💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › tiqqun-the-cybernetic-hypothesis.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:24:54. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Cybernetic Hypothesis
Author: Tiqqun
Language: en
Topics: cybernetics, technology
Source: Retrieved on May 29, 2010 from http://cybernet.jottit.com/

Tiqqun

The Cybernetic Hypothesis

“We can imagine a time when the machine of governance would replace —

for better or worse, who knows? — the insufficiency of the minds and

devices of politics that are customary today.”

— Father Dominique Dubarle, Le Monde, December 28^(th), 1948

“There is a striking contrast between the conceptual refinement and

dedication characterizing scientific and technical reasoning and the

summary and imprecise style that characterizes political reasoning...

One even asks oneself whether this is a kind of unsurpassable situation

marking the definitive limits of rationality, or if one may hope that

this impotence might be overcome someday and collective life be entirely

rationalized.”

— An encyclopedist cybernetician writing in the 1970s.

I

“There is probably no domain of man’s thinking or material activity that

cybernetics will not come to have a role in someday.”

Georges Boulanger, Dossier on Cybernetics: utopia or science of tomorrow

in the world today, 1968.

“The world circumscribing us [the “circumverse”] aims to have stable

circuits, equal cycles, the expected repetitions, and trouble-free

compatibility. It intends to eliminate all partial impulses and

immobilize bodies. Parallel to this, Borges discussed the anxiety of the

emperor who wanted to have such an exact map of the empire that he would

have to go back over his territory at all its points and bring it up to

scale, so much so that the monarch’s subjects spent as much time and

energy detailing it and maintaining it that the empire ‘itself’ fell

into ruins to the exact extent that its cartographical overview was

perfected — such is the madness of the great central Zero, its desire to

immobilize bodies that can only ever ‘be’ as representation.”

Jean-Francois Lyotard, Libidinal Economy, 1973.

“They wanted an adventure, and to live it out with you. In the end all

that’s all that can be said. They believed resolutely that the future

would be modern: different, impassioning, and definitely difficult.

Peopled by cyborgs and bare handed entrepreneurs, frenzied

stock-marketeers and turbine-men. And for those that are willing to see

it, the present is already like that. They think the future will be

human, feminine even — and plural; so that everyone can really live it,

so that everyone participates in it. They are the Enlightenment men

we’ve lost, infantrymen of progress, the inhabitants of the 21^(st)

century. They fight against ignorance, injustice, poverty, and suffering

of all kinds. They go where it’s happening, where things are going on.

They don’t want to miss out on a thing. They’re humble and courageous,

at the service of interests that are far beyond them, guided by a higher

principle. They can pose problems, and they can find solutions. They’ll

have us traversing the most perilous of frontiers, they’ll reach out a

hand to pull us up onto the shore of the future. They’re History

marching forth, at least what’s left of it, because the hardest part is

over. They’re the saints and the prophets, true socialists. They’ve

known for a long while that May 1968 wasn’t a revolution. The true

revolution is the one they’re making. Now it’s just a matter of

organization and transparency, intelligence and cooperation. A vast

program! Then...”

Excuse me? What? What’d you say? What program? The worst nightmares, you

know, are often the metamorphoses of a fable, fables PEOPLE tell their

kids to put them to sleep and perfect their moral education. The new

conquerors, who we’ll call the cyberneticians, do not comprise an

organized party — which would have made our work here a lot easier — but

rather a diffuse constellation of agents, all driven, possessed, and

blinded by the same fable. These are the murderers of Time, the

crusaders of Sameness, the lovers of fatality. These are the sectarians

of order, the reason-addicts, the go-between people. The Great Legends

may indeed be dead, as the post-modern vulgate often claims, but

domination is still comprised of master-fictions. Such was the case of

the Fable of the Bees published by Bernard de Mandeville in the first

years of the 18^(th) century, which contributed so much to the founding

of political economy and to justifying the advances made by capitalism.

Prosperity, the social order, and politics no longer depended on the

catholic virtues of sacrifice but on the pursuit by each individual of

his own interests: it declared the “private vices” to be guarantees of

the “common good.” Mandeville, the “Devil-Man” as PEOPLE called him at

the time, thus founded the liberal hypothesis, as opposed to the

religious spirit of his times, a hypothesis which would later have a

great influence on Adam Smith. Though it is regularly re-invoked, in a

renovated form given it by liberalism, this fable is obsolete today. For

critical minds, it follows that it’s not worth it anymore to critique

liberalism. A new model has taken its place, the very one that hides

behind the names “internet,” “new information and communications

technology,” the “new economy,” or genetic engineering. Liberalism is

now no longer anything but a residual justification, an alibi for the

everyday crimes committed by cybernetics.

Rationalist critics of the “economic creed” or of the “neo-technological

utopia,” anthropologist critics of utilitarianism in social sciences and

the hegemony of commodity exchange, marxist critics of the “cognitive

capitalism” that oppose to it the “communism of the masses,” political

critics of a communications utopia that resuscitates the worst phantasms

of exclusion, critics of the critiques of the “new spirit of

capitalism,” or critics of the “prison State” and surveillance hiding

behind neo-liberalism — critical minds hardly appear to be very inclined

to take into account the emergence of cybernetics as a new technology of

government, which federates and associates both discipline and

bio-politics, police and advertising, its ancestors in the exercise of

domination, all too ineffective today. That is to say, cybernetics is

not, as we are supposed to believe, a separate sphere of the production

of information and communication, a virtual space superimposed on the

real world. No, it is, rather, an autonomous world of apparatuses so

blended with the capitalist project that it has become a political

project, a gigantic “abstract machine” made of binary machines run by

the Empire, a new form of political sovereignty, which must be called an

abstract machine that has made itself into a global war machine. Deleuze

and Guattari link this rupture to a new kind of appropriation of war

machines by Nation-States: “Automation, and then the automation of the

war machine, only came truly into effect after the Second World War. The

war machine, considering the new antagonisms running through it, no

longer had War as its exclusive object, but rather it began to take

charge of and make Peace, policy, and world order into its object; in

short: such is its goal. Thus we see the inversion of Clausewitz’s

formula: politics becomes the continuation of war, and peace will

release, technologically, the unlimited material process of total war.

War ceases to be the materialization of the war machine, and rather it

is the war machine that itself becomes war itself materialized.” That’s

why it’s not worth it anymore to critique the cybernetic hypothesis

either: it has to be fought and defeated. It’s just a matter of time.

The Cybernetic Hypothesis is thus a political hypothesis, a new fable

that after the second world war has definitively supplanted the liberal

hypothesis. Contrary to the latter, it proposes to conceive biological,

physical, and social behaviors as something integrally programmed and

re-programmable. More precisely, it conceives of each individual

behavior as something “piloted,” in the last analysis, by the need for

the survival of a “system” that makes it possible, and which it must

contribute to. It is a way of thinking about balance, born in a crisis

context. Whereas 1914 sanctioned the decomposition of the

anthropological conditions for the verification of the liberal

hypothesis — the emergence of Bloom and the bankruptcy, plain to see in

flesh and bone in the trenches, of the idea of the individual and all

metaphysics of the subject — and 1917 sanctioned its historical

contestation by the Bolshevik “revolution,” 1940 on the other hand

marked the extinction of the idea of “society,” so obviously brought

about by totalitarian self-destruction. As the limit-experiences of

political modernity, Bloom and totalitarianism thus have been the most

solid refutations of the liberal hypothesis. What Foucault would later

call (in a playful tone) “the death of Mankind,” is none other than the

devastation brought about by these two kinds of skepticism, the one

directed at individuals, and the other at society, and brought about by

the Thirty Years’ War which had so effected the course of Europe and the

world in the first half of the last century. The problem posed by the

Zeitgeist of those years was once again how to “defend society” against

the forces driving it towards decomposition, how to restore the social

totality in spite of a general crisis of presence afflicting it in its

every atom. The cybernetic hypothesis corresponds, consequently, to a

desire for order and certitude, both in the natural and social sciences.

The most effective arrangement of a constellation of reactions animated

by an active desire for totality — and not just by a nostalgia for it,

as it was with the various variants of romanticism — the cybernetic

hypothesis is a relative of not only the totalitarian ideologies, but

also of all the Holisms, mysticisms, and solidarities, like those of

Durkheim, the functionalists, or the Marxists; it merely takes over from

them.

As an ethical position, the cybernetic hypothesis is the complement,

however strictly opposed to it, of the humanist pathos that has been

back in vogue since the 1940s and which is nothing more than an attempt

to act as if “Man” could still think itself intact after Auschwitz, an

attempt to restore the classical metaphysics on the subject in spite of

totalitarianism. But whereas the cybernetic hypothesis includes the

liberal hypothesis at the same time as it transcends it, humanism’s aim

is to extend the liberal hypothesis to the ever more numerous situations

that resist it: It’s the “bad faith” of someone like Sartre, to turn one

of the author’s most inoperative categories against him. The ambiguity

that constitutes modernity, seen superficially either as a disciplinary

process or as a liberal process, or as the realization of

totalitarianism or as the advent of liberalism, is contained and

suppressed in, with and by the new governance mentality emerging now,

inspired by the cybernetic hypothesis. This is but the life-sized

experimentation protocol of the Empire in formation. Its realization and

extension, with the devastating truth-effects it produces, is already

corroding all the social institutions and social relations founded by

liberalism, and transforming both the nature of capitalism and the

possibilities of its contestation. The cybernetic gesture affirms itself

in the negation of everything that escapes regulation, all the escape

routes that existence might have in the interstices of the norms and

apparatuses, all the behavioral fluctuations that do not follow, in

fine, from natural laws. Insofar as it has come to produce its own

truths, the cybernetic hypothesis is today the most consequential

anti-humanism, which pushes to maintain the general order of things, all

the while bragging that it has transcended the human.

Like any discourse, the cybernetic hypothesis could only check to verify

itself by associating the beings or ideas that reinforce it, by testing

itself through contact with them, and folding the world into its laws in

a continuous self-validation process. It’s now an ensemble of devices

aspiring to take control over all of existence and what exists. The

Greek word kubernèsis means “the act of piloting a vessel,” and in the

figurative sense, the “act of directing, governing.” In his 1981–1982

classes, Foucault insisted on working out the meaning of this category

of “piloting” in the Greek and Roman world, suggesting that it could

have a more contemporary scope to it: “the idea of piloting as an art,

as a theoretical and practical technology necessary for existence, is an

idea that I think is rather important and may eventually merit a closer

analysis; one can see at least three types of technology regularly

attached to this ‘piloting’ idea: first of all medicine; second of all,

political government; third of all self-direction and self-government.

These three activities (healing, directing others, and governing

oneself) are quite regularly attached to this image of piloting in

Greek, Hellenic and Roman literature. And I think that this ‘piloting’

image also paints a good picture of a kind of knowledge and practice

that the Greeks and Romans had a certain affinity for, for which they

attempted to establish a tekhnè (an art, a planned system of practices

connected to general principles, notions, and concepts): the Prince,

insofar as he must govern others, govern himself, heal the ills of the

city, the ills of the citizens, and his own ills; he who governs himself

as if he were governing a city, by healing his own ills; the doctor who

must give his advice not only about the ills of the body but about the

ills of individuals’ souls. And so you see you have here a whole pack of

ideas in the minds of the Greeks and Romans that have to do I think with

one and the same kind of knowledge, the same type of activity, the same

type of conjectural understanding. And I think that one could dig up the

whole history of that metaphor practically all the way up to the 16^(th)

century, when a whole new art of governing, centered around Reasons of

State, would split apart — in a radical way — self

government/medicine/government of others — not without this image of

‘piloting,’ as you well know, remaining linked to this activity, that

activity which we call the activity of government.”

What Foucault’s listeners are here supposed to know well and which he

refrains from pointing out, is that at the end of the 20^(th) century,

the image of piloting, that is, management, became the cardinal metaphor

for describing not only politics but also all human activity.

Cybernetics had become the project of unlimited rationalization. In

1953, when he published The Nerves of Government in the middle of the

development of the cybernetic hypothesis in the natural sciences, Karl

Deutsch, an American university social sciences academic, took the

political possibilities of cybernetics seriously. He recommended

abandoning the old concept that power was sovereign, which had too long

been the essence of politics. To govern would become a rational

coordination of the flows of information and decisions that circulate

through the social body. Three conditions would need to be met, he said:

an ensemble of capturers would have to be installed so that no

information originating from the “subjects” would be lost; information

handling by correlation and association; and a proximity to every living

community. The cybernetic modernization of power and the expired forms

of social authority thus can be seen as the visible production of what

Adam Smith called the “invisible hand,” which until then had served as

the mystical keystone of liberal experimentation. The communications

system would be the nerve system of societies, the source and

destination of all power. The cybernetic hypothesis thus expresses no

more or less than the politics of the “end of politics.” It represents

at the same time both a paradigm and a technique of government. Its

study shows that the police is not just an organ of power, but also a

way of thinking.

Cybernetics is the police-like thinking of the Empire, entirely animated

by an offensive concept of politics, both in an historical and

metaphysical sense. It is now completing its integration of the

techniques of individuation — or separation — and totalization that had

been developing separately: normalization, “anatomo-politics,” and

regulation, “bio-politics,” as Foucault calls it. I call his “techniques

of separation” the police of qualities. And, following Lukács, I call

his “techniques of totalization” the social production of society. With

cybernetics, the production of singular subjectivities and the

production of collective totalities work together like gears to

replicate History in the form of a feigned movement of evolution. It

acts out the fantasy of a Same that always manages to integrate the

Other; as one cybernetician puts it, “all real integration is based on a

prior differentiation.” In this regard, doubtless no one could put it

better than the “automaton” Abraham Moles, cybernetics’ most zealous

French ideologue, who here expresses this unparalleled murder impulse

that drives cybernetics: “We envision that one global society, one

State, could be managed in such a way that they could be protected

against all the accidents of the future: such that eternity changes them

into themselves. This is the ideal of a stable society, expressed by

objectively controllable social mechanisms.” Cybernetics is war against

all that lives and all that is lasting. By studying the formation of the

cybernetic hypothesis, I hereby propose a genealogy of imperial

governance. I then counterpose other wisdom for the fight, which it

erases daily, and by which it will be defeated.

II

“Synthetic life is certainly one of the possible products of the

evolution of techno-bureaucratic control, in the same way as the return

of the whole planet to the inorganic level, is -rather ironically —

another of the results of that same revolution, which has to do with the

technology of control.”

James R Beniger, The Control Revolution, 1986.

Even if the origins of the Internet device are today well known, it is

not uncalled for to highlight once again their political meaning. The

Internet is a war machine invented to be like the highway system, which

was also designed by the American Army as a decentralized internal

mobilization tool. The American military wanted a device which would

preserve the command structure in case of a nuclear attack. The response

would consist in an electronic network capable of automatically retaking

control over information itself if nearly the whole of the

communications links were destroyed, thus permitting the surviving

authorities to remain in communication with one another and make

decisions. With such a device, military authority could be maintained in

the face of the worst catastrophes. The Internet is thus the result of a

nomadic transformation of military strategy. With that kind of a plan at

its roots, one might doubt the supposedly anti-authoritarian

characteristics of this device. As is the Internet, which derives from

it, cybernetics is an art of war, the objective of which is to save the

head of the social body in case of catastrophe. What stands out

historically and politically during the period between the great wars,

and which the cybernetic hypothesis was a response to, was the

metaphysical problem of creating order out of disorder. The whole of the

great scientific edifice, in terms of what it had to do with the

determinist concepts of Newton’s mechanical physics, fell apart in the

first half of the century. The sciences, at that time, were like plots

of territory torn between the neo-positivist restoration and the

probabilist revolution, and slowly inching its way towards a historical

compromise so that the law could be re-established after the chaos, the

certain re-established after the probable. Cybernetics passed through

this whole movement — which began in Vienna at the turn of the century,

and was transported to England and the United States in the 1930s and

1940s, and constructed a Second Empire of Reason where the idea of the

Subject, up to that time considered indispensable, was absent. As a kind

of knowledge, it brought together an ensemble of heterogeneous

discourses all dealing with the practical problems of mastering

uncertainty. Discourses fundamentally expressing, in the various domains

of their application, the desire for a restoration of one order, and

furthermore the maintenance thereof.

Underlying the founding of Cybernetics was a context of total war. It

would be in vain to look for some malicious purpose or the traces of a

plot: one simply finds a handful of ordinary men mobilized by America

during the Second world war. Norbert Wiener, an American savant of

Russian origin, was charged with developing, with the aid of a few

colleagues, a machine for predicting and monitoring the positions of

enemy planes so as to more effectively destroy them. It was at the time

only possible at the time to predict with certitude certain correlations

between certain airplane positions and certain airplane

behaviors/movements. The elaboration of the “Predictor,” the prediction

machine ordered from Wiener, thus required a specific method of airplane

position handling and a comprehension of how the weapon interacts with

its target. The whole history of cybernetics has aimed to do away with

the impossibility of determining at the same time the position and

behavior of bodies. Wiener’s innovation was to express the problem of

uncertainty as an information problem, within a temporal series where

certain data is already known, and others not, and to consider the

object and the subject of knowledge as a whole, as a “system.” The

solution consisted in constantly introducing into the play of the

initial data the gap seen between the desired behavior and the effective

behavior, so that they coincide when the gap closes, like the mechanism

of a thermostat. The discovery goes considerably beyond the frontiers of

the experimental sciences: controlling a system would in the end require

a circulation of information to be instituted, called feed-back, or

retro-action. The wide implications of these results for the natural and

social sciences was exposed in 1948 in Paris in a work presented under

the foreboding name of Cybernetics, which for Wiener meant the doctrine

of “control and communication between animal and machine.”

Cybernetics thus emerged as a simple, inoffensive theory of information,

a theory for handling information with no precise origin, always

potentially present in the environment around any situation. It claims

that the control of a system is obtained by establishing an optimum

degree of communication between the parties to it. This objective calls

above all for the continuous extortion of information — a process of the

separation of beings from their qualities, of the production of

differences. In other words, as it were, mastery of a uncertainty would

arise from the proper representation and memorization of the past. The

spectacular image, binary mathematical encoding — invented by Claude

Shannon in Mathematical Theory of Communication in the very same year

that the cybernetic hypothesis was first expressed — on the one hand

they’ve invented memory machines that do not alter information, and put

incredible effort into miniaturizing them (this is the determinant

strategy behind today’s nanotechnology) and on the other they conspire

to create such conditions on the collective level. Thus put into form,

information would then be directed towards the world of beings,

connecting them to one another in the same way as commodity circulation

guarantees they will be put into equivalence. Retro-action, key to the

system’s regulation, now calls for communication in the strict sense.

Cybernetics is the project of recreating the world within an infinite

feedback loop involving these two moments: representation separating,

communication connecting, the first bringing death, the second mimicking

life.

The cybernetic discourse begins by dismissing as a false problem the

controversies of the 19^(th) century that counterposed mechanist visions

to vitalist or organicist visions of the world. It postulates a

functional analogy between living organisms and machines, assimilated

into the idea of “systems.” Thus the cybernetic hypothesis justifies two

kinds of scientific and social experiments. The first essentially aimed

to turn living beings into machines, to master, program, and determine

mankind and life, society and its “future.” This gave fuel for a return

of eugenics as bionic fantasy. It seeks, scientifically, the end of

History; initially here we are dealing with the terrain of control. The

second aims to imitate the living with machines, first of all as

individuals, which has now led to the development of robots and

artificial intelligence; then as collectives — and this has given rise

to the new intense circulation of information and the setting up of

“networks.” Here we’re dealing rather with the terrain of communication.

However much they may be socially comprised of highly diversified

populations — biologists, doctors, computer scientists, neurologists,

engineers, consultants, police, ad-men, etc. — the two currents among

the cyberneticians are perfectly in harmony concerning their common

fantasy of a Universal Automaton, analogous to Hobbes’ vision of the

State in Leviathan, “the artificial man (or animal).”

The unity of cybernetic progress arises from a particular method; it has

imposed itself as the world-wide method of universal enrollment,

simultaneously a rage to experiment, and a proliferating

oversimplification. It corresponds to the explosion of applied

mathematics that arose subsequent to the despair caused by the Austrian

Kurt Godel when he demonstrated that all attempts to give a logical

foundation to mathematics and unify the sciences was doomed to

“incompleteness.” With the help of Heisenberg, more than a century of

positivist justifications had just collapsed. It was Von Neumann that

expressed to the greatest extreme this abrupt feeling that the

foundations had been annihilated. He interpreted the logical crisis of

mathematics as the mark of the unavoidable imperfection of all human

creations. And consequently he laid out a logic that could only come

from a robot! From being a pure mathematician, he made himself an agent

of scientific crossbreeding, of a general mathematization that would

allow a reconstruction from below, in practice, of the lost unity of the

sciences of which cybernetics was to be the most stable theoretical

expression. Not a demonstration, not a speech, not a book, and no place

has not since then been animated by the universal language of

explanatory diagrams, the visual form of reasoning. Cybernetics

transports the rationalization process common to bureaucracy and to

capitalism up onto the plane of total templating (modeling). Herbert

Simon, the prophet of Artificial Intelligence, took up the Von Neumann

program again in the 1960s, to build a thinking automaton. It was to be

a machine equipped with a program, called expert system, which was to be

capable of handling information so as to resolve the problems that every

particular domain of technique had to deal with, and by association, to

be able to solve all the practical problems encountered by humanity! The

General Problem Solver (GPS), created in 1972, was the model that this

universal technique that gathered together all the others, the model of

all models, the most applied intellectualism, the practical realization

of the preferred adage of the little masters without mastery, according

to which “there are no problems, there are only solutions.”

The cybernetic hypothesis progresses indistinctly as theory and

technology, the one always certifying the other. In 1943, Wiener met

John Von Neumann, who was in charge of building machines fast and

powerful enough to carry out the Manhattan Project that 15,000 scholars

and engineers, and 300,000 technicians and workers were working on,

under the direction of the physicist Robert Oppenheimer: the modern

computer and the atomic bomb, were thus born together. From the

perspective of contemporary imagining, the “communications utopia” is

thus the complementary myth to the myth of the invention of nuclear

power and weaponry: it is always a question of doing away with

being-together (the ensemble of beings) either by an excess of life or

an excess of death, either by terrestrial fusion or by cosmic suicide.

Cybernetics presents itself as the response most suited to deal with the

Great Fear of the destruction of the world and of the human species. And

Von Neumann was its double agent, the “inside outsider” par excellence.

The analogy between his descriptive categories for his machines, living

organisms, and Wiener’s categories sealed the alliance between

cybernetics and computer science. A few years would pass before

molecular biology, when decoding DNA, would in turn use that theory of

information to explain man as an individual and as a species, giving an

unequalled technical power to the experimental genetic manipulation of

human beings.

The way that the systems metaphor evolved towards the network metaphor

in social discourse between the 1950s and 1980s points towards the other

fundamental analogy constituting the cybernetic hypothesis. It also

indicates a profound transformation of the latter. Because if PEOPLE

talked about “systems,” among cyberneticians it would be by comparison

with the nervous system, and if PEOPLE talk today about the cognitive

“network” sciences, THEY are thinking about the neuronal network.

Cybernetics is the assimilation of the totality of the phenomena that

exist into brain phenomena. By posing the mind as the alpha and omega of

the world, cybernetics has guaranteed itself a place as the avant-garde

of all avant-gardes, the one that they will now all forever be running

after. It effectively implements, at the start, the identity between

life, thought, and language. This radical Monism is based on an analogy

between the notions of information and energy. Wiener introduced it by

grafting onto his discourse the discourse of 19^(th) century

thermodynamics; the operation consisted in comparing the effect of time

on an energy system with the effect of time on an information system. A

system, to the extent that it is a system, is never pure and perfect:

there is a degradation of its energy to the extent that it undergoes

exchanges, in the same way as information degrades as it is circulated

around. This is what Clausius called entropy. Entropy, considered as a

natural law, is the cybernetician’s Hell. It explains the decomposition

of life, disequilibrium in economy, the dissolution of social bonds,

decadence... Initially, speculatively, cybernetics claimed that it had

thus opened up a common ground on which it would be possible to carry

out the unification of the natural and human sciences.

What would end up being called the “second cybernetics” was the superior

project of a vast experimentation on human societies:

anthropotechnology. The cybernetician’s mission is to fight the general

entropy threatening living beings, machines, and societies; that is, to

create the experimental conditions for a permanent revitalization,

endlessly restoring the integrity of the whole. “The important thing

isn’t that mankind is present, but that it exists as a living support

for technical ideas,” says Raymond Ruyer, the humanist commentator. With

the elaboration and development of cybernetics, the ideal of the

experimental sciences, already at the origins of political economy via

Newtonian physics, would once again lend a strong arm to capitalism.

Since then, the laboratory the cybernetic hypothesis carries out its

experiments in has been called “contemporary society.” After the end of

the 1960s, thanks to the techniques that it taught, this ‘second

cybernetics’ is no longer a mere laboratory hypothesis, but a social

experiment. It aims to construct what Giorgio Cesarano calls a

stabilized animal society, in which “[concerning termites, ants, and

bees] the natural presupposition is that they operate automatically, and

that the individual is negated, so the animal society as a whole

(termite colony, anthill, or beehive) is conceived of as a kind of

plural individual, the unity of which determines and is determined by

the distribution of roles and functions — all within the framework of an

‘organic composite’ where one would be hard pressed to not see a

biological model for the teleology of Capital.”

III

“You don’t have to be a prophet to acknowledge that the modern sciences,

in their installation within society, will not delay in being determined

and piloted by the new basic science: cybernetics. This science

corresponds to the determination of man as a being the essence of which

is activity in the social sphere. It is, in effect the theory whose

object is to take over all possible planning and organization of human

labor.”

Martin Heidegger, The End of Philosophy and the Task of Thought, 1966

“But cybernetics on the other hand, sees itself as forced to recognize

that a general regulation of human existence is still not achievable at

the present time. This is why mankind still has a function,

provisionally, within the universal domain of cybernetic science, as a

“factor of disturbance.” The plans and acts of men, apparently free, act

as a disturbance. But very recently, science has also taken over

possession of this field of human existence. It has taken up the

rigorously methodical exploration and planning of the possible future of

man as an active player. In so doing, it figures in all available

information about what there is about mankind that may be planned.

Martin Heidegger, The Origin of Art and the Destination of Thought, 1967

In 1946, a conference of scientists took place in New York, the

objective of which was to extend the cybernetic hypothesis to the social

sciences. The participants agreed to make a clear disqualification of

all the philistine philosophies that based themselves on the individual

or on society. Socio-Cybernetics was to concentrate on the intermediary

phenomena of social feedback, like those that the American

anthropological school believed it had found at the time between

“culture” and “personality,” to put together a characterization of the

various nations, intended for use by American soldiers. The operation

consisted in reducing dialectical thought to an observation of processes

of circular causality within what was considered a priori to be an

invariable social totality, where contradiction and non-adaptation

merged, as in the central category of cybernetic psychology: the double

bind. As a science of society, cybernetics was intended to invent a kind

of social regulation that would leave behind the macro-institutions of

State and Market, preferring to work through micro-mechanisms of control

— preferring devices. The fundamental law of socio-cybernetics is as

follows: growth and control develop in inverse proportion to each other.

It is thus easier to construct a cybernetic social order on the small

scale: “the quick re-establishment of balance requires that

inconsistencies be detected at the very location where they are

produced, and that corrective action take place in a decentralized

manner.” Under the influence of Gregory Bateson, the Von Neumann of the

social sciences, and of the American sociological tradition, obsessed by

the question of deviance (the hobo, the immigrant, the criminal, the

youth, me, you, him, etc.), socio-cybernetics was aimed, as a priority,

towards studying the individual as a feedback locus, that is, as a

“self-disciplined personality.” Bateson became the social editor in

chief of the second half of the 20^(th) century, and was involved in the

origins of the “family therapy” movement, as well as those of the “sales

techniques training” movement developed at Palo Alto. Since the

cybernetic hypothesis as a whole calls for a radically new physical

structuring of the subject, whether individual or collective, its aim is

to hollow it out. It disqualifies as a myth individual

inwardness/internal dialogue, and with it all 19^(th) century

psychology, including psychoanalysis. It’s no longer a question of

removing the subject from the traditional exterior bonds, as the liberal

hypothesis had intended, but of reconstructing the social bonds by

depriving the subject of all substance. Each person was to become a

fleshless envelope, the best possible conductor of social communication,

the locus of an infinite feedback loop which is made to have no nodes.

The cyberneticization process thus completes the “process of

civilization,” to where bodies and their emotions are abstracted within

the system of symbols. “In this sense,” writes Lyotard, “the system

presents itself as an avant-garde machine that drags humanity along

after it, by dehumanizing it so as to rehumanize it at another level of

normative capacities. Such is the great pride of the deciders, such is

their blindness... Even any permissiveness relative to the various games

is only granted on the condition that greater performance levels will be

produced. The redefinition of the norms of life consists in an

amelioration of the skills of the system in matters of power.”

Spurred on by the Cold War and its “witch hunts,” the

socio-cyberneticians thus tirelessly hunted down the pathological

couched behind the normal, the communist sleeping in everybody. In the

1950s, to this effect, they formed the Mental Health Federation, where

an original and quasi-final solution was elaborated to the problems of

the community and of the times: “It is the ultimate goal of mental

health to help people to live with their peers in the same world... The

concept of mental health is co-extensive with international order and

the global community, which must be developed so as to make men capable

of living in peace with each other.” By rethinking mental problems and

social pathologies in terms of informatics, cybernetics gave rise to a

new politics of subjects, resting on communication and transparency to

oneself and to others. Spurred on by Bateson, Wiener in turn began

thinking about a socio-cybernetics with a scope broader than the mere

project of mental hygiene. He had no trouble affirming the defeat of the

liberal experimentation: on the market information is always impure and

imperfect because of the lying implicit in advertising and the

monopolistic concentration of the media, and because of the ignorance of

the State, which as a collective contains less information than civil

society. The extension of commodity relations, by increasing the size of

communities and feedback chains, renders distortions of communication

and problems of social control ever more probable. The past processes of

accumulation had not only destroyed the social bonds, but social order

itself appeared cybernetically impossible within capitalism. The

cybernetic hypothesis’ stroke of luck can thus be understood in light of

the crises encountered by 20^(th) century capitalism, which questioned

once again the supposed “laws” of classical political economy — and that

was where the cybernetic discourse stepped into the breach.

The contemporary history of economic discourse must be looked at from

the angle of this increasing problem of information. From the crisis of

1929 to 1945, economists’ attention was focused on questions of

anticipation, uncertainty regarding demand, adjustments between

production and consumption, and forecasts of economic activity. Smith’s

classical economics began to give out like the other scientific

discourses directly inspired by Newton’s physics. The preponderant role

that cybernetics was to play in the economy after 1945 can be understood

in light of Marx’s intuitive observation that “in political economy the

law is determined by its contrary, that is, the absence of laws. The

true law of political economy is chance.” In order to prove that

capitalism was not a factor in entropy and social chaos, the economic

discourse gave primacy to a cybernetic redefinition psychology starting

in the 1940s. It based itself on the “game theory” model, developed by

Von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern in 1944. The first

socio-cyberneticians showed that homo economicus could only exist on the

condition that there would be a total transparency of his preferences,

regarding himself and others. In the absence of an ability to understand

the whole ensemble of the behaviors of other economic actors, the

utilitarian idea of a rationality of micro-economic choices is but a

fiction. On the impetus of Friedrich von Hayek, the utilitarian paradigm

was thus abandoned in preference to a theory of spontaneous mechanisms

coordinating individual choices, acknowledging that each agent only has

a limited understanding of the behaviors of others and of his or her own

behaviors. The response consisted in sacrificing the autonomy of

economic theory by grafting it onto the cybernetic promise of a

balancing of systems. The hybrid discourse that resulted from this,

later called “neo-liberal,” considered as a virtue the optimal market

allocation of information — and no longer that of wealth — in society.

In this sense, the market is but the instrument of a perfect

coordination of players thanks to which the social totality can find a

durable equilibrium. Capitalism thus becomes unquestionable, insofar as

it is presented as a simple means — the best possible means — of

producing social self-regulation.

Like in 1929, the planetary movement of contestation of 1968, and,

moreover, the post-1973 crisis present for political economy once more

the problem of uncertainty, this time on an existential and political

terrain. High-flown theories abound, with the old chatterbox Edgar Morin

and “complexity” theory, and Joel de Rosnay, that eccentric simpleton,

and “society in real-time.” Ecologist philosophy as well was nourished

by this new mystique of the Great Totality. Now totality was no longer

an origin to be rediscovered, but a future to build. For cybernetics it

is no longer a question of predicting the future, but of reproducing the

present. It is no longer a question of static order, but of a dynamic

self-organization. The individual is no longer credited with any power

at all: his knowledge of the world is imperfect, he doesn’t know his own

desires, he is opaque to himself, everything escapes him, as

spontaneously cooperative, naturally empathetic, and fatally in

interdependent as he his. He knows nothing of all this, but THEY know

everything about him. Here, the most advanced form of contemporary

individualism comes into being; Hayekian philosophy is grafted onto him,

for which all uncertainty, all possibilities of any event taking place

is but a temporary problem, a question of his ignorance. Converted into

an ideology, liberalism serves as a cover for a whole group of new

technical and scientific practices, a diffuse “second cybernetics,”

which deliberately erases the name it was originally baptized with.

Since the 1960s, the term cybernetics itself has faded away into hybrid

terms. The science explosion no longer permits any theoretical

unification, in effect: the unity of cybernetics now manifests itself

practically through the world itself, which it configures every day. It

is the tool by which capitalism has adjusted its capacity for

disintegration and its quest after profit to one another. A society

threatened by permanent decomposition can be all the more mastered when

an information network, an autonomous “nervous system” is in place

allowing it to be piloted, wrote the State lackeys Simon Nora and Alain

Minc, discussing the case of France in their 1978 report. What PEOPLE

call the “New Economy” today, which brings together under the same

official nomenclature of cybernetic origin the ensemble of the

transformations that the western nations have undergone in the last

thirty years, is but an ensemble of new subjugations, a new solution to

the practical problem of the social order and its future, that is: a new

politics.

Under the influence of informatization, the supply and demand adjustment

techniques originating between 1930–1970 have been purified, shortened,

and decentralized. The image of the “invisible hand” is no longer a

justificatory fiction but is now the effective principle behind the

social production of society, as it materializes within computer

procedures. The Internet simultaneously permits one to know consumer

preferences and to condition them with advertising. On another level,

all information regarding the behavior of economic agents circulates in

the form of headings managed by financial markets. Each actor in

capitalist valorization is a real-time back-up of quasi-permanent

feedback loops. On the real markets, as on the virtual markets, each

transaction now gives rise to a circulation of information concerning

the subjects and objects of the exchange that goes beyond simply fixing

the price, which has become a secondary aspect. On the one hand, people

have realized the importance of information as a factor in production

distinct from labor and capital and playing a decisive role in “growth”

in the form of knowledge, technical innovation, and distributed

capacities. On the other, the sector specializing in the production of

information has not ceased to increase in size. In light of its

reciprocal reinforcement of these two tendencies, today’s capitalism

should be called the information economy. Information has become wealth

to be extracted and accumulated, transforming capitalism into a simply

auxiliary of cybernetics. The relationship between capitalism and

cybernetics has inverted over the course of the century: whereas after

the 1929 crisis, PEOPLE built a system of information concerning

economic activity in order to serve the needs of regulation — this was

the objective of all planning — the economy after the 1973 crisis put

the social self-regulation process came to be based on the valorization

of information.

IV

“If motorized machines constituted the second age of the technical

machine, cybernetic and informational machines form a third age that

reconstructs a generalized regime of subjection: recurrent and

reversible ‘humans-machines systems’ replace the old nonrecurring and

nonreversible relations of subjection between the two elements; the

relation between human and machine is based on internal, mutual

communication, and no longer on usage or action. In the organic

composition of capital, variable capital defines a regime of subjection

of the worker (human surplus value), the principal framework of which is

the business or factory. But with automation comes a progressive

increase in the proportion of constant capital; we then see a new kind

of enslavement: at the same time the work regime changes, surplus value

becomes machinic, and the framework expands to all of society. It could

also be said that a small amount of subjectification took us away from

machinic enslavement, but a large amount brings us back to it.”

Gilles Deleuze, Felix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, 1980

“The only moment of permanence of a class as such is that which has a

consciousness of its permanence for itself: the class of managers of

capital as social machine. The consciousness that connotes is, with the

greatest coherence, that of apocalypse, of self-destruction.”

Giorgio Cesarano, Survival Manual, 1975

Nothing expresses the contemporary victory of cybernetics better than

the fact that value can now be extracted as information about

information. The commodity-cybernetician, or “neo-liberal” logic,

extends over all activity, including that which is still not

commodified, with an unflagging support of modern States. More

generally, the corollary to the precarization of capitalism’s objects

and subjects is a growth of circulation in information on their subject:

this is as true for unemployed workers as it is for cops. Cybernetics

consequently aims to disturb and control people in one and the same

movement. It is founded on terror, which is a factor in its evolution —

the evolution of economic growth, moral progress — because it supplies

an occasion for the production of information. The state of emergency,

which is proper to all crises, is what allows self-regulation to be

relaunched, and to maintain itself as a perpetual movement. Whereas the

scheme of classical economy where a balance of supply and demand was to

permit “growth” and thusly to permit collective well-being, it is now

“growth” which is considered an endless road towards balance. It is thus

just to critique western modernity as a “infinite mobilization” the

destination of which is “movement towards more movement.” But from a

cybernetic point of view, the self-production that equally characterizes

the State, the Market, robots, wage workers, or the jobless, is

indiscernible from the self-control that moderates and slows it down.

It comes across clearly then that cybernetics is not just one of the

various aspects of contemporary life, its neo-technological component,

for instance, but rather it is the point of departure and arrival of the

new capitalism. Cybernetic Capitalism — what does that mean? It means

that since the 1970s we’ve been dealing with an emerging social

formation that has taken over from Fordist capitalism which results from

the application of the cybernetic hypothesis to political economy.

Cybernetic capitalism develops so as to allow the social body,

devastated by Capital, to reform itself and offer itself up for one more

process of accumulation. On the one hand capitalism must grow, which

implies destruction. On the other, it needs to reconstruct the “human

community,” which implies circulation. “There is,” writes Lyotard, “two

uses for wealth, that is importance-power: a reproductive use and a

pillage use. The first is circular, global, organic; the second is

partial, death-dealing, jealous... The capitalist is a conqueror, and

the conqueror is a monster, a centaur. His front side feeds off of

reproducing the regulated system of controlled metamorphoses under the

law of the commodity-talion, and its rear side off of pillaging

overexcited energies. On the one hand, to appropriate, and thus

preserve, that is, reproduce in equivalence, reinvest; on the other to

take and destroy, steal and flee, hollowing out another space, another

time.” The crises of capitalism, as Marx saw them, always came from a

de-articulation between the time of conquest and the time of

reproduction. The function of cybernetics is to avoid crises by ensuring

the coordination between Capital’s “front side” and “rear side.” Its

development is an endogenous response to the problem posed to capitalism

— how to develop without fatal disequilibrium arising.

In the logic of Capital, the development of the piloting function, of

“control,” corresponds to the subordination of the sphere of

accumulation to the sphere of circulation. For the critique of political

economy, circulation should be no less suspect than production, in

effect. It is, as Marx knew, but a particular case of production as

considered in general. The socialization of the economy — that is, the

interdependence between capitalists and the other members of the social

body, the “human community” — the enlargement of Capital’s human base,

makes the extraction of surplus value which is at the source of profit

no longer centered around the relations of exploitation instituted by

the wage system. Valorization’s center of gravity has now moved over to

the sphere of circulation. In spite of its inability to reinforce the

conditions of exploitation, which would bring about a crisis of

consumption, capitalist accumulation can still nevertheless survive on

the condition that the production-consumption cycle is accelerated, that

is, on the condition that the production process accelerates as much as

commodity circulation does. What has been lost to the economy on the

static level can be compensated on the dynamic level. The logic of flows

is to dominate the logic of the finished product. Speed is now taking

primacy over quantity, as a factor in wealth. The hidden face of the

maintenance of accumulation is the acceleration of circulation. The

function of the control devices is thus to maximize the volume of

commodity flows by minimizing the events, obstacles, and accidents that

would slow them down. Cybernetic capitalism tends to abolish time

itself, to maximize fluid circulation to the maximum: the speed of

light. Such is already the case for certain financial transactions. The

categories of “real time,” of “just in time,” show clearly this hatred

of duration. For this very reason, time is our ally.

This propensity towards control by capitalism is not new. It is only

post-modern in the sense that post-modernity has been confused with the

latest manifestation of modernity. It is for this reason that

bureaucracy developed at the end of the 19^(th) century and computer

technology developed after the Second World War. The cybernetization of

capitalism started at the end of the 1870s with the growing control of

production, distribution, and consumption. Information regarding these

flows has since then had a central strategic importance as a condition

for valorization. The historian James Beniger states that the first

control-related problems came about when the first collisions took place

between trains, putting commodities and human lives in peril. The

signalization of the railways, travel time measurement and data

transmission devices had to be invented so as to avoid such

“catastrophes.” The telegraph, synchronized clocks, organizational

charts in large enterprises, weighing systems, roadmaps, performance

evaluation procedures, wholesalers, assembly lines, centralized

decision-making, advertising in catalogues, and mass communications

media were the devices invented during this period to respond, in all

spheres of the economic circuit, to a generalized crisis of control

connected to the acceleration of production set off by the industrial

revolution in the United States. Information and control systems thus

developed at the same time as the capitalist process of transformation

of materials was growing and spreading. A class of middlemen, which

Alfred Chandler called the “visible hand” of Capital, formed and grew.

After the end of the 19^(th) century, it was clear enough to PEOPLE that

expectability [had] become a source of profit as such and a source of

confidence. Fordism and Taylorism were part of this movement, as was the

development of control over the mass of consumers and over public

opinion via marketing and advertising, in charge of extorting from them

by force, and then putting to work, their “preferences,” which according

to the hypotheses of the marginalist economists, were the true source of

value. Investment in organizational or purely technical planning and

control technologies became more and more salable. After 1945,

cybernetics supplied capitalism with a new infrastructure of machines —

computers — and above all with an intellectual technology that permitted

the regulation of the circulation of flows within society, and making

those flows exclusively commodity flows.

That the economic sectors of information, communication, and control

have taken ever more of a part in the economy since the Industrial

Revolution, and that “intangible labor” has grown relative to tangible

labor, is nothing surprising or new. Today these account for the

mobilization of more than 2/3 of the workforce. But this isn’t enough to

fully define cybernetic capitalism. Because its equilibrium and the

growth depend continually on its control capacities, its nature has

changed. Insecurity, much more than rarity, is the core of the present

capitalist economy. As Wittgenstein understood by looking at the 1929

crisis — and as did Keynes in his wake — there is a strong bond between

the “state of trust” and the curbing of the marginal effectiveness of

Capital, he wrote, in chapter XII of General Theory, in February 1934 —

the economy rests definitively on the “play of language.” Markets, and

with them commodities and merchants, the sphere of circulation in

general, and, consequently, business, the sphere of production as a

place of the anticipation of coming levels of yield, do not exist

without conventions, social norms, technical norms, norms of the truth,

on a meta-level which brings bodies and things into existence as

commodities, even before they are subject to pricing. The control and

communications sectors develop because commodity valorization needs to

have a looping circulation of information parallel to the actual

circulation of commodities, the production of a collective belief that

objectivizes itself in values. In order to come about, all exchanges

require “investments of form” — information about a formulation of what

is to be exchanged — a formatting that makes it possible to put things

into equivalence even before such a putting of things into equivalence

has effectively taken place, a conditioning that is also a condition of

agreement about the market. It’s true for goods, and it’s true for

people. Perfecting the circulation of information will mean perfecting

the market as a universal instrument of coordination. Contrary to what

the liberal hypothesis had supposed, to sustain a fragile capitalism,

contracts are not sufficient unto themselves within social relations.

PEOPLE began to understand after 1929 that all contracts need to come

with controls. Cybernetics entered into the operation of capitalism with

the intention of minimizing uncertainties, incommensurability, the kinds

of anticipation problems that can interfere in any commodity

transaction. It contributes to consolidating the basis for the

installation of capitalism’s mechanisms, to oiling Capital’s abstract

machine.

With cybernetic capitalism, the political moment of political economy

subsequently dominates its economic moment. Or, as Joan Robinson

understands it looking from the perspective of economic theory, in her

comments on Keynes: “As soon as one admits the uncertainty of the

forecasts that guide economic behavior, equilibrium has no more

importance and History takes its place.” The political moment, here

understood in the broader sense of that which subjugates, that which

normalizes, that which determines what will happen by way of bodies and

can record itself in socially recognized value, what extracts form from

forms-of-life, is as essential to “growth” as it is to the reproduction

of the system: on the one hand the capture of energies, their

orientation, their crystallization, become the primary source of

valorization; on the other hand, surplus value can be extracted from any

point on the bio-political tissue on the condition that the latter

reconstitutes itself incessantly. That the ensemble of expenditures has

a tendency to morph into valorizable qualities also means that Capital

permeates all living flows: the socialization of the economy and the

anthropomorphosis of Capital are two symbiotic, indissoluble processes.

In order for these processes to be carried out, it suffices and is

necessary that all contingent action be dealt with by a combination of

surveillance and data capture devices. The former are inspired by

prison, insofar as they introduce a centralized system of panoptical

visibility. These have for a long while been monopolized by the modern

State. The latter, the data capture devices, are inspired by computer

technology, insofar as they are part of the construction of a

decentralized real-time gridding system. The common intent of these

devices is total transparency, an absolute correspondence between the

map and the territory, a will to knowledge accumulated to such degree

that it becomes a will to power. One of the advancements made by

cybernetics has consisted in enclosing its surveillance and monitoring

systems upon themselves, guaranteeing that the surveillers and the

monitorers are themselves surveilled and/or monitored, with the

development of a socialization of control which is the trademark of the

so-called “information society.” The control sector becomes autonomous

because of the need to control control, since commodity flows are

overlaid by their double, flows of information the circulation and

security of which must in turn be optimized. At the summit of this

terracing of control, state control, the police, and the law,

self-legitimating violence, and judicial authority play the role of

controllers of last resort. The surveillance one-upmanship that

characterizes “control societies” is explained in simple terms by

Deleuze, who says: “they have leaks everywhere.” This incessantly

confirms the necessity for control. “In discipline societies, one never

ceased to recommence (from school to barracks, etc...) [the disciplinary

process], whereas in control societies nothing is ever finished.”

Thus there is nothing surprising about the fact that the development of

cybernetic capitalism has been accompanied by the development of all the

forms of repression, by hyper-securitarianism. Traditional discipline,

the generalization of a state of emergency — emergenza — are

transplanted to grow inside a whole system focused on the fear of any

threat. The apparent contradiction between the reinforcement of the

repressive functions of the State and the neo-liberal economic discourse

that preaches “less State” — and permits Loïc Wacquant for instance to

go into a critique of the liberal ideology hiding the increasing “penal

State” — can only be understood in light of the cybernetic hypothesis.

Lyotard explains it: “there is, in all cybernetic systems, a unity of

reference that permits one to measure the disparity produced by the

introduction of an event within the system, and then, thanks to such

measurement, to translate that event into information to be fed into the

system; then, in sum, if it is a regulated ensemble in homeostasis, to

annul that disparity and return the system to the quantities of energy

or information that it had before... Let’s stop here a moment. We see

how the adoption of this perspective on society, that is, of the

despotic fantasies of the masters, of placing themselves at the supposed

location of the central zero, and thus of identifying themselves with

the matrix of Nothingness... must force one to extend one’s idea of

threat and thus of defense. Since what event would NOT be a threat from

this point of view? All are; indeed, because they are disturbances of a

circular nature, reproducing the same, and requiring a mobilization of

energy for purposes of appropriation and elimination. Is this too

‘abstract’? Should I give an example? It is the very project that is

being perpetrated in France on high levels, the institution of an

operational Defense of the territory, already granted an operating

Center of the army, the specific focus of which is to ward off the

‘internal’ threat, which is born within the dark recesses of the social

body, of which the “national state” claims to be the clairvoyant head:

this clairvoyance is called the national identification registry; ...

the translation of events into information for the system is called

intelligence, ... and the execution of regulatory orders and their

inscription into the “social body,” above all when the latter is racked

by some kind of intense emotion, for instance by the panicked fear which

would seize hold of it if a nuclear war were to be triggered (or if some

kind of a wave of protest, subversion, or civil desertion considered

insane were to hit) — such execution requires an assiduous and

fine-grained infiltration of the transmission channels in the social

‘flesh,’ or, as some superior officer or other put it quite marvelously,

the ‘police of spontaneous movements.’” Prison is thus at the summit of

a cascade of control devices, the guarantor of last resort that no

disturbing event will take place within the social body that would

hinder the circulation of goods and persons. The logic of cybernetics

being to replace centralized institutions and sedentary forms of control

by tracing devices and nomadic forms of control, prison, as a classical

surveillance device, is obviously to be expanded and prolonged with

monitoring devices such as the electronic bracelet, for instance. The

development of community policing in the English speaking world, of

“proximity policing” in France, also responds to a cybernetic logic

intended to ward off all events, and organize feedback. Within this

logic, then, disturbances in a given zone can be all the better

suppressed/choked off when they are absorbed/deadened by the closest

system sub-zones.

Whereas repression has, within cybernetic capitalism, the role of

warding off events, prediction is its corollary, insofar as it aims to

eliminate all uncertainty connected to all possible futures. That’s the

gamble of statistics technologies. Whereas the technologies of the

Providential State were focused on the forecasting of risks, whether

probabilized or not, the technologies of cybernetic capitalism aim to

multiply the domains of responsibility/authority. Risk-based discourse

is the motor for the deployment of the cybernetic hypothesis; it is

first distributed diffusely so as then to be internalized. Because risks

are much more accepted when those that are exposed to them have the

impression that they’ve chosen to take them on, when they feel

responsible, and most of all when they have the feeling that they

control them and are themselves the masters of such risks. But, as one

expert admits, “zero risk” is a non-existent situation: “the idea of

risk weakens causal bonds, but in so doing it does not make them

disappear. On the contrary; it multiplies them. ...To consider danger in

terms of risk is necessarily to admit that one can never absolutely

protect oneself against it: one may manage it, tame it, but never

annihilate it.” It is in its permanence in the system that risk is an

ideal tool for affirming new forms of power, to the benefit of the

growing stranglehold of devices on collectives and individuals. It

eliminates everything that is at stake in conflicts by obligatorily

bringing individuals together around the management of threats that are

supposed to concern all of them in the same way. The argument that THEY

would like to make us buy is as follows: the more security there is, the

more concomitant production of insecurity there must be. And if you

think that insecurity grows as prediction becomes more and more

infallible, you yourself must be afraid of the risks. And if you’re

afraid of the risks, if you don’t trust the system to completely control

the whole of your life, your fear risks becoming contagious and

presenting the system with a very real risk of defiance. In other words,

to fear risks is already to represent a risk for society. The imperative

of commodity circulation upon which cybernetic capitalism rests morphs

into a general phobia, a fantasy of self-destruction. The control

society is a paranoid society, which easily explains the proliferation

of conspiracy theories within it. Each individual is thus subjectivized,

within cybernetic capitalism, as a Risk Dividual, as some enemy or

another [a “whatever enemy”] of the balanced society.

It should not be surprising then that the reasoning of France’s François

Ewald or Denis Kessler, those collaborators in chief of Capital, affirms

that the Providential State, characteristic of the Fordist mode of

social regulation, by reducing social risks, has ended up taking

responsibility away from individuals. The dismantling of social

protection systems that we’ve been seeing since the start of the 1980s

thus has been an attempt to give responsibility to each person by making

everyone bear the “risks” borne by the capitalists alone towards the

whole “social body.” It is, in the final analysis, a matter of

inculcating the perspective of social reproduction in each individual,

who should expect nothing from society, but sacrifice everything to it.

The social regulation of catastrophes and the unexpected can no longer

be managed by simple social exclusion, as it was during the Middle Ages

in the time of lepers, the logic of scapegoating, containment, and

enclosure. If everybody now has to become responsible for the risks they

make society run, it’s only because they couldn’t exclude so many

anymore without the loss of a potential source of profit. Cybernetic

capitalism thus forcibly couples the socialization of the economy and

the increase of the “responsibility principle.” It produces citizens as

“Risk Dividuals” that self-neutralize, removing their own potential to

destroy order. It is thus a matter of generalizing self-control, a

disposition that favors the proliferation of devices, and ensures an

effective relay. All crises, within cybernetic capitalism, are

preparations for a reinforcement of devices. The anti-GMO protest

movement, as well as the “mad cow crisis” of these last few years in

France, have definitively permitted the institution of an unheard of

tracking of Dividuals and Things. The accrued professionalization of

control — which is, with insurance, one of the economic sectors whose

growth is guaranteed by cybernetic logic — is but the other side of the

rise of the citizen as a political subjectivity that has totally

auto-repressed the risk that he or she objectively represents. This is

how Citizen’s Watch contributes to the improvement of piloting devices.

Whereas the rise of control at the end of the 19^(th) century took place

by way of a dissolution of personalized bonds — which gave rise to

PEOPLE talking about “the disappearance of communities” — in cybernetic

capitalism it takes place by way of a new soldering of social bonds

entirely permeated by the imperative of self-piloting and of piloting

others in the service of social unity: it is the device-future of

mankind as citizens of the Empire. The present importance of these new

citizen-device systems, which hollow out the old State institutions and

drive the nebulous citizen-community, demonstrates that the great social

machine which cybernetic capitalism has to comprise cannot do without

human beings no matter how much time certain incredulous cyberneticians

have put into believing it can, as is shown in this flustered epiphany

from the middle of the 1980s:

“Systematic automation would in effect be a radical means of surpassing

the physical or mental limitations that give rise to the most common of

human errors: momentary losses of vigilance due to fatigue, stress, or

routine; a provisional incapacity to simultaneously interpret a

multitude of contradictory information, thus failing to master

situations that are too complex; euphemization of risk under pressure

from circumstances (emergencies, hierarchical pressures...); errors of

representation giving rise to an underestimation of the security of

systems that are usually highly reliable (as might be the case of a

pilot who categorically refuses to believe that one of his jet engines

is on fire). One must however ask oneself whether removing the human

beings — who are considered the weakest link in the man/machine

interface — from the circuit would not definitely risk creating new

vulnerabilities and necessarily imply the extension of those errors of

representation and losses of vigilance that are, as we have seen, the

frequent counterpart of an exaggerated feeling of security. Either way,

the debate deserves to remain open.”

It certainly does.

V

“The eco-society is decentralized, communitarian, and participatory.

Individual responsibility and initiative really exist in it. The

eco-society rests on the plurality of ideas about life, life styles and

behaviors in life. The consequence of this is that equality and justice

make progress. But also there is an upheaval in habits, ways of

thinking, and morals. Mankind has invented a different kind of life, in

a balanced society, having understood that maintaining a state of

balance is more of a delicate process than maintaining a state of

continual growth is. Thanks to a new vision, a new logic of

complementarity, and new values, the people of eco-society have invented

an economic doctrine, a political science, a sociology, a technology,

and a psychology of the state of controlled equilibrium.”

Joel de Rosnay, The Macroscope, 1975

“Capitalism and socialism represent two kinds of organization of the

economy, deriving from the same basic system, a system for quantifying

value added. ... Looking at it from this angle, the system called

‘socialism’ is but the corrective sub-system applied to ‘capitalism.’

One may therefore say that the most outdated capitalism is socialist in

certain ways, and that all socialism is a ‘mutation’ of capitalism,

destined to attempt to stabilize the system via redistribution — the

redistribution considered necessary to ensure the survival of all, and

to incite everyone to a broader consumption. In this sketch we call a

kind of organization of the economy that would be designed so as to

establish an acceptable balance between capitalism and socialism ‘social

capitalism.’”

Yona Friedman, Realizable Utopias, 1974.

The events of May 68 gave rise to a political reaction in all western

societies that PEOPLE hardly recall the scope of today. Capitalism was

very quickly restructured, as if an army were being put on the march to

war. The Rome Club — multinationals like Fiat, Volkswagen, and Ford —

paid sociologists and ecologists to determine what products corporations

should give up manufacturing so that the capitalist system could

function better and be reinforced. In 1972, the Massachusetts Institute

of Technology issued a report commissioned by said Rome Club, called

Limits to Growth, which made a big splash because it recommended

stopping the process of capitalist accumulation, including in the

so-called developing countries. From the lofty heights of domination,

THEY demanded “zero growth” so as to preserve social relations and the

resources of the planet, introducing qualitative components into their

analysis of development, against the quantitative projections focusing

on growth, and demanding — definitively — that it be entirely redefined;

that pressure grew until it burst in the 1973 crisis. Capitalism seemed

to have made its own self-critique. But I’m only bringing up the army

and war again because the MIT report, put together by the economist

Dennis H. Meadows, was inspired by the work of a certain Jay Forrester,

who in 1952 had been assigned by the US Air Force to the task of putting

together an alert and defense system — the SAGE system — which would for

the first time coordinate radars and computers in order to detect and

prevent a possible attack on American territory by enemy rockets.

Forrester had assembled infrastructure for communications and control

between men and machines, for the first time allowing them a “real time”

interconnection. After that he had been named to the MIT school of

management, to extend his skills in matters of systems analysis to the

economic world. He applied the same principles of order and defense to

business; he then went over cities and finally the whole of the planet

with these principles, in his book World Dynamics, which ended up an

inspiration to the MIT reporters. And so, the “second cybernetics” was a

key factor in establishing the principles applied in this restructuring

of capitalism. With it, political economy became a life science. It

analyzed the world as an open system for the transformation and

circulation of energy flows and monetary flows.

In France, an ensemble of pseudo-savants — the eccentric de Rosnay and

the blathering Morin, but also the mystic Henri Atlan, Henri Laborit,

René Passet and the careerist Attali — all came together to elaborate,

in MIT’s wake, Ten Commandments for a New Economy, an “eco-socialism,”

as they called it, following a systematic, that is, cybernetic,

approach, obsessed by the “state of equilibrium” everything and

everyone. It is useful, a posteriori, when listening to today’s “left”

and the “left of the left,” to remember certain of the principles de

Rosnay posited in 1975:

multi-culturality.

the regulation loops.

decentralization.

the visionary in chief of all cyberneticians said, “all real integration

is based on prior differentiation. ...Homogeneity, mixture, syncretism:

this is entropy. Only union within diversity is creative. It increases

complexity, and brings about higher levels of organization.”

It is no longer a matter — as PEOPLE could still pretend to believe in

1972 — of questioning capitalism and its devastating effects; it is more

a question of “reorienting the economy so as to better serve human

needs, the maintenance and evolution of the social system, and the

pursuit of a real cooperation with nature all at once. The balanced

economy that characterizes eco-society is thus a ‘regulated’ economy in

the cybernetic sense of the term.” The first ideologues of cybernetic

capitalism talked about opening a community-based management of

capitalism from below, about making everyone responsible thanks to a

“collective intelligence” which would result from the progress made in

telecommunications and informatics. Without questioning either private

property or State property, THEY invite us to co-management, to a kind

of control of business by communities of wage-workers and users. The

cybernetic reformist euphoria was at such extremes in the beginning of

the 1970s that THEY could even evoke the idea of a “social capitalism”

(as if that hadn’t been what we’ve had since the 19^(th) century)

without even trembling anymore, and defend it as did the architect

ecologist and graphomaniac Yona Friedman, for instance. Thus what PEOPLE

have ended up calling “third way socialism” and its alliance with

ecology — and PEOPLE can clearly see how powerful the latter has become

politically in Europe today — was crystallized. But if one had to refer

to just one event that in those years exposed the torturous progress

towards this new alliance between socialism and liberalism in France,

not without the hope that something different would come out of it, it

would have to be the LIP affair. With those events all of socialism,

even in its most radical currents, like “council communism,” failed to

take down the liberal arrangement and, without properly suffering any

real defeat to speak of, ended up simply absorbed by cybernetic

capitalism. The recent adherence of the ecologist Cohn-Bendit — the

mild-mannered ‘leader’ of the May 68 events — to the liberal-libertarian

current is but a logical consequence of a deeper reversal of “socialist”

ideas against themselves.

The present “anti-globalization” movement and citizen protest in general

show no break with this training by pronouncements made thirty years

ago. They simply demand that it be put into place faster. Behind the

thundering counter-summits they hold, one can see the same cold vision

of society as a totality threatened by break-up, one and the same goal

of social regulation. For them it is a matter of restoring the social

coherence pulverized by the dynamics of cybernetic capitalism, and

guaranteeing, in the final analysis, everyone’s participation in the

latter. Thus it is not surprising to see the driest economism impregnate

the ranks of the citizens in such a tenacious and nauseating manner. The

citizen, dispossessed of everything, parades as an amateur expert in

social management, and conceives of the nothingness of his life as an

uninterrupted succession of “projects” to carry out: as the sociologist

Luc Boltanski remarks, with a feigned naiveté, “everything can attain to

the dignity of a project, including enterprises which may be hostile to

capitalism.” In the same way as the “self-management” device was seminal

in the reorganization of capitalism thirty years ago, citizen protest is

none other than the present instrument of the modernization of politics.

This new “process of civilization” rests on the critique of authority

developed in the 1970s, at the moment when the second cybernetics

crystallized. The critique of political representation as separate

power, already co-opted by the new Management into the economic

production sphere, is today reinvested into the political sphere.

Everywhere there is only horizontality of relations, and participation

in projects that are to replace the dusty old hierarchical and

bureaucratic authority, counter-power and decentralization that is

supposed to defeat monopolies and secrecy. Thus the chains of social

interdependence can extend and tighten, chains which are sometimes made

of surveillance, and sometimes of delegation. Integration of civil

society by the State, and integration of the State by civil society more

and more work together like gears. It is thus that the division of the

labor of population management necessary for the dynamics of cybernetic

capitalism is organized — and the affirmation of a “global citizenship”

will, predictably, put the finishing touches on it.

After the 1970s socialism was just another democratism anymore, now

completely necessary for the progress of the cybernetic hypothesis. The

ideal of direct democracy and participatory democracy must be seen as

the desire for a general expropriation by the cybernetic system of all

the information contained in its parts. The demand for transparency and

traceability is but a demand for the perfect circulation of information,

a progressivism in the logic of flux that rules cybernetic capitalism.

Between 1965 and 1970, a young German philosopher, presumed to be the

inheritor of “critical theory,” laid the foundations for the democratic

paradigm of today’s contestation by entering noisily into a number of

controversies with his elders. Habermas countered the

socio-cybernetician Niklas Luhmann, hyper-functionalist systems

theoretician, by counterposing the unpredictability of dialogue,

arguments irreducible to simple information exchanges. But it was above

all against Marcuse that this project of a generalized “ethics of

discussion” which was to become radicalized in the critique of the

democratic project of the Renaissance. Marcuse explained, commenting on

Max Weber’s observations, that “rationalization” meant that technical

reasoning, based on the principles of industrialization and capitalism,

was indissolubly political reasoning; Habermas retorted that an ensemble

of immediate intersubjective relations escaped technology-mediated

subject-object relations, and that in the end it was the former that

framed and guided the latter. In other words, in light of the

development of the cybernetic hypothesis, politics should aim to become

autonomous and to extend the sphere of discourse, to multiply democratic

arenas, to build and research a consensus which in sum would be

emancipatory by nature. Aside from the fact that he reduced the “lived

world” and “everyday life” — the whole of what escaped the control

machine, to social interactions and discourses, Habermas more profoundly

ignored the fundamental heterogeneity of forms-of-life among themselves.

In the same way as contracts, consensus is attached to the objective of

unification and pacification via the management of differences. In the

cybernetic framework, all faith in “communicational action,” all

communication that does not assume the possibility of its impossibility,

ends up serving control. This is why science and technology are not, as

the idealist Habermas thought, simply ideologies which dress the

concrete tissue of inter-subjective relations. They are “ideologies

materialized,” a cascade of devices, a concrete government-mentality

that passes through such relations. We do not want more transparency or

more democracy. There’s already enough. On the contrary — we want more

opacity and more intensity.

But we can’t be done dealing with socialism (expired now as a result of

the cybernetic hypothesis) without mentioning another voice: I want to

talk about the critique centered around man-machine relations that has

attacked what it sees as the core of the cybernetics issue by posing the

question of technology beyond technophobia — the technophobia of someone

like Theodore Kaczynski, or of Oregon’s monkey-man of letters, John

Zerzan — and technophilia, and which intended to found a new radical

ecology which would not be stupidly romantic. In the economic crisis of

the 1970s, Ivan Illich was among the first to express the hope for a

re-establishment of social practices, no longer merely through a new

relations between subjects, as Habermas had discussed, but also between

subjects and objects, via a “reappropriation of tools” and institutions,

which were to be won over to the side of general “conviviality,” a

conviviality which would be able to undermine the law of value.

Simondon, philosopher of technology, used this same reappropriation as

his vaulting stick to transcend Marx and Marxism: “work possesses the

intelligence of the elements; capital possesses the intelligence of

groups; but it is not by uniting the intelligence of elements and of

groups that one can come up with an intelligence of the intermediary and

non-mixed being that is the technological individual... The dialogue of

capital and labor is false, because it is in the past. The socialization

of the means of production cannot alone give rise to a reduction in

alienation; it can only do so if it is the prior condition for the

acquisition, on the part of the human individual, of the intelligence of

the individuated technological object. This relationship of the human

individual to the technological individual is the most difficult to form

and the most delicate.” The solution to the problem of political

economy, of capitalist alienation, and of cybernetics, was supposed to

be found in the invention of a new kind of relationship with machines, a

“technological culture” that up to now had been lacking in western

modernity. Such a doctrine justified, thirty years later, the massive

development of “citizen” teaching in science and technology. Because

living beings, contrary to the cybernetic hypothesis’ idea, are

essentially different from machines, mankind would thus have the

responsibility to represent technological objects: “mankind, as the

witness of the machines,” wrote Simondon, “is responsible for their

relationship; the individual machine represents man, but man represents

the ensemble of machines, since there is no one machine for all the

machines, whereas there can be a kind of thinking that would cover them

all.” In its present utopian form, seen in the writings of Guattari at

the end of his life, or today in the writings of Bruno Latour, this

school claimed to “make objects speak”, and to represent their norms in

the public arena through a “parliament of Things.” Eventually the

technocrats would make way for the “mechanologues,” and other

“medialogues”; it’s hard to see how these would differ from today’s

technocrats, except for that they would be even more familiar with

technological life, citizens more ideally coupled with their devices.

What the utopians pretended not to know was that the integration of

technological thinking by everybody would in no way undermine the

existing power relations. The acknowledgement of the man-machines

hybridity in social arrangements would certainly do no more than extend

the struggle for recognition and the tyranny of transparency to the

inanimate world. In this renovated political ecology, socialism and

cybernetics would attain to their point of optimal convergence: the

project of a green republic, a technological democracy — “a renovation

of democracy could have as its objective a pluralistic management of the

whole of the machinic constituents,” wrote Guattari in the last text he

ever published — the lethal vision of a definitive civil peace between

humans and non-humans.

VI

“Just like modernization did in a prior era, today’s post-modernization

(or informatization) marks a new way of becoming human. Regarding the

production of souls, as Musil put it, one would really have to replace

the traditional technology of industrial machines with the cybernetic

intelligence of information and communications technologies. We will

need to invent what Pierre Levy has called an ‘anthropology of

cyberspace.’”

Michael Hardt & Toni Negri, Empire, 1999.

“Communication is the fundamental ‘third way’ of imperial control...

Contemporary communications systems are not subordinate to sovereignty;

on the contrary, it is sovereignty that appears to be subordinate to

communications... Communication is the form of capitalist production in

which capital has succeeded in entirely and globally subjugating society

to its regime, suppressing all the possible ways of replacing it.”

Michael Hardt & Toni Negri, Empire, 1999.

The cybernetic utopia has not only sucked all the blood out of socialism

and its force as an opposition by making it into a “proximity

democratism.” In the confusion-laden 1970s, it also contaminated the

most advanced Marxism, making its perspective inoffensive and untenable.

“Everywhere,” wrote Lyotard in 1979, “in every way, the Critique of

political economy and the critique of the alienated society that was its

corollary are used as elements in the programming of the system.” Faced

with the unifying cybernetic hypothesis, the abstract axioms of

potentially revolutionary antagonisms — class struggle, “human

community” (Gemeinwesen) or “social living” versus Capital, general

intellect versus the process of exploitation, “multitudes” versus

“Empire,” “creativity” or “virtuosity” versus work, “social wealth”

versus commodity value, etc. — definitively serve the political project

of a broader social integration. The critique of political economy and

ecology do not critique the economic style proper to capitalism, nor the

totalizing and systemic vision proper to cybernetics; paradoxically,

they even make them into the engines driving their emancipatory

philosophies of history. Their teleology is no longer that of the

proletariat or of nature, but that of Capital. Today their perspective

is, deeply, one of social economy, of a “solidarity economy,” of a

“transformation of the mode of production,” no longer via the

socialization or nationalization of the means of production but via a

socialization of the decisions of production. As writers like for

example Yann Moulier Boutang put it, it is in the end a matter of making

recognized the “collective social character of the creation of wealth,”

that the profession of living as a citizen be valorized. This pretend

communism is reduced to no more than an economic democratism, to a

project to reconstruct a “post-Fordist” State from below. Social

cooperation is presented as if it were a pre-ordained given, with no

ethical incommensurability and no interference in the circulation of

emotions, no community problems.

Toni Negri’s career within the Autonomia group, and the nebula of his

disciples in France and in the anglo world, show just how much Marxism

could authorize such a slippery slide towards the will to will, towards

“infinite mobilization,” sealing its unavoidable eventual defeat by the

cybernetic hypothesis. The latter has had no problem plugging itself

into the metaphysics of production that runs throughout Marxism and

which Negri pushed to the extreme by considering all affects, all

emotions, all communications — in the final analysis — as labor. From

this point of view, autopoïesis, self-production, self-organization, and

autonomy are categories which all play a homologous role in the distinct

discursive formations they emerged from. The demands inspired by this

critique of political economy, such as the demand for a guaranteed

minimum income and the demand for “citizenship papers for all” merely

attack, fundamentally, the sphere of production. If certain people among

those who today demand a guaranteed income have been able to break with

the perspective of putting everyone to work — that is, the belief in

work as a fundamental value — which formerly still had predominance in

the unemployed workers’ movements, it was only on condition —

paradoxically — that they’d be able to keep the restrictive definition

of value they had inherited, as “labor value.” Thus they were able to

ignore just how much they contributed, in the end, to the circulation of

goods and persons.

It is precisely because valorization is no longer assignable to what

takes place solely in the production sphere that we must now displace

political gestures — I’m thinking of normal union strikes, for example,

not even to mention general strikes — into the spheres of product and

information circulation. Who doesn’t understand by now that the demand

for “citizenship papers for all” — if it is satisfied — will only

contribute to a greater mobility of the labor force worldwide? Even

American liberal thinkers have understood that. As for the guaranteed

minimum income, if that were obtained, would it not simply put one more

supplementary source of income into the circuit of value? It would just

represent a formal equivalent of the system’s investment in its “human

capital” — just another loan in anticipation of future production.

Within the framework of the present restructuring of capitalism, the

demand for a guaranteed minimum income could be compared to a

neo-Keynesian proposal to relaunch “effective demand” which could serve

as a safety net for the hoped-for development of the “New Economy.” Such

reasoning is also behind the adherence of many economists to the idea of

a “universal income” or a “citizenship income.” What would justify such

a thing, even from the perspective of Negri and his faithful flock, is a

social debt contracted by capitalism towards the “multitudes.” When I

said, above, that Negri’s Marxism had in the end operated, like all

other Marxisms, on the basis of an abstract axiom concerning social

antagonism, it’s only because it has a concrete need for the fiction of

a united social body. In the days when he was most on the offense, such

as the days he spent in France during the unemployed workers’ movement

of winter 1997–1998, his perspectives were focused on laying the

foundation for a new social contract, which he’d call communist. Within

classical politics, then, Negriism was already playing the avant-garde

role of the ecologist movements.

So as to rediscover the intellectual circumstances explaining this blind

faith in the social body, seen as a possible subject and object of a

contract, as an ensemble of equivalent elements, as a homogeneous class,

as an organic body, one would need to go back to the end of the 1950s,

when the progressive decomposition of the working class in western

societies disturbed marxist theoreticians since it overturned the axiom

of class struggle. Some of them thought that they could find in Marx’s

Grundrisse a demonstration, a prefiguring of what capitalism and its

proletariat were becoming. In his fragment on machines, Marx envisaged

that when industrialization was in full swing, individual labor power

would be able to cease being the primary source of surplus value, since

“the general social understandings, knowledge” would become the most

immediate of productive powers. This kind of capitalism, which PEOPLE

call “cognitive” today, would no longer be contested by a proletariat

borne of large-scale manufacturing. Marx supposed that such contestation

would be carried out by the “social individual.” He clarified the

reasoning behind this unavoidable process of reversal: “Capital sets in

motion all the forces of science and nature; it stimulates cooperation

and social commerce so as to liberate (relatively speaking) the creation

of wealth from labor time... These are the material conditions that will

break up the foundations of capital.” The contradiction of the system,

its catastrophic antagonism, came from the fact that Capital measures

all value by labor time, while simultaneously diminishing it because of

the productivity gains granted it by automation. Capitalism is doomed,

in sum, because it demands — at the same time — more labor and less

labor. The responses to the economic crisis of the 1970s, the cycle of

struggles which in Italy lasted more than ten years, gave an unexpected

blow of the whip to this teleology. The utopia of a world where machines

would work instead of us appeared to be within reach. Creativity, the

social individual, the general intellect - student youth, cultivated

dropouts, intangible laborers, etc. — detached from the relations of

exploitation, would be the new subject of the coming communism. For

some, such as Negri or Castoriadis, but also for the situationists, this

meant that the new revolutionary subject would reappropriate its

“creativity,” or its “imagination,” which had been confiscated by labor

relations, and would make non-labor time into a new source of self and

collective emancipation. Autonomia was founded as a political movement

on the basis of such analyses.

In 1973, Lyotard, who for a long while had associated with Castoriadis

within the Socialism or Barbarism group, noted the lack of

differentiation between this new marxist, or post-marxist, discourse and

the discourse of the new political economy: “The body of machines which

you call a social subject and the universal productive force of man is

none other than the body of modern Capital. The knowledge in play within

it is in no way proper to all individuals; it is separate knowledge, a

moment in the metamorphosis of capital, obeying it as much as it governs

it at the same time.” The ethical problem that is posed by putting one’s

hopes in collective intelligence, which today is found in the utopias of

the autonomous collective use of communications networks, is as follows:

“we cannot decide that the primary role of knowledge is as an

indispensable element in the functioning of society and to act,

consequently, in place of it, if we have already decided that the latter

is itself just a big machine. Inversely, we can’t count on its critical

function and imagine that we could orient its development and spread in

such a direction if we’ve already decided that it is not an integral

whole and that it remains haunted by a principle of contestation.” By

conjugating the two nevertheless irreconcilable terms of such an

alternative, the ensemble of heterogeneous positions of which we have

found the womb in the discourse of Toni Negri and his adepts (which

represents the point of completion of the marxist tradition and its

metaphysics) is doomed to restless political wandering, in the absence

of any destination other than whatever destination domination may set

for it. The essential issue here — an issue which seduces many an

intellectual novice — is that such knowledge is never power, that this

understanding is never self-understanding, and that such intelligence

always remains separate from experience. The political trajectory of

Negriism is towards a formalization of the informal, towards rendering

the implicit explicit, making the tacit obvious, and in brief, towards

valorizing everything that is outside of value. And in effect, Yann

Moulier Boutang, Negri’s loyal dog, ended up dropping the following

tidbit in 2000, in an idiotic cocaine-addict’s unreal rasp: “capitalism,

in its new phase, or its final frontier, needs the communism of the

multitudes.” Negri’s neutral communism, the mobilization that it

stipulates, is not only compatible with cybernetic capitalism — it is

now the condition for its effectuation.

Once the propositions in the MIT Report had been fully digested, the

“growth” economists highlighted the primordial role to be played by

creativity and technological innovation — next to the factors of Labor

and Capital — in the production of surplus value. And other experts,

equally well informed, learnedly affirmed that the propensity to

innovate depended on the degree of education, training, health, of

populations — after Gary Becker, the most radical of the economicists,

PEOPLE would call this “human capital” — and on the complementarity

between economic agents (a complementarity that could be favored by

putting in place a regular circulation of information through

communications networks), as well as on the complementarity between

activity and environment, the living human being and the non-human

living thing. What explains the crisis of the 1970s is that there was a

whole cognitive and natural social base for the maintenance of

capitalism and its development which had up to that time been neglected.

Deeper still, this meant that non-labor time, the ensemble of moments

that fall outside the circuits of commodity valorization — that is,

everyday life — are also a factor in growth, and contain a potential

value insofar as they permit the maintenance of Capital’s human base.

PEOPLE, since then, have seen armies of experts recommending to

businesses that they apply cybernetic solutions to their organization of

production: the development of telecommunications, organization in

networks, “participatory” or project-based management, consumer panels,

quality controls — all these were to contribute to upping rates of

profit. For those who wanted to get out of the crisis of the 1970s

without questioning capitalism, to “relaunch growth” and not stop it up

anymore, would consequently need to work on a profound reorganization of

it, towards democratizing economic choices and giving institutional

support to non-work (life) time, like in the demand for “freeness” for

example. It is only in this way that PEOPLE can affirm, today, that the

“new spirit of capitalism” inherits the social critique of the years

1960–1970: to the exact extent that the cybernetic hypothesis inspired

the mode of social regulation that was emerging then.

It is thus hardly surprising that communications, the realization of a

common ownership of impotent knowledge that cybernetics carries out,

today authorizes the most advanced ideologues to speak of “cybernetic

communism,” as have Dan Sperber or Pierre Levy — the

cybernetician-in-chief of the French speaking world, collaborator on the

magazine Multitudes, and author of the aphorism, “cosmic and cultural

evolution culminate today in the virtual world of cyberspace.”

“Socialists and communists,” write Hardt and Negri, have for a long time

been demanding free access and control for the proletariat over the

machines and materials it uses to produce. However, in the context of

intangible and biopolitical production, this traditional demand takes on

a new aspect. Not only do the masses use machines to produce, the masses

themselves become more and more mechanical, and the means of production

more and more integrated into the bodies and minds of the masses. In

this context, reappropriation means attaining free access to (and

control over) knowledge, information, communication, and

feelings/emotions, since those are some of the primary means of

biopolitical production.” In this communism, they marvel, PEOPLE

wouldn’t share wealth, they’d share information, and everybody would be

simultaneously a producer and consumer. Everyone will become their own

“self-media”! Communism will be a communism of robots!

Whether it merely breaks with the individualist premises about economy

or whether it considers the commodity economy as a regional component of

a more general economy — which is what’s implied in all the discussions

about the notion of value, such as those carried out by the German group

Krisis, all the defenses of gift against exchange inspired by Mauss, and

‘the anti-cybernetic energetics of someone like Bataille, as well as all

the considerations on the Symbolic, whether made by Bourdieu or

Baudrillard — the critique of political economy, in fine, remains

dependent on economicism. In a health-through-activity perspective, the

absence of a workers’ movement corresponding to the revolutionary

proletariat imagined by Marx was to be dealt with by the militant labor

of organizing one. “The Party,” wrote Lyotard, “must furnish proof that

the proletariat is real and it cannot do so any more than one can

furnish proof of an ideal of thought. It can only supply its own

existence as a proof, and carry out a realistic politics. The reference

point of its discourse remains directly unpresentable, non-ostensible.

The repressed disagreement has to do with the interior of the workers’

movement, in particular with the form taken by recurring conflicts on

the organization question.” The search for a fighting class of producers

makes the Marxists the most consequential of the producers of an

integrated class. It is not an irrelevant matter, in existential and

strategic terms, to enter into political conflict rather than producing

social antagonism, to be a contradictor within the system or to be a

regulator within it, to create instead of wishing that creativity would

be freed, to desire instead of desiring desire — in brief, to fight

cybernetics, instead of being a critical cybernetician.

Full of a sad passion for one’s roots, one might seek the premises for

this alliance in historical socialism, whether in Saint-Simon’s

philosophy of networks, in Fourier’s theory of equilibrium, or in

Proudhon’s mutualism, etc. But what the socialists all have in common,

and have for two centuries, which they share with those among them who

have declared themselves to be communists, is that they fight against

only one of the effects of capitalism alone: in all its forms, socialism

fights against separation, by recreating the social bonds between

subjects, between subjects and objects, without fighting against the

totalization that makes it possible for the social to be assimilated

into a body, and the individual into a closed totality, a subject-body.

But there is also another common terrain, a mystical one, on the basis

of which the transfer of the categories of thought within socialism and

cybernetics have been able to form an alliance: that of a shameful

humanism, an uncontrolled faith in the genius of humanity. Just as it is

ridiculous to see a “collective soul” in the construction of a beehive

by the erratic behavior of bees, as the writer Maeterlinck did at the

beginning of the century from a Catholic perspective, in the same way

the maintenance of capitalism is in no way dependent upon the existence

of a collective consciousness in the “masses” lodged within the heart of

production. Under cover of the axiom of class struggle, the historical

socialist utopia, the utopia of the community, was definitively a utopia

of One promulgated by the Head on a body that couldn’t be one. All

socialism today — whether it more or less explicitly categorizes itself

as democracy-, production-, or social contract-focused — takes sides

with cybernetics. Non-citizen politics must come to terms with itself as

anti-social as much as anti-state; it must refuse to contribute to the

resolution of the “social question,” refuse the formatting of the world

as a series of problems, and reject the democratic perspective

structured by the acceptance of all of society’s requests. As for

cybernetics, it is today no more than the last possible socialism.

VII

“Theory means getting off on immobilization... What gives you

theoreticians a hard on and puts you on the level with our gang is the

coldness of the clear and the distinct; of the distinct alone, in fact;

the opposable, because the clear is but a dubious redundancy of the

distinct, expressed via a philosophy of the subject. Stop raising the

bar, you say! Escaping pathos — that’s your pathos.”

Jean-François Lyotard, Libidinal Economy, 1975

When you’re a writer, poet or philosopher it’s customary to talk about

the power of the Word to hinder, foil, and pierce the informational

flows of the Empire, the binary enunciation machines. You’ve heard the

eulogists of poetry clamoring that they’re the last rampart against the

barbarism of communication. Even when he identifies his position with

that of the minor literatures, the eccentrics, the “literary lunatics,”

when he hunts down the idiolects that belabor their tongues to

demonstrate what escapes the code, so as to implode the idea of

comprehension itself, to expose the fundamental misunderstanding that

defeats the tyranny of information, the author who knows himself to be

acted through, spoken through, and traveled through by burning

intensities, is for all that no less animated, when seated before his

blank page, by a prophetic concept of wording. For me, as a “receiver,”

the shock effect that certain writings have deliberately dedicated

themselves to the quest for starting in the 1960s are in this sense no

less paralyzing than the old categorical and sententious critical theory

was. Watching from my easy chair as Guyotat or Guattari get off on each

line, contorting, burping, farting, and vomiting out their

delirium-future makes me get it up, moan, and get off only very rarely;

that is, only when some desire sweeps me away to the shores of

voyeurism. Performances, surely, but performances of what? Performances

of a boarding school alchemy where the philosopher’s stone is hunted

down amid mixed sprays of ink and cum. Proclaiming intensity does not

suffice to engender the passage of intensity. As for theory and

critique, they remain cloistered in a typeface of clear and distinct

pronouncements, as transparent as the passage ought to be from “false

consciousness” to clarified consciousness.

Far from giving into some mythology of the Word or an essentialization

of meaning, Burroughs, in his Electronic Revolution proposed forms of

struggle against the controlled circulation of pronouncements, offensive

strategies of enunciation that came to light in his “mental

manipulation” operations that were inspired by his “cut-up” experiments,

a combination of pronouncements based on randomness. By proposing to

make “interference/fog” into a revolutionary weapon, he undeniably

introduced a new level of sophistication to all prior research into

offensive language. But like the situationist practice of

“detournement”/media-hijacking, which in its modus operandi is in no way

distinguishable from “recuperation”/co-optation — which explains its

spectacular fortune — “interference/fog” is merely a relative operation.

This is also true for the contemporary forms of struggle on the Internet

which are inspired by these instructions of Burroughs’: piracy, virus

propagation, spamming... all these can in fine only serve to temporarily

destabilize the operation of the communications network. But as regards

the matter we are dealing with here and now, Burroughs was forced to

agree, in terms inherited — certainly — from theories of communication

that hypostatized the issuer-receiver relationship: “it would be more

useful to try to discover how the models of exploration could be altered

so as to permit the subject to liberate his own spontaneous models.”

What’s at issue in any enunciation is not whether it’s received but

whether it can become contagious. I call insinuation — the illapsus,

according to medieval philosophy — a strategy consisting in following

the twists and turns of thought, the wandering words that win me over

while at the same time constituting the vague terrain where their

reception will establish itself. By playing on the relationship of the

sign to what it refers to, by using clichés against themselves, like in

caricatures, by letting the reader come closer, insinuation makes

possible an encounter, an intimate presence, between the subject of the

pronouncement and those who relate to the pronouncement itself. “There

are passwords hidden under slogans,” write Deleuze and Guattari, “words

that are pronounced as if in passing, components of a passage; whereas

slogans mark points of stoppage, stratified and organized compositions.”

Insinuation is the haze of theory and suits a discourse whose objective

is to permit struggles against the worship of transparency, attached at

its very roots to the cybernetic hypothesis.

That the cybernetic vision of the world is an abstract machine, a

mystical fable, a cold eloquence which continually escapes multiple

bodies, gestures, words — all this isn’t enough to conclude its

unavoidable defeat. What cybernetics needs in that regard is precisely

the same thing that maintains it: the pleasure of extreme

rationalization, the burn-scars of “tautism” [tautological autism], the

passion for reduction, the orgasm of binary flattening. Attacking the

cybernetic hypothesis — it must be repeated — doesn’t mean just

critiquing it, and counterposing a concurrent vision of the social

world; it means experimenting alongside it, actuating other protocols,

redesigning them from scratch and enjoying them. Starting in the 1950s,

the cybernetic hypothesis has been the secret fascination of a whole

generation of “critical” thinkers, from the situationists to

Castoriadis, from Lyotard to Foucault, Deleuze and Guattari. One might

map their responses in this way: these first opposed it by developing

their thought process outside it, overhanging it, and these second by

thinking within the heart of it, on the one hand “a metaphysical type of

disagreement with the world, which focuses on super-terrestrial,

transcendent worlds or utopian counter-worlds” and on the other hand “a

poïetic type of disagreement with the world, which sees the path to

freedom within the Real itself,” as Peter Sloterdijk summarizes. The

success of all future revolutionary experimentation will essentially be

measured by its capacity to make this conflict obsolete. This begins

when bodies change scale, feel themselves deepen, are passed through by

molecular phenomena escaping systemic points of view, escaping

representations of their molarity, make each of their pores into a

seeing machine clinging to the temporal evolutions of things instead of

a camera, which frames, delimits, and assigns beings. In the lines that

follow I will insinuate a protocol for experimentation, in an attempt to

defeat the cybernetic hypothesis and undo the world it perseveringly

persists in constructing. But like for other erotic or strategic arts,

its use isn’t something that is decided on nor something that imposes

itself. It can only originate in something totally involuntary, which

implies, of course, a certain casual manner.

VIII

“We also lack that generosity, that indifference to fate, which, if it

doesn’t give any great joy, does give one a familiarity with the worst

of degradations, and will be granted us by the world to come.”

Roger Caillois

“The Imaginary pays an ever higher price for its strength, while from

beyond its screen the possible Real shines through. What we have today,

doubtless, is but the domination of the Imaginary, having made itself

totalitarian. But this is precisely its dialectical and ‘natural’ limit.

Either, even desire itself and its subject, the process of attaining

corporeality of the latent Gemeinwesen, will be burnt away at the final

stake, or all simulacra will be dispelled: the extreme struggle of the

species rages on against the managers of alienation and, in the bloody

sunset of all these ‘suns of the future’ a truly possible future will at

last begin to dawn. Mankind, in order to truly Be, now only needs to

make a definitive break with all ‘concrete utopias.’

Giorgio Cesarano, Survival Manual, 1975

All individuals, groups, all lifestyles/forms-of-life, cannot fit into

the feedback loop. There are some that are just too fragile. That

threaten to snap. And there are some that are just too strong... that

threaten to break shit.

These temporal evolutions,

as an instance of breakage,

suppose that at a given moment of lived experience, bodies go through

the acute feeling that it can all abruptly come to an end,

from one moment to the next,

that the nothingness,

that silence,

that death are suddenly within reach of bodies and gestures.

It can end.

The threat.

Defeating the process of cybernetization, toppling the empire, will take

place through opening up a breach for panic. Because the Empire is an

ensemble of devices that aim to ward off all events, a process of

control and rationalization, its fall will be perceived by its agents

and its control apparatus as the most irrational of phenomena. The lines

that follow here give a cursory view of what such a cybernetic view of

panic might be, and indicate a contrario its effective power: “panic is

thus an inefficient collective behavior because it is not properly

adapted for danger (real or supposed); it is characterized by the

regression of mentalities to an archaic, gregarious level, and gives

rise to primitive, desperate flight reactions, disordered agitation,

physical violence, and general acts of self- or hetero-aggressivity:

panic reactions show the characteristics of the collective soul in a

altered state of perception and judgment; alignment on the basis of the

most unsophisticated behaviors; suggestibility; participation in

violence without any idea of individual responsibility.”

Panic makes the cyberneticians panic. It represents absolute risk, the

permanent potential threat that the intensification of relations between

lifestyles/forms-of-life presents. Because of this, it should be made as

terrifying as the appointed cybernetician himself endeavors to show it

being: “panic is dangerous for populations; it increases the number of

victims resulting from an accident by causing inappropriate flight

reactions, which may indeed be the only real reason for deaths and

injuries; every time it’s the same scenario: acts of blind rage,

trampling, crushing...” the lie in that description of course is that it

imagines panic phenomena exclusively from a sealed environment: as a

liberation of bodies, panic self-destructs because everyone tries to get

out through an exit that’s too narrow.

But it is possible to envision that there could be, as happened in Genoa

in July 2001, panic to a degree sufficient to fuck up the cybernetic

programming and pass through various social groups/milieus, panic that

would go beyond the annihilation stage, as Canetti suggests in Mass and

Power : “If we weren’t in a theater we could all run away together like

a flock of threatened animals, and increase the energy of our escape

with our movement in the same direction. An active mass fear of this

kind is the great collective event lived by all herd animals and who

save themselves together because they are good runners.” In this sense I

see as political fact of the greatest importance the panic involving

more than a million persons that Orson Welles provoked in 1938 when he

made his announcement over the airwaves in New Jersey, at a time when

radiophonics were still in early enough a state that people gave its

broadcasts a certain truth value. Because “the more we fight for our own

lives the more it becomes obvious that we are fighting against the

others hemming us in on all sides,” and alongside an unheard of and

uncontrollable expenditure, panic also reveals the naked civil war going

on: it is “a disintegration of the mass within the mass.”

In panic situations, communities break off from the social body,

designed as a totality, and attempt to escape it. But since they are

still physically and socially captive to it, they are obliged to attack

it. Panic shows, more than any other phenomenon, the plural and

non-organic body of the species. Sloterdijk, that last man of

philosophy, extends this positive concept of panic: “from a historical

perspective, the fringe elements are probably the first to develop a non

hysterical relationship with the possible apocalypse. ...Today’s fringe

consciousness is characterize by something that might be called a

pragmatic relationship with catastrophe.” To the question: “doesn’t

civilization have as a precondition the absence or even exclusion of the

panic element, to the extent that it must be built on the basis of

expectations, repetitions, security and institutions?” Sloterdijk

counters that “it is only thanks to the proximity of panic experiences

that living civilizations are possible.” They can thus ward off the

potential catastrophes of the era by rediscovering a primordial

familiarity with them. They offer the possibility of converting these

energies into “a rational ecstasy through which the individual opens up

to the intuitive idea: ‘I am the world’.” What really busts the levees

and turns panic in into a positive potential charge, a confused

intuition (in con-fusion) of its transcendence, is that each person,

when in a panic situation, is like the living foundation of his own

crisis, instead of undergoing it like some kind of exterior

inevitability. The quest after active panic — the “panic experience of

the world” — is thus a technique for assuming the risk of disintegration

that each person represents for society, as a risk dividual. It is the

end of hope and of all concrete utopias, forming like a bridge crossing

over to a state of waiting for/expecting nothing anymore, of having

nothing more to lose. And this is a way of reintroducing — through a

particular sensibility to the possibilities of lived situations, to

their possibilities of collapse, to the extreme fragility of their

organization — a serene relationship with the flight forward movement of

cybernetic capitalism. In the twilight of nihilism, fear must become as

extravagant as hope.

Within the framework of the cybernetic hypothesis, panic is understood

as a status change in the self-regulating system. For a cybernetician,

any disorder can only come from there having been a discrepancy between

the pre-set behaviors and the real behaviors of the system’s elements. A

behavior that escapes control while remaining indifferent to the system

is called “noise,” which consequently cannot be handled by a binary

machine, reduced to a 0 or a 1. Such noises are the lines of flight, the

wanderings of desires that have still not gone back into the

valorization circuit, the non-enrolled. What we call “the Imaginary

Party” is the heterogeneous ensemble of noises which proliferate beneath

the Empire, without however reversing its unstable equilibrium, without

modifying its state, solitude for instance being the most widespread

form of these passages to the side of the Imaginary Party. Wiener, when

he laid the foundation for the cybernetic hypothesis, imagined the

existence of systems — called “closed reverberating circuits” — where

the discrepancies between the behaviors desired by the whole and the

real behaviors of those elements would proliferate. He envisaged that

these noises could then brutally increase in series, like when a

driver/pilot’s panicked reactions make him wreck his vehicle after he’s

driven onto an icy road or hit a slippery spot on the highway. The

overproduction of bad feedbacks that distort what they’re supposed to

signal and amplify what they’re supposed to contain — such situations

point the way to a pure reverberatory power. The present practice of

bombarding certain nodal points on the Internet network with information

— spamming — aims to produce such situations. All revolt under and

against Empire can only be conceived in starting to amplify such

“noises,” capable of comprising what Prigogine and Stengers — who here

call up an analogy between the physical world and the social world —

have called “bifurcation points,” critical thresholds from which a new

system status becomes possible.

The shared error of Marx and Bataille with all their categories of

“labor power” or “expenditure” was to have situated the power to

overturn the system outside of the circulation of commodity flows, in a

pre-systemic exteriority set before and after capitalism, in nature for

the one, and in a founding sacrifice for the other, which were the

springboards from which one could think through the endless

metamorphosis of the capitalist system. In issue number one of the Great

Game [Le Grand Jeu], the problem of equilibrium-rupture is posed in more

immanent, if still somewhat ambiguous, terms: “This force that exists,

cannot remain unemployed in a cosmos which is full like an egg and

within which everything acts on and reacts to everything. So then there

must be some kind of trigger or lever that will suddenly turn the course

of this current of violence in another direction. Or rather in a

parallel direction, but on another plane thanks to a sudden shift. Its

revolt must become the Invisible Revolt.” It is not simply a matter of

the “invisible insurrection of a million minds” as the celestial Trocchi

put it. The force that we call ecstatic politics does not come from any

substantial outsideness, but from the discrepancy, the small variation,

the whirling motion that, moving outward starting from the interior of

the system, push it locally to its breaking point and thus pull up in it

the intensities that still pass between the various

lifestyles/forms-of-life, in spite of the attenuation of intensities

that those lifestyles effectuate. To put it more precisely, ecstatic

politics comes from desires that exceed the flux insofar as the flux

nourishes them without their being trackable therein, where desires pass

beneath the tracking radar, and occasionally establish themselves,

instantiating themselves among lifestyles that in a given situation are

playing the role of attractors. It is known that it is in the nature of

desire to leave no trace wherever it goes. Let’s go back to that moment

when a system at equilibrium can topple: “in proximity to bifurcation

points,” write Prigogine and Stengers, “where the system has a ‘choice’

between two operating regimes/modes, and is, in proper terms, neither in

the one nor the other, deviation from the general law is total: the

fluctuations can attain to the same heights of grandeur that the average

macroscopic values can... Regions separated by macroscopic distances

correlate together: the speed of the reactions produced there regulate

one another, and local events thus reverberate through the whole system.

This is when we truly see a paradoxical state, which defies all our

‘intuition’ regarding the behavior of populations, a state where the

smallest differences, far from canceling each other out, succeed one

another and propagate incessantly. The indifferent chaos of equilibrium

is thus replaced by a creative chaos, as was evoked by the ancients, a

fecund chaos from which different structures can arise.”

It would be naive to directly deduce, in this scientific description of

the potential for disorder, a new political art. The error of the

philosophers and of all thought that deploys itself without recognizing

in itself, in its very pronouncement, what it owes to desire, is that it

situates itself artificially above the processes that it is aiming to

discuss, even when it is based on experience; something Prigogne and

Stengers are not themselves immune to, by the way. Experimentation,

which does not consist in completed experiences but in the process of

completing them, is located within fluctuation, in the heart of the

noise, lying in wait for the bifurcation. The events that take place

within the social, on a level significant enough to influence fates in

general, are comprised of more than just a simple sum of individual

behaviors. Inversely, individual behaviors can no longer have, alone, an

influence on fates in general. There remain, however, three stages,

which are really one, and which, even though they are not represented,

are felt by bodies anyway as immediately political problems: I’m talking

about the amplification of non-conforming acts, the intensification of

desires and their rhythmic accord; the arrangement of territory, even if

“fluctuations cannot invade the whole system all at once. They must

first take place within a particular region. Depending on whether this

initial region has smaller than critical dimensions or not... the

fluctuation will either regress, or, contrarily, it will invade and

overtake the whole system.” So there are three questions, then, which

require investigation in view of an offensive against the Empire: a

question of force, a question of rhythm, and a question of momentum.

IX

“That’s what generalized programs sharpen their teeth on; on little bits

of people, on little bits of men who don��t want any program.”

Philippe Carles, Jean-Louis Comolli, “Free Jazz: Out of Program, Out of

Subject, in Out Field”, 2000

“The few active rebels should have the qualities of speed and endurance,

be ubiquitous, and have independent sources of provisions.”

T.E. Lawrence, “Guerrilla” Encyclopedia Britannica, Volume X, 1926

These questions, seen from the neutralized and neutralizing perspective

of the laboratory observer or of the chat-room/salon, must be reexamined

in themselves, and tested out. Amplifying the fluctuations: what’s that

mean to me? How can deviance, mine for example, give rise to disorder?

How do we go from sparse, singular fluctuations, the discrepancies

between each individual and the norm, each person and the devices, to

futures and to destinies? How can what capitalism routs, what escapes

valorization, become a force and turn against it? Classical politics

resolved this problem with mobilization. To Mobilize meant to add, to

aggregate, to assemble, to synthesize. It meant to unify little

differences and fluctuations by subjecting them to a great crime, an

un-rectifiable injustice, that nevertheless must be rectified.

Singularities were already there. They only had to be subsumed into a

unique predicate. Energy was also already there. It just needed to be

organized. I’ll be the head, they’ll be the body. And so the

theoretician, the avant-garde, the party, have made that force operate

in the same way as capitalism did, by putting it into circulation and

control in order to seize the enemy’s heart and take power by taking off

its head, like in classical war.

The invisible revolt, the “coup-du-monde” [world coup] that Trocchi

talked about, on the contrary, plays on potential. It is invisible

because it is unpredictable in the eyes of the imperial system.

Amplified, the fluctuations relative to the imperial devices never

aggregate together. They are as heterogeneous as desires are, and can

never form a closed totality; they can’t even form into a “masses,”

which name itself is just an illusion if it doesn’t mean an

irreconcilable multiplicity of lifestyles/forms-of-life. Desires flee;

they either reach a clinamen or not, they either produce intensity or

not, and even beyond flight they continue to flee. They get restive

under any kind of representation, as bodies, class, or party. It must

thus be deduced from this that all propagation of fluctuations will also

be a propagation of civil war. Diffuse guerrilla action is the form of

struggle that will produce such invisibility in the eyes of the enemy.

The recourse to diffuse guerrilla action taken by a fraction of the

Autonomia group in 1970s Italy can be explained precisely in light of

the advanced cybernetic character of the Italian govern-mentality of the

time. These years were when “consociativism,” which prefigured today’s

citizenism, was developing; the association of parties, unions, and

associations for the distribution and co-management of Power. This

sharing is not the most important thing here; the important thing is

management and control. This mode of government goes far beyond the

Providential State by creating longer chains of interdependence between

citizens and devices, thus extending the principles of control and

management from administrative bureaucracy.

It was T.E. Lawrence that worked out the principles of guerrilla war

from his experience of fighting alongside the Arabs against the Turks in

1916. What does Lawrence tell us? That the battle itself is no longer

the only process involved in war, in the same way as the destruction of

the heart of the enemy is no longer its central objective; a fortiori if

this enemy is faceless, as is the case when dealing with the impersonal

power materialized in the Empire’s cybernetic devices: “The majority of

wars are contact based; two forces struggling to remain close to one

another in order to avoid any tactical surprises. The war of the Arabs

had to be a rupture based war: containing the enemy with the silent

threat of a vast desert unknown to it and only revealing themselves at

the moment of attack.” Deleuze, though he too rigidly opposed guerrilla

war, posed the problem of individuality and war, and that of collective

organization, clarified that it was a question of opening up space as

much as possible, and making prophecies, or rather of “fabricating the

real instead of responding to it.” The invisible revolt and diffuse

guerrilla war do not sanction injustices, they create a possible world.

In the language of the cybernetic hypothesis, I can create invisible

revolt and diffuse guerrilla war on the molecular level in two ways.

First gesture: I fabricate the real, I break things down, and break

myself down by breaking it all down. This is the source of all acts of

sabotage What my act represents at this moment doesn’t exist for the

device breaking down with me. Neither 0 nor 1, I am the absolute

outsider/third party. My orgasm surpasses devices/my joy infuriates

them. Second gesture: I do not respond to the human or mechanical

feedback loops that attempt to encircle me/figure me out; like Bartleby,

I’d “prefer not to.” I keep my distance, I don’t enter into the space of

the flows, I don’t plug in, I stick around. I wield my passivity as a

force against the devices. Neither 0 nor 1, I am absolute nothingness.

Firstly: I cum perversely. Secondly: I hold back. Beyond. Before. Short

Circuiting and Unplugging. In the two cases the feedback does not take

place and a line of flight begins to be drawn. An external line of

flight on the one hand that seems to spread outwards from me; an

internal line of flight that brings me back to myself. All forms of

interference/fog come from these two gestures, external and internal

lines of flight, sabotage and retreat, the search for forms of struggle

and for the assumption of different forms-of-life. Revolution is now

about figuring out how to conjugate those two moments.

Lawrence also tells how it was also a question that it took the Arabs a

long time to resolve when fighting the Turks. Their tactics consisted

basically in “always advancing by making small hits and withdrawing,

neither making big drives, nor striking big blows. The Arab army never

sought to keep or improve their advantage, but to withdraw and go strike

elsewhere. It used the least possible force in the least possible time

and hit the most withdrawn positions.” Primacy was given to attacks

against war supplies, and primarily against communications channels,

rather than against the institutions themselves, like depriving a

section of railway of rail. Revolt only becomes invisible to the extent

that it achieves its objective, which is to “deny all the enemy’s

goals,” to never provide the enemy with easy targets. In this case it

imposes “passive defense” on the enemy, which can be very costly in

materials and men, in energies, and extends into the same movement its

own front, making connections between the foci of attack. Guerrilla

action thus since its invention tends to be diffuse. This kind of

fighting immediately gives rise to new relationships which are very

different than those that exist within traditional armies: “we sought to

attain maximum irregularity and flexibility. Our diversity disoriented

the enemy’s reconnaissance services... If anyone comes to lack

conviction they can stay home. The only contract bonding them together

was honor. Consequently the Arab army did not have discipline in the

sense where discipline restrains and smothers individuality and where it

comprises the smallest common denominator of men.” However, Lawrence did

not idealize the anarchist spirit of his troops, as spontaneists in

general have tended to do. The most important thing is to be able to

count on a sympathetic population which then can become a space for

potential recruitment and for the spread of the struggle. “A rebellion

can be carried out by two percent active elements and 98 percent passive

sympathizers,” but this requires time and propaganda operations.

Reciprocally, all offensives involving an interference with the opposing

lines imply a perfect reconnaissance/intelligence service that “must

allow plans to be worked out in absolute certainty” so as to never give

the enemy any goals. This is precisely the role that an organization now

might take on, in the sense that this term once had in classical

politics; serving a function of reconnaissance/intelligence and the

transmission of accumulated knowledge-powers. Thus the spontaneity of

guerrilleros is not necessarily opposed to organizations as strategic

information collection tanks.

But the important thing is that the practice of interference, as

Burroughs conceived it, and after him as hackers have, is in vain if it

is not accompanied by an organized practice of reconnaissance into

domination. This need is reinforced by the fact that the space where the

invisible revolt can take place is not the desert spoken of by Lawrence.

And the electronic space of the Internet is not the smooth neutral space

that the ideologues of the information age speak of it as either. The

most recent studies confirm, moreover, that the Internet is vulnerable

to targeted and coordinated attacks. The web matrix was designed in such

a way that the network would still function if there were a loss of 99%

of the 10 million routers — the cores of the communications network

where the information is concentrated — destroyed in a random manner, as

the American military had initially imagined. On the other hand, a

selective attack, designed on the basis of precise research into traffic

and aiming at 5% of the most strategic core nodes — the nodes on the big

operators’ high-speed networks, the input points to the transatlantic

lines — would suffice to cause a collapse of the system. Whether virtual

or real, the Empire’s spaces are structured by territories, striated by

the cascades of devices tracing out the frontiers and then erasing them

when they become useless, in a constant scanning sweep comprising the

very motor of the circulation flows. And in such a structured,

territorialized and deterritorialized space, the front lines with the

enemy cannot be as clear as they were in Lawrence’s desert. The floating

character of power and the nomadic dimensions of domination thus require

an increased reconnaissance activity, which means an organization for

the circulation of knowledge-powers. Such was to be the role of the

Society for the Advancement of Criminal Science (SASC).

In Cybernetics and Society, when he foresaw, only too late, that the

political use of cybernetics tends to reinforce the exercise of

domination, Wiener asked himself a similar question, as a prelude to the

mystic crisis that he was in at the end of his life: “All the techniques

of secrecy, interference in messages, and bluffing consist in trying to

make sure that one’s camp can make a more effective use than the other

camp of the forces and operations of communication. In this combative

use of information, it is just as important to leave one’s own

information channels open as it is to obstruct the channels that the

opposing side has at its disposal. An overall confidentiality/secrecy

policy almost always implies the involvement of much more than the

secrets themselves.” The problem of force reformulated as a problem of

invisibility thus becomes a problem of modulation of opening and

closing. It simultaneously requires both organization and spontaneity.

Or, to put it another way, diffuse guerrilla war today requires that two

distinct planes of consistency be established, however meshed they may

be — one to organize opening, transforming the interplay of

lifestyles/forms-of-life into information, and the other to organize

closing, the resistance of lifestyles/forms-of-life to being made into

information. Curcio: “The guerrilla party is the maximum agent of

invisibility and of the exteriorization of the proletariat’s

knowledge-power; invisibility towards the enemy cohabiting with it, on

the highest level of synthesis.” One may here object that this is after

all nothing but one more binary machine, neither better nor worse than

any of those that are at work in cybernetics. But that would be

incorrect, since it means not seeing that at the root of these gestures

is a fundamental distance from the regulated flows, a distance that is

precisely the condition for any experience within the world of devices,

a distance which is a power that I can layer and make a future from. It

would above all be incorrect because it would mean not understanding

that the alternation between sovereignty and unpower cannot be

programmed, that the course that these postures take is a wandering

course, that what places will end up chosen — whether on the body, in

the factory, in urban or peri-urban non-places — is unpredictable.

X

“The revolution is the movement, but the movement is not the revolution”

Paul Virilio, Speed and Politics, 1977

“In a world of regulated scenarios,

minutely pre-calculated programs,

impeccable music scores,

well-placed choices and acts,

what puts up any obstacles, what

hangs back, what wobbles?

Wobbliness indicates the body.

Of the body.

This limping/wobbling indicates a weak-heeled man.

A God held onto him there. He was God by the heel. The Gods limp

whenever they aren’t hunchbacked.

The dysfunction is the body. What wobbles, hurts, holds up poorly, the

exhaustion of breath, the miracle of balance. And music holds up no more

than man.

Bodies have still not been properly regulated by the law of commodities.

They don’t work. They suffer. They get worn out. They get it wrong. They

escape.

Too hot, too cold, too near, too far, too fast, too slow.”

Philippe Carles, Jean-Louis Comolli, “Free Jazz: Out of Program, Out of

Subject, in Out Field”, 2000

People have often insisted — T.E. Lawrence is no exception — on the

kinetic dimensions of politics and war as a strategic counterpoint to a

quantitative concept of relations of force. That’s the typical guerrilla

perspective as opposed to the traditional perspective. It’s been said

that if it can’t be massive, a movement should be fast, faster than

domination. That was how the Situationist International formulated their

program in 1957: “it should be understood that we are going to be seeing

and participating in a race between free artists and the police to

experiment with and develop the new techniques of conditioning. The

police already have a considerable head start. The outcome depends on

the appearance of passionate and liberating environments, or the

reinforcement — scientifically controllable and smooth — of the

environment of the old world of oppression and horror... If control over

these new means is not totally revolutionary, we could be led towards

the police-state ideal of a society organized like a beehive.” In light

of this lattermost image, an explicit but static vision of cybernetics

perfected as the Empire is fleshing it out, the revolution should

consist in a reappropriation of the most modern technological tools, a

reappropriation that should permit contestation of the police on their

own turf, by creating a counter-world with the same means that it uses.

Speed here is understood as one of the important qualities of the

revolutionary political arts. But this strategy implies attacking

sedentary forces. In the Empire, such forces tend to fade as the

impersonal power of devices becomes nomadic and moves around, gradually

imploding all institutions.

Conversely, slowness has been at the core of another section/level of

struggles against Capital. Luddite sabotage should not be interpreted

from a traditional marxist perspective as a simple, primitive rebellion

by the organized proletariat, a protest action by the reactionary

artisans against the progressive expropriation of the means of

production given rise to by industrialization. It is a deliberate slow

down of the flux of commodities and persons, anticipating the central

characteristic of cybernetic capitalism insofar as it is movement

towards movement, a will to potential, generalized acceleration. Taylor

conceived the Scientific Organization of Labor as a technique for

fighting “soldiering/go-slow” phenomena among laborers which represented

an effective obstacle to production. On the physical level, mutations of

the system also depend on a certain slowness, as Prigogine and Stengers

point out: “The faster communications within the system are, the bigger

is the proportion of insignificant fluctuations incapable of

transforming the state of the system: therefore, that state will be all

the more stable.” Slowdown tactics thus have a supplementary potential

in struggles against cybernetic capitalism because they don’t just

attack it in its being but in its process itself. But there’s more:

slowness is also necessary to putting lifestyles/forms-of-life that are

irreducible to simple information exchanges into relation with each

other. It expresses resistance of relations to interaction.

Above and beyond speed and slowness in communications, there is the

space of encounters which allow one to trace out an absolute limit to

the analogy between the social world and the physical world. This is

basically because two particles never encounter one another except where

their rupture phenomena can be deduced from laboratory observations. The

encounter is that durable instant where intensities manifest between the

forms-of-life present in each individual. It is, even above the social

and communications, the territory that actualizes the potentials of

bodies and actualizes itself in the differences of intensity that they

give off and comprise. Encounters are above language, outside of words,

in the virgin lands of the unspoken, in suspended animation, a potential

of the world which is also its negation, its “power to not be.” What is

other people? “Another possible world,” responds Deleuze. The Other

incarnates the possibility that the world has of not being, of being

otherwise. This is why in the so-called “primitive” societies war takes

on the primordial importance of annihilating any other possible world.

It is pointless, however, to think about conflict without also thinking

about enjoyment, to think about war without thinking about love. In each

tumultuous birth of love, the fundamental desire to transform oneself by

transforming the world is reborn. The hate and suspicion that lovers

excite around them is an automatic defensive response to the war they

wage, merely by loving each other, against a world where all passion

must misunderstand itself and die off.

Violence is the first rule of the game of encounters. And it polarizes

the various wanderings of desire that Lyotard invokes the sovereign

freedom of in his book Libidinal Economy. But because he refuses to

admit that enjoyments agree together on a particular territory to

precede them and where forms-of-life can mix and move together; because

he refuses to understand that the neutralization of all intensities is

itself a kind of intensification — that of the Empire, no less — because

he can’t deduce from this that while they are inseparable, life impulses

and death impulses are not neutral relative to a singular Other, Lyotard

in the end cannot go beyond the most cybernetization-compatible

hedonism: relax, let yourself go, let out your desires! Enjoy, enjoy;

there’ll always be something left! There’s no doubt that conduction,

abandon, and mobility in general can heighten the amplification of

deviations from the norm as long as they acknowledge what interrupts

flows within the very heart of circulation itself. In light of the

acceleration that cybernetics gives rise to, speed and nomadism can only

be secondary developments beside the primary slow-down policies.

Speed upholds institutions. Slowness cuts off flows. The kinetic

problem, properly speaking, in politics, thus isn’t about choosing

between two kinds of revolt but about abandoning oneself to a pulsation,

of exploring other intensifications besides those that are commanded by

the temporality of urgency. The cyberneticians’ power has been their

ability to give rhythm to the social body, which tends to prevent all

respiration. Canetti proposes that rhythm’s anthropological genesis is

associated with racing: “Rhythm is at its origin a rhythm of feet; it

produces, intentionally or not, a rhythmic noise.” But this racing is

not predictable as a robot’s would be; “the two feet never land with the

same force. The difference between them might be more or less vast,

depending on personal dispositions and moods. But you can also go faster

or more slowly, run, suddenly stop, jump...” This means that rhythm is

the opposite of a program, that it depends on forms-of-life, and that

speed problems can be dealt with by looking at rhythm issues. All

bodies, insofar as they are wobbly, have a certain rhythm that shows

that it is in their nature to hold untenable/unholdable positions. This

rhythm, which comes from the limping/wobble of bodies, the movement of

feet, Canetti adds, is — furthermore — at the origins of writing, in the

sense that it started with the tracks left by animals in motion, that

is, of History in motion. Events are the appearance of such traces and

making History means improvising in search of a rhythm. Whatever credit

we give to Canetti’s demonstrations, they do indicate — as true fictions

do — that political kinetics can be better understood as the politics of

rhythm. This means, a minima, that the binary techno-rhythm imposed by

cybernetics must be opposed by other rhythms.

But it also means that these other rhythms, as manifestations of

ontological wobbliness, have always had a creative political function.

Canetti himself also discusses how on the one hand “the rapid repetition

by which steps are added onto steps gives the illusion that there’s a

larger number of beings present. They do not move from place to place,

they carry on their dance always in the same location. The noise made by

their steps does not die, it is repeated and echoes out for a long time,

always with the same resonance and the same vivacity. They make up for

their small size in number by their intensity.” On the other hand, “when

their trampling is reinforced, it is as if they had called for backup.

They exercise a force of attraction on everybody in the area, a force

that doesn’t stop as long as they continue their dance.” Searching for

good rhythm, then, opens things up for an intensification of experience

as well as for numerical increase. It is an instrument of aggregation as

well as an exemplary action to be imitated. On the individual scale as

well as on the social scale, bodies themselves lose their sense of unity

in order to grow as potential weapons: “the equivalence of the

participants ramifies out into the equivalency of their members.

Everything mobile about a human body takes on a life of its own, each

leg, each arm lives as if for itself alone.” The politics of rhythm is

thus the search for a reverberation, another state, comparable to trance

on the part of the social body, through the ramification of each body.

Because there are indeed two possible regimes of rhythm in the

cybernetized Empire. The first, which Simondon refers to, is that of the

technician-man, who “ensure the integrative function and prolong

self-regulation outside of each monad of automatism,” technicians whose

“lives are made up of the rhythm of the machines surrounding them, and

that connect them to each other.” The second rhythm aims to undermine

this interconnective function: it is profoundly dis-integrating, rather

than merely noisy. It is a rhythm of disconnection. The collective

conquest of this accurate dissonant tempo must come from a prior abandon

to improvisation.

“Lifting the curtain of words, improvisation becomes gesture,

an act still unspoken,

a form still unnamed, un-normed, un-honored.

To abandon oneself to improvisation

to liberate oneself already — however beautiful they may be -

from the world’s already-present musical narratives.

Already present, already beautiful, already narratives, already a world.

To undo, o Penelope, the musical bandaging that forms

our cocoon of sound,

which is not the world, but is the ritual habit of the world.

Abandoned, it offers itself up to what floats outside and around

meaning,

around words,

around the codes;

it offers itself up to the intensities,

to reserve, to enthusiasm, to energy,

in sum, to the nearly-unnamable.

...Improvisation welcomes threats and transcends them,

it dispossesses them of themselves and records their potential and

risk.”

XI

“It’s the haze, the solar haze, filling space. Rebellion itself is a

gas, a vapor. Haze is the first state of nascent perception and produces

the mirage in which things climb and drop, like the movement of a

piston, and men rise and hover, suspended by a cord. Hazy vision,

blurred vision; a sketch of a kind of hallucinatory perception, a cosmic

gray. The gray splits in two, and gives out black when shadow wins out

or light disappears, but also gives out white when the luminous itself

becomes opaque.”

Gilles Deleuze, “Shame and Glory: T.E. Lawrence,” Critic and Clinic,

1993.

“No one and nothing gives an alternative adventure as a present: there’s

no possible adventure besides that of conquering a fate. You can’t wage

this conquest without starting from that spatio-temporal place where

‘your’ things stamp you as one of theirs.”

Giorgio Cesarano, Survival Manual, 1975

From the cybernetic perspective, threats cannot be welcomed and

transcended a fortiori. They must be absorbed, eliminated. I’ve already

said that the infinitely renewed impossibility of this annihilation of

events is the final certainty that practices of opposition to the

device-governed world can be founded on. Threat, and its generalization

in the form of panic, poses an unsolvable energetic problem for the

holders of the cybernetic hypothesis. Simondon thus explains that

machines with a high information outflow and control their environment

with precision have a weak energetic output. Conversely, machines that

require little energy to carry out their cybernetic mission produce a

poor rendering of reality. The transformation of forms into information

basically contains two opposing imperatives: “information is in one

sense that which brings a series of unpredictable, new states, following

no predefined course at all; it is thus that which requires absolute

availability from an information channel with respect to all the aspects

of modulation that it routes along; the information channel should in

itself have no predetermined form and should not be selective... On the

opposite hand, information is distinct from noise because information

can be assigned a certain code and given a relative uniformization; in

all cases where noise cannot be immediately/directly brought down to

below a certain level, a reduction of the margin of indetermination and

unpredictability in information signals is made.” In other words, for a

physical, biological, or social system to have enough energy to ensure

its reproduction, its control devices must carve into the mass of the

unknown, and slice into the ensemble of possibilities between what is

characterized by pure chance, and has nothing to do with control, and

what can enter into control as hazard risks, immediately susceptible to

a probability calculation. It follows that for any device, as in the

specific case of sound recording devices, “a compromise should be made

that preserves a sufficient information output to meet practical needs,

and an energy output high enough to keep the background noise at a level

that does not disturb the signal levels.” Or take the case of the police

as another example; for it, this would just be a matter of finding the

balance point between repression — the function of which is to decrease

social background noise — and reconnaissance/intelligence — which inform

them about the state of and movements in society by looking at the

signals it gives off.

To provoke panic first of all means extending the background

interference that imposes itself when the feedback loops are triggered,

and which makes the recording of behavioral discrepancies by the

ensemble of cybernetic apparatuses costly. Strategic thinking grasped

the offensive scope of such interference early on. When Clausewitz was

so bold as to say, for example, that “popular resistance is obviously

not fit to strike large-scale blows” but that “like something vaporous

and fluid, it should not condense anywhere.” Or when Lawrence

counterposed traditional armies, which “resemble immobile plants,” and

guerrilla groups, comparable to “an influence, an idea, a kind of

intangible, invulnerable entity, with no front or back, which spreads

everywhere like a gas.” Interference is the prime vector of revolt.

Transplanted into the cybernetic world, the metaphor also makes

reference to the resistance to the tyranny of transparency which control

imposes. Haze disrupts all the typical coordinates of perception. It

makes it indiscernible what is visible and what is invisible, what is

information and what is an event. This is why it represents one of the

conditions for the possibility of events taking place. Fog makes revolt

possible. In a novel called “Love is Blind,” Boris Vian imagined what

the effects of a real fog in existing relations. The inhabitants of a

metropolis wake up one morning filled by a “tidal wave of opacity” that

progressively modifies all their behaviors. The needs imposed by

appearances quickly become useless and the city is taken over by

collective experimentation. Love becomes free, facilitated by a

permanent nudity of all bodies. Orgies spread everywhere. Skin, hands,

flesh; all regain their prerogative, since “the domain of the possible

is extended when one is no longer afraid that the light might be turned

on.” Incapable of prolonging a fog that they did not contribute to the

formation of, they are relieved when “the radio says that experts have

noted that the phenomenon will be returning regularly.” In light of this

everyone decides to put out their own eyes so that life can go on

happily. The passage into destiny: the fog Vian speaks of can be

conquered. It can be conquered by reappropriating violence, a

reappropriation that can even go as far as mutilation. This violence

consists entirely in the clearing away of defenses, in the opening of

throughways, meanings, minds. “Is it never pure?” asks Lyotard. “Is a

dance something true? One could still say yes. But that’s not its

power.” To say that revolt must become foglike means that it should be

dissemination and dissimulation at the same time. In the same way as the

offensive needs to make itself opaque in order to succeed, opacity must

make itself offensive in order to last: that’s the cipher of the

invisible revolt.

But that also means that its first objective must be to resist all

attempts to reduce it away with demands for representation. Fog is a

vital response to the imperative of clarity, transparency, which is the

first imprint of imperial power on bodies. To become foglike means that

I finally take up the part of the shadows that command me and prevent me

from believing all the fictions of direct democracy insofar as they

intend to ritualize the transparency of each person in their own

interests, and of all persons in the interests of all. To become opaque

like fog means recognizing that we don’t represent anything, that we

aren’t identifiable; it means taking on the untotalizable character of

the physical body as a political body; it means opening yourself up to

still-unknown possibilities. It means resisting with all your power any

struggle for recognition. Lyotard: “What you ask of us, theoreticians,

is that we constitute ourselves as identities, as managers. But if

there’s one thing we’re sure of, it’s that this operation (of exclusion)

is just a cheap show, that incandescences are made by no one, and belong

to no one.” Nevertheless, it won’t be a matter of reorganizing a few

secret societies or conquering conspiracies like free-masonry,

carbonarism, as the avant-gardes of the last century envisioned — I’m

thinking mostly of the College of Sociology. Establishing a zone of

opacity where people can circulate and experiment freely without

bringing in the Empire’s information flows, means producing “anonymous

singularities,” recreating the conditions for a possible experience, an

experience which will not be immediately flattened out by a binary

machine assigning a meaning/direction to it, a dense experience that can

transform desires and the moments where they manifest themselves into

something beyond desire, into a narrative, into a filled-out body. So,

when Toni Negri asked Deleuze about communism, the latter was careful

not to assimilate it into a realized and transparent communication: “you

ask whether societies of control or communication would give rise to

forms of resistance capable of giving a new chance for a communism

conceived as a ‘transverse organization of free individuals.’ I don’t

know; perhaps. But this would be impossible if minorities got back hold

of the megaphone. Maybe words, communication, are rotten. They’re

entirely penetrated by money: not by accident, but by their nature. We

have to detourn/misuse words. Creating has always been something

different from communicating. The important thing is maybe to create

vacuoles of non-communication, interrupters who escape control.” Yes,

the important thing for us is to have opacity zones, opening cavities,

empty intervals, black blocs within the cybernetic matrix of power. The

irregular war waged against the Empire, on the level of a given place, a

fight, a riot, from now on will start with the construction of opaque

and offensive zones. Each of these zones shall be simultaneously a small

group/nucleus starting from which one might experiment without being

perceptible, and a panic-propagating cloud within the ensemble of the

imperial system, the coordinated war machine, and spontaneous subversion

at all levels. The proliferation of these zones of offensive opacity

(ZOO), and the intensification of their interrelations, will give rise

to an irreversible disequilibrium.

As a way of showing the kinds of conditions needed to “create opacity,”

as a weapon and as an interrupter of flows, it is useful to look one

more time to the internal criticisms of the cybernetic paradigm.

Provoking a change of status/state in a physical or social system

requires that disorder, deviations from the norm, be concentrated into a

space, whether real or virtual. In order that behavioral fluctuations

become contagious, it is necessary that they first attain a “critical

mass,” the nature of which is clarified by Prigogine and Stengers: “It

results from the fact that the ‘outside world,’ the environment around

the fluctuating region, always tends to deaden the fluctuation. Critical

mass measures the relationship between the volume, where the reactions

take place, and the contact surface, the place of linkage. Critical mass

is thus determined by a competition between the system’s ‘power of

integration’ and the chemical mechanisms that amplify the fluctuation

within the fluctuating subregion.” This means that all deployment of

fluctuations within a system is doomed to fail if it does not have at

its disposition a local anchor, a place from which the deviations that

arise can move outwards, contaminating the whole system. Lawrence

confirms it, one more time: “The rebellion must have an unassailable

base, a place sheltered not only from attack but from the fear of

attack.” In order for such a place to exist, it has to have “independent

supply lines,” without which no war is conceivable. If the question of

the base is central to all revolt, it is also because of the very

principles on the basis of which systems can attain equilibrium. For

cybernetics, the possibility of a contagion that could topple the system

has to be absorbed/deadened by the most immediate environment around the

autonomous zone where the fluctuations take place. This means that the

effects of control are more powerful in the periphery closest to the

offensive opacity zone that creates itself around the fluctuating

region. The size of the base must consequently grow ever greater as

proximity monitoring is upheld.

These bases must also be as inscribed in the space itself as in people’s

minds: “The Arab revolt,” Lawrence explains, “was to be found in the

ports of the red sea, in the desert, or in the minds of the men who

supported it.” These are territories as much as they are mentalities.

We’ll call them planes of consistency. In order that offensive opacity

zones can form and be reinforced, there need to be planes like that,

which connect deviations together, which work like a lever and fulcrum

to overturn fear. Autonomy, historically — the Italian Autonomia group

of the 1970s for example, and the Autonomy that is possible is none

other than the continual movement of perseverance of planes of

consistency that establish themselves as unrepresentable spaces, as

bases for secession from society. The reappropriation by the critical

cyberneticians of the category of autonomy/self-rule — along with the

ideas deriving from it, self-organization, auto-poïesis, self-reference,

self-production, self-valorization, etc. — is from this point of view

the central ideological maneuver of the last twenty years. Through the

cybernetic prism, giving oneself one’s own laws, producing

subjectivities, in no way contradict the production of the system and

its regulation. By calling for the multiplication of Temporary

Autonomous Zones (TAZ) in the real world and in the virtual world ten

years ago, Hakim Bey became the victim of the idealism of those who

wanted to abolish politics without having thought about it first. He

found himself forced to separate out a place for hedonistic practice

within the TAZ, to separate out a place for the “anarchist” expression

of forms-of-life from the place of political resistance, from the form

of the struggle. If autonomy is here thought of as something temporary,

it is because thinking about its duration would require conceiving of a

struggle that merges with all of life; envisioning for example the

transmission of warrior knowledge. Bey-type Liberal-anarchists are

unaware of the field of intensities in which their sovereignty cries out

to be deployed and their project of a social contract with no State at

root postulates the identity of all beings since in the end it is about

maximizing pleasures in peace until the end of time. On the one hand. On

the one hand the TAZ are defined as “free enclaves,” places whose law is

freedom, good things, the Marvelous. On the other, the secession from

the world that they issue from, the “folds” that they lodge themselves

in between the real and its encoding, would not come into being until

after a succession of “refusals.” This “Californian Ideology,” by posing

autonomy as an attribute of individual or collective subjects,

deliberately confuses two incommensurable planes: the “self-realization”

of persons and the “self-organization” of society. This is because

autonomy, in the history of philosophy, is an ambiguous notion that

simultaneously expresses liberation from all constraints and submission

to higher natural laws, and can serve to feed the hybrid and

restructuring discourses of the “anarcho-capitalist” cyborgs.

The autonomy I’m talking about isn’t temporary nor simply defensive. It

is not a substantial quality of beings, but the very condition of their

becoming/future. It doesn’t leave the supposed unity of the Subject, but

engenders multiplicities. It does not attack merely the sedentary forms

of power, like the State, and then skim over the circulating, “mobile,”

“flexible” forms. It gives itself the means of lasting and of moving

from place to place, means of withdrawing as well as attacking, opening

itself up as well as closing itself off, connecting mute bodies as

bodiless voices. It sees this alternation as the result of an endless

experimentation. “Autonomy” means that we make the worlds that we are

grow. The Empire, armed with cybernetics, insists on autonomy for it

alone, as the unitary system of the totality: it is thus forced to

annihilate all autonomy whenever it is heterogeneous. We say that

autonomy is for everyone and that the fight for autonomy has to be

amplified. The present form taken on by the civil war is above all a

fight against the monopoly on autonomy. That experimentation will become

the “fecund chaos,” communism, the end of the cybernetic hypothesis.