💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › anarcho-economic-democracy-the-new-mutualism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 06:48:26. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Economic Democracy: The new mutualism? Author: Anarcho Date: December 2, 2010 Language: en Topics: democracy, economics, mutualism, book review Source: Retrieved on 1st February 2021 from https://anarchism.pageabode.com/?p=469
Allan Engler is a lifelong trade unionist and social activist. Some may
recognise his name from his 1995 book Apostles of Greed when he first
presented his critique of capitalism and his alternative. His new
booklet Economic Democracy: The Working-Class Alternative to Capitalism
expands on this vision, which he terms “Economic Democracy” but which
others would call market socialism. He argues as well as that it is “a
working-class alternative” and “practical.” “Humankind,” he rightly
suggests, “does not need a capitalist class.” (7)
There is much in the book that libertarians can agree. Capitalism is
“based on workplace dictatorship.” (15–6); “Letting the market decide”
is “a euphemism for letting capitalists decide” (18); “means of
livelihood that requires co-operative social labour” are “owned by
wealth-holding minorities who are entitled to direct these for private
profit” (12); “buying and consuming” are “consolations for enduring
workplace dictatorship” (40); everyone is “entitled to participate as
equals in social labour and in the direction of economic life” (45); he
rightly rejects the idea of the working class being “narrowly defined as
the industrial proletariat” (97); we do need to replace “capitalist
ownership with social ownership and master-servant relations with
workplace democracy.” (83)
These arguments, and others like them, will be familiar to libertarians.
The question is, is Economic Democracy really the working class
alternative to capitalism? In part, yes – but only because he repeats
longstanding libertarian positions.
Engler does give the impression that he is a recovering Marxist, keen to
salvage something from the orthodox Marxist tradition while, in fact,
being far closer to Proudhon. Like Proudhon’s mutualism, his system is
based on a market exchange of products created using socialised means of
production and the suggestion that “socially owned financial
institutions” would ensure that interest rates “will be kept low, no
more than the minimum required to encourage saving and to cover the
experience-rated risk of loss” (61) has obvious parallels with
Proudhon’s “Bank of the People.” Sadly, Engler does not discuss any
links with mutualism, but given that Proudhon is persona non grata in
most Marxist circles this is no surprise. Indeed, the orthodox Leninists
think nothing of invoking Proudhon to dismiss market socialism – which
would not be too bad, if they had some idea of what he advocated.
Ironically, Engler does mention Proudhon, quoting “property is theft” by
the “French radical.” He thinks Proudhon “exaggerated” and contrasts him
to Marx whom Engler argues “held that property began as the right of
people to the products of their own labour” while capitalism was the
right to appropriate others’ labour. Which was Proudhon’s position, not
Marx’s who was a communist and aimed (eventually) to end even that kind
of property. Proudhon’s ideas are also unknowingly repeated when Engler
writes: “If property is the right of people to the products of their own
labour, capital is legalised theft.” (15)
It is a shame that Engler was not more familiar with Proudhon, as he may
see the similarities in their ideas. This would have allowed him to
avoid inaccurate claims that Economic Democracy “could be called
communism or socialism, but both are now identified with state ownership
and top-down central command.” (46) It is hardly communism as it is
based on markets and money. It could be called socialism as mutualism is
(as Proudhon stressed) a form of socialism, a position most orthodox
Marxists would reject as they confuse markets with capitalism. As such,
Engler is right to note that markets have existed “long before
capitalism” (67) and that with self-employment “capitalism would not
exist.” (18) Proudhon made this point and one which Marx, when not
mocking him, echoed.
Economic Democracy, Engler argues, will “not turn the world upside down”
as “workers as a class have no interest in abolishing wage labour,
industry, technology, markets or global exchange.” (46) If his system
does socialise and democratise the workplace then it does abolish wage
labour, as Proudhon and Marx argued. From the context, it seems likely
that he means that economic democracy does not abolish distribution
according to deed (“the wages system”, to use Kropotkin’s term) but it
is a strange comment to make by someone so aware of socialist ideas. So
remember that Engler, like Proudhon at times, uses the term wage/salary
to refer to labour income.
Libertarian communists have always argued against mutualism is that it
ignores the negative pressures associated with market forces and so
members of the co-operatives would be forced to work longer, harder and
allocate more to investment than they would like in order to survive on
the market (some call this, inaccurately, “self-exploitation” or
“self-managed capitalism”). It also ties consumption to labour done
rather than need. As such, he is right to argue that the “capitalist
market is the problem, not the solution” (37) but he does not address
whether there are problems with markets per se which make them
problematic in achieving socialist goals.
Engler, like Proudhon, is aware of some of the problems, arguing that
“competitive drive to maximise profits pushes capitalist firms to
simultaneously increase production and cut employment and wages. It
pushes enterprises to exploit resources at unsustainable rates and to
externalise environmental costs.” (7) “Enterprises with higher profits,”
he notes, “gain control of additional supplies, technologies and
markets.” (13) This would still affect socialised workplaces operating
in a market environment. He acknowledges this by arguing that economic
democracy “does not mean workers will own enterprises.” Workers’
ownership under capitalism, he argues, “remains a form of private
competitive ownership that pushes worker-owners to focus on narrow
immediate interests” as well as “tying workers’ income to the rise and
fall of enterprise new revenues.” (47)
Communist-anarchists would agree with this yet Engler also argues that
prices would “continue to be regulated by market forces” (67), money
would “continue to measure exchange value” (68) and people would
“exchange the products of one’s labour.” (59) He does acknowledge that
“[n]one of that makes markets inherently benevolent. Forces of supply
and demand reflect, reproduce and aggregate existing entitlements and
disparities” (67) All true, but admitting this does not really address
why would workplaces in Economic Democracy not be in a similar situation
as ones under capitalism?
Engler is, I think, arguing that while workplaces would be run by their
workers, the actual wage-rate and the policies they follow would be set
by the community: “All inhabitants will be entitled to a voice and an
equal vote in their communities’ economic and political decisions.” (7)
Thus product prices are to be “set to cover labour costs at
democratically agreed wages and salaries” while certain commodities
(steel, petroleum, etc.) “will be set globally.” In general, though,
prices “will be determined within national, regional and local markets.”
(64) This makes sense only if we assume communities set wage-rates and
market prices reflect these socially set values. This explains why
workers are “entitled to bargain collectively and freely associate in
unions of their choice” and these will “negotiate wage rates” as unions
“may not always agree with the policies of communities.” (53)
Which raises the question of whether “the community” would be able to
regularly set wages based on a full understanding of all relevant
information for all workers. It is all fine and well proclaiming that
“[e]veryone who engages in providing goods or services for others” has
“a legitimate claim to a voice and equal vote in the direction of their
communities’ means of livelihood,” (47) it is another to think that they
will have the time and ability to do so all the time on all issues.
There needs to be a balance between community involvement and the
practicalities of so doing otherwise important decisions may end up
being delegated into a few hands. Mutualism and communist-anarchism
solve this issue by recognising the existence and importance of
functional groupings and their federation but Engler is somewhat vague
on this issue and what, precisely, should be discussed by whom and at
what level.
Also, while labour would be paid in money, Engler argues that the
specifics will be decided upon by workers and communities. Some “may opt
for equal pay while others choose income differentials” and so Economic
Democracy “does not ... mean that everyone will be paid the same.” (57)
Yet needs, as communist-anarchists have long argued, do not reflect the
ability to labour and we would be see welfare provision as in
capitalism. He also argues that, over time, people “would see no point
in being paid more or less than others. This is a vision of communism –
a society of equality and abundance – that inspired nineteenth-century
opponents of capitalism.” (57) While this vision of equal pay did
inspire some in the nineteenth-century (Proudhon, at times) it is hardly
“a vision of communism” as Marx would have argued!
Which raises the question of how people would get paid. Would it be from
the income received from selling their products? From a community fund?
Engler seems to suggest the former when he argues that
“[c]ommunity-owned enterprises will retain funds to maintain and renew
means of livelihood.” (61) In that case, how do you ensure that the
income of workers equals the community agreed amount? Would incomes be
supplemented by community allowances? And if income is directly related
to the income generated by selling the product of your labour then why
is Economic Democracy immune to the issues he raised about co-operatives
under capitalism having “narrow immediate interests”?
Proudhon recognised the need to regulate markets, including (like
Engler) the right for communities could “refuse credits or close
enterprises.” (53) Thus it is hardly alien to mutualism to argue, as
Engler does, that communities will “democratically regulate economic
activity” (83) and “deliberately and openly act to protect the interests
of their residents” against market forces. (68) However, his ideas on
socialisation meant free access to workplaces and an income based on
what your products earned in exchange. This seems more straightforward
than Engler’s scheme (although it does raise the issue of market forces
as Engler notes).
The issue of free access is an important one if you argue that workers
should get the full product of their labour (as Engler seems to). He
argues that as well as “socially owned” workplaces there would also be
“producer co-ops owned by all workers” which “could be intermediate
alternatives in enterprises employing a dozen or fewer” (60) and that
the “self-employed may own their tools, equipment and machinery. They
could lease land and buildings and claim title to improvements;
community ownership of land and commercial buildings will keep rents
low.” (59) Yet are not these individuals part of the community and so,
in theory, have free access to the socialised means of production? Would
the producer co-ops also have to pay rent? Is the “community” as the
landlord to which we pay rent that different from capitalism? So if
communities do “own social means of livelihood, land, resources,
building, plant, machinery and equipment” (61) it seems ironic to expect
members of said communities to have to pay to use them.
Interest payments will also be made, as “[w]age and salary workers and
the self-employed will defer spending, providing savings for
investments.” (61) This accepts the “loanable funds” theory from
capitalist economics which post-Keynesian economics have shown is an
invalid assumption (Proudhon would not have been surprised). It is also
surprising to read, given his critique of wage-labour, that “some labour
will be privately employed.” Yet, contradictory, he also argues that
these people “have the same rights to a voice and vote in directing
their labour time.” (60) What is it to be? If “most people in owning
communities will be wage and salary workers and all workers will have a
voice and vote in their communities’ decisions” (53) then why should
some be excluded from a say in their time working? Either you sell your
labour (and so have no say in how it used) or you do (in which case you
have not really sold it). This is glossed over.
Then there is ownership. He states he is against state ownership
(rightly so!) and for “social ownership” and “community ownership” (48)
yet also suggests that ownership could rest, in certain cases, with
“provinces or states” or “Federal or national governments” (48) and that
“Federal or national governments will provide most of the funding for
public services.” (50) He also suggests that ownership could rest with
“federations of autonomous national, regional or continental
enterprises.” (48) While the latter fits with social ownership (echoing
as it does Proudhon’s agro-industrial federation), the former is at odds
with opposition to state ownership.
This is something which needs to be clarified, particularly as the
modern state is not neutral and should be replaced (a la Proudhon) with
a federation of communes. This leads to another key issue, namely belief
that the democratic (capitalist) state could be utilised to abolish
capitalism. Engler states that “[a]rmed upheaval is inherently
incompatible with working class interests” (93) although there are
obvious counter-examples to this (compare Barcelona in 1936 to Berlin in
1933) and even mildly reformist regimes have suffered military coups. To
exclude (popular) insurrection is simply as untenable as fetishising it.
Instead Engler argues that the working class “will rely on workplace
organisation, community mobilisations and democratic political action.
The objective will be to transform capitalism into economic democracy
through gains and reforms.” His vision for social transformation
included union organising and raising income taxes. (83) However, it is
all fine and well to quote the Communist Manifesto on the need to “win
the battle of democracy” (85) but this has been tried and it simply
proven anarchists right. Proudhon’s argument that the state was
“inevitably enchained to capital and directed against the proletariat”
and so “it is of no use to change the holders of power or introduce some
variation into its workings” has been more than confirmed and social
democracy became as reformist as Bakunin predicted.
Engler does argue that social transformation “rests on workplace
organisation, community mobilisations and democratic electoral action.”
(98) No anarchist would deny that any social transformation requires the
first two, but surely we have had enough experiences of the last since
Marx imposed it on the First International to recognise that this will
never work? Why bother with electioneering if we organise outside of
parliament as he suggests? The vision Engler presents is the same one
Bakunin advocated against Marx: “Local labour councils, regional
federations and national congresses will aim to unite wage and salary
workers in all occupations with the unorganised, the marginalised and
the unemployed everywhere.” (103)
So while he, correctly, invokes the “mass direct action” of the IWW,
Industrial Syndicalist League, anarcho-syndicalists in Italy, Spain and
France who were “leading strikes and factory occupations” (88) he fails
to learn from their ideas. However, his arguments that unions “will
identify with their communities and humanity as well as their
occupations” and become “organisations of human solidarity” (103) are
correct, but again just repeating what anarchists were arguing in the
1860s. Equally, the idea that “communities will mobilise for democratic
control of resources, social employment and markets” (103) is one which
anarchists have long advocated.
His account of the Bolshevik revolution is also marred by typical
(Leninist) confusions – only someone unfamiliar with Maurice Brinton’s
ground-breaking The Bolsheviks and Workers’ Control could proclaim that
the Bolsheviks “[o]n taking power, Lenin’s government had proclaimed its
support for the management of factories by workers’ committees.” He
follows a long line of Leninist apologists when he asserts that “the
long civil war accustomed Bolshevik officials to top-down central
command.” “Within months,” he states, “industry was nationalised.
Managers appointed by the government were given unilateral authority to
direct production and hire and fire workers.” (93) This true, yet
Bolshevik authoritarianism started before the start of “the long civil
war” and so cannot be used to excuse Bolshevik state-capitalist policies
– particularly as nationalisation was Lenin’s aim before seizing power.
Similarly, it is somewhat disingenuous to state that “[i]n the late
1920s, Stalin’s government” relied on repression, with power “in hands
of top party and state officials” (93) – it had been a feature of the
Bolshevik regime from the start.
Engler makes some very strange assertions. Thus we find it claimed that
only after Stalin’s forced collectivisation “in the 1930s, individual
enterprise came to be viewed as incompatible with socialism.” (59)
Stalin’s vision of planning was hardly his own – he was building on
arguments by Lenin and Marx against the likes of Proudhon that commodity
production was incompatible with socialism. So it was hardly in the
1930s that “opposition to market forces became a dogma of the
anti-capitalist left” (69) it was a position that Marx had been
expounding since 1847. Then there is the claim that by 1950 “communist
parties had abolished capitalism in countries that accounted for a third
of humankind.” (97) Yes, Engler may reject Stalinism but he still
accepts the notion that it was non-capitalist rather than
state-capitalist.
So is it the new mutualism? Not quite but there is much in common with
Proudhon’s vision of a socialist market system based on self-managed
co-operatives utilising socialised credit and means of production in a
socio-economic federation. Rather than trying to squeeze his ideas into
Marxism, Engler would have been better exploring the links with
mutualism, the anarchist critique of Socialists using elections and the
anarcho-syndicalist vision of social transformation.
Is Economic Democracy the alternative to capitalism? Some of aspects of
it are – the aim of abolishing wage-labour by workers’ self-management
is one such aspect, as is the need for social ownership rather than
nationalisation – but anarchists have been advocating those since 1840.
So the book presents a useful critique of capitalism as wage-slavery
(which any libertarian would agree with) but it is weak on the rich
tradition of ideas associated with libertarian socialism. While there is
much anarchists will agree and sympathise with, there is too much
acceptance of electioneering as a strategy and a too blasé acceptance of
markets.
Ultimately, the book raises far too many questions that remain
unanswered. More familiarity with the wider socialist tradition outside
of Marxism would aid Engler considerably and both help clarify his
arguments and identify his differences with mutualism.
Economic Democracy: The Working-Class Alternative to Capitalism
Allan Engler
Fernwood Publishing
Halifax & Winnipeg
2010