đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș wayne-price-anarchy-crime-and-prisons.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:48:07. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anarchy, Crime, and Prisons Author: Wayne Price Date: December 4, 2021 Language: en Topics: crime, prison, book review, criminology, abolition, justice, Anarcho-Syndicalist Review Source: Retrieved on 21st April 2022 from https://www.anarkismo.net/article/32481 Notes: Review of Jacques Lesage de La Haye, The Abolition of Prison and Anthony J. Nocella II, Mark Seis, & Jeff Shantz (Eds.), Classic Writings in Anarchist Criminology; A Historical Dismantling of Punishment and Domination. Written for Anarcho-Syndicalist Review.
Jamie Dimon is the CEO and chairman of JPMorgan Chase & Company, and
apparently something of a philanthropist. In a recent column in the New
York Times (8/8/21), he begins, âOne in three American adultsâmore than
70 million peopleâhave some type of criminal recordâŠabout the same
number of Americans [as] have college degreesâŠ.Nearly half of formerly
incarcerated people are unemployed one year after leaving prison. That
is a moral outrage.â
So it is, but what to do about the high rate of arrests, of
imprisonment, and of post-prison unemployment? Chairman Dimont wants to
find jobs for newly released convicts, but what about all that
incarceration in the first place?
Many people think that anarchists and other prison abolitionists simply
want society more-or-less as it is, but with no police, no courts, no
laws, and no prisons. âCommon senseâ tells them that such a society (if
it could miraculously come into existence) would quickly devolve into
chaos (âanarchyâ). Criminals would have a field dayâexcept in the
neighborhoods of the very rich, who would hire private security guards.
Eventually, a new repressive state would be formed by either organized
crime or the professional rent-a-cops (or both together).
Oddly enough, there are people who advocate something like this:
pseudo-âlibertarianâ right-wingers (some of whom call themselves
âanarcho-capitalists,â which is not a thing). Even the liberal program
of âdefund the policeâ is often misinterpreted to mean âabolish the
policeâânow, in this society. However, it is pretty easy to argue that
our current society, as it is organized with its marketplace in goods
and people, its inequality, its poverty, its white supremacy, its
sexism, its dog-eat-dog morality, its constant wars, and its general
lovelessnessâcould not exist without repressive laws, police, courts,
and prisons. Certainly, things could be made more humane, rational, and
flexibleâbut to altogether abolish prisons, etc., is beyond the scope of
capitalism and the state.
âOnly a true social revolution can bring the end of punishment by
imprisonmentâŠ. âA society without prisons can only be a society that
doesnât need prisons.â All the anarchists agree in saying that prison
cannot disappear without a radical change of society taking place.â
(Lesage de La Haye; pp. 8 & 18) And yet this is often used as a
justification for law, police, and prisons.
Let us imagine a different kind of society (call it anarchy, socialist
democracy, small-c communism, or a realistic utopia). It would be a
prosperous society with a comfortable life for everyone, decent work for
all which is productive and even creative, plenty of leisure and free
time, equality in all areas including everyoneâs standard of living,
democratic participation in decision making in industry and community
affairs, freedom and respect for women, equality for all racial and
ethnic groups, sexual freedom among consenting adults, few limitations
on âsofterâ drugs, and treating more dangerous drugs as issues of public
health. Finally, it would have an ideologyâtaught from childhoodâof
cooperation, mutual respect, and individual autonomy.
Is it not also âcommon senseâ that there would then be a great deal less
crime of any sort, a big decrease in violence, anti-social aggression,
abuse of women and of children? I do not say that all anti-social
behavior would vanish. But even today, Lesage de La Haye estimates,
based on current research, only about five percent of those convicted
are âclearly dangerousâ having committed ârape, murder, hostage
situations, assault with a deadly weapon, shootings.â (p. 95)
Especially in the period of the transition to a new society, a
generation will still show the effects of having been raised in the
loveless world of capitalism. But it is not necessary to assume that
humans will ever be perfect and without flaws. Kropotkin wrote that
under anarchism, âThere surely will remain a limited number of persons
whose anti-social passionsâŠmay still be a danger for the community.â
(Nocella et al.; p. 168)
There is a widespread misconception that anarchists think that people
are ânaturallyâ good. Anarchists do think that people are capable of
goodness, especially if in a society which encourages cooperation and
mutual respect. But anarchists also think that humans are capable of
badness. This is a major reason why people should not have power over
other people; âpower corrupts.â Therefore anarchists want to get rid of
politicians, bureaucrats, businesspeople, police, wardens, and prison
guards.
If there is a lot less anti-social action in a good society, then that
remaining bad behavior can be dealt with in a much less repressive, more
rational, and compassionate fashion. In their âIntroduction,â Nocella et
al. write, âIn an anarchist society, state definitions of crime would
disappear, but conflict between humans would remain. The nonhierarchical
and noncoercive strategies defining transformative justice will, to some
degree, always be necessary.â (p. 14)
These two books deal with anarchist views of crime and punishment,
especially in relation to prisons. The little book by Jacques Lesage de
La Haye covers his own history as a delinquent, his self-education in
prison, his efforts to form family-like communities to help young
delinquents, and his general research on the topic of abolition of
prisons. Anthony Nocella II, Mark Seis, and Jeff Shantz have edited a
collection of writings by early anarchists on the subject of crime and
imprisonment. The âclassicâ authors included are William Godwin (a major
precursor of anarchism), P.-J. Proudhon (the first to call himself an
âanarchistâ), Mikhail Bakunin (a founder of revolutionary anarchism),
Peter Kropotkin (a major theorist of anarchist-communism), the Haymarket
martyrs August Spies and Michael Schwab, Errico Malatesta, Voltairine de
Claire, Lucy Parsons, Alexander Berkman, and Emma Goldman. Much of their
selected writings cover general anarchist themes of opposition to the
state and capitalism as a background to considering crime and
punishment. I am not going to go over each writerâs contribution, but
rather review some overall themes of these foundational anarchists,
together with Lesage de La Haye.
The anarchist authors all agree that laws, legislatures, police, courts,
and prisons (and executioners) exist to maintain the power and wealth of
the capitalist class and its state officials. These laws justify the
greatest âcrimesâ of all, the robbery and murder of the people of this
country and the world by the bourgeoisie and its state forces These laws
and the conditions they uphold are the main creators of the crime,
violence, and anti-social aggression from below. This is the starting
point of the anarchist analysis of crime and punishment.
Of the conditions of suffering and oppression, the classical anarchists
reprinted here focus on poverty and class exploitation. These
socioeconomic factors are extremely important to relate to crime and
punishment. However, there is only one discussion of womenâs oppression
(by Emma Goldman) and none of racial injustice (except for a brief
passage by de Cleyre about the evil of lynching). This is not a
limitation of the editors but of the revolutionary anarchists of the
time.
An anarchist-socialist society would still have rules of some sort.
Kropotkin distinguishes between âtwo currents of custom,â which lay the
basis for two currents in the laws. These are, âthe maxims which
represent principles of morality and social union wrought out as a
result of life in common, and the mandates which are meant to
ensureâŠinequality.â (Nocella et al.; p. 141) This is the âdouble
character of law.â The first current is based on social interaction and
mutual aid, while the second current props up the exploiter, the priest,
and the king. âIt must be utterly destroyed on the day when the people
desire to break their chains.â (p. 142)
All the writers look at the irrationality of the laws and the penalties
for breaking them, above all of incarceration. Punishment and
retribution (really revenge) are denounced as unworthy motives for
dealing with harms caused by individualsâespecially in a society which
has harmed these and other individuals at least as much. The only just
motive for coercing anti-social actors would be to protect society from
their aggression. Yet the current system is not very effective at that.
The people arrested, tried, and sent to prison, mostly come out of
prison eventually. Few have been improved and many have been worsened.
Many will again break the law and be sent back to prison.
As an argument against the punishment of criminals, several of the
authors argue that individualsâ actions are determined by previous
conditions, Therefore they should not be blamed if they act harmfully
towards others. (This is argued in passages by Godwin, Bakunin, and de
Cleyre.) Certainly everyoneâs behavior is formed by the interaction of
heredity with their biological and social environment. But people do
make choices and decisions and may be held responsible for them. This is
not a justification for prisons, anymore than it is for whipping blocks,
torture, or burning at the stake.
It is not hard to show the evils of prisons. Causing great suffering,
they do not pretend to ârehabilitateâ their inmates. âRehabilitationâ
implies that there is a good society in which some aberrant people have
broken the rules, therefore they can be re-adjusted to the good society.
Yet actually, we have a bad society in which some people have followed
the general competitive, get-over-on-the-other-guy, philosophy, but have
done poorly at it. Of course rehabilitation does not work, although I
hope Chairman Dimon can find some good jobs for a number of former
inmates. (My barber, a good-hearted man, told me that he had offered to
teach prisoners his art, until he learned that convicted felons were not
eligible for a barberâs license.)
The Nocella et al. editors summarize the view of Malatesta: âAnarchists,
unlike authoritarians, do not claim to hold an infallible formula for
ending crime as authoritarians propose through laws and force.â (p. 179)
As he advocated in other areas of social organization, Malatesta
proposed experimentation with different approaches to maintaining public
safety. He responded to a fellow anarchist who advocated the communal
organization of public safety in a form similar to agencies for public
health or transportation, under popular control. But Malatesta was
opposed to a specialized or permanent police force, fearing that it
would become a new oppressor. Anarchists and revolutionary Marxists have
long advocated some sort of popular militia (an organized, armed,
people) to replace the police and army.
How would people in a free society deal with social conflicts and harms?
âWhat is the best method for settling problems and conflicts within a
collective? We all know it: dialogue, reconciliation, discussionâin
short, mediation. It has always existed.â (Lesage de La Haye p. 77)
Lesage de La Haye tells the story of the Indigenous people of Guerrero,
in the Costa Montana region of Mexico. (Pp. 67â70) 63 villages formed a
federation with locally elected âpolice captains,â judges, and overall
committees. Offenders are treated with mediation, re-education, and
reparationsâno prisons (the Mexican state was not happy about that).
Covering about a hundred thousand people, it has lasted for over ten
years (at the time of this publication). He also refers to other
examples of successful community management of public safety around the
world.
Movements against the police and prisons have burst out in the US and
around the world. They are part of broader rebellions against state
repression and the state itself, against exploitation and capitalism
itself, against ecological destruction and the whole
capitalist-statist-nature-destroying system. These two books are
valuable contributions to that struggle.