraticâ governmentâi.e., a government
more amenable to US or EU objectives. Such movements usually focus on
âcorruption,â implying that the system would work just fine if only the
right people were in power. When we enter the streets, rather than risk
being the dupes of some foreign policy initiative, we should not
mobilize against any particular government, but against government per
se.
The Egyptian revolution dramatically illustrates the dead end of
democratic revolution. After hundreds had given their lives to overthrow
dictator Hosni Mubarak and institute democracy, popular elections
brought another autocrat to power in the person of Mohamed Morsi. A year
later, in 2013, nothing had improved, and the people who had initiated
the revolution took to the streets once more to reject the results of
democracy, forcing the Egyptian military to depose Morsi. Today, the
military remains the de facto ruler of Egypt, and the same oppression
and injustice that inspired two revolutions continues. The options
represented by the military, Morsi, and the people in revolt are the
same ones that Lincoln described in his inaugural speech: tyranny,
majority rule, and anarchy.
Here, at the furthest limit of the struggle against poverty and
oppression, we always come up against the state itself. As long as we
submit to being governed, the state will shift back and forth as needed
between majority rule and tyrannyâtwo expressions of the same basic
principle. The state can assume many shapes; like vegetation, it can die
back, then regrow from the roots. It can take the form of a monarchy or
a parliamentary democracy, a revolutionary dictatorship or a provisional
council; when the authorities have fled and the military has mutinied,
the state can linger as a germ carried by the partisans of order and
protocol in an apparently horizontal general assembly. All of these
forms, however democratic, can regenerate into a regime capable of
crushing freedom and self-determination.
The one sure way to avoid cooptation, manipulation, and opportunism is
to refuse to legitimize any form of rule. When people solve their
problems and meet their needs directly through flexible, horizontal,
decentralized structures, there are no leaders to corrupt, no formal
structures to ossify, no single process to hijack. Do away with the
concentrations of power and those who wish to seize power can get no
purchase on society. An ungovernable people will likely have to defend
itself against would-be tyrants, but it will never put its own strength
behind their efforts to rule.
The classic defense of democracy is that it is the worst form of
governmentâexcept for all the others. But if government itself is the
problem, we have to go back to the drawing board.
Reimagining humanity without government is an ambitious project; two
centuries of anarchist theory only scratch the surface. For the purposes
of this analysis, weâll conclude with a few basic values that could
guide us beyond democracy, and a few general proposals for how to
understand what we might do instead of governing. Most of the work
remains to be done.
âAnarchism represents not the most radical form of democracy, but an
altogether different paradigm of collective action.â
â Uri Gordon, Anarchy Alive!
Under scrutiny, democracy does not live up to the values that drew us to
it in the first placeâegalitarianism, inclusivity, self-determination.
Alongside these values, we must add horizontality, decentralization, and
autonomy as their indispensible counterparts.
Horizontality has gained a lot of currency since the late 20th century.
Starting with the Zapatista uprising and gaining momentum through the
anti-globalization movement and the rebellion in Argentina, the idea of
leaderless structures has spread even into the business world.
But decentralization is just as important as horizontality if we do not
wish to be trapped in a tyranny of equals, in which everyone has to be
able to agree on something for anyone to be able to do it. Rather than a
single process through which all agency must pass, decentralization
means multiple sites of decision-making and multiple forms of
legitimacy. That way, when power is distributed unevenly in one context,
this can be counterbalanced elsewhere. Decentralization means preserving
differenceâstrategic and ideological diversity is a source of strength
for movements and communities, just as biodiversity is in the natural
world. We should neither segregate ourselves into homogenous groups on
the pretext of affinity nor reduce our politics to lowest common
denominators.
Decentralization implies autonomyâthe ability to act freely on oneâs own
initiative. Autonomy can apply at any level of scaleâa single person, a
neighborhood, a movement, an entire region. To be free, you need control
over your immediate surroundings and the details of your daily life; the
more self-sufficient you are, the more secure your autonomy is. This
neednât mean meeting all your needs independently; it could also mean
the kind of interdependence that gives you leverage on the people you
depend on. No single institution should be able to monopolize access to
resources or social relations. A society that promotes autonomy requires
what an engineer would call redundancy: a wide range of options and
possibilities in every aspect of life.
If we wish to foster freedom, itâs not enough to affirm autonomy
alone.[15] A nation-state or political party can assert autonomy; so can
nationalists and racists. The fact that a person or group is autonomous
tells us little about whether the relations they cultivate with others
are egalitarian or hierarchical, inclusive or exclusive. If we wish to
maximize autonomy for everyone rather than simply seeking it for
ourselves, we have to create a social context in which no one is able to
accumulate institutional power over anyone else.
We have to create anarchy.
Institutions exist to serve us, not the other way around. They have no
inherent claim on our obedience. We should never invest them with more
legitimacy than our own needs and desires. When our wishes conflict with
othersâ wishes, we can see if an institutional process can produce a
solution that satisfies everyone; but as soon as we accord an
institution the right to adjudicate our conflicts or dictate our
decisions, we have abdicated our freedom.
This is not a critique of a particular organizational model, or an
argument for âinformalâ structures over âformalâ ones. Rather, it
demands that we treat all models as provisionalâthat we ceaselessly
reappraise and reinvent them. Where Thomas Paine wanted to enthrone the
law as king, where Rousseau theorized the social contract and more
recent enthusiasts of capitalism Ăźber alles dream of a society based on
contracts alone, we counter that when relations are truly in the best
interests of all participants, there is no need for laws or contracts.
Likewise, this is not an argument in favor of mere individualism, nor of
treating relationships as expendable, nor of organizing only with those
who share oneâs preferences. In a crowded, interdependent world, we
canât afford to refuse to coexist or coordinate with others. The point
is simply that we must not seek to legislate relations.
Instead of deferring to a blueprint or protocol, we can evaluate
institutions on an ongoing basis: Do they reward cooperationâor
contention? Do they distribute agencyâor create bottlenecks of power? Do
they offer each participant the opportunity to fulfill her potential on
her own termsâor impose external imperatives? Do they facilitate the
resolution of conflict on mutually agreeable termsâor punish all who run
afoul of a codified system?
âHe expressed himself to us that we should never allow ourselves to be
tempted by any consideration to acknowledge laws and institutions to
exist as of right if our conscience and reason condemned them. He
admonished us not to care whether a majority, no matter how large,
opposed our principles and opinions; the largest majorities were
sometimes only organized mobs.â
â August Bondi, writing about John Brown
In place of formal sites of centralized decision-making, we propose a
variety of spaces of encounter where people may open themselves to each
otherâs influence and find others who share their priorities. Encounter
means mutual transformation: establishing common points of reference,
common concerns. The space of encounter is not a representative body
vested with the authority to make decisions for others, nor a governing
body employing majority rule or consensus. It is an opportunity for
people to experiment with acting in different configurations on a
voluntary basis.
The spokescouncil immediately preceding the demonstrations against the
2001 Free Trade Area of the Americas summit in Quebec City was a classic
space of encounter. This meeting brought together a wide range of
autonomous groups that had converged from around the world to protest
the FTAA. Rather than attempting to make binding decisions, the
participants introduced the initiatives that their groups had prepared
and coordinated for mutual benefit wherever possible. Much of the
decision-making occurred afterwards in informal intergroup discussions.
By this means, thousands of people were able to synchronize their
actions without need of central leadership, without giving the police
much insight into the wide array of plans that were to unfold. Had the
spokescouncil employed an organizational model intended to produce unity
and centralization, the participants could have spent the entire night
fruitlessly arguing about goals, strategy, and which tactics to allow.
Most of the social movements of the past two decades have been hybrid
models juxtaposing spaces of encounter with some form of democracy. In
Occupy, for example, the encampments served as open-ended spaces of
encounter, while the general assemblies were formally intended to
function as directly democratic decision-making bodies. Most of those
movements achieved their greatest effects because the encounters they
facilitated opened up opportunities for autonomous action, not because
they centralized group activity through direct democracy.[16] If we
approach the encounter as the driving force of these movements, rather
than as a raw material to be shaped through democratic process, it might
help us to prioritize what we do best.
Anarchists frustrated by the contradictions of democratic discourse have
sometimes withdrawn to organize themselves according to preexisting
affinity alone. Yet segregation breeds stagnation and fractiousness. It
is better to organize on the basis of our conditions and needs so we
come into contact with all the others who share them. Only when we
understand ourselves as nodes within dynamic collectivities, rather than
discrete entities possessed of static interests, can we make sense of
the rapid metamorphoses that people undergo in the course of experiences
like the Occupy movementâand the tremendous power of the encounter to
transform us if we open ourselves to it.
If no institution, contract, or law should be able to dictate our
decisions, how do we agree on what responsibilities we have towards each
other?
Some have suggested a distinction between âclosedâ groups, in which the
participants agree to answer to each other for their actions, and âopenâ
groups that need not reach consensus. But this begs the question: how do
we draw a line between the two? If we are accountable to our fellows in
a closed group only until we choose to leave it, and we may leave at any
time, that is little different from participating in an open group. At
the same time, we are all involved, like it or not, in one closed group
sharing a single inescapable space: earth. So it is not a question of
distinguishing the spaces in which we must be accountable to each other
from the spaces in which we may act freely. The question is how to
foster both responsibility and autonomy at every order of scale.
Towards this end, we set out to create mutually fulfilling
collectivities at each level of societyâspaces in which people identify
with each other and have cause to do right by each other. These can take
many forms, from housing cooperatives and neighborhood assemblies to
international networks. At the same time, we recognize that we will have
to reconfigure them continuously according to how much intimacy and
interdependence proves beneficial for the participants. When a
configuration must change, this need not be a sign of failure: on the
contrary, it shows that the participants are not competing for hegemony.
Instead of treating group decision-making as a pursuit of unanimity, we
can approach it as a space for differences to arise, conflicts to play
out, and transformations to occur as different social constellations
converge and diverge. Disagreeing and dissociating can be just as
desirable as reaching agreement, provided they occur for the right
reasons; the advantages of organizing in larger numbers should suffice
to discourage people from fracturing gratuitously.
Our institutions should help us to tease out differences, not suppress
or submerge them. Some witnesses returning from Rojava report that when
an assembly there cannot reach consensus, it splits into two bodies,
dividing its resources between them. If this is true, it offers a model
of voluntary association that is a vast improvement on the Procrustean
unity of democracy.
Sometimes dividing into separate groups isnât enough to resolve
conflicts. To dispense with centralized coercion, we have to come up
with new ways of addressing strife. Conflicts between those who oppose
the state are one of the chief assets that preserve its supremacy.[17]
If we want to create spaces of freedom, we must not become so fractured
that we canât defend those spaces, and we must not resolve conflicts in
a way that creates new power imbalances.
One of the most basic functions of democracy is to offer a way of
concluding disputes. Voting, courts, and police all serve to decide
conflicts without necessarily resolving them; the rule of law
effectively imposes a winner-take-all model for addressing differences.
By centralizing force, a strong state is able to compel feuding parties
to suspend hostilities even on mutually unacceptable terms. This enables
it to suppress forms of strife that interfere with its control, such as
class warfare, while fostering forms of conflict that undermine
horizontal and autonomous resistance, such as gang warfare. We cannot
understand the religious and ethnic violence of our time without
factoring in the ways that state structures provoke and exacerbate it.
When we accord institutions inherent legitimacy, this offers us an
excuse not to resolve conflicts, relying instead on the intercession of
the state. It gives us an alibi to conclude disputes by force and to
exclude those who are structurally disadvantaged. Rather than taking the
initiative to work things out directly, we end up jockeying for power.
If we donât recognize the authority of the state, we have no such
excuses: we must find mutually satisfying resolutions or else suffer the
consequences of ongoing strife. This gives us an incentive to take all
partiesâ needs and perceptions seriously, to develop skills with which
to defuse tension. It isnât necessary to get everyone to agree, but we
have to find ways to differ that do not produce hierarchies, oppression,
pointless antagonism. The first step down this road is to remove the
incentives that the state offers not to resolve conflict.
Unfortunately, many of the models of conflict resolution that once
served human communities are now lost to us, forcibly replaced by the
court systems of ancient Athens and Rome. We can look to experimental
models of transformative justice for a glimpse of the alternatives we
will have to develop.
Envisioning what a horizontal and decentralized society might look like,
we can imagine overlapping networks of collectives and assemblies in
which people organize to meet their daily needsâfood, shelter, medical
care, work, recreation, discussion, companionship. Being interdependent,
they would have good reason to settle disputes amicably, but no one
could force anyone else to remain in an arrangement that was unhealthy
or unfulfilling. In response to threats, they would mobilize in larger
ad hoc formations, drawing on connections with other communities around
the world.
In fact, a great many stateless societies have looked something like
this in the course of human history. Today. models like this continue to
appear at the intersections of indigenous, feminist, and anarchist
traditions.
âThe principle that the majority have a right to rule the minority,
practically resolves all government into a mere contest between two
bodies of men, as to which of them shall be masters, and which of them
slaves; a contest, thatâhowever bloodyâcan, in the nature of things,
never be finally closed, so long as man refuses to be a slave.â
â Lysander Spooner, No Treason
That brings us back to our starting placeâto modern-day Athens, Greece.
In the city where democracy first came of age, thousands of people now
organize themselves under anarchist banners in horizontal, decentralized
networks. In place of the exclusivity of ancient Athenian citizenship,
their structures are extensive and open-ended; they welcome migrants
fleeing the war in Syria, for they know that their experiment in freedom
must grow or perish. In place of the coercive apparatus of government,
they seek to maintain a decentralized distribution of power reinforced
by a collective commitment to solidarity. Rather than uniting to impose
majority rule, they cooperate to prevent the possibility of rule itself.
This is not an outdated way of life, but the end of a long error.
Letâs return to the high point of the uprisings. Thousands of us flood
into the streets, finding each other in new formations that offer an
unfamiliar and exhilarating sense of agency. Suddenly everything
intersects: words and deeds, ideas and sensations, personal stories and
world events. Certaintyâfinally, we feel at homeâand uncertainty:
finally, an open horizon. Together, we discover ourselves capable of
things we never imagined.
What is beautiful about such moments transcends any political system.
The conflicts are as essential as the flashes of unexpected consensus.
This is not the functioning of democracy, but the experience of
freedomâof collectively taking our destinies in our hands. No set of
procedures could institutionalize this. It is a prize we must wrest from
the jaws of habit and history again and again.
Next time a window of opportunity opens, rather than reinventing âreal
democracyâ yet again, let our goal be freedom, freedom itself.
[1] âI am truly free only when all human beings, men and women, are
equally free. The freedom of others, far from negating or limiting my
freedom, is, on the contrary, its necessary premise and confirmation.â
âMikhail Bakunin
[2] This seeming paradox didnât trouble the framers of the US
Constitution because the minority whose rights they were chiefly
concerned with protecting was the class of property ownersâwho already
had plenty of leverage on state institutions. As James Madison said in
1787, âOur government ought to secure the permanent interests of the
country against innovation. Landholders ought to have a share in the
government, to support these invaluable interests, and to balance and
check the other. They ought to be so constituted as to protect the
minority of the opulent against the majority.â
[3] In this context, arguing that âthe personal is politicalâ
constitutes a feminist rejection of the dichotomy between oikos and
polis. But if this argument is understood to mean that the personal,
too, should be subject to democratic decision-making, it only extends
the logic of government into additional aspects of life. The real
alternative is to affirm multiple sites of power, arguing that
legitimacy should not be confined to any one space, so decisions made in
the household are not subordinated to those made in the sites of formal
politics.
[4] This is a fundamental paradox of democratic governments: established
by a crime, they sanctify lawâlegitimizing a new ruling order as the
fulfillment and continuation of a revolt.
[5] âObedience to the law is true liberty,â reads one memorial to the
soldiers who suppressed Shayâs Rebellion.
[6] Just as the âlibertarianâ capitalist suspects that the activities of
even the most democratic government interfere with the pure functioning
of the free market, the partisan of pure democracy can be sure that as
long as there are economic inequalities, the wealthy will always wield
disproportionate influence over even the most carefully constructed
democratic process. Yet government and economy are inseparable. The
market relies upon the state to enforce property rights, while at
bottom, democracy is a means of transferring, amalgamating, and
investing political power: it is a market for agency itself.
[7] The objection that the democracies that govern the world today
arenât real democracies is a variant of the classic âNo true Scotsmanâ
fallacy. If, upon investigation, it turns out that not a single existing
democracy lives up to what you mean by the word, you might need a
different expression for what you are trying to describe. This is like
communists who, confronted with all the repressive communist regimes of
the 20th century, protest that not a single one of them was properly
communist. When an idea is so difficult to implement that millions of
people equipped with a considerable portion of the resources of humanity
and doing their best across a period of centuries canât produce a single
working model, itâs time to go back to the drawing board. Give
anarchists a tenth of the opportunities Marxists and democrats have had,
and then we may speak about whether anarchy works!
[8] Without formal institutions, democratic organizations often enforce
decisions by delegitimizing actions initiated outside their structures
and encouraging the use of force against them. Hence the classic scene
in which protest marshals attack demonstrators for doing something that
wasnât agreed upon in advance via a centralized democratic process.
[9] In theory, categories that are defined by exclusion, like
citizenship, break down when we expand them to include the whole world.
But if we wish to break them down, why not reject them outright, rather
than promising to do so while further legitimizing them? When we use the
word citizenship to describe something desirable, that canât help but
reinforce the legitimacy of that institution as it exists today.
[10] In fact, the English word âpoliceâ is derived from polis by way of
the ancient Greek word for citizen.
[11] See Kantâs argument that a republic is âviolence with freedom and
law,â whereas anarchy is âfreedom and law without violenceââso the law
becomes a mere recommendation that cannot be enforced.
[12] This far, at least, we can agree with Booker T. Washington when he
said, âThe Reconstruction experiment in racial democracy failed because
it began at the wrong end, emphasizing political means and civil rights
acts rather than economic means and self-determination.â
[13] At the end of May 1968, the announcement of snap elections broke
the wave of wildcat strikes and occupations that had swept across
France; the spectacle of the majority of French citizens voting for
President de Gaulleâs party was enough to dispel all hope of revolution.
This illustrates how elections serve as a pageantry that represents
citizens to each other as willing participants in the prevailing order.
[14] As economic crises intensify alongside widespread disillusionment
with representational politics, we see governments offering more direct
participation in decision-making to pacify the public. Just as the
dictatorships in Greece, Spain, and Chile were forced to transition into
democratic governments to neutralize protest movements, the state is
opening up new roles for those who might otherwise lead the opposition
to it. If we are directly responsible for making the political system
work, we will blame ourselves when it failsânot the format itself. This
explains the new experiments with âparticipatoryâ budgets from PĂ´rto
Alegre to PoznaĹ. In practice, the participants rarely have any leverage
on town officials; at most, they can act as consultants, or vote on a
measly 0.1% of city funds. The real purpose of participatory budgeting
is to redirect popular attention from the failures of government to the
project of making it more democratic.
[15] âAutonomyâ is derived from the ancient Greek prefix auto-, self,
and nomos, lawâgiving oneself oneâs own law. This suggests an
understanding of personal freedom in which one aspect of the selfâsay,
the superegoâpermanently controls the others and dictates all behavior.
Kant defined autonomy as self-legislation, in which the individual
compels himself to comply with the universal laws of objective morality
rather than acting according his desires. By contrast, an anarchist
might counter that we owe our freedom to the spontaneous interplay of
myriad forces within us, not to our capacity to force a single order
upon ourselves. Which of those conceptions of freedom we embrace will
have repercussions on everything from how we picture freedom on a
planetary scale to how we understand the movements of subatomic
particles.
[16] Many of the decisions that gave Occupy Oakland a greater impact
than other Occupy encampments, including the refusal to negotiate with
the city government and the militant reaction to the first eviction,
were the result of autonomous initiatives, not consensus process.
Meanwhile, some occupiers interpreted consensus process as a sort of
decentralized legal framework in which any action undertaken by any
participant in the occupation should require the consent of every other
participant. As one participant recalls, âOne of the first times the
police tried to enter the camp at Occupy Oakland, they were immediately
surrounded and shouted at by a group of about twenty people. Some other
people werenât happy about this. The most vocal of these pacifists
placed himself in front of those confronting the police, crossed his
forearms in the X that symbolizes strong disagreement in the sign
language of consensus process, and said âYou canât do this! I block
you!â For him, consensus was a tool of horizontal control, giving
everyone the right to suppress whichever of othersâ actions they found
disagreeable.â
[17] Witness the Mexican autodefensas who set out to defend themselves
against the cartels that are functionally identical with the government
in some parts of Mexico, only to end up in gang warfare against each
other.