💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › amedeo-bertolo-democracy-and-beyond.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 06:30:04. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Democracy and beyond
Author: Amedeo Bertolo
Date: 1994
Language: en
Topics: democracy
Source: Retrieved on 17th May 2021 from https://autonomies.org/2020/10/amedeo-bertolo-democracy-and-beyond/
Notes: This text was originally presented at the conference, “El anarquismo ante la crisis de las ideologias”, Barcelona, 1–3 of October, 1993, and subsequently published in Volontà, nº 4, 1994 (Translation by April Retter, with minor alterations)

Amedeo Bertolo

Democracy and beyond

If understood to the letter, a democracy must be a stateless society …

Power belongs to the people insofar as the people truly exercise it

themselves.

Giovanni Sartori

The concern in this essay is with democracy from an anarchist point of

view and – secondarily – with anarchism from a democratic point of view.

In the course of this reflection, I will occupy myself above all with

those aspects of the two political and philosophical categories which

are relevant to a confrontation between them, that is to say the

essential differences and similarities between democracy and anarchism.

This means that neither democracy as it is commonly understood

(“representative” democracy) nor political anarchism (as anarchists see

it), nor even that particular primary form of democracy, “direct

democracy”, which is a sort of category of passage between democracy and

anarchism, will be analysed in depth. Each one of these categories would

require, for an adequate critical reflection, much more space, so that

we will limit ourselves to brief definitions for the purpose of

comparison, or better yet, to a general assessment of their

compatibility/comparability.

The thesis that I will defend is precisely that democracy and anarchism

are not reducible one to the other, but (under certain conditions) they

are also not antithetical. Anarchism is at the same time the most fully

developed form of democracy and its irreducible overcoming; a beyond it

– as the title of this text suggests.

Accordingly, is a beyond democracy conceivable? Yes it is, a

quantitative as well as qualitative beyond. By analogy to what I once

wrote about freedom,[1] the anarchist conception of freedom is both more

than and different from the liberal one. In simpler terms, this

difference or diversity lies in the fact that for liberals, the freedom

of single individuals is limited by that of others, while for anarchists

it is enhanced.

However the different freedom of the anarchists also encompasses that of

the liberals, while moving beyond both quantitatively and qualitatively.

Quantity is essential as without it there is no guarantee of quality; a

different freedom must at the same time signify a greater one. Even

religious fundamentalists (Christian, Muslim, etc.) speak of different

freedoms which are however less freedom, both at the individual level

and at the collective one –particularly individual.

Thus the political idea of the anarchists is – and must necessarily be –

greater democracy, over and above anything else; otherwise, it would be

a less than. This is in fact what anarchists maintain: that it is both

greater and different.

So the anarchist concept of the political space is of something both

quantitatively and qualitatively beyond the democratic one. This is so

above all as regards the reigning democratic idea, that is,

representative democracy, but also in comparison to more radical

conceptions, such as for example “participatory democracy” …[2] and even

for so-called “direct democracy”.[3]

The anarchist idea of political space – which we could call “political

anarchy” – is, in fact, together more profoundly democratic and

something different, something else.

How then can something be one thing and at the same time another? It is

possible. Difficult though it may be to comprehend, it is in fact

possible. Here we are not speaking of “things” in the physical world,

but of “things” of the social-political imaginary. And these latter

“are” according to different modalities which depend on the point of

view from which they are viewed. Anarchism, in this case, can be seen as

an extreme form of democracy and as a different form of constructing the

political space, or even as something which lies beyond the political

space. We will see.

Before preceeding, it must be clearly stated that we have in mind

certain definitions of democracy (or better democracies)[4], which were

always until now implicit, but which have gradually become more

explicit. These definitions are relatively neutral – total neutrality

being neither possible nor useful. They are definitions of anarchism

first and foremost from an anarchist perspective (although bearing in

mind the democratic critique) and of democracy from the democratic

perspective[5] (although bearing in mind the anarchist critique).

First, however, grant us a digression which is only apparently off

topic.

Ideological warehouse

When I am in a bad mood (and I almost always am when I have to submit an

article, and even more so when I am late with it) and I look around me

in the “ideological warehouse” of anarchism, I feel as if I were in the

back of some second-hand shop. Not of an antique shop, as some malicious

enemy of anarchism might have it, but worse – amid a scrap merchant’s

wares. In among timeworn set phrases, declarations of principle,

articles of faith, slogans, fine sentiments, verbal extremism,

statements of affection, recollections, the dearly departed … for the

most part, what I see are retro pieces.

As is known, retro pieces are not not old enough to be antiques, but

they are old enough to not be truly modern, contemporary, or almost. I

know that anarchism has produced original and important things in the

last fifty years (and particularly in the last twenty to thirty),

original and important and “new” things, that is, modern things in the

proper sense. And I also know of course that anarchist thought has

preserved very beautiful “antiquarian” pieces, that is, of classical

anarchism, and that it still bases itself largely on these and that it

is by humiliating the ingenuity and rich potential of the “modern” that

the “old”, that is, the “vulgate”, has built itself a shell of common

sense to protect its fragile identity.

The identity of the “classics”, of the founding fathers of anarchism,

was so strong that they could even contradict themselves (or apparently

contradict each other) without any great difficulties. Lucky them!

In 1848 Pierre-Joseph Proudhon was a member of the National Assembly; in

1849 he wrote a crystal clear and devastating attack not only on the

state and the government but on the political dimension tout court. In

1863 (with Du Principe fédératif) he put forward a plan that proposes

anew an autonomous political sphere and he speaks of communes,

provinces, regions, and, – Hear ye, hear ye! -, of states and

governments.[6]

And listen to what Mikhail Bakunin wrote to his friend and comrade from

Naples, Carlo Gambuzzi, “You will perhaps be surprised to hear that I, a

passionately convinced abstentionist, am now suggesting to my friends

that they stand for election to the national assembly. This can be

explained by the fact that the circumstances have changed”.[7] The

circumstances … Was good old Bak by chance no longer an anarchist? Just

think of it. It is just that while anarchism today holds up

abstentionism as a principle, for Bakunin it was a strategic choice; or

even, judging from the above quote, a tactical choice.[8]

Very well then, but what does this have to do with the theme of the

present text? It has to do with it, but tangentially; it has because the

image that anarchists today have of democracy is heavily influenced by

the anarchist vulgate, just as the idea that democrats have of anarchism

(apart from some clear cases of ignorance and bad faith) is heavily

influenced by their vulgate.

Let us take, for example, the statement of principle that “anarchists do

not vote”. If this is a fundamental principle, it is inevitable that the

vulgate maintains that not only are anarchists opposed to voting in

certain historical (social, economic, political) conditions, but that

anarchists do not vote and will never vote in any event. This is

something that is sublimely absurd. Sublimely because it is a

declaration of faith that is totally utopian, and utopia is an essential

element of anarchism. Absurd because it is entirely devoid of that

common sense (rebellious common sense, of course, not a “casalinga de

Voghera” [idiomatic: “petty bourgeois house wife” -T.N.] common sense)

without which there can be no “possible anarchism”, that is, an

anarchism that is significantly present in social transformation, with

revolutionary strategies.

To avoid any misunderstandings, I should say that I am fifty-seven years

of age, I have never voted in any of the many elections – almost all of

them touted as “decisive” – in Italy in the last thirty-two years. And I

am well with this. But this is not the point, or at least not here.

So what then is the point? I will again let Bakunin speak and his

program for a post-revolutionary society: “The basis of all political

organisation in a country must be the totally autonomous commune, always

represented by the majority of the votes of all adult men and women

there residing” (my italics).[9] And again: “The election of all

national, provincial and communal representatives […] shall be by

universal suffrage of all adult men and women”(my italics).[10]

And this brings us back to the subject.

The Government of All

Francesco Saverio Merlino, who was an anarchist until the last decade of

the 19^(th) century, and later moved towards libertarian socialism and

then liberal socialism, wrote in his testament: “the government by all =

the government by none”.[11] And, shortly before he died, he left a

handwritten note: “democracy = anarchy”. Merlino goes beyond the

similarities that I see and dissolves their identities, either because

he underestimates anarchy or because he overvalues democracy; or for

both reasons.

We can always begin with Merlino’s two statements (which seem to derive

from pairs of clear affinities: government by all/democracy, government

by none/anarchy) as a starting point for a more deep-reaching

comparative analysis of democracy and anarchy. Starting, as we said,

with certain useful definitions for such a comparison.

Let us begin with anarchy. Anarchy can be (and indeed has been)

understood in different ways, even by anarchists themselves. In

particular, for what interests us here, anarchy can signify a society

without government, or without a state, or without power (or better,

without domination). There is a need to further specify these

interpretations. What, for example, is meant by government? Anarchists

often speak in positive terms of self-government, so that what they

reject must be a hetero-government, government imposed on one part of

society by another, a subordination of the governed to those who govern,

and not the function of government per se.

And the State? The state is a particular historical form of

legitimisation and organisation of political power. Its legitimacy is

rational, bestowed by a real or supposed “popular will” rather than by

the will of God or who knows what else. However, it has within itself a

hierarchical conception of society, of the State as a paradigm of power,

or better of domination;[12] the State is an institution (or a sum of

institutions), but above all the imaginary instituting [constituting]

form of modern class domination.[13]

As regards power, the majority of anarchists understood or understand by

“evil” power (that which they deny) hierarchical power which entails a

relationship of command/obedience. In the case of political power

(always in the negative sense), it is not the normative function of

society, nor the “collective political force”[14], but the expropriation

of society as a whole, the political corpus of society, of this function

and its corresponding appropriation by a minority. As was said: in a

society divided between those who govern and the governed, the power

which anarchists reject is that which is constantly exercised by the

former over the latter. Anarchy is not equivalent to anomy (i.e. the

absence of norms), but, rather, with the necessary specifications, to

autonomy.

Personally, for reasons of semantic articulation, I prefer the term

domination[15] to signify the expropriated power of the “collective

force”, retaining a more neutral meaning for the term power, although

fraught with hierarchical potentialities in a hierarchical society. I

also prefer to use the term domination to talk of permanently

asymmetrical power relations, including those social relations which

fall outside the political sphere. This includes those “analogously”

asymmetric relations between humans and nature which can be traced back

to the same imaginary of domination carried over from the social.[16]

Let us return to anarchy. Anarchy is a principle of organisation of

reality, a non-hierarchical conception of the world, libertarian in the

strong sense, which extends equally, but not only, to the political

sphere. Not only. Anarchy pertains to the the realm of philosophy,

ethics and aesthetics before belonging to – and is more than – the

domain of politics. Although it is this latter political dimension which

is of interest to us here.

So since anarchists claim to have a conception of society which rejects

domination but not the collective functions of the organisation of

society (rejecting only the hierarchical forms and the implications of

domination), it can perhaps be said that anarchists believe in a

government/non-government, in a state/non-state, in a power/non-power.

This only seems to be paradoxical since the first term in each pair

refers to a neutral concept of the corresponding function, while the

second refers to the actual function founded on a hierarchical

principle.

For the State, too, it is necessary to be clear about what we really

mean by this term. We do not mean the State as it has been historically

configured, legitimised and rationalised, which anarchists have

rightfully shown to be an exemplary form of modern domination, the

central hierarchical institution of reality and of the social imaginary

of the post-Enlightenment, but rather the State in the sense of a

“republic” (res publica,[17] the public domain), a term which the

classics of anarchism used more than once in a neutral sense.

Words do of course very often carry heavy emotional and ideological

connotations – and in this case, most certainly -, which is why

anarchists prefer not to use in a neutral sense words like “government”,

“State” and “power”, words which History has profoundly marked. In the

same way, they reject the word “party” for their political

organisations, even though these are undeniably forms of

party/non-party. It is a party because it is a social group organised to

pursue certain values and interests, but it is a non-party because it

has no hierarchical structure and is not directed towards gaining power.

Forms of the Political

Anarchists, even when they have wanted to go beyond politics, as we said

and as we will see further on, they have not however refused to propose,

both in words and deeds, forms of politics compatible (although not

identifiable) with anarchism, understood as the absence/negation of

domination. In the same way, in the economic field, even while

recognising something beyond economics, they have always suggested

economic forms which essentially boil down to what can be called

self-management.

What then is the government/non-government that anarchists have proposed

and propose for the political function of society?

The forms of the political proposed by them are essentially reducible to

so-called direct democracy. Whatever Merlino may have said, democracy,

even in its direct form, is not anarchism (and nor is self-management in

the economic field). It is not true that the power of all is at the same

time the power of none, or at least not entirely true. There is still

some measure of coercive power (or better, imperative power), even if

only through moral sanctions. It is power over someone, not over no one.

So even the limited form of direct democracy, democracy that operates

face-to-face and through unanimity (i.e. only through unanimous

decisions), limited also by its limited area of practical functioning,

is not necessarily anarchist in the fullest sense. It may perhaps be so

in political terms, since theoretically there is no domination if each

norm is decided upon and each decision is taken by all, and above all,

by every individual concerned.

This distinction between all and every individual is important since for

the anthropological type suggested as desirable for anarchism (what one

author[18] has called the communitarian individual), “political

sovereignty” does not lie with society or with the individual, but in

the continual unresolved tension between the two. If the former

prevails, even in a democratic form, it is tyranny. If the latter

prevails, then there is disintegration and loss of sense. Anarchism is

jealously individualist, but also generously communitarian. And it is

perfectly aware that the individual, the unique, is also and inevitably

a social product.

If everyone – to return to our subject – deliberates consciously and

freely and, at the same time, respects the deliberations (not “obey”,

notice) this is not the domination of one part of society, even less of

“all” over the individual. I leave aside the problem, not insignificant

theoretically, of norms established in the past and still in force due

to social inertia, norms which an individual has not always joined in

setting or approved of and which they cannot modify and which therefore

represent a form of domination of the past over the present. But for the

present we can leave this aside. So if everyone … etc, sovereignty lies

both and harmoniously in the individual and the collective. Direct

democracy, on a theoretical level and in its “purist” form, can

reconcile the apparently irreconcilable.

However what we have outlined is a limit case, as used to be said.

Unanimous direct democracy is only applicable to non-generalisable

situations, that is, on a small level and with an extreme homogeneity of

values and interests. Beyond this smallest dimension, delegation becomes

essential. Without a strong homogeneity there must be a mechanism for

decision making over and above unanimity.

If decisions were always and only really unanimous, very few would ever

be taken, even within groups with a high level of social and cultural

homogeneity. It is true that when there is a certain level of

homogeneity and where there are no opposing interests, “unanimous”

decisions can often be reached without any great difficulty or

exhausting discussions as an individual (or a minority) may well

withdraw their opposition to the opinions and so to the decisions of the

majority. But is this not a particular (consensual) form of majority

decision?

When the collective subject of decisions (whether composed by ten, one

hundred or one thousand people…) is heterogeneous in terms of values and

interests, unanimous decisions, even in the limited form described

above, become difficult, if not impossible. It is then that the

democratic mechanism of the majority comes to seem the lesser evil among

the possible decision-making criteria. A lesser evil that is from the

anarchist point of view. The majorities may be simple, absolute,

qualified, even highly qualified (two thirds, four fifths, nine

tenths…), but they are majorities nonetheless. When the anarchist Errico

Malatesta replied to Merlino, who had accused him of having said that in

certain situations a majority decision is better than none… he did so by

accepting, in substance, the majority criteria.[19]

The Scale

Once we move beyond a certain numerical threshold (one hundred, five

hundred, a thousand people?), direct democracy in the strict sense of

face to face, democratic assemblies, no longer works. It cannot work,

because for face-to-face democracy to work, those present at a meeting

must know each other – at least a little – and have a certain degree of

mutual trust. They must be able to talk in other situations as well and,

last but not least, they must be able to contribute directly to the

discussion, if they wish, leading up to a decision, as this is an

integral part of the decision-making process.

Anyone with any experience of assemblies knows that beyond a certain

dimension they tend to move closer to demagogy than to direct democracy,

with the majority of the “participants” in fact merely being present. In

this way, the “public” changes from a deliberating people to spectators

with varying degrees of interest and motivation, just like the audience

of a spectacle (theatre, concert, cinema) or a football match. They are

transformed from the thing to its representation, even if emotionally

involved. Direct democracy becomes represented democracy.

Where does this threshold lie? This depends on many factors: the greater

or lesser complexity of the subjects in question, the “democratic

maturity” of the participants, their knowledge of the subjects, their

psychological makeup, their willingness to be really involved in the

decision-making process, and the relative homogeneity of their values

and their effective interests. But whatever the circumstances, there is

a threshold and it is not very high.

The long-lasting “utopian” experiment of the Israeli kibbutzim shows

that the upper limit for a real directly democratic assembly is

somewhere around a hundred persons. It is certainly far from hundreds of

thousands. To gather this number of persons together in a stadium does

not mean they will discuss a question and reach an agreement, seeking an

acceptable compromise. Even putting a decision to the hypothetical

electronic vote of a million people means having to simplify questions

and the possible options to a binary level of yes/no. In such a case,

whoever simplifies the question has in a certain sense already partly

decided the answer. Not even in the best possible scenario can this be

considered direct democracy in the true sense.

So over and above face-to-face democracy, there is inevitably a

dimension of democracy which is in some way indirect, at least in fact.

There are federal and confederal forms of “direct” democracy. As Bakunin

said, “every organisation must work from the bottom up, from the commune

to the central organ, the State, by the route of federation”.[20] And

such federal and confederal forms must inevitably make use of some form

of “representation” (the quotation marks are to distinguish it from the

particular forms of representation familiar from representative

democracy).

The form which anarchists have given to such “federal” representation

(in both theory and practice) is an imperative and revocable mandate.

This mandate can at any time be revoked by those “who gave it”, that is,

through direct democracy in the strict sense. It is difficult, but not

impossible, to imagine this “immediacy” even for second and third degree

mandates (delegates elected by delegates and so on). But, imperative?

The authority of the mandate comes with the fact that politics is also

the art of mediation, of compromise, and the decision-making process (at

all levels, from the local meeting, through to all the different levels

of delegation) is one of compromise between opinions and interests that

need not be opposing (although they sometimes are), as much as diverse.

How then is it possible to find an equilibrium on the basis of

authoritative, that is, rigid mandates? Only mandates that are

reasonably flexible can produce a satisfactory compromise.

Among the three features of direct democracy which anarchists see as

“necessary” (unanimity, imperative and revocable mandates) two at least

are – if taken to the letter – difficult to reconcile (to put it mildly)

with the functioning of a society that is a little more complex than

that of the Inuit (Eskimos), of the Yanomani (based in Amazon) or of the

Nuer (a Sudanese population). That is, if they are taken to the letter.

It is worth leaving this question to one side for a while, as we turn to

the question of representative democracy.

The Dominant and the Dominated

Democracy as it is generally understood, as vaunted by various

self-styled liberal-democrats, is representative democracy and not

simply democracy. Even the “people’s democracy” of the former so-called

socialist States was representative democracy, on their own terms, of

course.

Even Fascism was, in its own way, a representative democracy. Its

“political class” represented the Italian demos, it was just that the

forms and modes of representation were different from those of

pluralist, multi-party political systems. And, of course, a

non-negligible detail, the freedom of speech, of the press, of

association… were significantly limited. But then what belongs to the

“liberal” ambit does not necessarily belong to the “democratic” one. Who

can deny that on the eve of the second world war, the fascist regime

enjoyed the support, active or passive, of the majority of Italians,

i.e. of the people? And who can deny that the Camera dei Fasci e delle

Corporazioni (the Italian Fascist parliament) was an elected body

representing the demos?

An anarchist friend from Portugal recently pointed out to me that

Antonio Salazar’s regime regularly held semi-democratic elections

(“semi” according to a liberal conception, freer anyway than in Cuba or

Bulgaria) … and he won them all. Even in the last one, shortly before

the “carnations revolution”, the regime won an (admittedly slight)

majority.

Let it be quite clear that I am by no means trying to equate fascism and

liberal democracy. May the Non-existent Supreme Being spare me this!

This would be a logical operation (so to speak) of the worst anarchist

“modernism”. I am simply trying to show that the term “democracy” covers

a semantic space that stretches from direct democracy in the strict

sense to authoritarian democracy, passing through forms of limited and

controlled delegation, to forms of representation that are generically

limited (a true and proper “limited partnership”) and periodically

renewed through electoral mechanisms (in the dual sense of choice and

selection), which unite the elements of agreement and co-opting to

varying degrees. If direct democracy in its “pure” form represents one

pole of this continuum, the liberal version of representative democracy

(which is the best form, I believe, that has been theorised and

practised to date), does not represent the opposite pole (to

authoritarian democracy), but is undoubtedly closer to it.

It is no coincidence that in periods of social crisis, when confronted

by the risk not so much of revolution as of radical reform of economic

power, liberal democracy has shown no great difficulty or reluctance in

“letting itself be transformed” into its authoritarian counterpart (and

on occasions into true dictatorship) for however long it may take to

remake, with the good and the bad, the consensus of the ruling/dominant

class to allow for a return to a more “liberal” form of democracy.

And it is only natural that representative liberal democracy should be

closer to the authoritarian pole of democracy than to the libertarian

one. It is in fact the “human face” of the “rational” division between

the ruler and the ruled, the political counterpart of the division

between dominant and dominated, of the class division of society and of

its hierarchical structure. There is no reason to belabour this point

here since there is a wealth of writings, both anarchist and

non-anarchist, which have demolished the myth of representative

democracy, that is, the myth of its democratic nature, in the original

sense of the word.[21]

Democracy is the government of the demos, of the people.[22] The demos

has been defined in various ways, on the basis of sex-gender, of

citizenship, of electoral census, of age, and so on. In its most

wide-reaching form (as, for example, in Italy today) it includes

virtually all citizens (which is not the same as all inhabitants, though

almost), regardless of class, wealth, sex and race over the age of 18.

How then does this demos, which is the great majority of Italians,

exercise its “government”, its “power”? It does not exercise it in

person; that would be self-government, direct democracy. Instead it

delegates its declared right to an elected oligarchy which then

exercises this power in its own name. And it is not as if the only

choice was that between an unlikely anarchism and an electoral oligarchy

(representative democracy)… As Dahl says,[23] even though representative

democracy may have major defects (euphemism) there is no better

alternative… Ah, but there is.

There is the alternative of direct democracy integrated in a system of

federations and confederations, in the broadest sense, in a greatly

decentralised political sphere in which the mandates of even the

delegates of the basic social structures can be revoked and limited

(albeit with relative room for manoeuvre) to specific decisions, and

where the power delegated in a coordinated situation is always less than

that which is not delegated. This would be a democracy in which the

interests of a community of ten thousand inhabitants would primarily be

governed by its own decisions and not by those of the province, let

alone those of the region, etc. etc. in a federal succession. This would

be a democracy in which “peripheral” political realities (city

neighbourhoods, towns, regions, etc.) would not be entities far from a

central power, but in which the “central” body would be a federal

articulation of the power base. This is not just playing with words.

Under representative democracy, on the other hand, the power to decide

is delegated to a body of political professionals and the only power

left to the demos is that of choosing its representatives (however,

under conditions in which there is good reason to doubt the real and

conscious freedom of choice), and power grows rather than decreases as

you move from the political “periphery” to the centre, from the local to

the national. This is a different dimension of democracy. It is not a

demos which governs itself, despite contradictions which cannot be

eliminated, but which can be controlled once their existence is

recognised, but a demos in whose name someone governs, with some

mechanisms for creating and/or simulating consent.

There is a qualitative leap in the nature of the apparent continuum of

democratic forms.

A democracy that is compatible with the anarchist rejection of

domination (and in political terms, of the division between the rulers

and the ruled) is necessarily a “direct” democracy in the above sense,

that is, strongly rooted in democratic assemblies and with a necessary

but controlled system of temporary political delegates. Delegates may be

elected or chosen by lot (why not, as it was the case with the

magistrates of Athens), but would be truly representatives. Under no

circumstances would there be a political class (whether of one party or

several, makes no difference) cut off from the demos by the simple fact

of being professional politicians.

A Model

Planning forms of direct democracy is already a move beyond democracy as

it is generally understood, as representative liberal democracy. A

beyond that – as we have said many times – presupposes more democracy

(not less) and, jointly, a different democracy. Direct democracy places

much greater power in the hands of every individual who constitutes and

institutes the demos, while breaking up, decentralising and diffusing

political power.

Direct democracy is a discrete approximation to political “an-archy”

(absence of domination). And in fact, in both theory (as with Proudhon

and Bakunin) and practice (in the various revolutionary situations where

anarchists have played a decisive role, like Spain in 1936), the

political forms suggested and experimented with have been those of

“direct democracy on a federal basis”.

This is a good approximation to political anarchism. It is nothing more

but nor is it anything less than that. Political anarchism is certainly

founded on a further beyond, but just as the Christian ideal is

sainthood “in the image of Christ” and yet all Christians – including

the saints – settle for less, indeed for much less, as tending towards

the ideal, so too do anarchists.

There is another sense in which anarchism goes beyond democracy. As has

already been said, anarchism is a principle for organising reality which

goes beyond the political sphere (and indeed beyond the social sphere

too, but this is beyond the scope of this article). As a philosophical,

ethical and aesthetic principle, it stretches beyond the political arena

(which is that of democracy) and indeed rejects it. It moves beyond it

because even the extreme model of direct democracy is not really enough.

Even a face-to-face assembly could pass unanimous decisions that are

horribly incompatible with anarchism. The direct democracy of Athens

could burn Pythagoras’ “books” or condemn Socrates to death, but nobody

can make an anarchist accept the justice of a verdict which punishes

heterodox ideas. Unanimity, and (even less) a majority, may be accepted

by anarchists as the criteria for political decisions in specific

contexts, but never as a way of deciding in absolute terms what is good

and what is bad, what is beautiful and what is ugly. Even liberals see

certain areas of “human rights” as lying outside the majority mechanism,

and among its wiser exponents, they are quite sceptical towards the

power of the majority. For example: “for the democratic doctrine, the

simple fact that the majority wants something is enough to make what it

wants good; […] the will of the majority determines not only that

something is a law, but also that it is a good law”. And again, “it is

at least conceivable that under the rule of a very homogeneous and

doctrinaire majority, a democratic regime could be as oppressive as the

worst dictatorship”.[24]

There is yet another and perhaps even greater way in which anarchism

goes beyond politics. Politics, like economics, is a dimension of

society which became visible and “autonomous” of the totality of social

functions at a “certain point” in history. As such, it can be seen as a

historical creation. The political function, like the economic one, has

always existed in some form and to some degree in every society, but

(apart from the Athenian interlude) it is only in recent centuries that

it has been perceived, described, prescribed, studied and practised as a

form in itself of the social. After Machiavelli, Hobbes, etc., and above

all after the Enlightenment disenchantment of the world and its

“worldly” de-sacralisation/re-sacralisation of domination.

Libertarian Democracy

Like economics, and almost at the same time, politics too was

“autonomised” in relation to the social magma in its imaginary and

institutional representations. Economics tried and tries to explain the

social in terms of its own categories (the “utopian” undertaking of

capitalist ideology is in fact impossible) and to bend it to its own

“rationality”.[25] Politics, more modestly, but no less dangerously,

tried to explain itself “from its own perspective”. There have been

attempts to submit society to politics, which have had considerable

historical and ideological significance: Leninism, and its

third-worldist forms more or less contaminated by it, as well as

fascism: “everything for the State, nothing outside and against the

State”, as Mussolini said.

But the economic, political, legal, ideological-religious, etc, are

precisely functions of society, functions of a “social body” which is

not economic, nor political, nor… The awareness of the existence of

diverse functions within the complex physiology of the social body is

undoubtedly an important addition to our knowledge, knowledge necessary

for a radical transformation of society as it is, but it is also

important to recognise and understand the close links and

interrelationships between the various organs and functions.

“Holistic” medicine can only be seen as progressive after anatomy and

physiology have already identified and studied the various processes of

the human body, including the as yet little understood psychosomatic

relationships. The holistic conception may be valuable as something

beyond anatomy and physiology. Practised as something less than, it will

be just magic or charlatanism.

Anarchism, as a “holistic” conception of society, can only be a beyond

politics, economics, and so on (not an ingenuous and primitivist less

than or before). The social is not just an arithmetic sum, a mechanical

combination, of politics, economics…, but rather an organic

interrelationship of political, economic and other functions. There can

be no real democracy in the political sphere unless all those acting in

it are socially equal (or if you prefer, equivalent). Thus it is not

possible to have political democracy without economic democracy,[26]

which we may call self-management. And it is not possible to have

self-management unless the economic subjects involved are equal, that

is, without the integration of manual and intellectual work … [27]

A libertarian democracy (to employ a neologism[28] which is more or less

synonymous with possible, practical anarchism) is impossible unless the

ethos of society and its fundamental values do not have at least a

certain coherence with direct democracy and self-management, that is to

say, with equality, freedom, solidarity and diversity in the strong

sense. In the strong sense. That is, anarchy or something close to it,

as I wanted to demonstrate.

[1] Amedeo Bertolo, “I fanatici della libertà”, Volontà, n. 3–4, 1996.

An abridged English translation of a previous version of this writing

was published as “Fanatics of Freedom” in Our Generation, vol. 23, n. 2

(1992), pp. 50–66.

[2] David Held, Modelli di democrazia, Bologna 1989, p. 332 (English

edition: Models of Democracy, Cambridge, 1987).

[3] For a fairly full discussion and benevolent critique of direct

democracy from non-anarchist perspectives (the first neo-marxist and the

second liberal socialist) see David Held, op. cit., pp. 157–178, and

Norberto Bobbio, Il futuro della democrazia, Torino, 1993, pp. 36–61.

[4] See David Held, op. cit.

[5] See Murray Bookchin, Democrazia diretta, Milano, 1993; Id. Remaking

Society, Montreal, 1993; Id., “Communalism: The Democratic Dimension of

Anarchism”, Democracy and Nature, 1995, pp. 1–17; Robert Dahl, Democracy

and its Critics, Yale, 1989; Giovanni Sartori, Democrazia. Cos’è,

Milano, 1993.

[6] Giampietro Berti (ed.), La dimensione libertaria di Proudhon, Roma,

1982, p. 77.

[7] Quoted in François Munoz, Bakounine et la Liberté, Paris 1965, p.

228.

[8] Errico Malatesta too, 25 years later, wrote that “for us

abstentionism is a question of tactics”, although he added that it is so

important that when it is abandoned we risk abandoning the principles

(E. Malatesta, F.S. Merlino, Anarchismo e democrazia, Ragusa, 1974, p.

60.

[9] Michail Bakunin, LibertĂ  eguaglianza rivoluzione, Milano, 1976, p.

93.

[10] Ibid., p. 88.

[11] Quoted in Giampietro Berti, Francesco Saverio Merlino, Milano,

1993, p. 414.

[12] Eduardo Colombo, “Lo Stato come paradigma del potere”, Volontà, n.

3, 1984.

[13] See René Lourau, L’Etat incoscient, Paris, 1978.

[14] Giampietro Berti (ed.), op. cit., p.45.

[15] See Amedeo Bertolo, “Potere, autorità, dominio”, Volontà, n. 2,

1983. An abridged English translation was published with the title

“Authority, Power and Domination”, in Laslo Sekelj (ed.), Anarchism.

Community and Utopia, Praha, 1993, pp. 137–166.

[16] See Murray Bookchin, The Ecology of Freedom, Palo Alto, 1982.

[17] As E. Colombo shows (“Della polis e dello spazio sociale plebeo”,

Volontà, n. 4, 1989), publicus is derived from populicus, i.e. “of the

people”, which is clearly relevant to democracy.

[18] Alan Ritter, Anarchism: A Theoretical Analysis, Cambridge,1980,

chap. II.

[19]

E. Malatesta, F.S. Merlino, op. cit., pp. 42–43.

[20] Michail Bakunin, op. cit., p. 92.

[21] See Robert Dale, op. cit., who sets out and argues against the

critique of democracy from various points of view, including the

anarchist one, even if in fact the critique is based on a writer who is

not an anarchist (Robert Paul Wolff). See also E. Colombo, “Della

polis…”, cit.

[22]

E. Colombo (“Della polis…”, cit.) in fact says that, according to some

Hellenists, the term democracy (which was created by enemies of

democracy) is inappropriate as kratos which means domination or

force exercised by one part of the society over an other, while

legitimate authority is arkhè. It would thus be more correct to

speak of demarchy than democracy and maybe of acracy than anarchy.

[23] Robert Dahl, op. cit., pp. 75–76.

[24] Friedrich von Hayek, quoted in D. Held, op. cit., p. 314.

[25] See Luciano Lanza, “Il mercante e l’utopista”, Volontà, n. 1–2,

1990.

[26] See Takis Fotopoulos, Toward an Inclusive Democracy, London, 1997.

[27] See two “classics” of anarchism: Mikhail Bakunin, op. cit., chap.

on “Integral Education”, and Pëtr Kropotkin, Fields, Factories and

Workshops Tomorrow (ed. by C. Ward), London, 1974, chap. on

“Intellectual and Manual Work”.

[28] To my knowledge, this expression was first used by Gaston Leval

(Espagne Libertaire. 1936–1939, Paris, 1971, pp. 217–225).