💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › elisee-reclus-death-penalty.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:47:59. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Death Penalty
Author: Elisée Reclus
Date: 1879
Language: en
Topics: law, death penalty, the State, prison, justice
Source: Translated from https://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k819083.image
Notes: Translation by João Black for the Anarchist Library. This is a lecture given by Reclus at a meeting of the Workers’ Association [Association Ouvrière] of Lausanne, 1879. It was later printed several times as a pamphlet.

Elisée Reclus

The Death Penalty

GENTLEMEN,

I do not have the honor to be a Swiss citizen and I know only very

imperfectly the constitution of which some petitioners ask to suppress

an article; but this is a human question agitated in all civilized

countries. As a man and an international, I have the right to deal with

this question, and unfortunately I also have to deal with it as a

Frenchman, because my homeland is still a country of head-cutters, and

the guillotine, which was invented there, still works there.

Enemy of the death penalty, I must first try to know its origins. Is it

rightly that we make it derive from the right of personal defense? If it

were so, it would be difficult to fight it, because each of us certainly

has the right to defend ourselves and our loved ones, either against the

beast or against the fierce man who attacks us. But is it not obvious

that the right of personal defense cannot be delegated, because it

ceases immediately when the danger ceases? When we take the lives of our

fellow human beings into our own hands, it means that there is no social

recourse against them, it means that no one can help us; in the same way

when a man places himself apart from the others, above any contract, and

makes his power weigh on citizens changed into subjects, the latter have

the right to rise up and kill whoever oppresses them. Fortunately,

history gives us numerous examples of the claiming of this right.

The origin of the death penalty, as now applied by States, is certainly

revenge, revenge without measure, as terrible as hatred may inspire, or

revenge regulated by a kind of summary justice, in other words, the

penalty of retaliation: “Tooth for tooth, eye for eye, head for head”.

As soon as the family was formed, it took the place of the individual to

exercise revenge or vendetta. It demands the price of blood: each wound

is paid for by another wound, each death by another death, and this is

how hatreds and wars drag on. This was the state of a large part of

Europe in the Middle Ages, it was in the last century that of Albania,

the Caucasus and many other countries.

However, a little order has been introduced into the perpetual wars,

thanks to redemption. Individuals or families could usually redeem

themselves, and this kind of transaction was fixed by custom. So many

oxen, sheep or goats, so many ringing crowns or acres of land were fixed

for the redemption of blood. The condemned man could also redeem himself

by having himself adopted by another family, sometimes even by that

which he had offended; he could also become free by a brilliant action;

finally, he could fall too low for anyone to deign to punish him. It was

enough for him to hide behind a woman and henceforth he was free, too

vile to be killed, but more unhappy than if he had been covered with

wounds. He lived, but his life was worse than death.

The law of retaliation from family to family could not obviously be

maintained in large centralized states, monarchies, aristocracies or

republics. There it is society, represented by its government, king,

councils or magistracies, which is responsible for revenge or

condemnation [vindicte], as we say in the language of jurisprudence. But

history proves to us that by monopolizing the right to punish in the

name of all, the State, caste or king, was above all concerned with

avenging its particular injuries, and we know with what fury it pursued

its enemies and what refinements of cruelty it put into making them

suffer. There is no torture that imagination can invent and which has

not been thus applied to millions of men: here they were slowly burned,

elsewhere they were flayed or successively cut off the limbs, in

Nuremberg, they locked up the condemned man in the body of the iron

“Virgin”, reddened with fire; in France, they broke his limbs or dragged

him on four horses; in the East, they impale the unfortunate ones; in

Morocco, they are immured, leaving only the head outside the wall. And

why all this revenge? Is it to punish real crimes? No, the hatred of

kings and the ruling classes has always turned against men who claimed

freedom of thought and action. The death penalty has always been in the

service of tyranny. What did Calvin, master of power, do? He had Michael

Servetus burned, one of those men of scientific divination like there

are barely ten or twelve in the history of all mankind. What did Luther,

another founder of religion, do? He excited his friends the lords to run

after the peasants: “Kill them all, kill them, hell will take them back

sooner.” What did the triumphant Catholic Church do? It organized book

burnings. It kindled the stakes, held the noble people of Spain in

terror for three centuries. And recently when a free city, guilty of

having maintained its autonomy, was reconquered by its oppressors, did

we not see them killing by the thousands, men, women, children and using

the machine gun to grow bigger quickly the heaps of corpses? And those

who took part in the massacre, proud of their work, did they not come

cynically to brag about it? We could hear them right here.

(The speaker is alluding to the repression of the Paris Commune.)

But if the State is fierce when it comes to avenging an attack on its

power, it brings less passion in the condemnation [vindicte] of private

crimes, which little by little made it ashamed to apply the death

penalty. Gone are the days when the executioner, dressed in red, showed

his person behind the king: he is no longer the second personage of the

State, he is no longer the “living miracle” as he was called by Joseph

de Maistre; he has become the shame of society and does not even allow

himself to be known by his name. Men have been seen blowing off their

right hands so as not to be forced to serve as executioners. In many

countries where the death penalty still exists, people are beheaded,

hanged and garroted only inside prisons. Finally, in several countries,

the death penalty has been abolished; for more than a hundred years the

blood of the decapitated no longer fouls the soil of Tuscany, and

Switzerland is one of the nations which have had the honor of burning

the scaffold. And now it would be ashamed to restore it! Switzerland has

really little concern for her glory. Before it adopts the restoration of

the death penalty, let it at least be proven that the countries where

there are fewer crimes are those where the penalty is the most terrible!

However, it is precisely the opposite that happens: because blood calls

for blood, it is around the scaffolds and in the prisons that murderers

and thieves are formed. Our courts are schools of crime. What more vile

beings than all those whom public condemnation uses for repression:

informers and jailers, executioners and policemen!

So the death penalty is unnecessary. But is it fair?

No, it’s not fair. When an individual avenges himself in isolation, he

can consider his adversary responsible, but society, taken as a whole,

must understand the bond of solidarity which binds it to all its

members, virtuous or criminal, and recognize that in each crime it also

has its share. Did society take care of the criminal’s childhood? Did it

give him a complete education? Did it make the paths of life easier for

him? Has it always given him good examples? Has it ensured that he has

every chance of remaining honest, or of becoming so again after a first

fall? And if society has not done so, can the criminal not accuse it of

injustice?

The economist Stuart Mill, this honest scholar whom it is good to set as

an example to all his colleagues, compares all members of society to

runners to whom some Caesar would set the same goal. One of the

competitors is young, agile, fresh, another is already old: some are

sick, lame, legless. Would it be fair to condemn the latter: some to

misery, others to slavery or death, while the former would be crowned

victorious? And do we do anything else in society? Some have chances of

happiness, education and strength: they are declared virtuous; the

others are condemned by the environment to remain wallowing in misery or

in vice: is it on them that social condemnation must fall?

But there is yet another cause which forbids bourgeois society from

pronouncing the death penalty. It is that she [bourgeois society]

herself kills and kills by the millions. If there is a fact proven by

the study of hygiene, it is that the average life could be doubled.

Misery shortens the life of the poor. One profession kills in the space

of a few years, another in a few months. If all had the enjoyments of

life, they would live like peers in England, they would grow older than

sixty; but practically condemned either to forced labor or―which is

worse―to lack of work, they die before their time, and during their

short life, disease has tortured them. The calculation is easy to do. It

is at least 8 to 10 million men that society exterminates each year, in

Europe alone, not by killing them with gunshots, but by forcing them to

die by removing their couvert at the banquet of life. Ten years ago, an

English worker, Duggan, committed suicide with all his family. An

infamous newspaper, always busy extolling the merits of kings and the

powerful, had the impudence to congratulate itself on this workman’s

suicide. “What a good riddance,” they exclaimed, “workers for whom there

is no place, by killing themselves, relieve us of the disagreeable task

of killing them with our hands.” This is the cynical confession of what

all worshipers of the God Capital think!

What, then, is the remedy for all these mass murders, together with the

murders which are committed in isolation? You know in advance what a

socialist proposes. It is a complete social change, it is collectivism,

the appropriation of land and instruments by all those who work. It is

thus that the chasm of hatred can be filled between men, that misery and

the pursuit of fortune, that great adviser of crimes, will cease to

excite citizens against each other, and that social punishment can

finally rest. To the right of force, which prevails in wild nature, it

is time to make justice succeed, which is the ideal of any man worthy of

the name.

But in the transformed society, there may still be crimes.

Physiologically the type of the criminal may present itself again. What

will we do then? Will we kill the criminal? Certainly not. The one in

whom the crime comes from madness, we will treat him, as we treat the

mad or the other sick, by guarding against their violence. As for men

who have become criminals through fiery temperament or ardor of blood,

it would now be possible to offer them rehabilitation through heroism.

We have seen it a hundred times: galley slaves throw themselves into the

flames or into the waters to save the unfortunate and thus feel reborn

in the esteem of other men. The convicts whom the commune of Cartagena

freed and whom France made slaves again, were sublime in their heroism

during their short freedom of a few months. Obey, said Christianity, and

the people degraded themselves. Get rich, say the bourgeois to their

sons, and they seek to get rich in every way, either by violating the

law or, with more skill, by circumventing the law. Become heroes, say

the revolutionary socialists, and even brigands will be able to recover

through heroism.

Elisée Reclus.

(Lecture given at a meeting convened by the “Workers’ Association” of

Lausanne.)